RE: Requirement that cabbies transport alcohol = tiny burden?

2012-03-08 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Yes, State v. Hershberger, 462 N.W.2d 393 (Minn. 1990).

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
Sent: Wednesday, March 07, 2012 12:18 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Requirement that cabbies transport alcohol = tiny burden?

Eugene-- just a point of information--is there a lead MN Sup Court case that 
applying  strict scrutiny in cases involving neutral generally applicable laws 
and worship conduct that is illegal?


Thanks!

On Mar 7, 2012, at 3:11 PM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
But the Minnesota Constitution has been interpreted as 
following Sherbert and Yoder, so isn’t the question indeed why the cab drivers 
aren’t constitutionally entitled to an exemption?  As it happens, I oppose 
constitutional exemption regimes, at the state and federal levels, and support 
jurisdiction-by-jurisdiction RFRAs, which means the question becomes statutory, 
and trumpable by the state legislature.  But the Minnesota rule is one of 
constitutionally mandated exemptions, unless strict scrutiny is satisfied, no?

Eugene

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Steven Jamar
Sent: Wednesday, March 07, 2012 7:22 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Requirement that cabbies transport alcohol = tiny burden?

For the record, I was in favor of the accommodation attempted for the Somali 
Muslim cab drivers in Minneapolis and am in favor of most accommodations of 
religion done by employers and public agencies and the government in general -- 
even quite odd ones like this particular interpretation of the Quran by this 
group of Somalis.

But that is quite different from positing that there is a right in the Somalis 
to engage in this sort of discrimination let alone a constitutional right to do 
so.

Doug is right -- sometimes hostility to religious accommodation is motivated by 
a universalist thrust that we should in fact all be treated equally -- the same 
sort of hostility one sees against affirmative action for Blacks.  And Doug is 
also right that sometimes the hostility is directed against a religion and 
members of that religion -- as JWs, Muslims, Jews, and in some settings and 
some times, Catholics and others have experienced (19th Century Baptist prayer 
-- God save us from the Unitarians who at the time had circuit riders and 
were quite evangelical, unlike today).

No doubt both of these played into this event -- especially hostility to Islam.

But the subtextual motivation of hostility to the religion cannot make what is 
otherwise lawful discrimination unlawful, or does it?  Is there a 
constitutionally meaningful distinction between -- I don't like your religion 
and therefor will not accommodate you  and I don't think you are entitled to 
an accommodation as a matter of constitutional right -- where there is in fact 
no constitutional right to accommodation, as here.

Steve
___
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Discrimination against people with religious motivations for their actions

2012-03-08 Thread Marc Stern
Might I suggest another way of looking at this debate: race. Not the race of 
the drivers and that of their passengers. instead i take it as common ground 
that no one would tolerate taxi drivers turning down passengers on the basis of 
race. Does it follow that we should treat all prohibited grounds of 
discrimination with the same rigor, both as a matter of primary law-all 
forbidden categories are treated equal-or because once the prohibition on 
discrimination is weakened, even in good cause, the pressure for other 
exemptions will grow and will weaken the non discrimination norm in regard to 
race. The latter argument was raised after Boerne when the question was whether 
to include civil rights claims in a statute protecting religious liberty..
Marc

From: Steven Jamar [mailto:stevenja...@gmail.com]
Sent: Wednesday, March 07, 2012 09:45 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Discrimination against people with religious motivations for their 
actions



I hope it comes as no surprise to anyone on this list that there are 
irreconcilable doctrinal problems with religious liberty no matter how one 
looks at it.  Religious motivation matters.  Particular facts matter.  Details 
matter.  Eugene's hypothetical restaurant is not analogous to the cabbies in 
Minneapolis or in general.

I am not at all sure that Lukumi extends to private conduct and general 
anti-discrimination laws.  In that case the state singled out a particular 
religion by ordinance -- not the application of an anti-discrimination law.  
There is also a world of difference between actions by private parties that 
discriminate on the basis of religion and ordinances by states (or cities) that 
ban particular religious practices.

