Stephen J. - I'm not sure that your response deals with the point of my 
comment, which was that 'knowledge' is not all gained by experience - that was 
the 'Empty Bucket' theory to which I was referring. Instead, my point was that 
a certain amount of knowledge is innate, more so in plants, insects, animals 
and less so in the human species - but - nevertheless, our species has an 
innate capacity for symbolic language, for reasoning, for imagination which 
enables hypothetical or anticipatory decision-making, etc. 

Therefore, knowledge is not confined to experience.  This has nothing to do 
with total genocentric determinism (is there such a thing?) nor with 'naive 
cultural relativism'. Instead, the question focuses around two issues:

1) How much of the knowledge base is innate, i.e., genetic. As I suggested, I 
think the ability to use symbolic language, to think rationally etc..is 
genetic. And how does this affect the community as well as the individual 
(i.e., mathematical ability, musical ability which can be shown in many cases 
to be genetic rather than learned)..
vs
2) And how much is social; i.e., collective knowledge - which is NOT subjective 
but communal, (and not necessarily truthful to objective reality) and how does 
the collective knowledge base adapt and change?

Edwina
  ----- Original Message ----- 
  From: Stephen Jarosek 
  To: 'Edwina Taborsky' ; 'Ozzie' 
  Cc: 'Matt Faunce' ; 'Peirce-L' 
  Sent: Monday, October 12, 2015 3:29 PM
  Subject: RE: [PEIRCE-L] Re: A Second-Best Morality


  Edwina, on the face of the points you raise, I won't disagree with you. 
However, for clarification, let us draw a clear distinction between naive 
idealism versus realistic (semiotic) idealism. In the spirit of naive idealism 
(naive cultural relativism), we cannot just wake up one morning and announce 
"today is the first day of the rest of my life" and then proceed to become a 
different person from that point forwards, simply by the force of will.

  As you would realize, one must contend with mind-body predispositions and how 
they relate to pragmatism and semiotic principles, within the context of a 
compelling axiomatic framework. Thus there is an objective Truth in the sense 
of a Truth about semiotic principles, but experience (knowing) can only ever be 
subjective.

  Naive idealism is the flip-side of the genocentric paradigm. One says "it's 
all in the genes." The other says "no it's not, don't oppress me... I can be 
whatever I want to be." Both are embodiments of the same kind of simplistic 
linear thinking.

  sj

   

  From: Edwina Taborsky [mailto:tabor...@primus.ca] 
  Sent: Monday, 12 October 2015 3:03 PM
  To: Stephen Jarosek; 'Ozzie'
  Cc: 'Matt Faunce'; 'Peirce-L'
  Subject: Re: [PEIRCE-L] Re: A Second-Best Morality

   

  To my understanding, Stephen J.,  you subscribe to what is known as the 
'Empty Bucket' or tabula rasa theory of the mind (Locke's theory) where the 
human species is born with an empty brain and 'learns how to be' from almost 
passive experience. A subjectivist theory - i.e., there is only one kind of 
knowledge - that possessed by a knowing subject. This of course leads to 
nominalism and relativism and of course precludes Truth, which can't exist in 
such an epistemology. 

   

  See Karl Popper's strong criticism of this approach in his 'Objective 
Knowledge'. He opts instead, as did Peirce, for the existence of 'the real', 
the objective reality which exists outside of human cultural beliefs;  and 
human knowledge can examine this reality and arrive at its truth, as a Peircean 
'community of scholars' - within our innate dispositions to be rational, to 
imagine, to be analytical and to communicate - such as the disposition to learn 
a language. 

   

  Now, you also seem to define the acquisition of knowledge as based on and 
only on individual subjective experience; that is, you reject any common will 
to knowledge or any innate capacity for examination of the objective world. I 
don't subscribe to the extreme reductionism of Dawkins, who places all 
causality in 'the genes' - and I totally reject his memes theory of culture - 
BUT, I think that all species have both innate knowledge of 'how to be' and the 
human species has the least amount of innate knowledge - and this is  genetic. 
What the human species has, genetically, is the capacity for logic, order, 
organization and symbolic communication. These permit its knowledge base of 
'how to be' to evolve, adapt, change, while the knowledge base of, let's say a 
frog, is limited, and it must change its physiology to adapt, while the human 
species changes its technology - a far easier and faster method of adaptation. 
Language - and the rational analysis of the world - which are both genetic 
within our species - enables man to critique, describe, the objective reality 
and change his methods of interaction with it.

   

  Your references to the Buddhist and Zen 'emptying the bucket' so to speak, 
are merely desires to empty oneself of one's beliefs - the subjectivist beliefs 
that one has learned - but this action doesn't include obtaining another set of 
beliefs to 'fill the bucket' but to open the mind to the objective world such 
that one's innate capacity for reason and analysis can view it objectively.

