Re: Speech and conduct

2007-11-03 Thread Hamilton02
 
I strongly disagree with Eugene here.  It's not the speech per  se, but 
rather the location of the speech that is outrageous.  And this  speech in its 
chosen location in particular is not allegedly  outrageous, but rather 
outrageous on every meter known to civilized  individuals.  Death is when 
families are 
most vulnerable, desperately  need privacy, and operate in deep communion with 
their own  religious worldview and faith.  That's why this group has chosen  
these funerals -- to get the most attention and be the most  destructive.  
 
Picking up on Alan's point, I don't think there is any question that there  
is a compelling interest in keeping these speakers away from families during 
the  funeral. Another point is that a person only has one funeral, so a  
funeral-related restriction is extremely limited in time and  place.   There is 
no 
less restrictive means than  restricting the location of such speech vis-a-vis 
the time and place  of the funeral itself.  
 
Marci 
 
 
In a message dated 11/2/2007 8:00:13 P.M. Eastern Daylight Time,  
[EMAIL PROTECTED] writes:

What  makes the behavior allegedly outrageous
infliction of severe emotional  distress (or for that matter an
actionable invasion of privacy) is  precisely the speech.

Eugene







** See what's new at http://www.aol.com
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Speech and conduct

2007-11-03 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I agree with Marci about one thing:  This was indeed outrageous; the
allegedly was an inartful way to cover the possibility of IIED
applying to several hypotheticals at once (If there were a half dozen
people standing on the street corner near the funeral talking to each
other, the attendees to the funeral might be very slightly put off, but
very slightly.  If there were people engaged in labor picketing against
the cemetery's practices, they might think it's mildly disrespectful,
but not remotely 'outrageous.'  If there were people standing with signs
saying 'Our condolences for your and our nation's loss,' the attendees
would likely be pleased, unless they were a very private sort of people,
in which case they might find this a little tacky or annoying.  What
makes the behavior allegedly outrageous infliction of severe emotional
distress (or for that matter an actionable invasion of privacy) is
precisely the speech), but I'm happy to say that the allegations were
perfectly true here.
 
But as my hypotheticals show, I think, the IIED liability is based
precisely on *what is said* in this place.  It's possible that a jury
might have found IIED even if it wasn't said at the funeral, but was
said in a local newspaper ad bought the day of the funeral -- I agree
the jury would have been less likely to find IIED there, but the IIED
tort is broad and vague enough that no-one can tell for sure.  But it's
impossible that the jury would have found outrageousness if the speech
were at the funeral, but was merely labor picketing, or casual
conversation among a few people gathered on a corner, or the Our
condolences for your and our nation's loss.
 
Nor -- returning to the thread -- is it proper to discuss the
location as a conduct issue.  The choice of which ordinance to target
is just as much a speech factor as the choice of what to say.  It may
be regulable under the Ward standard for content-neutral time, place,
and manner regulations; but this is not such a content-neutral
regulation.  It may be restrictable under strict scrutiny, as Marci
suggests, though I don't think so.  (I think a content-neutral limit on
all picketing in front of a funeral would likely pass muster, by analogy
to Frisby v. Schultz, if it's limited to speech in front of the funeral;
but, as I said, the IIED tort is not such a content-neutral law.)  But
any restriction on this should be judged as the speech restriction that
it is, not as a conduct restriction.
 
Eugene




From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Saturday, November 03, 2007 6:38 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Speech and conduct



I strongly disagree with Eugene here.  It's not the speech per
se, but rather the location of the speech that is outrageous.  And this
speech in its chosen location in particular is not allegedly
outrageous, but rather outrageous on every meter known to civilized
individuals.  Death is when families are most vulnerable, desperately
need privacy, and operate in deep communion with their own religious
worldview and faith.  That's why this group has chosen these funerals --
to get the most attention and be the most destructive.  
 
Picking up on Alan's point, I don't think there is any question
that there is a compelling interest in keeping these speakers away from
families during the funeral. Another point is that a person only has one
funeral, so a funeral-related restriction is extremely limited in time
and place.   There is no less restrictive means than restricting the
location of such speech vis-a-vis the time and place of the funeral
itself.  
 
Marci 
 
 
In a message dated 11/2/2007 8:00:13 P.M. Eastern Daylight Time,
[EMAIL PROTECTED] writes:

What makes the behavior allegedly outrageous
infliction of severe emotional distress (or for that
matter an
actionable invasion of privacy) is precisely the speech.

Eugene


 






See what's new at AOL.com
http://www.aol.com?NCID=AOLCMP0030001170  and Make AOL Your
Homepage http://www.aol.com/mksplash.adp?NCID=AOLCMP0030001169 .

