[EM] Quotaless STV-PR suggestion

2013-07-03 Thread Chris Benham
On 07/02/2013 07:09 PM, Chris Benham wrote:

 I am sure this meets Droop Proportionality for Solid Coalitions.
 
Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote (3 July 2013):

Does that mean that the method reduces to largest remainders Droop when 
the voters vote for all candidates of a single party each?
 
Kristopher,
 
Yes.
 
STV meets Later-no-Harm because lower preferences only count after the
the fate (elected or definitely eliminated) of more preferred candidates has
been set.
 
My suggestion doesn't because by not truncating a voter could have their
ballot count towards the election of a non-favourite in an early round (and
a candidate that might have won anyway), and so be reduced in weight and
then not be heavy enough to elect the voter's favourite in a later round
(when it would have been if the voter had truncated).
 
Some STV fans might not like that, but I'm not fully on board with the LNHarm
religion. While I think a very strong truncation incentive is a bad thing, 
absolute
compliance with LNHarm makes it more likely that the result will (at least 
partly) be
determined by the weak, maybe ill-informed, preferences of voters who are only
really interested in their favourites (and certainly wouldn't have turned out 
if their
favourites weren't on the ballot); thereby reducing the  Social Utility of 
the full
set of winners (and maybe compromising the legitimacy of some of them).

I like IRV, but its compliance with LNHarm isn't IMO one of its best features.
 
Chris Benham
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Quotaless STV-PR suggestion

2013-07-02 Thread Chris Benham
I'd like to propose an STV-like PR method that does without a quota.

Here is the procedure for filling 3 seats:
 
*Voters rank from the top however many candidates they wish.
 
To fill the first seat, one-at-time 'eliminate' the candidate highest-ranked
(among remaining candidates) on the fewest ballots until 4 candidates
remain. The candidate A that is then top-ranked on the highest number of
ballots is elected.
 
A is dropped from the ballots and the 'eliminated' candidates are restored.
Ballots that contributed to A's winning tally are now given a weight of 2 and
all the other ballots a weight of 3.
 
To fill the second seat, one-at-a-time 'eliminate' the candidate that is 
highest 
ranked on the smallest total weight of ballots until 3 candidates remain.
The candidate B that is then highest ranked on the greatest total weight of
ballots is elected.
 
B is  dropped from the ballots and previously 'eliminated' candidates are 
restored.
Ballots that contributed to both A's  and B's winning tallies are given a 
weight of 1.
Ballots that contributed to the winning tally of a single candidate (A or B) 
are given
a weight of 2.  All the other ballots are given a weight of 3.
 
To fill the final seat, one-at-a-time eliminate the candidate that is highest 
ranked 
on the smallest total weight of ballots until 2 remain. The candidate C that is 
then
highest ranked on the greatest total weight of ballots is elected.*
 
So initially each ballot is given a weight that is equal to the number of seats 
to be filled, and then they reduce in weight by 1 for each candidate they've 
helped elect.
 
The number of candidates the field is reduced to in each round is equal to the 
numbers of seats not-yet-filled plus 1.
 
I am sure this meets Droop Proportionality for Solid Coalitions. 
 
At least some versions of STV-PR  have the problem that adding or removing
a few ballots that vote for nobody (say just plump for some X that is ignored
or voted no higher than equal-bottom on all the other ballots) can change at
least one of the winners by changing the size of the quota.

It is much simpler than Meek to explain and operate, but seems (from some 
examples I've seen) to give Meek-like results.
 
Chris Benham
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Preferential voting system where a candidate may win multiple seats

2013-07-01 Thread Chris Benham
Kristopher Munsterhjelm wrote (30 June 2013):

Would you suggest that the elimination ordering only be calculated based 
on the votes of those who currently don't get any representation?
 
No, because that is only provisional. You'd have to go back to using quotas
for that to be maybe ok. So votes tied up in the quotas of definitely elected
candidates have no other say in who is elected or eliminated.
 
Chris Benham
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Preferential voting system where a candidate may win multiple seats

2013-06-29 Thread Chris Benham
 
Kristofer Munsterhjelm  wrote (29 June 2013):
 
The combined method would go like this:

1. Run the ballots through RP (or Schulze, etc). Reverse the outcome ordering 
(or the ballots; these systems are reversal symmetric so it doesn't matter). 
Call the result the elimination order.
2. Distribute seats using Sainte-Laguë.
3. Call parties that receive no seats unrepresented. If there are 
unrepresented parties, remove the unrepresented party that is listed first in 
the elimination order.
4. Go to 2 until no party is unrepresented.

This should help preserve parties that are popular as second preferences but 
not as first preferences, because the elimination order will remove parties 
that hide the second preferences before it removes the party 
that is being hidden, thus letting the second-preference party grow in support 
before it is at risk of being eliminated.

Note that this doesn't solve the small-council problem. If we have:

46: L  C  R
44: R  C  L
10: C  R  L

1 seat,

then the first seat goes to L just like in Plurality. The elimination order 
never enters the picture.
 
Kristopher,
I don't see this. Your elimination order is obviously L, R,C.  R and C are 
unrepresented so we eliminate R.
 
Then we have
46: L 
54: C 

Then we redistribute the seat to C and then eliminate L and confirm the final 
redistribution.
 
But I'm not on board with the spirit of this method, because it seems to give a 
say to voters who are efficiently represented a say in which party/candidate 
will represent other voters.
 
Chris Benham
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] MAV on electowiki

2013-06-28 Thread Chris Benham
Jameson,
 
...But I don't think it's realistic...
 
I don't think any of the multiple majorities scenarios are very realistic. 
Irrespective of how they are resolved,
all voters who regard one or more of the viable candidates as unacceptable will 
have a strong incentive to top-rate all the candidates they regard as 
acceptable, out of fear that an unacceptable candidate gets a majority before 
their vote can help all the acceptable ones.
 
I still say that your suggestion only increases that incentive (even though 
maybe more psychologically than likely to cause extra actual post-election 
regret).
 
Forget about using the mechanism for resolving the (probably very rare) 
multiple-majorities scenario to try to gain some whiff of later-no-harm.
 