   

  Edwina

   

   

   

   

   

   

    ----- Original Message ----- 

    From: Stephen Jarosek 

    To: 'Ozzie' 

    Cc: 'Matt Faunce' ; 'Peirce-L' 

    Sent: Monday, October 12, 2015 5:09 AM

    Subject: RE: [PEIRCE-L] Re: A Second-Best Morality

     

    Hi Tom, list,

    >”Can we use it [knowing how to be] to animate our logic and make 
predictions about behavior? “

    Absolutely. There are several ways that an entity “learns how to be” and 
none of that has anything to do with instinct or programming within a DNA 
blueprint. Central to this concept is pragmatism... or is that pragmaticism... 
establishing how said entity defines the things that matter. The simplest and 
most obvious example I can think of here is imitation. Richard Dawkins based 
his memetic theory on imitation. But there are other ways of defining the 
things that matter, not just imitation. Imitation is a subset of “knowing how 
to be.”

    Animals have to “know how to be.” In the absence of human contact, we 
recognize their untamed feral natures in the wild. But subject to being raised 
among humans, they learn from humans civil behaviour, incorporating it within 
the terms of their bodily predispositions. By the same token, there are records 
(of varying credibility) of children raised by wild animals (e.g., the “Wild 
Boy of Aveyron or the Dog Girl from the Ukraine, variously affirmed or debunked 
by “experts” who know nothing of neural plasticity, pragmatism, or semiotic 
principles). There is nothing necessarily “wrong” or “broken” with the brains 
of feral children... their brains do what brains are meant to do, when learning 
how to be. Thomas Szasz has it mostly right... mental illness is a fiction... 
it’s about experience, choices and wiring.

    Then there is culture and “knowing how to be” within culture. Most people, 
when they travel, force-fit their observations into the pigeon-holes of their 
home culture. It does not occur to them that the new narratives that they must 
contend with are entirely different to the narratives back home. Often, 
radically different. In this there is utility in the theory of “knowing how to 
be” by realizing the extent to which one’s personal narratives are alien to 
those of the new culture. You make the same transactions as everyone else does, 
in your new culture, so you assume that they are connecting with the same 
narratives... nothing could be farther from the truth.

    So what sort of prediction would you like to make? I can predict that an 
animal in the wild, beyond the sphere of human knowing, will become feral. I 
can predict that a child raised in a knowing of abuse and violence, is going to 
grow up knowing the narratives of abuse and violence. And whether or not they 
rise above it will be contingent on the experiences to which they are exposed 
and the choices that they make. If they are lucky, they might chance upon a 
role model who might show them an alternative way of “knowing how to be.” In 
Christianity, Jesus provides a role model, an example of “knowing how to be.” 
How practical is that? Religious conflicts arise from different ways of 
“knowing how to be.”

    But of course this is where the entrenched objectivist, genocentric 
narrative kicks in... “it’s all in the genes, silly.” No, it’s not in the 
genes. It’s about knowing how to be. It’s about plasticity, especially neural 
plasticity, and how the brain wires itself to incorporate experience into its 
narratives and its identity. Genes and DNA are important, of course, but 
nothing as described in the spirit of the genocentric narrative.

    >”Finally - I don't personally believe that Pragmatic logic requires DNA 
(you suggest that I probably do) “

    Might I suggest that, while you have an appreciation for the semiotic 
theory of Peirce, your narratives continue to be influenced by the established 
genocentric narrative. The scaffolding* for your semiotic theory is not 
complete, it is a work in progress. And therefore you do not have an intuitive 
feel for the reach of semiotic theory. This is why you have trouble with 
“knowing how to be” and still see it is vague.

    As an engineering/business graduate ignorant of Peirce, I first formulated 
my own theoretical outline, independently of Peirce, a couple of decades ago. 
And prior to that, I devoted much effort to trying to understand what motivates 
people in a cultural context... why are they so trapped in their cultural bs? 
So my scaffolding has been a work in progress for a very long time... and yet 
to this day, I continue to be surprised that I am still learning new things... 
the adventure continues. Putting the scaffolding in place takes a long time and 
requires considerable effort. And each stage yields more insights, more layers 
to work on. When I talk about the domestication of animals, for example, some 
less experienced Peirceans might think to themselves “how nice, I buy that” and 
then fail to grasp the reach of what I am trying to say because, continuing to 
whisper into their ears, is the genocentric narrative, along the lines of “yes, 
what sj is saying sounds pretty cool, but instinct because genes.” You can 
entertain a theory on the surface, but remain mired in a scaffolding that 
continues to inform the rest of your thinking.