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Speech and conduct

2007-11-03 Thread Steven Jamar
IIED can be treated just like defamation and not protected by free
speech, though Eugene would not want it treated like that.

Or this can be (properly in my view) viewed as mixed conduct and
speech and regulated by modest extension of time place and manner and
secondary effects doctrines -- easy enough to fashion a narrow rule
for this sort of situation that avoids the serious concerns of
censorship.

Or it can be viewed as purely content-based (improperly in my view)
and upheld under some version of speech strict scrutiny such as
compelling interest, narrowly tailored, ample alternative avenues
availalble.

I am unpersuaded by Eugene's underinclusive argument -- as I was in R.A.V.

Just as categories of unprotected speech are not so pure, neither is
the idea of content nuetrality as simple or absolute or pure as Eugene
wants it to be.

Steve


On 11/3/07, Volokh, Eugene [EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:


 I agree with Marci about one thing:  This was indeed outrageous; the
 allegedly was an inartful way to cover the possibility of IIED applying to
 several hypotheticals at once (If there were a half dozen people standing
 on the street corner near the funeral talking to each other, the attendees
 to the funeral might be very slightly put off, but very slightly.  If there
 were people engaged in labor picketing against the cemetery's practices,
 they might think it's mildly disrespectful, but not remotely 'outrageous.'
 If there were people standing with signs saying 'Our condolences for your
 and our nation's loss,' the attendees would likely be pleased, unless they
 were a very private sort of people, in which case they might find this a
 little tacky or annoying.  What makes the behavior allegedly outrageous
 infliction of severe emotional distress (or for that matter an actionable
 invasion of privacy) is precisely the speech), but I'm happy to say that
 the allegations were perfectly true here.

 But as my hypotheticals show, I think, the IIED liability is based
 precisely on *what is said* in this place.  It's possible that a jury might
 have found IIED even if it wasn't said at the funeral, but was said in a
 local newspaper ad bought the day of the funeral -- I agree the jury would
 have been less likely to find IIED there, but the IIED tort is broad and
 vague enough that no-one can tell for sure.  But it's impossible that the
 jury would have found outrageousness if the speech were at the funeral,
 but was merely labor picketing, or casual conversation among a few people
 gathered on a corner, or the Our condolences for your and our nation's
 loss.

 Nor -- returning to the thread -- is it proper to discuss the location
 as a conduct issue.  The choice of which ordinance to target is just as
 much a speech factor as the choice of what to say.  It may be regulable
 under the Ward standard for content-neutral time, place, and manner
 regulations; but this is not such a content-neutral regulation.  It may be
 restrictable under strict scrutiny, as Marci suggests, though I don't think
 so.  (I think a content-neutral limit on all picketing in front of a funeral
 would likely pass muster, by analogy to Frisby v. Schultz, if it's limited
 to speech in front of the funeral; but, as I said, the IIED tort is not such
 a content-neutral law.)  But any restriction on this should be judged as the
 speech restriction that it is, not as a conduct restriction.

 Eugene


  
  From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of
 [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 Sent: Saturday, November 03, 2007 6:38 AM
 To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Subject: Re: Speech and conduct




 I strongly disagree with Eugene here.  It's not the speech per se, but
 rather the location of the speech that is outrageous.  And this speech in
 its chosen location in particular is not allegedly outrageous, but rather
 outrageous on every meter known to civilized individuals.  Death is when
 families are most vulnerable, desperately need privacy, and operate in
 deep communion with their own religious worldview and faith.  That's why
 this group has chosen these funerals -- to get the most attention and be the
 most destructive.

 Picking up on Alan's point, I don't think there is any question that there
 is a compelling interest in keeping these speakers away from families during
 the funeral. Another point is that a person only has one funeral, so a
 funeral-related restriction is extremely limited in time and place.   There
 is no less restrictive means than restricting the location of such speech
 vis-a-vis the time and place of the funeral itself.

 Marci


 In a message dated 11/2/2007 8:00:13 P.M. Eastern Daylight Time,
 [EMAIL PROTECTED] writes:
 What makes the behavior allegedly outrageous
 infliction of severe emotional distress (or for that matter an
 actionable invasion of privacy) is precisely the speech.

 Eugene







  
  See what's new at AOL.com

Re: Speech and conduct

2007-11-03 Thread Steven Jamar
isn't this a case of private plaintiffs?  Do you need to show actual
malice in private libel?  I don't think so, and it is still
constitutional.