BTW, the Majority Choice Approval Bucklin-like method using ratings (or 
grading) ballots, simply elected the candidate whose majority tally was the 
biggest. I also prefer that to your suggestion. It and yours are simpler to 
count than the Mike Ossipoff idea I support.
 
I'm very glad to hear you think IBIFA is a great method.
I'll stop quibbling about how you classify it.
 
Condorcet is too complex.
 
Does that mean that you don't care that it fails FBC?Condorcet//Approval is 
pretty simple (and IMO quite good).

Am I right in assuming that you only like methods that meet FBC or Condorcet 
and maybe Mono-raise? And/or are biased towards electing centrists?  And for 
some or all of these reasons you don't like IRV?

Chris Benham
 

Jameson Quinn wrote (27 June 2013):

2013/6/27 Chris Benham cbenha...@yahoo.com.au

Jameson,


I don't see it...

Say on an ABCD grading ballot you give your Lesser Evil X a B, and then in the 
second round both X and  your Greater Evil Y reach the majority threshold. In 
that case you obviously might have cause to regret that you didn't give X an 
A. 

OK, I see what you're saying now.

But I don't think it's realistic. If X and Y both reach a majority at B, then 
there are some voters giving both of them a B or above. This looks a lot more 
like a chicken dilemma situation between two similar frontrunners, than like a 
situation where X versus Y is a gaping difference which justifies the use of a 
just-in-case strategy for a low-probability occurrence. Especially because, in 
a chicken dilemma situation, multiple majorities would tend to slide down 
towards the second-to-bottom rating, not up at the second-to-top one. 


That is why your suggestion makes it (even) less safe to not simply give all 
the acceptable candidates an A. 

I think that's [IBIFA] a great method, but I would classify it as improved 
Condorcet rather than Bucklin-like.

No. There isn't any pairwise component in the algorithm, and unlike the 
Improved Condorcet methods it doesn't directly aim to come as close as 
possible to meeting Condorcet without violating Favorite Betrayal. 

There is no pairwise component in the narrowest sense, but it still is only 
summable at (R-1)*(N²), which is actually worse than a regular Condorcet method.

Again, I think this method would deliver excellent results, and I see why it is 
in certain ways akin to a Bucklin or median method. But its quasi-pairwise 
counting complexity still makes me see it as more similar to improved Condorcet 
methods than to Bucklin ones. 



But another method I support is in that category, TTPBA//TR.  Mike Ossipoff  
promoted it as Improved Condorcet, Top  (or ICT). 

http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2012-January/029577.html
 


Right, there's a lot of good methods out there. Any of these would satisfy me 
as more resistant to strategy than either Condorcet or Score. And those two in 
turn are quite satisfactory as being at least as good as approval with more 
expressivity, and approval is satisfactory as being a giant and strict 
improvement over plurality. Great. 

And I like to talk about the relative merits of each proposal here on the list.

But if we talk like this in front of non-mathematical voters, we'll only turn 
them off. We need simple proposals. Approval is step one; most of us agree on 
that. But some voters, like Bruce Gilson, will never be satisfied with approval 
because it doesn't feel expressive enough.  

So I think it's worth having a second option to offer. To me, pitching Score 
feels dishonest: Look at this great system! Amazing great things it can do! 
(But watch out, if you vote other than approval-style, you'll probably regret 
it.) Condorcet is too complex. I want a simple, good system. MAV would fit the 
bill. If you have another proposal that would, then the way to get me onto your 
side is to demonstrate that it has more supporters than just you. That goes for 
you, Chris, and also for you, Abd. 

Jameson
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Preferential voting system where a candidate may win multiple seats

2013-06-28 Thread Chris Benham
Vidar Wahlberg wrote (28 June 2013):

I'm sticking to quota election because I don't fully grasp how to apply other 
methods (Sainte-Laguë, for instance) to determine when to start excluding 
parties.
 
Vidar,
Here is a hopefully clearer rewording of my suggestion:

 
*Use the best formula for apportioning seats in List PR 
(based on first preference votes) to provisionally apportion the seats. If 
this apportionment gives every party at least one seat, confirm this 
apportionment as final. 

Otherwise, eliminate the party voted top on the fewest ballots and transfer 
that party's second-preference votes IRV-style.

Based on the updated tallies (that include votes transferred from the 
eliminated party) again make a provisional apportionment. If that apportionment 
gives every uneliminated party at least one seat, then confirm it as final.

Otherwise, again eliminate the party with the smallest vote tally (that might 
include votes from the already eliminated candidate) and again transfer votes 
IRV-style
to uneliminated parties.

Keep repeating this process until an apportionment is confirmed as final (when 
every uneliminated party has at least one seat).*

I hope that is now clear.

Chris Benham
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Preferential voting system where a candidate may win multiple seats

2013-06-27 Thread Chris Benham
 Vidar,

I'm a bit confused about the details of the method you say is used in Norway. 
You write that voters may rank parties in a preferred order instead of only 
being able to vote for a single party. but further down you refer to the one 
person, one vote system.

Since you are not attempting to do anything with surpluses, I don't see any 
point in using a quota at all.
I suggest instead simply:

*Use the best formula for apportioning seats in List PR 
(based on first preference votes).
If every list/party has at least one seat, finish.

Otherwise, eliminate the party voted top on the fewest ballots and promote the 
next most preferred uneliminated candidate on those ballots to top. (In other 
words transfer the vote, Alternative Vote/IRV style).

Based on the updated tallies (that include votes transferred from eliminated 
parties) repeat until the final apportionment leaves no party without a seat.*

I think some free-riding incentive in PR is unavoidable.

Not using a quota and distributing surpluses might reduce proportionality a bit 
among sincere coalitions, but doing so allows parties (whose voters only care 
about their favourites and are happy to take how-to-vote advice from them) 
doing cynical preference-swap deals, motivated by nothing but increasing the 
chance that they will get an extra seat (by having the biggest surplus fraction 
of a quota).

I hope that helps.

Chris Benham


Vidar Wahlberg wrote (26 June 2013):

Greetings!

