At 12:18 PM 11/25/2008, Markus Schulze wrote:

If I remember correctly, Abd wrote that, in every
IRV election for public office ever held in the
USA, the IRV winner was identical to the plurality
winner. Doesn't that mean that -- when we apply
your logic -- plurality voting always elects the
right winner?

Since I'm being mentioned, I'd better correct what was said.

In every *nonpartisan* election for public office held in the U.S., since San Francisco started RCV up, the winner was the first round leader. Something similar has been noted in Australia; vote transfers tend, strongly, to benefit the first round leader (and probably do so in proportion to the relative votes of the leader and the runner-up).

I thought, at first, that Pierce County -- the very recent election -- was an exception, but it turns out that this was a partisan election.

I think I understand what's going on. In nonpartisan elections, it turns out that, more or less, on average, voters who prefer C are a representative sample of the rest of the electorate with respect to the A/B pair, so that if C is eliminated, the votes from the C voters will tend to transfer in the same ratio as already exists with those who prefer A or B. Hence vote transfers don't radically shift the position of the frontrunners, normally. (It's also, apparently, rare for a third-place candidate in the first round to go on to win an election, I'm not sure it has ever happened in Australian, or if it has, it's been once or twice, in a huge number of elections.)

When an election is close, it may become an exception. Usually, however, the lead of the frontrunner is simply amplified with each round of eliminations. Exceptions may be, in fact, due to a false lead, i.e., one which was simply a reflection of statistical variations.

Yes, this means that plurality voting is a much better method *in practice* than we have thought, particularly for nonpartisan elections. It is roughly as good as IRV *in that context,* and there is no clear evidence that IRV produces better results there. However, Top Two Runoff is better than both of these, and in particular if write-in votes are allowed, for reasons that have been neglected by voting systems theorists, in general, who tend to assume fixed preferences, a single electorate, and both assumptions are far from the truth.

In a real runoff, voters have an opportunity to examine a reduced set of candidates, and will make a more informed choice between them, on average. Thus voters may reverse the preferences that they voted in the first round, i.e., even if they voted for A as their favorite, they might vote for B in the runoff.

Secondly, voter turnout may be different in the runoff, if it is a delayed runoff with a special election. (Not all are that way: Cary, NC, had a primary held in October, as I recall, with any necessary runoff being with the November general election. The city elections were held in off-years, not with the Presidential election, and what I saw for runoff turnout was that it was about the same as with the primary.) Top-Two Runoff is a method which effectively considers preference strength, and my expectation is that this would improve results from an overall voter satisfaction perspective, exerting a Range-like effect. Voters who, for example, don't have a strong preference between A and B, whether this is because they like both, or don't like both, will be less likely to turn out to vote in the runoff. I can say that I wouldn't bother, unless there was something important on the ballot besides that. Australia's practice of mandatory voting probably has a somewhat negative effect on the quality of results. None of this was likely to be noticed until we started realizing how important preference strength is. It's kind of amazing that it took so long. I attribute the delay to the disconnect between economists and political scientists.

(Borda was probably attractive because of an assumption that if a preference was "long," with many intermediate candidates, it was probably stronger than if it was "weak," with just a single candidate in between. But it is far more straightforward to simply allow the use of ratings, which automatically show preference strength. I.e., Range Voting and Borda Count are really the same method, except that Borda has this rigid assumption about preference strengths that makes it vulnerable to cloning, for example. Range is Borda with equal ranking allowed, and a fixed number of ranks such that ranks can be empty on a ballot. It's also been shown that Borda with a very large number of candidates, broadly distributed across an issue space, is equivalent to Range. And while we are mentioning large numbers of candidates, Range probably handles them better than any method, even Condorcet methods can have a lot of trouble finding a decent winner, because of the neglect of preference strength and the difficulty of defining majority approval of a result.)

Regardless, we know that, with the nonpartisan elections held in the U.S. recently, and FairVote has been successful, mostly, in gaining implementations only as top-two runoff replacements in nonpartisan elections, there aren't any comeback elections happening, whereas, from real runoff elections, as I recall the number, we should have expected about three, so far (before this year, I have not looked at this year's results yet; quite a few of them are not available yet!)

That's serious, if it is not a statistical fluke. Real runoff elections have a cost, to be sure, but they are necessary if one is to look for a true majority winner. IRV does not fix the problem; whenever runoffs are necessary, most of the time -- exceptions are uncommon, actually -- no majority is found. The same thing happens in Australia where they have optional preferential voting.

Consider a dark horse candidate, someone who is a good candidate, but who, for whatever reason, perhaps lower funding, hasn't attracted much attention. With IRV, that candidate may manage to get up to number two, but still loses the election. Getting up to number two in a Plurality election, with enough other votes cast that there is majority failure, the dark horse is now a serious candidate, and voters will make a far more informed choice. In addition, the supporters of the dark horse, who may have been relatively dispirited, are now highly motivated to work for the final election, and there will be high turnout among supporters. If supporters of the first-round winner only have a weak preference for their favorite over the dark horse candidate, they may not be highly motivated to turn out. Hence it's not surprising that we see roughly one out of three real runoff elections result in the runner-up in the first round winning the runoff.