If the past decades of religious jurisprudence have taught us anything it 
should be to by chary of expanding any decision by the court much beyond its 
peculiar facts.  Witness the recent distinguishing of Smith.  Who knew?

I do not contend that these cases are easy or that they are or can be decided 
with great consistency -- indeed, I contend exactly the opposite.  Motivation 
matters and I cannot transmute a religious motivated action against someone 
into a neutral action without any religious motivation.

The response to the accommodation in Minneapolis shows a societal anti-Islam 
animus.  Who is surprised?

But the claim of a person who has been denied a ride on a common carrier for no 
reason other than doing something he has an absolutely legal right to do and is 
denied the ride because of a religious belief by the driver is sure going to 
feel like religious discrimination whatever niceties one might want to draw.  
And in fact IS religiously-motivated action excluding someone.  It is.  Should 
it be permitted?  Should it be accommodated?  Probably, in the absence of 
showing hardship to riders.  But if it s the last cab of the night?  No way.

I generally think we should accommodate religious exercise rights of employers 
and service providers and everyone to the extent practicable.  But that is a 
long way from finding a constitutional or statutory right to engage in such 
conduct when engaged in the provision of such public services.

There is no constitutional principle or statutory provision that would or 
should require that.  The situations are too nuanced for hard-edged application 
of generally applicable rules in this area.  Minneapolis Airport Authority 
approached it sensibly and if the solution had been implemented and if it had 
worked as planned (I have doubts, but maybe it would have), then that is what 
should be done.  We are not a secular universalist society -- not by a long 
shot.  Nor should we be -- it is not within our traditions and experience and 
our polyglot amalgam of people -- but nor should it be heavy-handed 
rights-based regime with what becomes a unit veto.

Steve






--
Prof. Steven D. Jamar vox:  202-806-8017
Associate Director, Institute for Intellectual Property and Social Justice 
http://iipsj.org
Howard University School of Law   fax:  202-806-8567
http://iipsj.com/SDJ/


Never doubt that the work of a small group of thoughtful, committed citizens 
can change the world. Indeed, it’s the only thing that ever has.


Margaret Meade




___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Minneapolis Taxicab Controversy

2012-03-08 Thread Marty Lederman
Thanks very much, Marie.  Is any or all of this documented somewhere, in
addition to the state court of appeals case?

On Wed, Mar 7, 2012 at 12:31 PM, Marie A. Failinger 
mfailin...@gw.hamline.edu wrote:

  Just to add to my previous post in response to Marty's questions:

 1.  Not all of the Muslim cabbies felt religiously obliged to refuse to
 carry passengers with open displays of al to the cohol (or dogs) as I
 remember. However, there was a fatwa issued by a local Muslim organization
 saying that they shouldn't do it.  Since a fatwa is a legal opinion, it
 certainly provides legal authority for the cabbies' insistence that they
 shouldn't do it; it wasn't simply their personal view per se.

 2.  Airport regulation 102 now provides that taxi drivers cannot refuse to
 take a passenger unless he refuses to pay, is seriously intoxicated or is a
 physical threat.  One provision of the section also prohibits drivers from
 refusing service based on race, gender, religion, national origin,
 ethnicity, marital status, disability, sexual orientation, or age, or
 having a service dog.

 3.  The cabbies' appeal for an injunction was denied by the trial court
 and upheld by Minnesota Court of Appeals in 2008 on the basis that they had
 an adequate remedy at law--any license denial could be appealed and the
 cabbie could keep his license in the meantime.  Dolal v. Metropolitan
 Airports Com'n, 2008 WL 4133517

 http://minnesota.publicradio.org/display/web/2008/09/09/muslim_cabs_court/

 I couldn't find much recently about the effect on Muslims serving the
 airport except this related news, in January, a major airport taxi company
 here fired Somali drivers who protested the refusal of the company to sit
 down and negotiate their working conditions
 http://minnesota.publicradio.org/collections/special/columns/news_cut/archive/2012/01/report_somali_cabbies_learn_pr.shtml