I'm new here, I'm not a mathematician and merely a layman on the subject of 
voting methods so please grant me some leeway, but do feel free to correct any 
misconceptions I may have.

Briefly about my goals:
I'm trying to find a better alternative to the voting system used in Norway 
(party-list PR, counting votes using a modified Sainte-Laguë method where first 
divisor is 1.4 instead of 1), where you still vote for parties rather than 
persons and may rank parties in a preferred
order instead of only being able to vote for a single party. A party may win 
multiple seats in each
 district.
The short answer to why not vote directly for persons? would be that in 
Norway there's more focus on the goals of a party rather than the goal of its 
politicians, and some may argue that the extra abstraction layer is a good 
thing, as well as I'd like an alternative that won't be
completely alien to the common people. I'm hoping that any discussion that may 
arise won't focus on this aspect, though.
As of why I'm interested in this then that's because I'm arguing for a 
preferential election rather than the one person one vote system which I 
believe is leading us towards a two/three party system, and I need to know 
(better) what options are out there.

So far I've not been able to find much information on preferential voting 
system where you vote for a party rather than a person. If anyone have more 
insight and can guide me to more literature I would appreciate
it.

And here's the part where
 I hope you'll be gentle:
I tinkered a bit on my own. Where as I am a fan of Ranked Pairs and Beatpath, I 
find those difficult to explain to someone with no insight in voting systems, 
and neither could I figure out how to apply RP in a
way where a candidate can win multiple seats.
The basics behind PR-STV on the other hand are fairly easy to explain, and I 
did manage to implement a way of counting votes to candidates which can win 
multiple seats based on the ideas behind STV, but I'm no expert on voting 
methods and would like to hear your thoughts.

This is the general approach:
1. Calculate quota (Droop): votes / (seats + 1) + 1
2. Tally votes, assign seats to candidates with enough votes to exceed the 
quota [1]: candidate.seats = candidate.votes / quota
3. Calculate new vote weight:
   vote.weight = vote.weight - candidate.seats * quota / candidate.votes
4. Exclude candidate with
 least votes and redistribute those votes [2]
5. Repeat step 2-4 until all but one candidate has been excluded (which gets 
the final seat)

[1]: Since a candidate is not excluded from further seat allocations upon 
reaching the quota the surplus votes are not redistributed. I do not know which 
adverse effects this may have that are not present in STV
where candidates are excluded upon reaching the quota.
[2]: It troubles me to decide which candidate that should be considered to have 
the fewer votes. If I choose the one with fewest first preference votes, then I 
may exclude a candidate that is very popular as
a second choice, while a candidate that is popular by a few and despised by 
many may stay longer in the election. Since votes to elected candidates are not 
distributed to secondary preference then this issue
is likely elevated. I'm contemplating on rather excluding the candidate that is 
least
 common on any ballot, regardless of rank, but I'm not certain on the 
implications this would cause.

Since a candidate may win multiple seats, it should be more difficult to use 
Hylland free

[EM] MAV on electowiki

2013-06-27 Thread Chris Benham
Jameson,


I don't see it...

Say on an ABCD grading ballot you give your Lesser Evil X a B, and then in the 
second round both X and  your Greater Evil Y reach the majority threshold. In 
that case you obviously might have cause to regret that you didn't give X an A.

That is why your suggestion makes it (even) less safe to not simply give all 
the acceptable candidates an A.

I think that's [IBIFA] a great method, but I would classify it as improved 
Condorcet rather than Bucklin-like.

No. There isn't any pairwise component in the algorithm, and unlike the 
Improved Condorcet methods it doesn't directly aim to come as close as 
possible to meeting Condorcet without violating Favorite Betrayal.

But another method I support is in that category, TTPBA//TR.  Mike Ossipoff  
promoted it as Improved Condorcet, Top  (or ICT).

http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2012-January/029577.html

Chris Benham


Jameson Quinn wrote (27 June 2013):

2013/6/26 Chris Benham cbenha...@yahoo.com.au

 Jameson,
  
 I don't like this version at all. These methods all have the problem that the 
 voters have a strong incentive to just submit approval ballots, i.e. only use 
 the top and bottom grades.

You are right... if they believe that all other voters will act the same way. 
But if experience has shown that there are enough honest voters so that 
winning medians¹ tend to be in a given range, then it is safe to vote 
expressively outside that range. 

¹ Actually, as long as your vote for your preferred frontrunner is above the 
second-place median, and your vote for your less-preferred frontrunner is below 
the first-place median, your vote is strategically optimal.
  
 Your suggested way of determining a winner among candidates who first get a 
 majority in the same round only makes that incentive a bit stronger still.

I don't see it. The MAV completion method is as close to later-no-harm as is 
possible in a Bucklin system; which tends to balance out the later-no-help. I 
think you're the one who's pointed out before that passing one and failing the 
other is usually worse than failing both; by the same token, if one is passed 
by all Bucklin systems, then the Bucklin system which fails the other by the 
least is the best. 

  
 I agree with a Mike Ossipoff suggestion, that we elect the member of that set 
 of candidates with the most above-bottom votes.

That completion is fine. My larger point is that it's silly to fight about 
these issues. We should settle on one Bucklin proposal and stick to it. I 
currently believe that MAV is most viable in that sense, but I'd be happy if 
you got enough support for the Ossipoff suggestion to convince me otherwise. 

  
 Also, given the strong truncation incentive, I think 5 grades is one too 
 many. In my opinion 4 grades would be adequately expressive.

I personally slightly prefer 5 grades. It increases the probability that a 
voter who wants to be strategic and confidently knows the expected range of 
possible winning (and second-place) medians, will have room to make 
purely-expressive distinctions at the top and/or bottom of the ballot. In other 
words, if you know that the winner always gets a C, then it is strategically 
safe to make honest distinctions between A/B or between D/F. 

But that's a slight preference. If demonstrate that your position has more 
support among the active posters here, I'd join with you for the sake of unity.

