List,

This chapter on the philosophy of science breaks with the established pattern 
of following Peirce's architectonic.  Given the centrality of scientific 
inquiry in his philosophical theory, there is good reason to devote a separate 
chapter to this topic.  When I compare Peirce's view to those developed by 
other major philosophers, I can't help but wonder if Peirce has drawn the 
boundaries of philosophical theorizing too narrowly.  In his phenomenological 
theory and in his normative sciences, so much attention has been devoted to the 
philosophical foundations of the scientific method, that one might wonder if he 
has paid too little attention to the kinds of questions that figure prominently 
in the philosophical theories developed by the likes of Plato, Aristotle, 
Aquinas, Kant, Heidegger, and others.

With these kinds of concerns in mind, let me try to frame two questions.  
Peirce is trying to model philosophical inquiry on the scientific method.  In 
turn, the scientific method is itself the main focus of his philosophical 
inquiries.  Has the single minded focus on scientific method come at too high a 
price?  Has it caused him to pay too little attention to other methods:  
dialectical, genealogical, hermeneutic?  Has it caused him to pay too little 
attention to other kinds of philosophical questions about morality, art, and 
the like?

--Jeff

Jeff Downard
Associate Professor
Department of Philosophy
NAU
(o) 523-8354
________________________________________
From: Benjamin Udell [bud...@nyc.rr.com]
Sent: Sunday, April 13, 2014 8:46 AM
To: peirce-l@list.iupui.edu
Subject: Re: Fwd: [PEIRCE-L] RE: de Waal Seminar:  Chapter 6, Philosophy of 
Science

Jeffrey, Sam, Jeff K., list,

Jeffrey, you wrote,

is this list of three methods for fixing belief only a partial list of the 
possible alternatives to the scientific method?

Joe Ransdell and Jerry Dozoretz transcribed many draft manuscripts that Peirce 
wrote back in the 1870s. Joe posted the transcriptions to the Papers by Peirce 
page http://www.cspeirce.com/menu/library/bycsp/bycsp.htm at Arisbe. Scroll 
down to "1872-1873" where there are a number of drafts on the inquiry methods. 
It's been a while since I've read them, maybe somebody can find something on 
the methods there as to their list's exhaustiveness.

I'd say that the method of contest needs to be accounted for somehow. I tend to 
see the method of authority as a species of it, though maybe one could do it 
the other way around. In a previous post I said that the method of contest 
doesn't seem obviously generally infallibilistic, but, as a method of arriving 
at truth/falsity of the general opinions of the contestants, arguably it is 
infallibilistic, insofar as it's winner-take-all, never mind who would have won 
under different circumstances, 'the gods have spoken' and all that.

Peirce presents the inquirial methods as tending, for reasons that he describes 
along the way, to be adopted and (three of them) abandoned in the order in 
which he presents them. I think that he is trying to bring to light a 
systematic character that they have collectively.

I would guess that Peirce did use the categories as a heuristic in organizing 
his ideas of three unscientific methods of inquiry in hopes of arriving at an 
exhaustive list and that nevertheless he was not persuaded that the result, on 
which he worked for years, was a genuine, categorially-correlated trichotomy.  
Peirce or a Peircean would hope for a genuine trichotomy there because the 
distinctions are logical, not natural.

I've had the notion that some Peirceans would be inclined to try (and may have 
done so in some publication) to clarify the trio of unscientific inquiry 
methods as an exhaustive, categorially-based trichotomy, logically related to 
other such trichotomies of related issues. The exhaustiveness would be further 
corroborated if other infallibilistic methods could be classified as subclasses 
in the trichotomy, or maybe there could be other global trichotomies of classes 
of the same things, as Peirce did with classes of signs. Likewise, some 
fallibilistic methods of inquiry, such as inquiry by trial-and-error, could be 
classified as dimensions or elements or at least rudiments of scientific 
inquiry.

I've generally thought of the three unscientific methods as the bad methods 
despite Peirce's insistence that one should be, well, scientific about it, 
anyway, impartial, and give them their due, weigh them carefully, etc. So I'll 
just call them 'methodologically infallibilistic'.

I doubt that I'm the first to entertain following picture, in which the three 
unscientific methods seem to have the lineaments of a Peircean trichotomy of 
infallibilistics:

1. Method of tenacity - policy of adherence to FIRST opinion - a 
methodologically infallibilistic First?

2. Method of authority - deciding opinion by force or threat of force, the 
knocking of heads - a methodologically infallibilistic Second?