  Marie A. Failinger

 Professor of Law
 Editor, Journal of Law and Religion
 Hamline University School of Law
 1536 Hewitt Avenue
 Saint Paul, MN 55104 U.S.A.
 651-523-2124 (work phone)
 651-523-2236 (work fax)
 mfailin...@hamline.edu (email)


  Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com 3/7/2012 5:35 AM 

 Can anyone point me to a good, thorough account of what happened in
 Minneapolis, including (i) the explanations, if any, the cabbies offered
 for why the lack of the exemption burdened their religious exercise (did it
 mean they were unable to accept work as other forms of common carriers,
 such as pilots, UPS/FedEx delivery employees, bus drivers, etc.?); (ii) how
 the controversy was resolved as a matter of law; and (iii) what became of
 the Muslim drivers after the exemption was revoked.

 Thanks in advance.

 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Discrimination against people with religious motivations for their actions

2012-03-08 Thread Marci Hamilton
I have to say that I find Steve's analysis more sound and based on common 
sense.   


Marci

On Mar 7, 2012, at 3:07 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

 I think the analysis below is mistaken:  Whether or not cabbies’ refusal to 
 carry alcohol should be barred by some general common-carriage requirement, 
 it shouldn’t be treated as religious discrimination.  What’s more, I think 
 the argument that such a refusal is religious discrimination itself calls for 
 discrimination against those with religious motivations for their actions.
  
 1.  To begin with, as others have pointed out, the cabbies’ actions affected 
 Christians, Jews, Muslims, the irreligious, and anyone else who carried 
 alcohol.  Moreover, they didn’t affect Christian, Jews, Muslims, the 
 irreligious, and anyone else who didn’t carry alcohol.
  
 2.  Now I take it that the response is that the really devout Muslims of the 
 same religious views as the cabbies generally wouldn’t be affected (just as, 
 I suppose, Mormons or Methodists wouldn’t be affected), because they 
 generally wouldn’t carry alcohol.  But that analysis strikes me as unsound, 
 and here’s why.
  
 Imagine a case closely modeled on Rasmussen v. Glass (Minn. Ct. App. 1993) 
 (review granted but appeal later dismissed), 
 http://scholar.google.com/scholar_case?case=648897692635049631.  A restaurant 
 owner refuses to deliver food to a doctor who performs abortions, because the 
 owner believes abortions are evil, and doesn’t want to provide any help, even 
 indirect, to such evil.  And say the restaurant owner’s is irreligious, and 
 his opposition to abortion is based on his own personal moral views (e.g., he 
 follows Nat Hentoff, 
 http://groups.csail.mit.edu/mac/users/rauch/nvp/consistent/indivisible.html). 
  I take it that we would all agree that the restaurant owner is not 
 discriminating based on religion.  To be sure, devout Catholics, and devout 
 members of other anti-abortion religious groups, wouldn’t perform abortions.  
 But that doesn’t mean the restaurant owner is discriminating based on the 
 would-be customers’ religions – he’s discriminating based on their secular 
 actions.
  
 Now say that another restaurant owner acts precisely the same way, but his 
 opposition to abortion is based on his religious views.  As I understand the 
 argument below, he would be seen as discriminating based on religion, because 
 the performing of abortion is “a badge of a religion different from yours.”  
 And thus he would be presumptively required to deliver to the doctor’s 
 office, if state public accommodations law covers discrimination based on 
 religion in restaurant delivery.  But this would mean that the law itself has 
 become religiously discriminatory:  The secular anti-abortion restaurant 
 owner is free to do something (here, refusing to deliver to an abortion 
 provider), but the religious anti-abortion restaurant owner is barred from 
 doing precisely the same thing.
  
