Sorry,
I should have included section 1 _and_ 2 from Einstein's paper. The second
section is added below.
Harry

On Wed, Mar 12, 2014 at 12:39 PM, H Veeder <hveeder...@gmail.com> wrote:

> Of the six videos, this one is the most important one...
>
> [ The Neo-classical Theory of Relativity ] Einstein's incorrect method to
> synchronize clocks - case (A).
> http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=H2qYCvw1UiE&list=UUek3dPxFThe8FLl-ONbOeVw
>
> ...because it uses the same thought experiment described by Einstein his
> 1905 paper On the Electrodynamics of Moving Bodies.**
> The video shows that Einstein was wrong to conclude from this thought
> experiment that simultaneous events in a stationary frame cannot be
> synchronized
> with events in a moving frame.
>
> The criticisms in other videos could/will be ignored on the grounds that
> they don't include relativistic corrections. (Whether or not the
> corrections are sufficient to address all the criticisms doesn't actually
> matter as long as one can say there aren't any.)
>
> Harry
>
> **1. Definition of Simultaneity
>
> Let us take a system of co-ordinates in which the equations of Newtonian
> mechanics hold good.2 In order to render our presentation more precise and
> to distinguish this system of co-ordinates verbally from others which will
> be introduced hereafter, we call it the "stationary system."
>
> If a material point is at rest relatively to this system of co-ordinates,
> its position can be defined relatively thereto by the employment of rigid
> standards of measurement and the methods of Euclidean geometry, and can be
> expressed in Cartesian co-ordinates.
>
> If we wish to describe the motion of a material point, we give the values
> of its co-ordinates as functions of the time. Now we must bear carefully in
> mind that a mathematical description of this kind has no physical meaning
> unless we are quite clear as to what we understand by "time." We have to
> take into account that all our judgments in which time plays a part are
> always judgments of simultaneous events. If, for instance, I say, "That
> train arrives here at 7 o'clock," I mean something like this: "The pointing
> of the small hand of my watch to 7 and the arrival of the train are
> simultaneous events."3
>
> It might appear possible to overcome all the difficulties attending the
> definition of "time" by substituting "the position of the small hand of my
> watch" for "time." And in fact such a definition is satisfactory when we
> are concerned with defining a time exclusively for the place where the
> watch is located; but it is no longer satisfactory when we have to connect
> in time series of events occurring at different places, or--what comes to
> the same thing--to evaluate the times of events occurring at places remote
> from the watch.
>
> We might, of course, content ourselves with time values determined by an
> observer stationed together with the watch at the origin of the
> co-ordinates, and co-ordinating the corresponding positions of the hands
> with light signals, given out by every event to be timed, and reaching him
> through empty space. But this co-ordination has the disadvantage that it is
> not independent of the standpoint of the observer with the watch or clock,
> as we know from experience. We arrive at a much more practical
> determination along the following line of thought.
>
> If at the point A of space there is a clock, an observer at A can
> determine the time values of events in the immediate proximity of A by
> finding the positions of the hands which are simultaneous with these
> events. If there is at the point B of space another clock in all respects
> resembling the one at A, it is possible for an observer at B to determine
> the time values of events in the immediate neighbourhood of B. But it is
> not possible without further assumption to compare, in respect of time, an
> event at A with an event at B. We have so far defined only an "A time" and
> a "B time." We have not defined a common "time" for A and B, for the latter
> cannot be defined at all unless we establish by definitionthat the "time"
> required by light to travel from A to B equals the "time" it requires to
> travel from B to A. Let a ray of light start at the "A time" from A towards
> B, let it at the "B time"  be reflected at B in the direction of A, and
> arrive again at A at the "A time" .
>
> In accordance with definition the two clocks synchronize if
>
> We assume that this definition of synchronism is free from contradictions,
> and possible for any number of points; and that the following relations are
> universally valid:--
>
> If the clock at B synchronizes with the clock at A, the clock at A
> synchronizes with the clock at B.
> If the clock at A synchronizes with the clock at B and also with the clock
> at C, the clocks at B and C also synchronize with each other.
>
> Thus with the help of certain imaginary physical experiments we have
> settled what is to be understood by synchronous stationary clocks located
> at different places, and have evidently obtained a definition of
> "simultaneous," or "synchronous," and of "time." The "time" of an event is
> that which is given simultaneously with the event by a stationary clock
> located at the place of the event, this clock being synchronous, and indeed
> synchronous for all time determinations, with a specified stationary clock.
>
> In agreement with experience we further assume the quantity
>
> to be a universal constant--the velocity of light in empty space.
>
> It is essential to have time defined by means of stationary clocks in the
> stationary system, and the time now defined being appropriate to the
> stationary system we call it "the time of the stationary system."
>
> from
> https://www.fourmilab.ch/etexts/einstein/specrel/www/
>
>
>