 My favourite Bucklin-like method is Irrelevant-Ballot Independent 
 Fallback-Approval (aka IBFA) that I introduced in May 2010.
  
 http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2010-May/026479.html
  

I think that's a great method, but I would classify it as improved Condorcet 
rather than Bucklin-like. I think it would be productive to do the same work 
for the improved Condorcet systems that I'm trying to do with Bucklin: that is, 
to settle on a single simple proposal that people can agree is among the better 
options (even if they can't agree it's best), and find a simple descriptive 
name for that proposal. I expect IBIFA would be a strong contender in that 
process. It's possible that in the future, Bucklin and Improved Condorcet 
advocates could agree to join forces, but I suspect it's premature for that at 
the moment. 

If you disagree with the above, I'd be interested to hear how you see it.

Jameson
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Preferential voting system where a candidate may win multiple seats

2013-06-27 Thread Chris Benham
Vidar wrote:
If I'm not to use a quota, but rather something like Sainte-Laguë as it's done 
today, how would I know when to start excluding the smaller parties?
 
When one (or more) of them doesn't have a seat according to the initial (trial) 
apportionment.
 
*Use the best formula for apportioning seats in List PR 
(based on first preference votes).
If every list/party has at least one seat, finish.

Otherwise, eliminate the party voted top on the fewest ballots and promote the 
next most preferred uneliminated candidate on those ballots to top. (In other 
words transfer the vote, Alternative Vote/IRV style).

Based on the updated tallies (that include votes transferred from eliminated 
parties) repeat until the final apportionment leaves no party without a seat.*

As for eliminating the party voted top on fewest ballots, that does seem to 
have a weakness I'm trying to mend. For example, take the following votes:

7 A,B,E,C,D
9 C,B,D,E,A
6 B,D,E,A,C

Here B would be eliminated first, even though B is popular among all these 
voters, where as A and C are popular among fewer voters. I believe Ranked Pairs 
 Beatpath would rank B above A  C in this scenario.
This is why I'm contemplating on rather eliminating the candidates that are 
least represented on the ballots regardless of rank, and rather fall back to 
eliminate the candidate with least first preference votes if
there are multiple candidates least represented on ballots. I'm not entirely 
certain of the implications of such a change, though. And for it to have any 
effect, you would have to limit the amount of preferences instead of listing 
all candidates as I did in the example above.

I think it is desirable that voters are free to rank as many candidates as they 
wish. My suggestion is simpler and meets the Later-no-Harm criterion. 

The problem you allude to I am sure would affect very few seats. 

Chris Benham
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] MAV on electowiki

2013-06-26 Thread Chris Benham
Jameson,
 
I don't like this version at all. These methods all have the problem that the 
voters have a strong incentive to just submit approval ballots, i.e. only use 
the top and bottom grades.
 
Your suggested way of determining a winner among candidates who first get a 
majority in the same round only makes that incentive a bit stronger still.
 
I agree with a Mike Ossipoff suggestion, that we elect the member of that set 
of candidates with the most above-bottom votes.
 
Also, given the strong truncation incentive, I think 5 grades is one too many. 
In my opinion 4 grades would be adequately expressive.

My favourite Bucklin-like method is Irrelevant-Ballot Independent 
Fallback-Approval (aka IBFA) that I introduced in May 2010.
 
http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2010-May/026479.html
 
A, B, C, D are probably better names for the ratings slots than the Top, 
Middle1, Middle2, Bottom in that post.

Comparing it to Bucklin, it meets Independence from Irrelevant Ballots which 
means that adding or removing a few ballots that bullet-vote for nobody 
(ignored on all the other ballots) can't change the winner.

The small price paid for this (apart from greater complexity) is that it 
fails Later-no-Help. That is mostly a benefit because it weakens the truncation 
incentive.

The other advantage of IBIFA over Bucklin is that it is far more likely to 
elect the Condorcet winner. If the winners are different then the IBIFA winner 
will always pairwise beat the Bucklin (or Majority Judgement) winner.

Chris Benham

Jameson Quinn wrote (19 June 2013):
 
Here's the current version of the article. Note the new paragraph on strategy 
at the bottom.
-

Majority Approval Voting (MAV) is a modern,
evaluativehttp://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/Evaluative version of Bucklin 
voting http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/Bucklin_voting. Voters rate each 
candidate into one of a predefined set of ratings or grades, such as the letter 
grades A, B, C, D, and F. As with any Bucklin system, first the 
top-grade (A) votes for each candidate are counted as
approvals. If one or more candidate has a majority, then the highest majority 
wins. If not, votes at next grade down (B) are added to each candidate's 
approval scores. If there are one or more candidates with a
majority, the winner is whichever of those had more votes at higher grades (the 
previous stage). If there were no majorities, then the next grade down(C) is 
added and the process repeats; and so on.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Question about the Plurality Criterion

2013-06-24 Thread Chris Benham
Ben,
 
MinMax(Margins) fails the Plurality criterion. It elects the candidate with the 
weakest pairwise loss as measured by the  difference between the two 
candidates' vote tallies.

An alternative definition is that it elects the candidate who needs the fewest 
number of extra bullet-votes to be able to pairwise-beat all the other 
candidates.
 
3:A
5:BA
6:C

CB 6-5,  BA 5-3,  AC 8-6.
 
That method elects B, but the Plurality criterion says that B can't win because 
of C. 

Given that if the B voters had truncated the winner would have been C, this is 
also a failure of the Later-no-Help criterion.
 
The method meets the Condorcet criterion and Mono-add-Top. It has been promoted 
here by Juho Laatu.
 
Chris Benham

 
 
 
Ben grant wrote (24 June 2013):
 
As I have had it explained to me, the Plurality Criterion is: If there are two 
candidates X and Y so that X has more first place votes than Y has any place 
votes, then Y shouldn't win.

Which I think means that if X has, for example, 100 votes, then B would have to 
appear on less than 100 ballots and still *win* for this criterion to be 
failed, yes?

I cannot imagine a (halfway desirable) voting system that would fail the 
Plurality Criterion - can anyone tell me the simplest one that would? Apart 
from a lame one like least votes win, I mean?
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Score Voting and Approval Voting not practically substantially different from Plurality?