 3.  I think the same applies to the alcohol example.  A secular cab driver 
 who opposes alcohol on secular grounds would presumably not be treated as 
 discriminating based on religion.  But to treat the religious cab driver who 
 opposes alcohol on religious grounds would be treated as discriminating based 
 on religion, and would thus be potentially violating relevant public 
 accommodations bans.  Yet such an approach would itself impermissibly 
 discriminate (in violation of Lukumi Babalu) against the religious cab driver 
 based on the religiosity of his motivation for his conduct.  Or am I missing 
 something here?
  
 Eugene
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Steven Jamar
 Sent: Wednesday, March 07, 2012 7:10 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Cabbies vs. lawyers
  
 Of course it is a proxy -- just like a collar or burka or yarmulke -- a badge 
 of a religion different from yours -- only in this case it is alcohol 
 possession -- a badge of a religion different from yours.  The dodge of oh, 
 I'm not against their religion, just against their conduct can't be allowed 
 can it?  The person transporting the alcohol is the passenger, not the cab 
 driver.  The fact of hidden vs. open possession of the bottle of wine gives 
 it away, doesn't it -- it is not about the action, it is about the religious 
 nature of the action -- the violation of the religious beliefs of the driver 
 by the religious beliefs (ok to have and transport alcohol) by the passenger.
  
 It is action based on a difference of religious belief.  That is 
 discrimination no matter how one twists it.
  
 Maybe we should allow this discrimination, just like maybe we should allow 
 discrimination in allowing landlords to discriminate against gays based on 
 the landlord's religious beliefs, but that is still religious-based 
 discrimination.  
  
 You can't suddenly say that motivation doesn't matter just 

RE: Once it took the step of opening play to non-Christians

2012-03-08 Thread Paul Horwitz

I won't extend the conversation too much, but I appreciate the points Eugene 
makes. I'm not sure they change my mind entirely, although I do very much think 
one should be sensitive to these counter-arguments.  I suppose the reason I 
take the position I do, notwithstanding what Eugene says about incentives for 
and against ecumenicalism, is that I don't treat ecumenicalism as an 
unqualified good. It depends for me in part on the group's own sense of its 
mission and what it demands. The more ecumenical its own sense of itself is, 
the more its ecumenicalism suggests a need to try and accommodate others, at 
least in the demographic universe it is seeking to inhabit; the more sectarian 
its sense of itself, the less I think it should be obliged to make shift to 
meet others' needs. That it might face public criticism is a possibility, but, 
if it was open about wanting to live out a specifically sectarian mission, I 
would probably not be among the critics. I should add that I'm speaking more in 
civic terms than legal ones. I tend to think that 1) the Court was right in 
both BSA and Hosanna-Tabor, 2) that doesn't mean that those groups should be 
immune from public criticism for their views and decisions; sometimes they will 
hold fast despite that criticism, and sometimes their own sense of mission may 
change as a result of both public criticism and internal debate; and 3) in any 
event, groups that are or ought to be entitled to some legal protection qua 
groups should engage in serious reflection about their mission and what it 
requires, even if the courts themselves are obliged to defer to them for the 
most part about that mission.
Best to all,
Paul  

From: vol...@law.ucla.edu
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Date: Sun, 4 Mar 2012 16:26:06 -0800
Subject: Once it took the step of opening play to non-Christians