Steve


On 11/3/07, Bezanson, Randall P [EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:
 Unless I'm mistaken, I think the constitutional narrow tailoring and
 compelling interest ideas are accomplished in public libel cases by the
 requirements of actual malice and proven falsity.  In IIED I suppose
 those requirements could by analogy be satisfied by a form of specific
 intent to inflict serious emotional harm on a particular person(s) and
 outrageousness of the conduct/speech, though we don't know because the
 Supreme Court has not, to my knowledge, explicitly addressed the
 question in what by libel standards would likely be a private libel case
 governed by Gertz, not NYT v. Sullivan.

 Randy Bezanson

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Steven Jamar
 Sent: Saturday, November 03, 2007 1:36 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Speech and conduct

 IIED can be treated just like defamation and not protected by free
 speech, though Eugene would not want it treated like that.

 Or this can be (properly in my view) viewed as mixed conduct and
 speech and regulated by modest extension of time place and manner and
 secondary effects doctrines -- easy enough to fashion a narrow rule
 for this sort of situation that avoids the serious concerns of
 censorship.

 Or it can be viewed as purely content-based (improperly in my view)
 and upheld under some version of speech strict scrutiny such as
 compelling interest, narrowly tailored, ample alternative avenues
 availalble.

 I am unpersuaded by Eugene's underinclusive argument -- as I was in
 R.A.V.

 Just as categories of unprotected speech are not so pure, neither is
 the idea of content nuetrality as simple or absolute or pure as Eugene
 wants it to be.

 Steve


 On 11/3/07, Volokh, Eugene [EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:
 
 
  I agree with Marci about one thing:  This was indeed outrageous;
 the
  allegedly was an inartful way to cover the possibility of IIED
 applying to
  several hypotheticals at once (If there were a half dozen people
 standing
  on the street corner near the funeral talking to each other, the
 attendees
  to the funeral might be very slightly put off, but very slightly.  If
 there
  were people engaged in labor picketing against the cemetery's
 practices,
  they might think it's mildly disrespectful, but not remotely
 'outrageous.'
  If there were people standing with signs saying 'Our condolences for
 your
  and our nation's loss,' the attendees would likely be pleased, unless
 they
  were a very private sort of people, in which case they might find this
 a
  little tacky or annoying.  What makes the behavior allegedly
 outrageous
  infliction of severe emotional distress (or for that matter an
 actionable
  invasion of privacy) is precisely the speech), but I'm happy to say
 that
  the allegations were perfectly true here.
 
  But as my hypotheticals show, I think, the IIED liability is based
  precisely on *what is said* in this place.  It's possible that a jury
 might
  have found IIED even if it wasn't said at the funeral, but was said in
 a
  local newspaper ad bought the day of the funeral -- I agree the jury
 would
  have been less likely to find IIED there, but the IIED tort is broad
 and
  vague enough that no-one can tell for sure.  But it's impossible that
 the
  jury would have found outrageousness if the speech were at the
 funeral,
  but was merely labor picketing, or casual conversation among a few
 people
  gathered on a corner, or the Our condolences for your and our
 nation's
  loss.
 
  Nor -- returning to the thread -- is it proper to discuss the
 location
  as a conduct issue.  The choice of which ordinance to target is just
 as
  much a speech factor as the choice of what to say.  It may be
 regulable
  under the Ward standard for content-neutral time, place, and manner
  regulations; but this is not such a content-neutral regulation.  It
 may be
  restrictable under strict scrutiny, as Marci suggests, though I don't
 think
  so.  (I think a content-neutral limit on all picketing in front of a
 funeral
  would likely pass muster, by analogy to Frisby v. Schultz, if it's
 limited
  to speech in front of the funeral; but, as I said, the IIED tort is
 not such
  a content-neutral law.)  But any restriction on this should be judged
 as the
  speech restriction that it is, not as a conduct restriction.
 
  Eugene
 
 
   
   From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
  [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of
  [EMAIL PROTECTED]
  Sent: Saturday, November 03, 2007 6:38 AM
  To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
  Subject: Re: Speech and conduct
 
 
 
 
  I strongly disagree with Eugene here.  It's not the speech per se, but
  rather the location of the speech that is outrageous.  And this speech
 in
  its

RE: Speech and conduct

2007-11-03 Thread Bezanson, Randall P
Were it libel, the case would (as I suggested in my comment) likely be a
private libel governed by Gertz (negligence and not actual malice.

Randy Bezanson
Univ. of Iowa

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Steven Jamar
Sent: Saturday, November 03, 2007 4:43 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Speech and conduct

isn't this a case of private plaintiffs?  Do you need to show actual
malice in private libel?  I don't think so, and it is still
constitutional.