2013-06-24 Thread Chris Benham
Ben Grant wrote:
 
 - Approval Voting tends to result in irrelevant approval votes being given to 
weak candidates – which is pointless, or slightly stronger (but still losing) 
candidates can once again present a spoiler effect where a person’s
least preferred choice is elected because they cast their approval only toward 
their most preferred choice, who was nowhere near supported enough to stop 
their least preferred choice.

Am I substantially wrong about any of this? Ultimately, in real and practical 
terms, it seems that done intelligently, Score Voting devolves into Approval 
Voting, and Approval Voting devolves into Plurality Voting.
 
The idea is that some voters dislike feeling strategically pressured to vote 
their sincere favourites below equal-top. With voters never needing to vote 
their sincere favourites below equal-top, previous elections become a much 
better indicator of which candidates are really weak.
 
So I don't see compliance with the Favorite Betrayal Criterion as pointless.
 
Chris Benham
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Participation Criteria and Bucklin - perhaps they *can* work together after all?

2013-06-18 Thread Chris Benham
Oops! Yes, thanks Abd.
 
I made an error. The A and B group was supposed to add up to 49, not 51. So it 
should be:
 25: AYX
24: BYX
17: CDX
17: EFX
17: GHX
 
100 ballots, Bucklin election.
 
The majority threshold is 51 and X wins in the third round. But if we add 
anywhere between 3 and 100
XY ballots then Y wins in the second round.
 
Chris Benham


 At 03:58 PM 6/17/2013, Chris Benham wrote:
Benjamin,
The criterion (criteria is the plural) you suggest is not new. It 
is called Mono-add-Top, and comes from Douglas Woodall.

It is met by IRV and MinMax(Margins) but is failed by Bucklin. In my 
opinion IRV is the best of the methods that meet it.

26: AYX
25: BYX
17: CDX
17: EFX
17: GHX

The majority threshold is 51 and X wins in the third round. But if 
we add anywhere between 3 and 100
XY ballots then Y wins in the second round.

Some error there. Total votes are 102. Majority is 52 votes. 

snip 
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Participation Criteria and Bucklin - perhaps they *can* work together after all?

2013-06-17 Thread Chris Benham
Benjamin,

The criterion (criteria is the plural) you suggest is not new. It is called 
Mono-add-Top, and comes from Douglas Woodall.

It is met by IRV and MinMax(Margins) but is failed by Bucklin. In my opinion 
IRV is the best of the methods that meet it.
 
26: AYX
25: BYX
17: CDX
17: EFX
17: GHX
 
The majority threshold is 51 and X wins in the third round. But if we add 
anywhere between 3 and 100 
XY ballots then Y wins in the second round.
 
You'll find some interesting stuff on Kevin Venzke's old page:
http://nodesiege.tripod.com/elections/
 
Notice that your version (in an earlier post) of the Plurality criterion is 
wrong.
 
Chris Benham
 
Benjamin Grant wrote (17 June 2013):
OK, let's assume that as defined, Bucklin fails Participation. 



Let me specify a new criteria, which already either has its own name that I do 
not know, or which I can call Prime Participation:



Adding one or more ballots that vote X as a highest preference should never
change the winner from X to Y



In other words, expressing a first place/greatest magnitude preference for
X, if X was already winning, cannot make X not win.



This may be another one so basic that few or maybe no real voting systems
fail it?



-Benn Grant

eFix Computer Consulting

mailto:benn at 4efix.com benn at 4efix.com

603.283.6601

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] A better 2-round method that uses approval ballots

2013-06-13 Thread Chris Benham

 
I just want to repeat a suggestion I've made here more than once.  Take my 
previous example where the Centre-Right candidate is elected due to some of the 
Left candidate's supporters using the Compromise strategy.

49: Right
28: Centre-Right (7 are sincere LeftCentre-Right)
23: Left

Centre-Right beats Right in the runoff 51-49.

But the Right supporters have an easy Push-over strategy to (from their 
perspective) rectify this.

If anywhere between 6 and *all* of them change their vote to approving both of 
Right and Left, then Left will be dragged back into the runoff with Right and 
then be beaten.

My suggested 2-round method using Approval ballots is to elect the most 
approved first-round candidate A if A is approved on more than half the 
ballots, otherwise elect the winner of a runoff between A and the candidate 
that is most approved on ballots that don't show approval for A. 

This destroys the incentive for parties to field 2 candidates, and greatly 
reduces the Push-over incentive
(to about the same as in normal plurality-ballot Top-2 Runoff).

Chris Benham
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Does Top Two Approval fail the Favorite Betrayal Criterion [?]

2013-06-08 Thread Chris Benham
Yes. 
Say there are three candidates: Right, Centre-Right and Left, and the approval 
votes cast are

49: Right
21: Centre-Right (all prefer Right to Left)
23: Left
07: Left, Centre-Right (sincere favourite is Left)
 
Approval votes: Right 49, Left 30, Centre-Right 28.

The top-2 runoff is between Right and Left and Right wins
70-30.
 
All the voters who approved Left prefer Centre-Right to Right. The 7 voters who 
approved both Left and Centre-Right can change the winner to Centre-Right by 
dumping Left (their sincere favourite) in the first round.

49: Right
28: Centre-Right 
23: Left
 
Now the top-2 runoff is between Right and Centre-Right and Centre-Right wins 
51-49.

Seven voters have succeeded with a Compromise strategy.
 
Chris Benham
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Losing Votes (ERABW)

2012-12-17 Thread Chris Benham
Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote (13 Dec 2012):

The method should provide good results and/or strategy 
resistance and then whether or not it pays attention to the top is 
secondary.

Which leads to marketing. Perhaps having the method elect most from the 
tops is a marketing advantage. However, it may come at a cost of results 
(or strategy resistance). In that case, what is better? Should one pick 
a method for marketability and try to build upon it to go further later, 
or try to make one leap instead of two?

I agree with the first sentence above, but good results can be a bit 
subjective
and some people think that paying attention to the top is part of it.

When I wrote that my suggested version of  Schulze (Losing Votes) has a feature
that might help with marketing, I wasn't admitting that anything in terms of 
results
(or strategy resisatnce) had been sacrificed for greater marketability.