I think I understand Paul’s point, and the arguments in favor it, 
but I wonder whether it might get things backward.  TAPPS could likely have 
focused itself on Christian private schools with little difficulty for it.  (It 
might have benefited from including secular schools, but it likely could have 
survived just as well limited to Christian schools.)  On the other hand, my 
sense is that in such situations it’s a great benefit to minority schools – 
both secular schools and especially Jewish schools – to be able to join such an 
association, since otherwise there might be very few schools for them to play 
against.  In many places, an all-Orthodox-Jewish league would have very few 
teams, and very long travel times to games. So TAPPS generally did 
Jewish schools a good turn by letting them participate.  And if it hadn’t let 
them participate, I suspect many would have faulted them for being unfairly 
exclusionary, with the argument being “What’s it to you that the school is 
Jewish?”  But now TAPPS is being told that by being somewhat more open, it now 
incurs this extra obligation.  That strikes me as both creating perverse 
incentives, and being a poor reward for TAPPS’ moderate ecumenicalism, because 
it demands that this moderate ecumenicalism lead to considerably more demanding 
ecumenicalism. As to the guest/host analogy, I would think that 
this too cuts the opposite direction at least as much as in the direction 
suggested below (and perhaps more).  If I invite someone to my home, or into my 
private association, I surely would feel some impulse to accommodate him; if 
someone comes for dinner but says that he can’t eat pork (and doesn’t otherwise 
demand a kosher kitchen), I’ll probably try to give him a non-pork option even 
if the main course is ham.  But I would hope that he would feel an even 
stronger impulse not to reward my hospitality with excessive demands, or with 
repeating his demands after I say no (even if I’m being not as hospitable as I 
might be in saying so) – and I would certainly hope that he wouldn’t reward my 
hospitality with a lawsuit. Eugene  Paul Horwitz writes: In this 
case, it seems to me that the road to a reasonable resolution of the problem 
lies in the fact that TAPPS opened itself to a situation in which it welcomed 
the possibility of sporting events involving others whose religious needs might 
require accommodation. If the league had remained solely devoted to Christian 
schools and, in effect, had valued Christian community over sports or all-state 
intramural play itself, then refusing to change its schedule would a) be 
reasonable and b) not be much of a problem, since the issue would be unlikely 
ever to arise. Once it took the step of opening play to non-Christians, 
however, including those with an equally thick set of religious commitments, 
then common sense, if not simply being a good host, would suggest that the 
league ought to anticipate and accommodate the religious needs of its guests. 
But certainly the work here is not done by invoking common sense alone.  

Re: Minneapolis Taxicab Controversy

2012-03-08 Thread Marie A. Failinger
Marty, the fatwa is described in the following Star Tribune article, 
http://www.startribune.com/local/11586646.html (which also reports one local 
well-respected imam's opinion that carrying a disability service dog should not 
pose a problem for Muslim cabdrivers.)
 
The airport ordinance can be found on the Twin Cities Metropolitan Airports 
Commission website.
 
I am trying to investigate the fallout issue with a local Muslim civil rights 
leader and will report back if I get any info.
 
In fact, if anyone is interested in investigating the extreme nature of some 
opinions about Muslims in the U.S., I would suggest that you Google this issue 
and read some of the non-news postings.  

 
Marie A. Failinger

Professor of Law
Editor, Journal of Law and Religion
Hamline University School of Law
1536 Hewitt Avenue
Saint Paul, MN 55104 U.S.A.
651-523-2124 (work phone)
651-523-2236 (work fax)
mfailin...@hamline.edu (email)


 Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com 3/8/2012 5:29 AM 
Thanks very much, Marie. Is any or all of this documented somewhere, in 
addition to the state court of appeals case?

On Wed, Mar 7, 2012 at 12:31 PM, Marie A. Failinger mfailin...@gw.hamline.edu 
wrote:


Just to add to my previous post in response to Marty's questions:
1. Not all of the Muslim cabbies felt religiously obliged to refuse to carry 
passengers with open displays of al to the cohol (or dogs) as I remember. 
However, there was a fatwa issued by a local Muslim organization saying that 
they shouldn't do it. Since a fatwa is a legal opinion, it certainly provides 
legal authority for the cabbies' insistence that they shouldn't do it; it 
wasn't simply their personal view per se.
2. Airport regulation 102 now provides that taxi drivers cannot refuse to take 
a passenger unless he refuses to pay, is seriously intoxicated or is a physical 
threat. One provision of the section also prohibits drivers from refusing 
service based on race, gender, religion, national origin, ethnicity, marital 
status, disability, sexual orientation, or age, or having a service dog. 
3. The cabbies' appeal for an injunction was denied by the trial court and 
upheld by Minnesota Court of Appeals in 2008 on the basis that they had an 
adequate remedy at law--any license denial could be appealed and the cabbie 
could keep his license in the meantime. Dolal v. Metropolitan Airports Com'n, 
2008 WL 4133517
http://minnesota.publicradio.org/display/web/2008/09/09/muslim_cabs_court/
I couldn't find much recently about the effect on Muslims serving the airport 
except this related news, in January, a major airport taxi company here fired 
Somali drivers who protested the refusal of the company to sit down and 
negotiate their working conditions 
http://minnesota.publicradio.org/collections/special/columns/news_cut/archive/2012/01/report_somali_cabbies_learn_pr.shtml