3. Method of the _a priori_ - deciding opinion in a deductive spirit from 
principles reached through fermentation, some capricious sort of mediation, 
comparison and conversation, a choosing of or adherence to principles by 
intellectual taste and fashion, 'agreeability to Reason',  - a methodologically 
infallibilistic Third?

In a previous post I connected the idea of the method of tenacity (putatively 
the 'methodologically infallibilistic First') with the idea of practice and 
repetition (of one's first opinion), however practice and repetition are not 
mainly a First. But all three infallibilistic methods involve the idea of 
conduct of ongoing activity, so maybe that intrusion of a non-First into the 
method of tenacity doesn't prevent it from being relatively First within the 
trichotomy.

Now, the various more-or-less non-cognitive methods of learning (such as 
practice and repetition in general) that I mentioned in that post do not seem 
to me to constitute a Peircean trichotomy, so I'd guess that a Peircean who 
were to think that there's something to them as correlating with the 
infallibilistic inquiry methods would be inclined to rework the conceptions of 
those three non-cognitive methods, perhaps making one of them cognitive, since 
Peirce tends to divide the mind's powers into those of feeling (sensation, more 
or less), sense of reaction (including volition), and general conception. 
Again, there would be an idea of clarifying a genuine trichotomy of the 
infallibilistic methods by relating that trichotomy (i.e., relating its 
divisions one-to-one) to (the divisions of) other genuine trichotomies.

Best, Ben

On 4/11/2014 6:25 PM, Jeffrey Brian Downard wrote:

Sam, Ben, Jeff K., List,
You point out that "An interesting interpretation of the moral dimension of FoB 
is to be found in the 5th Chapter of Richard Smyth’s <Reading Peirce Reading>, 
where Smyth draws an extended comparison between Peirce’s argumentative 
strategy in FoB and the argumentative strategy Kant uses in his ethics, 
particularly the second Critique."  A nice way to test this reconstruction of 
Peirce's argument is to ask if the list of methods is meant to be a complete of 
the major classes of methods, or if there is a larger list of possible methods 
for fixing belief--some of which he does not consider in this essay.
The basic gist of Smyth's reconstruction of the argument is that Peirce is 
employing a Kantian strategy, and that the target of his argument is any 
philosophical position to tries to ground the methods of inquiry on material 
practical principles.  As such, he thinks that Peirce is borrowing the strategy 
Kant uses in his ethics and is putting it to work in his theory of logic.  As 
such, Peirce is arguing that the scientific method is the only one that is 
grounded on an understanding of the requirements of logical inquiry as *formal* 
constraints on our conduct.  As you suggest, the defect of all material 
practical principles is that, in one way or another, they are all based on a 
principle of self-love.  That is, they all rely on a pattern of justification 
that is based on the idea that the fact that someone has a desire for X is a 
good enough reason to adopt X as an end.  Kant points out that this kind of 
principle does not function as an imperative.  As such, it is does not !
 function
 as a rational constraint on deliberation.  When Peirce claims that we should 
adopt those ends that can be consistently pursued, it certainly has echoes of 
Kant's claims that moral duties are grounded on rational constraints of 
consistency.
Here is a follow up question that is designed to see who agrees and who 
disagrees with this reconstruction of the argument in "Fixation":  Do you think 
Peirce's list of tenacity, authority and the a priori methods is exhaustive of 
the major classes of material principles that one might claim are fundamental 
in a normative theory of logic?  Or, is this list of three methods for fixing 
belief only a partial list of the possible alternatives to the scientific 
method?
I think it is worth noting that, if it is a partial list, it would be hard to 
see how Peirce could argue that the scientific method is the only method that 
admits of any distinction of a right and a wrong way of fixing beliefs.  At 
most, he could argue that the scientific method is the only one of the four 
that he considers that admits of such a difference, but that others methods he 
has not considered might admit of the same difference.
--Jeff
Jeff Downard
Associate Professor
Department of Philosophy
NAU
(o) 523-8354
________________________________________
From: Sam Bruton [samuel.bru...@usm.edu<mailto:samuel.bru...@usm.edu>
]
Sent: Thursday, April 10, 2014 2:03 PM
To: Benjamin Udell; peirce-l@list.iupui.edu<mailto:peirce-l@list.iupui.edu>
Subject: RE: Fwd: [PEIRCE-L] RE: de Waal Seminar:  Chapter 6, Philosophy of 
Science
Ben, Jeff, Jeffrey, List,
          I appreciate Ben’s reconstruction and interpretive remarks – thanks.  
With regards to Jeff’s question about the role of ethics in FoB, and at the 
risk of stating the obvious, paragraph 5.387 seems to me simply shot through 
with ethical claims that are clearly distinct from the various 
efficiency-related points that also run through the essay, e.g., “what is more 
wholesome than any particular belief is integrity of belief, and that to avoid 
looking into the support of any belief from a fear that it may turn out rotten 
is quite as immoral as it is disadvantageous.”  And at the end of the para., 
“one who dares not know the truth and seeks to avoid it, is in a sorry state of 
mind indeed.”
          So perhaps I’m missing the point at issue, but my simple-minded 
reconstruction is that Peirce is arguing that anyone who experiences doubts 
(i.e., virtually all of us) is committed to an interest in arriving at the 
truth, or caring about the truth, or something like that.  For all such people, 
there is an essentially moral obligation not to avoid looking at the truth, 
i.e., an obligation not to adopt one of the failed three methods described in 
the essay.  It’s an assertion of the moral status of epistemic responsibility. 
Or at least that’s how I take it.
          An interesting interpretation of the moral dimension of FoB is to be 
found in the 5th Chapter of Richard Smyth’s Reading Peirce Reading, where Smyth 
draws an extended comparison between Peirce’s argumentative strategy in FoB and 
the argumentative strategy Kant uses in his ethics, particularly the second 
Critique.  Hints of that strategy can be seen in Peirce’s passing reference to 
the “costs” of the method of science, and his praise of the advantages of the 
other three methods.  Like a commitment to morality, the method of science may 
require sacrifice of personal interests.
          Hopefully someone else can take these thoughts further.  – Sam
From: Benjamin Udell [mailto:bud...@nyc.rr.com
]
Sent: Wednesday, April 09, 2014 2:12 PM
To: peirce-l@list.iupui.edu<mailto:peirce-l@list.iupui.edu>
Subject: Re: Fwd: [PEIRCE-L] RE: de Waal Seminar: Chapter 6, Philosophy of 
Science
Jeff, Jeffrey, Sam, list,
Jeff, I have trouble making more of Peirce's esthetic and ethical frames of 
inquiry in "The Fixation of Belief." When the inquirially good is the 
inquirially efficient (apart from countervailing moral concerns such as 
involuntary tests of people), it seems a simple Peircean genus-species relation 
of the good to the true. Insofar as theoretical inquiry is subject to 
extra-inquirial ends, the ethical and esthetic issues get more complex, and 
this happens inevitably. A lot may be implicit, but the explicit statements 
toward the end of "Fixation" seem to sum up pretty well the esthetic and 
ethical frames as conceived of in that article. But I think that the problem is 
probably just me, in need of an IQ boost.
Anyway, in "Fixation" he is trying to get away from, or perhaps to _precede_, 
metaphysical nominalist-realist arguments over truth, the real, etc., so he 
pursues the issues in terms of belief, belief's security, a hypothesis that 
there are reals, etc., and even denies that anybody cares about truth _per se_. 
In later years he embraces the inquirial importance of a hearty will to truth, 
and even disparages the idea of beliefs (in some sense) in genuine science. But 
in those later years it is still essentially truth as eventually distinguished 
from falsehood and defined in "Fixation" and "How to Make Our Ideas Clear" - 
e.g., that opinion which, unlike a false opinion, will not steer one wrong in 
what one aims at, and the final opinion that _would_ be reached by sufficient 
inquiry - it is truth so distinguished and presuppositionally defined that he 
embraces as inquiry's end. He does not come to drop the idea that belief and 
doubt are important terms in which to understand the !
 ideas of