    The full impact of “knowing how to be” came to me only in 2013, as I was 
starting a new life in the northern hemisphere. I am reminded of that cliché, 
“like a child seeing the world for the first time.” It’s ALL about “knowing how 
to be.” The concept is not vague at all. It is precise, laser sharp. It is the 
core with all the layers removed. You don’t see it because you continue to 
interpret the world with the narratives of the mainstream and the scaffolding 
that has established your “knowing how to be.” You need to address your 
scaffolding, along the lines of the following Buddhist koan:

                A Cup of Tea 
                Nan-in, a Japanese master during the Meiji era (1868-1912), 
received a university professor who came to inquire about Zen. 
                Nan-in served tea. He poured his visitor’s cup full, and then 
kept on pouring. 
                The professor watched the overflow until he no longer could 
restrain himself. 
                “It is overfull. No more will go in!” 
                “Like this cup,” Nan-in said, “you are full of your own 
opinions and speculations. How can I show you Zen unless you first empty your 
cup?”

    *I only recently stumbled across the fairly new term “scaffolding” (the 
structure of narratives) within a semiotic context, without having access to 
the full journal (Biosemiotics, Springer) documents... hope I’m using the word 
in the right context.

    sj

     

    From: Ozzie [mailto:ozzie...@gmail.com] 
    Sent: Friday, 9 October 2015 11:03 PM
    To: Stephen Jarosek
    Cc: Matt Faunce; Peirce-L
    Subject: Re: [PEIRCE-L] Re: A Second-Best Morality

     

    Stephen, List ~

    In your account, the old buffalo no longer knows "how to be" while the 
young ones do -- but I don't recall whether (in the story) the old buffalo was 
eaten by crocs or made it safely across the river.  

     

    If he survived the swim, then not knowing how to be evidently didn't 
endanger his survival.  Then, the old buffalo's bulging eyes before being 
pushed into the water does not reveal a lot about the evolutionary story of his 
species.  Are buffalo who are acting like real buffalo supposed to volunteer 
for hazardous duty, disregard their own past experiences, and not let their 
eyes bulge?  

     

    If we don't actually know whether the old buffalo made it across the river, 
drawing any conclusion about evolution from a few frames of video is premature.

     

    What about the same old buffalo when he was only half that age.  Did he 
know how to be a buffalo when he was younger?  What caused the transformation?  
Did he have buffalo offspring who did or did not know how to be buffalo?  

     

    I have trouble with "knowing how to be" because it is vague and doesn't 
mean anything specific to me.  (Yet, perhaps it does to others.)  Can we use it 
to animate our logic and make predictions about behavior?

     

    Finally - I don't personally believe that Pragmatic logic requires DNA (you 
suggest that I probably do) -- but I don't perceive the two are in conflict, 
either.  For example, social institutions do not have DNA.  Neither do water 
molecules.  

     

    Regards,

    Tom Wyrick 

     

     


    On Oct 9, 2015, at 2:16 PM, Stephen Jarosek <sjaro...@iinet.net.au> wrote:

      >” Pushing that old buffalo to the crocs may represent nothing more 
complicated than self-interest.  I don't believe that any species can survive 
(long term) without individual members having a self-interest motive.“

      But Tom, self-interest relates to pragmatism, and how an entity defines 
the things that matter. And defining the things that matter relates to “knowing 
how to be.” “Knowing how to be” comes first, and the self-interest, as 
motivation (firstness?), is established within the context of that knowing. 
This vaguely defined notion “self-interest” infers a deterministic narrative... 
it seems to imply an “instinct” “programmed” into the DNA blueprint, which I 
for one do not buy into.

      sj

       

      From: Ozzie [mailto:ozzie...@gmail.com] 
      Sent: Friday, 9 October 2015 8:42 PM
      To: Stephen Jarosek
      Cc: Matt Faunce; Peirce-L
      Subject: Re: [PEIRCE-L] Re: A Second-Best Morality

       

      Stephen, Matt ~ 

      Pushing that old buffalo to the crocs may represent nothing more 
complicated than self-interest.  I don't believe that any species can survive 
(long term) without individual members having a self-interest motive.  Perhaps 
the old buffalo knows "how to be," and doesn't want to swim with crocs.  Maybe 
that's how he got to be old.  And perhaps the young bulls behind him are 
impatient and less afraid.  Both may be self-interested, though not endowed 
with equal wisdom.  (Don't we observe the same behavior in human wars?  The 
young soldier charges into a machine gun nest, while the more experienced 
soldier keeps his head down.  It's a matter of knowing how to be alive 
tomorrow.)