Steve


On 11/3/07, Bezanson, Randall P [EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:
 Unless I'm mistaken, I think the constitutional narrow tailoring and
 compelling interest ideas are accomplished in public libel cases by
the
 requirements of actual malice and proven falsity.  In IIED I suppose
 those requirements could by analogy be satisfied by a form of specific
 intent to inflict serious emotional harm on a particular person(s) and
 outrageousness of the conduct/speech, though we don't know because the
 Supreme Court has not, to my knowledge, explicitly addressed the
 question in what by libel standards would likely be a private libel
case
 governed by Gertz, not NYT v. Sullivan.

 Randy Bezanson

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Steven Jamar
 Sent: Saturday, November 03, 2007 1:36 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Speech and conduct

 IIED can be treated just like defamation and not protected by free
 speech, though Eugene would not want it treated like that.

 Or this can be (properly in my view) viewed as mixed conduct and
 speech and regulated by modest extension of time place and manner and
 secondary effects doctrines -- easy enough to fashion a narrow rule
 for this sort of situation that avoids the serious concerns of
 censorship.

 Or it can be viewed as purely content-based (improperly in my view)
 and upheld under some version of speech strict scrutiny such as
 compelling interest, narrowly tailored, ample alternative avenues
 availalble.

 I am unpersuaded by Eugene's underinclusive argument -- as I was in
 R.A.V.

 Just as categories of unprotected speech are not so pure, neither is
 the idea of content nuetrality as simple or absolute or pure as Eugene
 wants it to be.

 Steve


 On 11/3/07, Volokh, Eugene [EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:
 
 
  I agree with Marci about one thing:  This was indeed outrageous;
 the
  allegedly was an inartful way to cover the possibility of IIED
 applying to
  several hypotheticals at once (If there were a half dozen people
 standing
  on the street corner near the funeral talking to each other, the
 attendees
  to the funeral might be very slightly put off, but very slightly.
If
 there
  were people engaged in labor picketing against the cemetery's
 practices,
  they might think it's mildly disrespectful, but not remotely
 'outrageous.'
  If there were people standing with signs saying 'Our condolences for
 your
  and our nation's loss,' the attendees would likely be pleased,
unless
 they
  were a very private sort of people, in which case they might find
this
 a
  little tacky or annoying.  What makes the behavior allegedly
 outrageous
  infliction of severe emotional distress (or for that matter an
 actionable
  invasion of privacy) is precisely the speech), but I'm happy to say
 that
  the allegations were perfectly true here.
 
  But as my hypotheticals show, I think, the IIED liability is
based
  precisely on *what is said* in this place.  It's possible that a
jury
 might
  have found IIED even if it wasn't said at the funeral, but was said
in
 a
  local newspaper ad bought the day of the funeral -- I agree the jury
 would
  have been less likely to find IIED there, but the IIED tort is broad
 and
  vague enough that no-one can tell for sure.  But it's impossible
that
 the
  jury would have found outrageousness if the speech were at the
 funeral,
  but was merely labor picketing, or casual conversation among a few
 people
  gathered on a corner, or the Our condolences for your and our
 nation's
  loss.
 
  Nor -- returning to the thread -- is it proper to discuss the
 location
  as a conduct issue.  The choice of which ordinance to target is
just
 as
  much a speech factor as the choice of what to say.  It may be
 regulable
  under the Ward standard for content-neutral time, place, and manner
  regulations; but this is not such a content-neutral regulation.  It
 may be
  restrictable under strict scrutiny, as Marci suggests, though I
don't
 think
  so.  (I think a content-neutral limit on all picketing in front of a
 funeral
  would likely pass muster, by analogy to Frisby v. Schultz, if it's
 limited
  to speech in front of the funeral; but, as I said, the IIED tort is
 not such
  a content-neutral law.)  But any restriction on this should be
judged
 as the
  speech restriction that it is, not as a conduct restriction.
 
  Eugene

Re: Speech and conduct

2007-11-02 Thread Steven Jamar
No it is not being regulated just because of the content of the
speech.  That speech in other places, other times, other means is not
banned or sanctioned.  People disrupting a funeral even with entirely
different words would still be disrupting a funeral.  The disruption
can be prohibited -- the conduct can be regulated.

This was disruptive.

Of course it was more than disruptive and the tort required the
physical and the aural and the emotional aspects.  But it is still a
mischaracterization to call it purely or merely speech content
regulation.  Or to treat it as if that is all that is going on.

