>>But Justin, do you accept that what you criticise as being redundant some
of us would merely call a labor theory of prices?<<

Justin responds:> Not merely. Marx attempted to use value theory to do a lot
of work, e.g., as  part od [of?] a theory of crisis, as a component of his
account of commodity fetishism, as an account of the nature of money, and,
of course, as the explanation of profit, exploitation, surplus value, and
the rate of these things.<

That's right: Marx's Law of Value was a component of his account of
commodity fetishism, or is rather implied by his whole vision of the
capitalist system, which involves commodity fetishism (or the "illusions
created by competition" of volume III). Like Locke before him (who developed
a very non-Marxian labor theory of property), money is central to Marx's
LoV. The key thing about the LoV is that it "applies" -- as a
true-by-definition accounting system that's an alternative to doing one's
accounting in price terms -- for the capitalist system as a whole or to the
average capital (abstract capital) representing the system as a whole. 

>However, he correctly started from the premises that to do this work, value
had to be quantity with a determinable magnitude, and price is the point of
entry into that because value "appears" as price and profit in the
phenonemal world. If value theory breaks down there, it's toast, as Marx
also recognized, which is why he and Engels and traditional Marxism were
concerned with the transformation problem.<

It's surplus-value that "appears" as profit in the "phenomenal world," i.e.,
the world that we perceive rather than the world revealed by applying the
acid of abstraction. (It's only Roemer who sees profit as in essence a
scarcity price.) But no matter. Marx's concern with the so-called
transformation problem (the derivation of values from prices or vice-versa)
comes from his early learning from Ricardo. But then he takes the whole
issue in a different direction. 

For Marx, as I read him, the movement from value to price (or price of
production) is not mathematical as much as it is one of moving from a high
level of abstraction (volume I of CAPITAL) to a lower one (volume III). In
volume I, he focused on capital as a whole (as represented by the
representative capitalist, Mr. Moneybags), abstracting from the
heterogeneity of many capitals and the relationships amongst them.
Step-by-step, he brings in aspects of the picture from which he had
abstracted, until he gets to volume III, where he deals with how the
"configurations of capital" "appear on the surface of society, in the action
of different capitals on one another, i.e., in competition, and in the
everyday consciousness of the agents of production themselves" (from the
first page of text in volume III). 

In this light, the so-called "transformation problem" should be seen as a
"disaggregation problem," going from the whole to the heterogeneous parts
that make it up. In Marx's thought, the distinction between individual
values and individual prices is as important as their unity. (For example,
the value produced by money-lenders equals zero in Marx's theory, but they
receive revenues: they are paid a price for their services.)  The
distinction represents the role of heterogeneity of capitals and
competition, whereas the unity (represented by his equations total value =
total price and total surplus-value = total profits+interest+rent)
represents the fact that the heterogeneity and competition take place within
a unified whole. (The revenues received by the money-lenders is a deduction
from the surplus-value that the industrial capitalists have organized the
production of.) 

>In these respect he was more intellectually honest that the latter-day
defenders of value  theory who want the "quantity" without being able to
determine its measure.<

to whom are you referring? and what does this mean? 

It should also be noted that prices are very hard to measure, especially
since the quality of diffferent products varies among them and over time. 
> 
> >
> >And from the perspective of it being an expanation of 
> exploitation, some of
> >us would say that childen notice there are grossly unfair 
> and inexplicable
> >differences in society.
> 
> Unlike me, right? I think that all the inequalities that 
> exist are just 
> great. But here you depart from Marxism: "Unfair" is a charge 
> he would 
> dismissa sa  bourgeois whine. As a liberal democrat, I myself 
> think he was 
> wrong about that--I think justice talk is very important--but 
> I find it odd 
> that you insist on orthodoxy in political economy while 
> rejecting Marx's 
> ideologiekritik of morality in general and talk of justice 
> and fairness in 
> particular.
> 
> Finally, I don't understand why you think you can't explain 
> inequality with 
> value theory. Here's Roemer['s explanation: the bourgeoisie 
> grabbed the 
> means of production by force or acquired them by luck, and used their 
> ill-gotten resources to maintain their unfair advantages. Not 
> a whisper of 
> value, and so far as it goes a perfectly true, and indeed Marxian 
> explanation.
> 
> Some of us would say that the marxian theory
> >of
> >value is much bigger than an explanation of exploitation.
> >
> >Without being persuaded by us, do you acknowedge that such different
> >perspectives exist?
> 
> Do you mean, do I recognize that you persist in error? Yes.
> 
> jks
> 
> _________________________________________________________________
> Join the world's largest e-mail service with MSN Hotmail. 
> http://www.hotmail.com
> 

Reply via email to