With regard to strategy resistance in Condorcet methods, it seems that we have
to choose between trying to reduce Compromise incentive for voters whose main
concern is to prevent the election of their Greater Evil and trying to reduce 
defection
incentive by voters trying to get their Favourite elected versus the sincere 
CW.

The Losing Votes method I advocate goes for the latter.

Chris Benham
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Losing Votes (ERABW)

2012-12-13 Thread Chris Benham
I recently proposed  (16 Nov 2012)  the Losing Votes (Equal-Ranking 
Above-Bottom Whole)
method:

*Voters rank from the top however many candidates they wish. Equal-ranking is 
allowed.

The result is determined from a pairwise matrix. On that matrix, ballots that 
rank above bottom
any X=Y contribute one whole vote to XY and another to YX.

Ballots that truncate both X and Y  have no effect on the XY and YX entries 
in the pairwise
matrix.

With the thus created pairwise matrix, decide the winner with Schulze (Losing 
Votes).*

35 A
10 A=B
30 BC
25 C

AB 35-30 (ignoring the 10 A=B ballots unlike my proposal, according to which 
AB 45-40)
BC 40-25
CA 55-45

(This is an old example from Kevin Venke in a different discussion.)

B is pairwise beaten and positionally dominated by A and is the least 
approved (ranked above
bottom) candidate.  C is the most approved candidate and has the biggest single 
pairwise score
(55 verus A).  A has the most top rankings.

Both Winning Votes and Margins (using the Schulze or equivalent algorithm) 
elect B, the clearly
weakest candidate. Notice that electing B is another outrageous failure of 
Later-no-Help.

Losing Votes elects A.  Part of the case against electing C is that the 25 C 
truncators could be
defecting from a sincere BC coalition (and if so, shouldn't be rewarded).

Part (at least) of the case for electing C is that if the 30 BC voters are 
sincere (and detest A)
they have a strong incentive to order-reverse and maybe C has a disincentive to 
run.

But other than in effect just portraying the Margins or Winning Votes 
algorithms as in themselves
standards, there is no case for electing B.

Of the various proposed ways of weighing defeat strengths in Schulze, Losing 
Votes is the one
that elects most from the tops of the ballots.  Given that we are seeking to 
convert supporters
of FPP (and to I hope a lesser extent, IRV), I think that is a marketing 
advantage.

Chris Benham

But there is no case for electing B, other than 
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] TTR,MinMax, Losing Votes (TERW)

2012-11-25 Thread Chris Benham
Here is an example of  my suggested new FBC-complying method performing better 
than ICT 
(Improved Condorcet, Top, a name coined by Mike Ossipoff for a method I 
defined).

30: A=B
30: B
20: A
10: CA
10: DA

According to the TTR (Kevin Venzke's Tied at the Top Tule),
AB 70-30 and BA 60-40.    A C 50-10, AD 50-10,   BC 60-10, BD 60-10.

Only A and B are qualified by TTR, and ICT elects the qualified candidate with 
highest
Top ratings (we'll say these are Top-Middle-Bottom 3-slot ratings ballots, with 
default
rating being Bottom). 

TR scores:  B60,   A50,  C10,  D10.

So ICT elects B.

The first part of my new method is the same, so only A and B are qualified.

To determine the winner a different pairwise matrix is looked at to weigh 
defeats (while keeping
the same TTR direction).

So AB 70-60 and  BA 60-70  (the 30 A=B ballots each give a whole vote to 
both A and B).

A and B have no other pairwise defeats, so (weighing them by Losing Votes) 
A's MinMax score is
70 and B's is 60 so A wins.

A is rescued from the splitting of the  AB faction''s vote by C and D being 
on the ballot.

As it does here, the new method is much more likely than ICT to elect the real 
Condorcet winner.

Chris Benham


I wrote (Tues.20 Nov 2012):

I have an idea for a not-very-sinple FBC-complying method that behaves like ICT 
with 3 candidates, but better
handles more candidates and ballots with more than 3 ratings-slots or ballots 
that allow full ranking of the candidates.
 
*Voters rank from the top however many candidates they wish. Equal-top ranking 
and truncation must be allowed.
 
Use the Tied-at-the-Top Rule (invented by Kevin Venzke) to discover if any 
candidate/s pairwise beats (according
to that rule's special definition) all the others, and if so to disqualify all 
those that don't.
 
http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/Tied_at_the_top_rule
 
Then construct a pairwise matrix that is normal except that ballots that 
equal-rank at the top any X and Y contribute
a whole vote (in the X versus Y pairwise comparison) to each of X and Y.  
Ballots that equal-rank any X and Y in any
below-top position contribute (in that pairwise comparison) no vote to either.
 
The purpose of that matrix is just to determine Losing Votes scores. The 
directions of the defeats are determined by
the Tied-at-the-Top rule (according to which X and Y can pairwise defeat each 
other.
 
Elect the qualified candidate whose worse defeat (as identified by TTR and 
measured by Losing Votes with the above
equal top-ranking rule) is the weakest.*
 
I hope that inelegant waffle is at least clear.
 
Chris Benham

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Losing Votes (ERABW)

2012-11-20 Thread Chris Benham
 
 
On 16 Nov 2012 07:29:52 -0800, Chris Benham wrote:


It isn't a big deal if Ranked Pairs or River are used instead of
Schulze.  Losing Votes means that the pairwise results are weighed
purely by the number of votes on the losing side. The weakest
defeats are those with the most votes on the losing side, and of
course conversely the strongest victories are those with the
fewest votes on the losing side.

Hi Chris,

Just so I understand this correctly:

You're saying that the pairwise contest A:3  B:1 should be weighted
more strongly than C:3,000,001  D:2,999,999?  Even though only 4
people care to vote in the A vs. B contest?

Ted
-- 

Ted,
 
Yes.  
 
I'm not interested in moral arguments about this or that part of  an
algorithm.  If you don't like it, give an example with a result you don't
like.
 
Chris Benham
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Name of Weak Participation

2012-11-16 Thread Chris Benham
Mike Ossipoff wrote:
 
Weak Participation is such a natural consistency desideratum, it
probably already has a name. Maybe it's called Mono-Add-Solo-Top. If
not, that might be a good name for it. More descriptive than Weak
Participation.