Our free speech jurisprudence is neither as consistent nor as rigid as
Eugene would like -- and that seems to be the bottom line here -- I
prefer more play in the joints here for regulating this sort of thing
(and would like to find some way to regulate hate speech more than we
do -- though that is even more problematic for reasons often enough
discussed -- though I think we could fashion something there involving
targeting individuals or groups in ways calculated to cause various
sorts of harms, but that is still much tougher than this case).

I don't see an appellate court pushing the boundaries of free speech
in the direction Eugene wants in this case.  Indeed, I hope this one
gets appealed because I think we could see some further recognition
that society can demand some level of civility even where speech is
concerned.

I would expect this to be treated ultimately as  closer to
time-place-manner standard (innumerable alternative means available)
than a straight-up content based regulation.Indeed, if one wants
to establish the principle of no content-based regulation ever, this
is about the worst case one can imagine in which to do it (short of
genuine national security disclosures).

Steve


On 11/2/07, Volokh, Eugene [EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:
 Setting aside all the other factors for now, I hope we could
 agree that viewing this sort of picketing as conduct is the wrong way
 for courts to go.  The picketing is offensive precisely because of the
 message it communicates.  The noncommunicative components (the presence
 of people, the fact that they occupy space on the sidewalk, the fact
 that they carry signs on sticks) are irrelevant here (unless the
 picketing somehow blocked the driveway into the cemetery or some such,
 which I don't believe it did).

 Treating this speech as conduct works as poorly, I think, as
 Justice Blackmun's view in Cohen v. California that Cohen's absurd and
 immature antic ... was mainly conduct and little speech.  Whatever the
 bottom line, it seems to me that courts should confront the true nature
 of what's going on here, and what's going on here is speech that's
 offensive precisely because it's speech.

 Eugene


 Alan Brownstein writes:

 I think Eugene is right. This is, at its core, a content-based
 restriction on speech. The context, in my judgment, is primarily
 relevant to three questions: whether the penalty on speech can be
 justified because of the consequences of the speech, whether the context
 is such that we want to view this expression as something other than
 speech (some kind of conduct) or  whether we view this as some kind of
 speech that is not protected by the first amendment. It is never been
 clear to me which of these reasons explains why certain kinds of
 expressive activities can be punished as harassment - but clearly it is
 permissible to punish harassment in certain circumstances. The tort of
 IIED raises a similar mystery. I'm not suggesting that there isn't an
 answer that justifies at least some applications of the cause of action.
 But I don't think courts have told us what that answer is yet.

 I would prefer that the situation in this case (and others like
 it) be resolved by statutory limits on disruptive speech on public
 property adjacent to places like cemeteries, funeral homes, hospitals
 etc..  The benefit of a statute is that it can designate the contexts
 which we consider totally inappropriate for extremely hurtful speech at
 specific times and places. IIED leaves that question up to the
 discretion of juries.

 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.



-- 
Prof. Steven Jamar
Howard University School of Law
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that 

Re: Speech and conduct

2007-11-02 Thread Jean Dudley
It occurs to me that all of this could have been avoided if the  
father of the deceased soldier, in a fit of grief-driven rage, had  
taken Mr. Phelp's (or possibly Mr. Phelp's daughter's) life and then  
claimed temporary insanity.

But then I might have been tempted to show up at the funeral with a  
sign that says God hates homobigots.Would the Westboro Baptist  
Church have the right to sue me for damages?  Frankly, I suspect that  
this decision is going to be overturned, or at the very least, the  
amount will be lowered dramatically.  All I can say it's a damn shame  
there's no law against malicious bad manners in this country.

Jean Dudley
You can't get blood from a turnip.

P. S.  Would someone kindly clue me in on what IIED stands for, please?
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Speech and conduct

2007-11-02 Thread Conkle, Daniel O.
I'm largely (90%?) in agreement with Eugene, but I'd add a slight caveat.  I 
think that some (small?) part of the offensiveness or invasion of privacy 
here is, indeed, the mere presence of strangers in close proximity to the 
funeral - an event that, as a matter of social custom, decency, and respect for 
the dead and their families, ordinarily is confined to those who are in some 
broad sense invited guests who wish to participate in or observe the ceremony.

Compare Frisby on targeted picketing.  If my house is the target of picketing, 
I think that some (small?) part of the offensiveness or invasion-of-privacy 
concern is that a stranger is persistently standing right in front of my house 
- even though he is on public property and is not legally trespassing.  It 
bothers me simply that he is *there*; that he's not moving on.  (I'd be 
concerned even if the person carried a blank picket sign or carried no sign at 
all and said nothing at all.)