What we don't know, because of poor data, is why this happens, in detail. I've given some speculations that may be reasonable. That the voters are more informed and focused is a common opinion. On the other hand, FairVote offers "evidence" that real runoffs are a problem because of the lower turnout, which is assumed to be a Bad Thing. (The number of voters for the winner in the runoff may be lower than the number of voters for the loser in the first round. Yes. So? Preferential voting methods don't collect preference strength information, and many of those first round voters may not really care which candidate wins the runoff, so they don't vote. Not a bad thing; in fact, it is normal in democratic process that those who care, vote. Those who don't, don't.)

Why are partisan elections different? Well, here, the candidates have clear affiliations, easily recognized by the electorate. In Ann Arbor, Michigan, in the single preferential voting mayoral election held there, there was a "comeback election," where the Democratic candidate was behind the Republican one in the first round, and, in fact, Democratic candidates had been losing to Republicans for some time due to vote-splitting with the Human Rights Party candidate. The Human Rights Party later morphed into the Green Party in Michigan. The Democratic candidate was the first African-American mayor of Ann Arbor. So IRV allowed those HRP members to vote for their party favorite, but then support the Democrat.

Good thing? Probably in that election. However, the problem there was a politically naive or careless HRP, that apparently didn't care about spoiling elections. We've seen this with Nader in Florida, he's still defending his candidacy. He claims that he had the right to run, and, of course, he did. We have the right to cause all kinds of political damage, we could vote for Adolf Hitler, if he were on our ballot. The issue, though, is the effect of the actions. If HRP members didn't care that they were "spoiling" elections, well, they were making a statement. The claim that Gore would have won in Florida if it had been IRV is actually quite questionable.

Nader's position then, and it is still the same, was that there was no important difference between the Democrat and the Republican. If those who supported him believed that, why would they have added a second preference for Gore? Maybe they would have. Maybe not.

No doubt about it. In partisan elections, in the presence of a minor-party spoiler, IRV is an improvement. But we probably get the same improvement simply by allowing multiple votes and counting all of them. We'd get the improvement with Bucklin, which is "instant runoff Approval." And both of these are simpler than IRV to implement, much simpler. Approval is really easy to vote; I'm recommending, as I have been for quite some time now that voting activists promote Approval immediately, because of its minimal cost (it might even be cheaper than Plurality; certainly there would be no overvotes to worry about). Approval need not be the end of the road; it opens the door for Range, or for Bucklin, or for other hybrid methods. Even IRV would be improved if voting more than one candidate at each rank were allowed. (I.e, the voter could vote for A and B in first rank, say. I won't address the technical complications here.... But you want to avoid "harming" your favorite, don't vote for anyone else in first rank. Don't care about that, and want to support two alternate candidates, equally, so that neither of them is eliminated early because of your concealing vote for the other, vote for both of them. Anybody but Joe? Vote in last votable rank (or above) rank for every other candidate besides Joe.

One more consequence to IRV. IRV makes the world safe for major parties; it becomes more difficult for a minor party to spoil the show; this may, in fact, harm minor parties; certainly the long-term effect in Australia has been the fading of independent minor parties. Warren Smith calls the support of minor parties in the U.S. for IRV "suicidal," and he's probably right. Because candidates are rated individually in both Approval and Range, and most accurately, of course, in Range, Range probably will have an "incubator effect," as Smith claims. Both Range and Approval fix the spoiler effect, and more deeply than IRV.

It should be realized that a Range ballot, with at least as many distinct ratings as there are candidates, is a more expressive ballot than that used by any other method. It also is obvious to me that preference strength matters. If a group of friends are trying to decide what pizza to buy, preference strength is crucial, if the group is to be satisfied overall. No business which neglected preference strength and only looked at raw preference in its market would be likely to survive, at least not on the basis of those analyses! So why do we use methods for *political* decision-making which don't even collect that information? And once you have it, how are you going to use it?

It's obvious: Count All the Votes. Voters will *naturally* vote von Neumann-Morganstern utilities, a big name for asking for and supporting with your voting power what you think you might succeed in getting, instead of merely to express moot preferences. The method is good if they can simply vote for a candidate or not, i.e., Approval. The method, from Smith's simulations, gets better if they can express those utilities with more accuracy. There is probably a point of diminishing returns where higher resolution in Range doesn't produce enough benefit to be worth the trouble.

But, politically, right now: Approval Voting. Just Count All the Votes. We need some bumper stickers.

The only concern I've seen about Range, expressed with any coherence, is that some kind of damage will be done by voters "exaggerating." This exaggeration, however, is what preferential systems *require*.

It is so ironic. A voter votes only for A, because the voter prefers A, even though the voter supposedly "also approves" of B. This is then considered strategic voting; the solution being supported through this criticism is to require voters to express exclusive preferences, which are tantamount to requiring all voters to vote this allegedly insincere way. But, of course, the critics never will explore these implications.

I have been looking for quite some time for the logic behind prohibiting overvotes. The only argument I've seen in print is that overvoted ballots are rejected because the "true intent of the voter cannot be discerned." But that is circular.

----
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info

Reply via email to