 truth and inquiry - for example in the 1902 Carnegie application. Thus truth 
is a belief's ideal security or 'stability' as some put it - but it's a 
stability not only in actual situations but across would-be situations as well. 
I think that Peirce is quite right to see modal realism as a necessary 
implication of his kind of pragmatism.
Peirce in later years allows of practical certainty, as opposed to theoretical 
certainty. A practical general certainty would still in principle be 
'falsifiable', i.e., testable for falsity, at least by critical discussion. 
Otherwise it would be a belief that makes no practical difference, and thus, as 
you put it, not to be prized, not worth having. One might say that an 
in-principle untestable belief lacks all intellectual _vividness_, at least at 
heart. It's interesting how you link this with how we don't value that which 
comes to us inevitably and free of cost, risk, etc. I wish that I had thought 
of that; you've traced a connection from logic back through ethics to esthetics.
There's another point that I can make, however. In "Fixation", Peirce argues 
that the scientific method is, _among the four methods that he outlines_, the 
only one that leaves room for its own misapplication.
Peirce's big picture of inquiry methods is part of an even bigger picture of 
methods of learning and development cognitive and otherwise, which beckons when 
one starts to consider esthetic and ethical frames of inquiry, a bigger picture 
that people like me, who are far less encyclopedic than Peirce, find it helpful 
to thematize and explore now and then.
>From here onward, my post becomes something of a ramble. Those who continue 
>should not worry too much about what I'm 'driving at'.
One could outline further methods - e.g., the method of struggle, trial as 
combat - which could be seen as a not-generally-obviously-infallibilistic genus 
of which the method of (despotic) authority is an infallibilistic species, a 
species such that one side in combat has become dominant and seemingly 
infallible. Then there is the method of trial-and-error, which is 
fallibilistic, and is the method of 'men of experience', whom Aristotle rated 
below artisans and scientists, because the 'men of experience' are least able 
to give an account of their supposed knowledge. Yet Peirce defines a scientific 
intelligence as an intelligence capable of learning from experience. One could 
argue that the method of trial-and-error is a rudiment of scientific method, in 
a way trial-and-error, especially as involving personal stakes (even if 'only' 
those of one's time, energy, reputation, etc.), is the struggle-level of 
scientific inquiry. However, struggle as trial-and-error is also, in addi!
 tion to


that, a way of learning not so much cognitively as volitionally, i.e., some 
sort of strengthening or unshackling of virtues or character strengths, 
particularly in areas, arenas so to speak, where the struggle element is 
predominant - conflicts for power and freedom, competition for means and 
wealth, more-or-less cultural rivalries for glory, glamour, and at least 
non-eclipse, and more-or-less societal disputes for standing, honor, 
legitimacy. From these one could derive conceptions of (infallibilistic) 
inquirial methods of authority - authority of power, authority of wealth, 
authority of glamour (obviously related to the method of the _a priori_), and 
authority of status (like the traditional 'argument from authority', known in 
Latin as _argumentum ad verecundiam_ (respect, reverence, etc.)), which settle 
opinions by the wrongs of coercion, corruption, emotional manipulation, and 
delusion. Anyway, while all inquiry involves learning, there is a broad sense 
of 'learning' suc!
 h that n

o
t all learning is cognitive (and even cognitive learning is not always 
particularly inquirial or opinion-fixative even when it is a bit of struggle, 
e.g., rote memorization).
Among the methods of authority, perhaps the biggest temptation in discovery 
research is the method of status, especially when it is a method of 
_self_-deception, such that one grants oneself a status of greater 
knowledgeability, etc., than one fairly has; it's a temptation of the 
intelligent; magicians find it easier to bewilder or beguile 'smart' people 
than to do so with 'stupid' people, by whom magicians mean, the people who are 
unimpressed and chuckle, "well, you did it somehow" (but those people are 
obviously smart enough in another way). As Feynman said, the person whom it is 
easiest for one to fool is oneself. Peirce focuses, near the end of "Fixation," 
on the closing of one's eyes or ears to the information or evidence that might 
bring one the truth particularly when one should know better. This closing of 
one's perception, in sometimes less guilty ways, plays a particularly 
vulnerable role in the method of tenacity because it is there unprotected by 
folds of authori!
 ty or of


 aprioristic emulation of some fermented paradigm; instead there is to keep 
practicing and repeating one's initial opinion, it seems a bit like the 
gambler's fallacy, boosted sometimes by some initial luck. Well, practice and 
repetition of something that has shown _some_ success is the core 
practical-learning method, not inevitably infallibilistic, of artisans and more 
generally practitioners productive and otherwise; to which method they add the 
appreciational method of devotees (including the religious) - identification 
(appreciation) and imitation (emulation) and, these days, the methods of 
reflective disciplines as well (sciences, fine arts, etc.). What I'm getting at 
is that some infallibilistic methods of inquiry can be seen as misapplications, 
or at least as echoes, of methods that have some validity outside of inquiry as 
the struggle to settle opinion, and thus have validity in applications in 
inquiry (e.g., one needs to keep _in practice_ in doing math, etc.), as lo!
 ng as th