Marie A. Failinger

Professor of Law
Editor, Journal of Law and Religion
Hamline University School of Law
1536 Hewitt Avenue
Saint Paul, MN 55104 U.S.A.
651-523-2124 ( tel:651-523-2124 ) (work phone)
651-523-2236 ( tel:651-523-2236 ) (work fax)
mfailin...@hamline.edu (email)


 Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com 3/7/2012 5:35 AM 
Can anyone point me to a good, thorough account of what happened in 
Minneapolis, including (i) the explanations, if any, the cabbies offered for 
why the lack of the exemption burdened their religious exercise (did it mean 
they were unable to accept work as other forms of common carriers, such as 
pilots, UPS/FedEx delivery employees, bus drivers, etc.?); (ii) how the 
controversy was resolved as a matter of law; and (iii) what became of the 
Muslim drivers after the exemption was revoked.

Thanks in advance.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private. 
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Requirement that cabbies transport alcohol = tiny burden?

2012-03-08 Thread Volokh, Eugene
(1)  Can you say a bit more about the circumstances of the 
hour-long delays, given that it seems that many cab drivers were happy to 
transport anyone who is willing to pay?  Were they at the airport, with 
dispatches cabs, or with cabs hailed on the street?

(2)  Can you also please say a bit more about the cabbies’ 
reactions to the imams’ statements – is it just that they all said “OK, no 
problem then”?  Or did some continue to insist on their own interpretation of 
the religious doctrine?  If a few did persist in their “it’s sinful for us to 
transport alcohol” view, then I would think their position would be 
constitutionally protected – and the fact that there were so few would cut in 
favor of an exemption, because it would reduce the likelihood of the hour-long 
delays that are being discussed, no?

Marci Hamilton writes:

Thanks Eugene for taking us back to the facts.  I received many emails and 
calls regarding the situation and there were people who had to wait an hour for 
a cab because of the objection.  None of them were anti-Muslim.   They did have 
the sense that the cabbies were discriminating against them because they did 
not share their religious affiliation.

   I raised earlier the fact that the imams had intervened saying there was no 
rule about transporting alcohol because that is why the issue died away and did 
not resurface.

Marci
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Discrimination against people with religious motivations for their actions

2012-03-08 Thread Steven Jamar
Yes, Eugene, I think you are missing the essential point that common carriers 
are not the same as other employers and when it comes to choice as to serve or 
not serve, they are more limited in what they can and cannot do.  They are 
bound by more than non-discrimination laws.  Or that is how I always understood 
the law in this field, but I could be mistaken - I've not worked in it for over 
2 decades now.  So the baseline is different.  It is not the same as for 
ordinary businesses.

I get the distinction you are trying so to make. And I agree that it is not the 
same as excluding someone because of a particular affiliation with a sect.  But 
it still is discrimination based on religion whether it is based on the 
customer not conforming to the religious expectations and demands of the 
business or the business excluding because of a status of the customer -- in 
both instances it is because of the religious beliefs and conduct of the 
business, not the customer.

I am troubled by the blame-the-customer attitude evinced in the solicitude for 
the  person engaged in provision of a public service such as common carriers 
and public transportation.