To this limited extent, in both Frisby and in the funeral context, the harm is 
grounded in part on an intangible privacy concern about the presence of 
strangers, which might be characterized as a concern about conduct and which is 
independent of any message.

Dan Conkle
***
Daniel O. Conkle
Robert H. McKinney Professor of Law
Indiana University School of Law
Bloomington, Indiana  47405
(812) 855-4331
fax (812) 855-0555
e-mail [EMAIL PROTECTED]
***



-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Friday, November 02, 2007 2:43 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Speech and conduct

Setting aside all the other factors for now, I hope we could
agree that viewing this sort of picketing as conduct is the wrong way
for courts to go.  The picketing is offensive precisely because of the
message it communicates.  The noncommunicative components (the presence
of people, the fact that they occupy space on the sidewalk, the fact
that they carry signs on sticks) are irrelevant here (unless the
picketing somehow blocked the driveway into the cemetery or some such,
which I don't believe it did).

Treating this speech as conduct works as poorly, I think, as
Justice Blackmun's view in Cohen v. California that Cohen's absurd and
immature antic ... was mainly conduct and little speech.  Whatever the
bottom line, it seems to me that courts should confront the true nature
of what's going on here, and what's going on here is speech that's
offensive precisely because it's speech.

Eugene


Alan Brownstein writes:

I think Eugene is right. This is, at its core, a content-based
restriction on speech. The context, in my judgment, is primarily
relevant to three questions: whether the penalty on speech can be
justified because of the consequences of the speech, whether the context
is such that we want to view this expression as something other than
speech (some kind of conduct) or  whether we view this as some kind of
speech that is not protected by the first amendment. It is never been
clear to me which of these reasons explains why certain kinds of
expressive activities can be punished as harassment - but clearly it is
permissible to punish harassment in certain circumstances. The tort of
IIED raises a similar mystery. I'm not suggesting that there isn't an
answer that justifies at least some applications of the cause of action.
But I don't think courts have told us what that answer is yet.

I would prefer that the situation in this case (and others like
it) be resolved by statutory limits on disruptive speech on public
property adjacent to places like cemeteries, funeral homes, hospitals
etc..  The benefit of a statute is that it can designate the contexts
which we consider totally inappropriate for extremely hurtful speech at
specific times and places. IIED leaves that question up to the
discretion of juries.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


Re: Speech and conduct

2007-11-02 Thread Susan Freiman
I assumed it's Intentional Infliction of Emotional Distress.

I would assume the damages will be dramatically reduced, but the point's 
been made.  As with OJ, the defendants haven't anything like the assets 
needed to satisfy even the actual damages part of the award.

Susan

Jean Dudley wrote:
 It occurs to me that all of this could have been avoided if the  
 father of the deceased soldier, in a fit of grief-driven rage, had  
 taken Mr. Phelp's (or possibly Mr. Phelp's daughter's) life and then  
 claimed temporary insanity.

 But then I might have been tempted to show up at the funeral with a  
 sign that says God hates homobigots.Would the Westboro Baptist  
 Church have the right to sue me for damages?  Frankly, I suspect that  
 this decision is going to be overturned, or at the very least, the  
 amount will be lowered dramatically.  All I can say it's a damn shame  
 there's no law against malicious bad manners in this country.

 Jean Dudley
 You can't get blood from a turnip.

 P. S.  Would someone kindly clue me in on what IIED stands for, please?
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
   

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Speech and conduct

2007-11-02 Thread Newsom Michael
No, we don't all agree on a rigid speech-conduct distinction.

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Friday, November 02, 2007 2:43 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Speech and conduct


Setting aside all the other factors for now, I hope we could
agree that viewing this sort of picketing as conduct is the wrong way
for courts to go.  The picketing is offensive precisely because of the
message it communicates.  The noncommunicative components (the presence
of people, the fact that they occupy space on the sidewalk, the fact
that they carry signs on sticks) are irrelevant here (unless the
picketing somehow blocked the driveway into the cemetery or some such,
which I don't believe it did).  

Treating this speech as conduct works as poorly, I think, as
Justice Blackmun's view in Cohen v. California that Cohen's absurd and
immature antic ... was mainly conduct and little speech.  Whatever the
bottom line, it seems to me that courts should confront the true nature
of what's going on here, and what's going on here is speech that's
offensive precisely because it's speech.