o
se applications are not confused with inquiry itself. Anyway, one's barring of 
one's own way to truth inhabits the core of all infallibilistic inquiry. 
Perhaps one can reduce all logical sins to this, as long as one remembers the 
difference between logical sin and other logical errors, errors sometimes 
imposed on one.
Best, Ben
On 4/9/2014 1:09 AM, Kasser,Jeff wrote:
Sorry. I originally sent this only to Ben.
Sent from my iPhone
Begin forwarded message:
From: "Kasser,Jeff" <jeff.kas...@colostate.edu<mailto:jeff.kas...@colostate.edu>
<mailto:jeff.kas...@colostate.edu><mailto:jeff.kas...@colostate.edu>
 >
Date: April 8, 2014 at 10:54:58 PM MDT
To: Benjamin Udell <bud...@nyc.rr.com<mailto:bud...@nyc.rr.com>
<mailto:bud...@nyc.rr.com><mailto:bud...@nyc.rr.com>
 >
Subject: RE: [PEIRCE-L] RE: de Waal Seminar:  Chapter 6, Philosophy of Science
Hi Ben, Sam, Jeffrey, et al.
I like Jeffrey's question about the status in Peirce's argument of the claim 
that the scientific method is the only method that leaves room for its own 
misapplication. And I like the answer Ben gave below. Peirce rightly prefers 
overlapping strands of argumentation to a single line of reasoning, but it's 
hard to resist raising questions about what in "Fixation" depends on what.
I tend to trace his argumentative resources back to the doubt-belief theory.  I 
think Peirce wants to come as close as he can to deriving such things as 
fallibility and openness to improvement from those resources centered on 
Section III of the paper. For belief to be worth wanting, it has to be 
something that can go wrong. Any game that makes it trivially true that I win 
every time isn't worth playing, and if there's no prospect at all of going 
wrong, there's no real sense in which one can claim to be right.  So belief 
couldn't be satisfactory unless it were, in principle at least, open to 
correction.  I can use a method that as a matter of fact guarantees that I 
can't go wrong, but I can't think of myself as doing that w/o undercutting the 
very notion of success. So such methods as authority can be used but can't be 
voluntarily and clear-headedly adopted.  This comes close to building the 
hypothesis of reality into the notion of belief, but Peirce does that a couple 
of tim!
 es in "F


ixation," so far as I can tell.
I'd like to hear and talk more about how you see the role of ethics and 
esthetics in the argument of "Fixation," Ben. I think you and I agree that the 
contrast between the efficiency aspects of the argument and the normative 
appeals involved isn't as clear as it's often been taken to be.
Best to all,
Jeff
________________________________________
From: Benjamin Udell [bud...@nyc.rr.com<mailto:bud...@nyc.rr.com>
<mailto:bud...@nyc.rr.com><mailto:bud...@nyc.rr.com>
 ]
Sent: Tuesday, April 08, 2014 11:10 AM
To: peirce-l@list.iupui.edu<mailto:peirce-l@list.iupui.edu>
<mailto:peirce-l@list.iupui.edu><mailto:peirce-l@list.iupui.edu>
Subject: Re: [PEIRCE-L] RE: de Waal Seminar:  Chapter 6, Philosophy of Science
Jeffrey, Jeff,
Off to an excellent start!
Jeffrey, you wrote,
[Peirce] says:  “This is the only one of the four methods which presents any 
distinction of a right and a wrong way.” (EP, vol. 1, 121)
What is Peirce saying here?  Let us try to clarify the bases of this claim.  In 
a number of places, including the lectures in Reasoning and the Logic of 
Things, he stresses and develops the idea that the scientific method is 
self-correcting.  I’d like to ask a question about the relationship between 
these two claims.
Peirce means that, of the four methods, the scientific method is the only one 
whereby inquiry, according to the method's own account, can go wrong as well as 
right; scientific method alone among them presupposes, or hypothesizes, that 
there are real things that are what they are independently of the opinion of 
particular minds or communities - hence the scientific method's fallibilism. 
According to each of the other three methods' own accounts, inquiry by the 
method in the account cannot go wrong. On the other hand, scientific method is 
like the other methods in that, according its own account, inquiry by it can go 
right - hence, the scientific method's rejection of radical skepticism, a 
rejection also expressed in the opposition to merely quarrelsome or verbal 
doubt. The scientific method's supposition of real things, external permanency, 
to be cognized albeit fallibly, is what gives it hope of inquiry's not 
floundering in opinion's vicissitudes. The scientific method takes!
  fallibi