Weak Participation:

Adding a ballot shouldn't cause the defeat of the candidate whom it
votes over all of the other candidates.

[end of Weak Participation definition]
 
Mono-add-Top.
 
http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/Mono-add-top_criterion
 
Chris Benham
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] 3 or more choices - Condorcet

2012-11-11 Thread Chris Benham
Ted Stern wrote (8 Nov 2012):

Hi Chris,

You discuss Winning Votes vs. Margins below.

What do you think about using the Cardinal-Weighted Pairwise array in
conjunction with the traditional Condorcet array?

In other words, either WV or Margins is used to decide whether there
is a defeat, but the CWP array is used to determine the defeat
strength, in either Ranked Pairs or Schulze.

To recap for those not familiar with the technique (due to James
Green-Armytage in 2004), a ratings ballot is used: give a score of a_i
to candidate i.  Ranks are inferred: candidate i receives one
Condorcet vote over candidate j if a_i  a_j.

Whenever that Condorcet vote is recorded into the standard A_ij array,
you also tally the difference (a_i - a_j) into the corresponding
CWP_ij location.

Ted,
Actually I talked more about Losing Votes than Winning Votes.

I can't remember all the reasons I don't like CWP, but it is far too complicated
with not enough bang for buck.  I prefer Smith//Approval (ranking), or a 
method
that Forest and I discussed a  while ago. It is a bit better (and more elegant) 
than
Smith//Approval, and nearly always gives the same winner.

Chris Benham

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] 3 or more choices - Condorcet

2012-11-08 Thread Chris Benham
Robert Bristow-Johnson wrote (1 Oct 2012):

my spin is similar.  Ranked Pairs simply says that some elections (or 
runoffs) speak more loudly than others.  those with higher margins are 
more definitive in expressing the will of the electorate than elections 
with small margins.  of course, a margin of zero is a tie and this says 
*nothing* regarding the will of the electorate, since it can go either way.

the reason i like margins over winning votes is that the margin, in vote 
count, is the product of the margin as a percent (that would be a 
measure of the decisiveness of the electorate) times the total number of 
votes (which is a measure of how important the election is).  so the 
margin in votes is the product of salience of the race times how 
decisive the decision is.

Say there are 3 candidates and the voters have the option to fully rank them,
but instead they all just choose to vote FPP-style thus:

 
49: A
48: B
03: C
 
Of course the only possible winner is A. Now say the election is held again 
(with
the same voters and candidates), and the B voters change to BC giving:


49: A
48: BC
03: C


Now to my mind this change adds strength to no candidate other than C, so the 
winner 
should either stay the same or change to C. Does anyone disagree?
 
So how do you (Robert or whoever the cap fits) justify to the A voters (and any 
fair-minded 
person not infatuated with the Margins pairwise algorithm) that the new Margins 
winner is B??
 
The pairwise comparisons: BC 48-3,  CA 51-49,  AB 49-48.

Ranked Pairs(Margins) gives the order BCA. 

I am happy with either A or C winning, but a win for C might look odd to people 
accustomed
to FPP and/or IRV.

 
*If* we insist on a Condorcet method that  uses only information contained in 
the pairwise
matrix (and so ignoring all positional or approval information) then *maybe* 
Losing Votes
is the best way to weigh the pairwise results. (So the strongest pairwise 
results are those where
the loser has the fewest votes and, put the other way, the weakest results are 
those where the
loser gets the most votes).

 
In the example Losing Votes elects A. Winning Votes elects C which I'm fine 
with, but I don't
like Winning Votes for other reasons.

Chris Benham
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Two more 3-slot FBC/ABE solutions (not)

2012-01-24 Thread Chris Benham
Jameson,
 
You're not missing anything.  You are right.  Thanks for pointing that out.

I should have thought more about those methods before suggesting them. I 
withdraw those suggestions.
 
I still stand by  APPMM as a good criterion. But the set can't be a component 
of a method algorithm that
meets the FBC.
 
Chris Benham
 



From: Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
To: C.Benham cbenha...@yahoo.com.au 
Cc: em election-meth...@electorama.com 
Sent: Wednesday, 25 January 2012 5:11 AM
Subject: Re: [EM] Two more 3-slot FBC/ABE solutions


In fact, that would seem to be a pretty strong argument that these methods 
don't meet the FBC. What am I missing?


2012/1/24 Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com

The problem with these methods is that you can't afford to vote for the 
marginal candidate whom only you have heard of, because that candidate will not 
be part of any S, and so your ballot will count against any S, even an S that 
you otherwise like.

Jameson


2012/1/24 C.Benham cbenha...@yahoo.com.au 


Following on from my recent definition of  the APPMM criterion/set, I'd like 
to propose two not bad 3-slot methods that meet the FBC..

Recall that I defined the APPMM criterion thus:


*If the number of ballots on which some set S of candidates is voted strictly 
above all the candidates outside S is greater than the number of ballots on 
which any outside-S candidate is voted strictly above any member of S, then 
the winner must come from S.* 


The APPMM set is the set of candidates not disqualified by the APPMM 
criterion.

APMM//TR:

* Voters fill out 3-slot ratings ballots. Default rating is Bottom 
(signifying least preferred and not approved.) The other slots are Top 
(signifying most preferred) and Middle.

From the set of candidates not disqualified by the APPMM criterion, elect the 
one with the most Top ratings.*


APMM//CR:

* Voters fill out 3-slot ratings ballots. Default rating is Bottom 
(signifying least preferred and not approved.) The other slots are Top 
(signifying most preferred) and Middle.

From the set of candidates not disqualified by the APPMM criterion, elect the 
one with the highest  Top minus Bottom ratings score.*


So far I can't see that these are technically any better  than my earlier 
suggestion of  TTPBA//TR, and unlike that method they fail the Tied at the 
Top Pairwise Beats All criterion.

But like that method they meet the Plurality and  Mono-add-Plump criteria, 
and also have no problem with Kevin's bad MMPO example.