Eugene

 
Alan Brownstein writes:

I think Eugene is right. This is, at its core, a content-based
restriction on speech. The context, in my judgment, is primarily
relevant to three questions: whether the penalty on speech can be
justified because of the consequences of the speech, whether the context
is such that we want to view this expression as something other than
speech (some kind of conduct) or  whether we view this as some kind of
speech that is not protected by the first amendment. It is never been
clear to me which of these reasons explains why certain kinds of
expressive activities can be punished as harassment - but clearly it is
permissible to punish harassment in certain circumstances. The tort of
IIED raises a similar mystery. I'm not suggesting that there isn't an
answer that justifies at least some applications of the cause of action.
But I don't think courts have told us what that answer is yet.

I would prefer that the situation in this case (and others like
it) be resolved by statutory limits on disruptive speech on public
property adjacent to places like cemeteries, funeral homes, hospitals
etc..  The benefit of a statute is that it can designate the contexts
which we consider totally inappropriate for extremely hurtful speech at
specific times and places. IIED leaves that question up to the
discretion of juries.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Speech and conduct

2007-11-02 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I appreciate Dan's point; but I think that if the mere presence
of strangers is a factor here, it's a small factor indeed.  If there
were a half dozen people standing on the street corner near the funeral
talking to each other, the attendees to the funeral might be very
slightly put off, but very slightly.  If there were people engaged in
labor picketing against the cemetery's practices, they might think it's
mildly disrespectful, but not remotely outrageous.  If there were
people standing with signs saying Our condolences for your and our
nation's loss, the attendees would likely be pleased, unless they were
a very private sort of people, in which case they might find this a
little tacky or annoying.  What makes the behavior allegedly outrageous
infliction of severe emotional distress (or for that matter an
actionable invasion of privacy) is precisely the speech.

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Conkle, Daniel O.
 Sent: Friday, November 02, 2007 6:47 AM
 To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
 Subject: RE: Speech and conduct
 
 I'm largely (90%?) in agreement with Eugene, but I'd add a 
 slight caveat.  I think that some (small?) part of the 
 offensiveness or invasion of privacy here is, indeed, the 
 mere presence of strangers in close proximity to the 
 funeral - an event that, as a matter of social custom, 
 decency, and respect for the dead and their families, 
 ordinarily is confined to those who are in some broad sense 
 invited guests who wish to participate in or observe the ceremony.
 
 Compare Frisby on targeted picketing.  If my house is the 
 target of picketing, I think that some (small?) part of the 
 offensiveness or invasion-of-privacy concern is that a 
 stranger is persistently standing right in front of my house 
 - even though he is on public property and is not legally 
 trespassing.  It bothers me simply that he is *there*; that 
 he's not moving on.  (I'd be concerned even if the person 
 carried a blank picket sign or carried no sign at all and 
 said nothing at all.)
 
 To this limited extent, in both Frisby and in the funeral 
 context, the harm is grounded in part on an intangible 
 privacy concern about the presence of strangers, which 
 might be characterized as a concern about conduct and which 
 is independent of any message.
 
 Dan Conkle
 ***
 Daniel O. Conkle
 Robert H. McKinney Professor of Law
 Indiana University School of Law
 Bloomington, Indiana  47405
 (812) 855-4331
 fax (812) 855-0555
 e-mail [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 ***
 
 
 
 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Volokh, Eugene
 Sent: Friday, November 02, 2007 2:43 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Speech and conduct
 
 Setting aside all the other factors for now, I hope 
 we could agree that viewing this sort of picketing as 
 conduct is the wrong way for courts to go.  The picketing 
 is offensive precisely because of the message it 
 communicates.  The noncommunicative components (the presence 
 of people, the fact that they occupy space on the sidewalk, 
 the fact that they carry signs on sticks) are irrelevant here 
 (unless the picketing somehow blocked the driveway into the 
 cemetery or some such, which I don't believe it did).
 
 Treating this speech as conduct works as poorly, I 
 think, as Justice Blackmun's view in Cohen v. California that 
 Cohen's absurd and immature antic ... was mainly conduct and 
 little speech.  Whatever the bottom line, it seems to me 
 that courts should confront the true nature of what's going 
 on here, and what's going on here is speech that's offensive 
 precisely because it's speech.
 
 Eugene
 
 
 Alan Brownstein writes:
 
 I think Eugene is right. This is, at its core, a 
 content-based restriction on speech. The context, in my 
 judgment, is primarily relevant to three questions: whether 
 the penalty on speech can be justified because of the 
 consequences of the speech, whether the context is such that 
 we want to view this expression as something other than 
 speech (some kind of conduct) or  whether we view this as 
 some kind of speech that is not protected by the first 
 amendment. It is never been clear to me which of these 
 reasons explains why certain kinds of expressive activities 
 can be punished as harassment - but clearly it is permissible 
 to punish harassment in certain circumstances. The tort of 
 IIED raises a similar mystery. I'm not suggesting that there 
 isn't an answer that justifies at least some applications of 
 the cause of action.
 But I don't think courts have told us what that answer is yet.
 