lity as well as the possibility of success into account by having inquiry 
genuinely address genuine doubts. By this it can improve the security of 
beliefs, sometimes by changing them. It lets such doubts in, instead of leaving 
them to accrue against overall scientific method itself.
It seems to me that the claim that the inquirer is fallible but has the 
potential for success is the basis for the scientific method's claim that 
inquiry should be self-critical and self-corrective. The argument does not seem 
to me to run in the opposite direction.
Near the end of "The Fixation of Belief" Peirce does frame inquiry in terms of 
ethical and esthetic issues, even though he did not at that time regard the 
studies of esthetics and ethics as preceding the study of logic.
http://www.peirce.org/writings/p107.html
But, above all, let it be considered that what is more wholesome than any 
particular belief is integrity of belief, and that to avoid looking into the 
support of any belief from a fear that it may turn out rotten is quite as 
immoral as it is disadvantageous. The person who confesses that there is such a 
thing as truth, which is distinguished from falsehood simply by this, that if 
acted on it should, on full consideration, carry us to the point we aim at and 
not astray, and then, though convinced of this, dares not know the truth and 
seeks to avoid it, is in a sorry state of mind indeed.
Yes, the other methods do have their merits: a clear logical conscience does 
cost something -- just as any virtue, just as all that we cherish, costs us 
dear. [....]
"...immoral...", "Just as any virtue..." - those words point to ethics.
"...just as all that we cherish..." - those words point to esthetics (in 
Peirce's sense of 'esthetics').
Now, in ethics there is usually the idea of a struggle, e.g., in virtue ethics, 
courage is due boldness (or at least due confident behavior) despite pressure 
to do otherwise; prudence is due caution despite contrary pressure; and so on. 
In the above-quoted passage, Peirce sees issues of struggle, costs, and 
trade-offs reaching into issues of one's most general values, i.e., the 
esthetic level. "The Fixation of Belief" starts with the idea of inquiry as 
struggle, and this struggle is also a case of ethical right and wrong and of 
esthetic good and bad, in Peirce's view at that time, even though he didn't yet 
see the studies of esthetics and ethics as preceding that of logic.
As regards your last paragraph, the scientific method's fallibilism about 
opinion seems quite thoroughgoing enough to apply to premisses, conclusions, 
methods, etc., since all premisses, conclusions, and methods that are actually 
adopted are adopted on the basis of actual opinions. The infallibilism of the 
other three methods seems likewise.
Best, Ben
On 4/7/2014 3:12 PM, Jeffrey Brian Downard wrote:
List,
In addition to joining Jeff K. in looking forward to the prospect of bouncing 
ideas off each other as we explore this chapter of the ’ <Guide for the 
Perplexed>, I’d like t0o start by saying that I found his introductory remarks 
about “The Fixation of Belief” clear and to the point.
For the sake of getting the discussion started, I’d like raise a question about 
a claim Peirce makes in part V of the essay.  He says:  “This is the only one 
of the four methods which presents any distinction of a right and a wrong way.” 
(EP, vol. 1, 121)
What is Peirce saying here?  Let us try to clarify the bases of this claim.  In 
a number of places, including the lectures in Reasoning and the Logic of 
Things, he stresses and develops the idea that the scientific method is 
self-correcting.  I’d like to ask a question about the relationship between 
these two claims.
Peirce seems to suggest that the self-correcting character of the scientific 
method is quite remarkable because it is able to correct for three kinds of 
errors:
1)      in the premises (i.e., the observations) we’ve used as starting points,
2)      in the conclusions we’ve drawn (i.e., the beliefs we’ve formed) in our 
scientific reasoning,
3)      and in the method itself.
I want ask a question about these three different kinds of error.  Call them, 
if you will, observational errors, errors in our conclusions, and 
methodological errors.  How might the claim that the scientific method is the 
only one that admits of any distinction of a right and wrong way be used in 
arguments to support each of these three claims about the self-correcting 
character of scientific inquiry?  My hunch is that the other three methods he 
is considering—tenacity, authority and the a priori methods--fail on each of 
these three fronts.
Yours,
Jeffrey D.
Jeff Downard
Associate Professor
Department of Philosophy
NAU
(o) 523-8354
________________________________________
From: Kasser,Jeff [jeff.kas...@colostate.edu<mailto:jeff.kas...@colostate.edu>
<mailto:jeff.kas...@colostate.edu><mailto:jeff.kas...@colostate.edu>
 <mailto:jeff.kas...@colostate.edu ><mailto:jeff.kas...@colostate.edu>
 ]
Sent: Monday, April 07, 2014 10:55 AM
To: Jeffrey Brian Downard
Cc: Peirce List
Subject: de Waal Seminar:  Chapter 6, Philosophy of Science
-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .




Reply via email to