       

      I enjoy the video (and others like it), but I see the discussion as one 
that describes mechanisms in nature in general terms instead of offering a 
definitive account of nature's logic.  For example, consider the example of 
beautiful fish that attract more mates and also attract more predators.  I'm 
not persuaded that after a female fish lays her eggs in the weeds she can be 
said to be "selecting" handsome suitors for her offspring.  Maybe she can do so 
despite having left the area, but her method is not obvious.  ("Internal 
fertilization is not the norm for fish, and the majority of species use 
external fertilization. In this mating system, eggs and sperm are released 
separately and are fertilized outside of the body.")

       

      In some species, sex is pleasurable.  In those cases an "ugly" male or 
female may attract short-term suitors who are looking for a good time.  That 
allows the ugly gene to survive, and removes the genetic bias toward 
nonfunctional adaptations (that don't promote survival). 

       

      Continuing this example, a lot of sex in nature appears to be what modern 
humans would describe as rape.  Then, selection is more a case of the relative 
strength of one partner and opportunity -- not choice geared toward individual 
survival or that of the species.  That institution (rape) mixes up the gene 
pool, selects for size and signals to targets of unwilling sex to stay close to 
home for protection.  (This process may describe early human evolution.)

       

      Other species may have emotional lives (experiences) we are not aware of, 
and those emotions may influence behavior in ways that are presently attributed 
to kinship genes. 

       

      Regards, 

      Tom Wyrick

       

       


      On Oct 9, 2015, at 4:28 AM, Stephen Jarosek <sjaro...@iinet.net.au> wrote:

        Matt,

        Good points. The point where you cue the talk, where your ‘expert’ 
disses cooperation... we can understand how organisms work for the good of the 
group only from a semiotic perspective and the realization that every organism 
has to “learn how to be.” As soon as you factor in “knowing how to be”, you 
factor in the motivation for an organism to work for the good of the group... 
not directly, of course, but by default... natural selection meets semiotics. 
Easy peazy, there is nothing illogical in that crucial insight. His reference 
to an elderly wildebeest being pushed into the river by the herd can also be 
understood within the context of “knowing how to be.” Regarding the passing of 
the elderly wildebeest, Darwinian natural selection is SECONDARY to its 
demise... PRIMARY is its failure to keep up with the “knowing how to be” of the 
herd. When it loses its ability to keep up with the herd and its behaviour, 
that is when natural selection kicks in. Natural selection is better understood 
in the context of failing to keep up with the group, whereas “knowing how to 
be” is of greater importance, first cause, and the source of complexity.  
Indeed, factoring in “knowing how to be” and its role in cooperation is, imho, 
much more compelling than reductionism and Dawkins’ idea of selfish genes. 
“Knowing how to be”... humans do it, bees do it, neurons do it, stem cells do 
it, men and women do it. “Knowing how to be” is the first source of variety. 
Natural selection is the filter of variety, the penalty/reward for 
improper/successful conduct. “Knowing how to be” is semiotics.

        sj

         

         

        From: Matt Faunce [mailto:mattfau...@gmail.com] 
        Sent: Thursday, 8 October 2015 10:48 PM
        To: Peirce-L
        Subject: Re: [PEIRCE-L] Re: A Second-Best Morality

         

        On 10/7/15 8:47 AM, Edwina Taborsky wrote:

          Matt - I have some logical questions:

           

          1) "instincts are no longer considered to work toward the probable 
perpetuation of the species, but they work only toward the probable 
perpetuation of their specific gene type, sometimes at the expense of the 
species."

           

          I always dislike the passive tense "no longer considered to 
work'...because it leaves out the important AGENT. Who says that instincts no 
longer work toward the continuity of the species"? Proof? Or just some 'expert' 
(Appeal-to-Authority Fallacy).


        Here's my 'expert' cued up to where he explicitly states it:
        https://youtu.be/Y0Oa4Lp5fLE?t=16m21s





        Instincts work only toward the perpetuation of their gene type? Ah, a 
reductionist view - and how does the gene harm the species? Examples of both 
privileging the gene and harming the species? 


        Reductionism would be the case for a theory that genes determine 
behavior, but I said the opposite, that behavior (instincts) works toward 
preserving a gene type.

        He later mentions fish who choose mates who are bright and colorful 
despite this trait making them more likely to be preyed on.

        A seed beetle's aggressive mating behavior favors its gene type over 
its competitor's but harms the species:
        http://www.mediadesk.uzh.ch/articles/2011/paarungsverhalten_en.html

        Matt


        -----------------------------
        PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON 
PEIRCE-L to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . 
To UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with 
the line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .






----------------------------------------------------------------------------


    -----------------------------
    PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON 
PEIRCE-L to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . 
To UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with 
the line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .




-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .




Reply via email to