As I have written some time ago now, I think we should indeed recognize the 
religious needs or constraints or beliefs of the employer -- but one should 
also recognize and support the interests of the others.

If a system can be worked out with minimal harm to all involved, that is best.  
But I would favor the weaker party to the stronger -- in this situation the one 
needing the cab is decidedly in the weaker position.

Steve



On Mar 7, 2012, at 3:07 PM, Volokh, Eugene wrote:

 I think the analysis below is mistaken:  Whether or not cabbies’ refusal to 
 carry alcohol should be barred by some general common-carriage requirement, 
 it shouldn’t be treated as religious discrimination.  What’s more, I think 
 the argument that such a refusal is religious discrimination itself calls for 
 discrimination against those with religious motivations for their actions.
  
 1.  To begin with, as others have pointed out, the cabbies’ actions affected 
 Christians, Jews, Muslims, the irreligious, and anyone else who carried 
 alcohol.  Moreover, they didn’t affect Christian, Jews, Muslims, the 
 irreligious, and anyone else who didn’t carry alcohol.
  
 2.  Now I take it that the response is that the really devout Muslims of the 
 same religious views as the cabbies generally wouldn’t be affected (just as, 
 I suppose, Mormons or Methodists wouldn’t be affected), because they 
 generally wouldn’t carry alcohol.  But that analysis strikes me as unsound, 
 and here’s why.
  
 Imagine a case closely modeled on Rasmussen v. Glass (Minn. Ct. App. 1993) 
 (review granted but appeal later dismissed), 
 http://scholar.google.com/scholar_case?case=648897692635049631.  A restaurant 
 owner refuses to deliver food to a doctor who performs abortions, because the 
 owner believes abortions are evil, and doesn’t want to provide any help, even 
 indirect, to such evil.  And say the restaurant owner’s is irreligious, and 
 his opposition to abortion is based on his own personal moral views (e.g., he 
 follows Nat 
 Hentoff,http://groups.csail.mit.edu/mac/users/rauch/nvp/consistent/indivisible.html).
   I take it that we would all agree that the restaurant owner is not 
 discriminating based on religion.  To be sure, devout Catholics, and devout 
 members of other anti-abortion religious groups, wouldn’t perform abortions.  
 But that doesn’t mean the restaurant owner is discriminating based on the 
 would-be customers’ religions – he’s discriminating based on their secular 
 actions.
  
 Now say that another restaurant owner acts precisely the same way, but his 
 opposition to abortion is based on his religious views.  As I understand the 
 argument below, he would be seen as discriminating based on religion, because 
 the performing of abortion is “a badge of a religion different from yours.”  
 And thus he would be presumptively required to deliver to the doctor’s 
 office, if state public accommodations law covers discrimination based on 
 religion in restaurant delivery.  But this would mean that the law itself has 
 become religiously discriminatory:  The secular anti-abortion restaurant 
 owner is free to do something (here, refusing to deliver to an abortion 
 provider), but the religious anti-abortion restaurant owner is barred from 
 doing precisely the same thing.
  
 3.  I think the same applies to the alcohol example.  A secular cab driver 
 who opposes alcohol on secular grounds would presumably not be treated as 
 discriminating based on religion.  But to treat the religious cab driver who 
 opposes alcohol on religious grounds would be treated as discriminating based 
 on religion, and would thus be potentially violating relevant public 
 accommodations bans.  Yet such an approach would itself impermissibly 
 discriminate (in violation of Lukumi Babalu) against the 

Re: you in today?

2012-03-08 Thread Saperstein, David
No prob

Sent from my iPhone

On Mar 8, 2012, at 9:17 AM, Marty Lederman 
lederman.ma...@gmail.commailto:lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:

sorry about that -- wrong address!