 I would prefer that the situation in this case (and 
 others like
 it) be resolved by statutory limits on disruptive speech on 
 public property adjacent

RE: Speech and conduct

2007-11-02 Thread Volokh, Eugene
A content-based ban on speech isn't a conduct ban just because
speech in other places, other times, other means is not banned or
sanctioned.  It's just a content-based restriction rather than a
categorical content-based prohibition.  And that it leaves open ample
alternative channels is *not* enough to save it if it's content-based.
See, e.g., Boos v. Barry; Carey v. Brown; and many more.

Moreover, the speakers here are disrupting a funeral precisely
because of what they say, as well as where they say it.  IIED liability
would surely not have been imposed here if the speakers carried signs
saying This cemetery is unfair to labor, or Our condolences to you
and to our nation.  So it's a classic example of a content-based
restriction, even if one limited by place; that's no more a permissible
time, place, and manner restriction than is a ban on antiwar
demonstrations in front of government buildings, or antigovernment
parades (while antigovernment billboards are allowed), or profanity on
jackets (if spoken profanity were permitted).

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Steven Jamar
 Sent: Friday, November 02, 2007 4:30 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Speech and conduct
 
 No it is not being regulated just because of the content of 
 the speech.  That speech in other places, other times, other 
 means is not banned or sanctioned.  People disrupting a 
 funeral even with entirely different words would still be 
 disrupting a funeral.  The disruption can be prohibited -- 
 the conduct can be regulated.
 
 This was disruptive.
 
 Of course it was more than disruptive and the tort required 
 the physical and the aural and the emotional aspects.  But it 
 is still a mischaracterization to call it purely or merely 
 speech content regulation.  Or to treat it as if that is all 
 that is going on.
 
 Our free speech jurisprudence is neither as consistent nor as 
 rigid as Eugene would like -- and that seems to be the bottom 
 line here -- I prefer more play in the joints here for 
 regulating this sort of thing (and would like to find some 
 way to regulate hate speech more than we do -- though that is 
 even more problematic for reasons often enough discussed -- 
 though I think we could fashion something there involving 
 targeting individuals or groups in ways calculated to cause 
 various sorts of harms, but that is still much tougher than 
 this case).
 
 I don't see an appellate court pushing the boundaries of free 
 speech in the direction Eugene wants in this case.  Indeed, I 
 hope this one gets appealed because I think we could see some 
 further recognition that society can demand some level of 
 civility even where speech is concerned.
 
 I would expect this to be treated ultimately as  closer to 
 time-place-manner standard (innumerable alternative means available)
 than a straight-up content based regulation.Indeed, if one wants
 to establish the principle of no content-based regulation 
 ever, this is about the worst case one can imagine in which 
 to do it (short of genuine national security disclosures).
 
 Steve
 
 
 On 11/2/07, Volokh, Eugene [EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:
  Setting aside all the other factors for now, I hope 
 we could 
  agree that viewing this sort of picketing as conduct is the wrong 
  way for courts to go.  The picketing is offensive precisely 
 because of 
  the message it communicates.  The noncommunicative components (the 
  presence of people, the fact that they occupy space on the 
 sidewalk, 
  the fact that they carry signs on sticks) are irrelevant 
 here (unless 
  the picketing somehow blocked the driveway into the 
 cemetery or some 
  such, which I don't believe it did).
 
  Treating this speech as conduct works as poorly, I 
 think, as 
  Justice Blackmun's view in Cohen v. California that Cohen's absurd 
  and immature antic ... was mainly conduct and little speech.  
  Whatever the bottom line, it seems to me that courts should 
 confront 
  the true nature of what's going on here, and what's going 
 on here is 
  speech that's offensive precisely because it's speech.
 
  Eugene
 
 
  Alan Brownstein writes:
 
  I think Eugene is right. This is, at its core, a 
 content-based 
  restriction on speech. The context, in my judgment, is primarily 
  relevant to three questions: whether the penalty on speech can be 
  justified because of the consequences of the speech, whether the 
  context is such that we want to view this expression as something 
  other than speech (some kind of conduct) or  whether we 
 view this as 
  some kind of speech that is not protected by the first 
 amendment. It 
  is never been clear to me which of these reasons explains 
 why certain 
  kinds of expressive activities can be punished as harassment - but 
  clearly it is permissible to punish harassment in certain 
  circumstances