2. On the Relativity of Lengths and Times

The following reflexions are based on the principle of relativity and on
the principle of the constancy of the velocity of light. These two
principles we define as follows:--

The laws by which the states of physical systems undergo change are not
affected, whether these changes of state be referred to the one or the
other of two systems of co-ordinates in uniform translatory motion.
Any ray of light moves in the "stationary" system of co-ordinates with the
determined velocity c, whether the ray be emitted by a stationary or by a
moving body. Hence

where time interval is to be taken in the sense of the definition in § 1.

Let there be given a stationary rigid rod; and let its length be l as
measured by a measuring-rod which is also stationary. We now imagine the
axis of the rod lying along the axis of x of the stationary system of
co-ordinates, and that a uniform motion of parallel translation with
velocity v along the axis of x in the direction of increasing x is then
imparted to the rod. We now inquire as to the length of the moving rod, and
imagine its length to be ascertained by the following two operations:--

(a) The observer moves together with the given measuring-rod and the rod to
be measured, and measures the length of the rod directly by superposing the
measuring-rod, in just the same way as if all three were at rest.
(b) By means of stationary clocks set up in the stationary system and
synchronizing in accordance with § 1, the observer ascertains at what
points of the stationary system the two ends of the rod to be measured are
located at a definite time. The distance between these two points, measured
by the measuring-rod already employed, which in this case is at rest, is
also a length which may be designated "the length of the rod."

In accordance with the principle of relativity the length to be discovered
by the operation (a)--we will call it "the length of the rod in the moving
system"--must be equal to the length l of the stationary rod.

The length to be discovered by the operation (b) we will call "the length
of the (moving) rod in the stationary system." This we shall determine on
the basis of our two principles, and we shall find that it differs from l.

Current kinematics tacitly assumes that the lengths determined by these two
operations are precisely equal, or in other words, that a moving rigid body
at the epoch t may in geometrical respects be perfectly represented by the
same body at rest in a definite position.

We imagine further that at the two ends A and B of the rod, clocks are
placed which synchronize with the clocks of the stationary system, that is
to say that their indications correspond at any instant to the "time of the
stationary system" at the places where they happen to be. These clocks are
therefore "synchronous in the stationary system."

We imagine further that with each clock there is a moving observer, and
that these observers apply to both clocks the criterion established in § 1
for the synchronization of two clocks. Let a ray of light depart from A at
the time4 , let it be reflected at B at the time , and reach A again at the
time . Taking into consideration the principle of the constancy of the
velocity of light we find that

where  denotes the length of the moving rod--measured in the stationary
system. Observers moving with the moving rod would thus find that the two
clocks were not synchronous, while observers in the stationary system would
declare the clocks to be synchronous.

So we see that we cannot attach any absolute signification to the concept
of simultaneity, but that two events which, viewed from a system of
co-ordinates, are simultaneous, can no longer be looked upon as
simultaneous events when envisaged from a system which is in motion
relatively to that system.









> On Tue, Mar 11, 2014 at 7:54 PM, John Berry <berry.joh...@gmail.com>wrote:
>
>> http://www.neoclassicalrelativity.org/
>>
>> There are 6 simple videos showing arguments against various parts of
>> Special Relativity.
>>
>> http://www.youtube.com/user/NeoclassicRelativity
>>
>>
>>
>

Reply via email to