On Thu, Mar 8, 2012 at 9:01 AM, Marty Lederman 
lederman.ma...@gmail.commailto:lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:
I had a couple of questions about Section 7 students.  Thanks

___
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Discrimination against people with religious motivations for their actions

2012-03-08 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I agree with the statement in the first paragraph that, if a 
cab driver is treated as a common carrier, then he might have to transport 
people who are carrying alcohol (unless he is entitled to a religious exemption 
under a Sherbert/Yoder-model state constitutional regime, or a state RFRA 
regime).  And this is so regardless of whether he's discriminating based on a 
characteristic such as religion.

But the second paragraph goes on and says that a business owner 
who discriminates against a customer who is doing something that the owner 
thinks is religiously improper is engaging in discrimination based on 
religion.  The logic of that paragraph goes far beyond the common carrier 
situation (and indeed in the common carrier situation is irrelevant whether the 
common carrier is discriminating based on religion).

If the claim is that this discrimination based on the actor's 
religious beliefs is the sort of religious discrimination prohibited by public 
accommodation discrimination laws, that strikes me as mistaken.  As I mentioned 
in my earlier post, a secular restaurant owner who refuses to deliver to an 
abortion provider because of the owner's secular opposition to abortion should 
be precisely on the same footing as a religious restaurant owner who refuses to 
deliver to an abortion provider because of the owner's religious opposition to 
abortion - neither is guilty of actionable religious discrimination.  Likewise, 
a secular cab driver who refuses to transport people carrying alcohol because 
of the driver's secular opposition to alcohol should be precisely on the same 
footing as a religious cab driver who refuses to transport people carrying 
alcohol because of the driver's religious opposition to alcohol.  Again, 
neither is guilty of actionable religious discrimination.  Perhaps both are 
guilty of violating some common carrier obligation; but that's another story.

In either case, the suggestion that there's something illegally 
religiously discriminatory about a business owner's acting based on his own 
religious beliefs and conduct strikes me as mistaken - indeed, unconstitutional 
given Lukumi Babalu.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Steven Jamar
Sent: Wednesday, March 07, 2012 3:40 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Discrimination against people with religious motivations for their 
actions

Yes, Eugene, I think you are missing the essential point that common carriers 
are not the same as other employers and when it comes to choice as to serve or 
not serve, they are more limited in what they can and cannot do.  They are 
bound by more than non-discrimination laws.  Or that is how I always understood 
the law in this field, but I could be mistaken - I've not worked in it for over 
2 decades now.  So the baseline is different.  It is not the same as for 
ordinary businesses.

I get the distinction you are trying so to make. And I agree that it is not the 
same as excluding someone because of a particular affiliation with a sect.  But 
it still is discrimination based on religion whether it is based on the 
customer not conforming to the religious expectations and demands of the 
business or the business excluding because of a status of the customer -- in 
both instances it is because of the religious beliefs and conduct of the 
business, not the customer.

I am troubled by the blame-the-customer attitude evinced in the solicitude for 
the  person engaged in provision of a public service such as common carriers 
and public transportation.

As I have written some time ago now, I think we should indeed recognize the 
religious needs or constraints or beliefs of the employer -- but one should 
also recognize and support the interests of the others.

If a system can be worked out with minimal harm to all involved, that is best.  
But I would favor the weaker party to the stronger -- in this situation the one 
needing the cab is decidedly in the weaker position.

Steve



On Mar 7, 2012, at 3:07 PM, Volokh, Eugene wrote:


I think the analysis below is mistaken:  Whether or not cabbies' refusal to 
carry alcohol should be barred by some general common-carriage requirement, it 
shouldn't be treated as religious discrimination.  What's more, I think the 
argument that such a refusal is religious discrimination itself calls for 
discrimination against those with religious motivations for their actions.

1.  To begin with, as others have pointed out, the cabbies' actions affected 
Christians, Jews, Muslims, the irreligious, and anyone else who carried 
alcohol.  Moreover, they didn't affect Christian, Jews, Muslims, the 
irreligious, and anyone else who didn't carry alcohol.

2.  Now I take it that the response is that the really devout Muslims of the 
same religious views as the cabbies generally wouldn't be affected