I'm happy for APMM//CR to be also called APMM//Range. This method is more 
Condorcetish than APMM//TR, for example:

49: CB
27: AB
24: BA

BA 73-27,  BC 51-49,  AC 51-49.

APMM//TR elects A, while  APMM//CR elects B (like TTPBA//TR).

I am sure that APMM//TR has no defection incentive in the Approval Bad 
Example, and the other method also does in the example normally given.

Of course some other points-score scheme (perhaps giving greater weight to to 
Top Ratings) is possible.

Chris Benham





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Approval vs. IRV (hopefully tidier re-send)

2011-11-28 Thread Chris Benham
Matt Welland wrote (26 Nov 2011): 


Also, do folks generally see approval as better than or worse than IRV? 

To me Approval seems to solve the spoiler problem without introducing 
any unstable weirdness and it is much simpler and cheaper to do than 
IRV. 


If we are talking about the classic version of IRV known as the  Alternative 
Vote 
in the UK and  Optional Preferential Voting in Australia, then I see IRV on 
balance 
as being better than Approval. 

The version of IRV I'm referring to: 

*Voters strictly rank from the top however many or few candidates they wish. 
Until one candidate remains, one-at-a time eliminate eliminate the candidate 
that 
(among remaining candidates) is highest-ranked on the fewest ballots.* 

The unstable weirdness of  Approval is in the strategy games among the rival 
factions of voters, rather than anything visible in the method's algorithm. 

Approval is more vulnerable to disinformation campaigns. Suppose that those 
with plenty of money and control of the mass media know from their polling 
that the likely outcome of an upcoming election is  A 52%, B 48% and they 
much prefer B. 

In Approval they can sponsor and promote a third candidate C, one that the A 
supporters find much worse than B, and then publish false polls that give C 
some 
real chance of winning. If they can frighten/bluff some of A's supporters into 
approving 
B (as well as A) their strategy can succeed. 

47: A 
05: AB (sincere is AB) 
41: B 
07: BC 

Approvals: B53,   A52,  C7 

Approval is certainly the bang for buck champion, and voters never have any 
incentive to 
vote their sincere favourites below equal-top. But to me the ballots are 
insufficiently expressive 
by comparison with the strict ranking ballots used by IRV. 

IRV has some Compromise incentive, but it is vastly less than in FPP.  
Supposing we assume 
that there are 3 candidates and that you the voter want (maybe for some 
emotional or long-term 
reason)  to vote your sincere favourite F top even if  you think (or know) 
that F can't win 
provided you don't thereby pay too high a strategic penalty, i.e. that the 
chance is small that by 
doing that you will lose some (from your perspective positive) effect you might 
otherwise have 
had on the result. 

In FPP, to be persuaded to Compromise (i.e.vote for your compromise might win 
candidate C 
instead of your sincere favourite F) you only have to be convinced that F won't 
be one of the top two 
first-preference place getters. 

In IRV if you are convinced of that you have no compelling reason to compromise 
because you 
can expect F to be eliminated and your vote transferred to C. No, to have a 
good reason to compromise 
you must be convinced that F *will* be one of the top 2 (thanks to your vote) 
displacing C, but will 
nonetheless lose when C would have won if  you'd top-voted C. 

In my opinion IRV is one of the reasonable algorithms to use with ranked 
ballots, and the best for those 
who prefer things like Later-no-Harm and Invulnerability to Burial to either 
the Condorcet or  FBC 
criteria. 

Chris Benham 
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] An ABE solution

2011-11-24 Thread Chris Benham
Forest,

In reference to your new Condorcet method suggestion (pasted at the bottom), 
which elects an
uncovered candidate and if there is none one-at-time disqualifies the Range 
loser until a remaining
candidate X covers all the other remaining candidates and then elects X, you 
wrote:

Indeed, the three slot case does appear to satisfy the FBC...

No. Here is my example, based on that Kevin Venke proof you didn't like.
 
Say sincere is
 
3: BA
3: A=C
3: B=C
2: AC
2: BA
2: CB
1: C
 
Range (0,1,2) scores: C19,   B17,   A12.

CB 8-5,   BA 10-5,   AC  7-6.
 
C wins.
 
Now we focus on the 3 BA preferrers. Suppose (believing the method meets the 
FBC)
they vote B=A.
 3: B=A  (sincere is BA)
3: A=C
3: B=C
2: AC
2: BA
2: CB
1: C
 Range (0,1,2) scores: C19,   B17,   A15.


CB 8-5,   BA 7-5,   AC  7-6.
 
C still wins.
 
Now suppose they instead rate their sincere favourite Middle:
 
3: AB  (sincere is BA)
 
3: A=C
3: B=C
2: AC
2: BA
2: CB
1: C
 Range (0,1,2) scores: C19,   A15,   B12.

AB  8-7,   AC  7-6,    CB  8-5
 
Now those 3 voters get a result they prefer, the election of their compromise
candidate A. Since it is clear they couldn't have got a result for themselves as
good or better by voting BA or  BC or B this is a failure of the FBC.
 
 
Chris Benham 




From: fsimm...@pcc.edu fsimm...@pcc.edu
Sent: Wednesday, 23 November 2011 9:01 AM
Subject: Re: An ABE solution

voters to avoid the middle slot.  Then the method reduces to Approval, which 
does satisfy the FBC.
  
The FBC doesn't stipulate that all the voters use optimal  strategy, so that 
isn't relavent.
 
http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/FBC
  
http://nodesiege.tripod.com/elections/#critfbc
 
Chris  Benham

Forest Simmons wrote (17 Nov 2011):

Here’s my current favorite deterministic proposal: Ballots are Range Style, say 
three slot for simplicity.

When the ballots are collected, the pairwise win/loss/tie relations are
determined among the candidates.

The covering relations are also determined.  Candidate X covers candidate Y if X
beats Y as well as every candidate that Y beats.  In other words row X of the
win/loss/tie matrix dominates row Y.

Then starting with the candidates with the lowest Range scores, they are
disqualified one by one until one of the remaining candidates X covers any other
candidates that might remain.  Elect X.


You are right that although the method is defined for any number of slots, I 
suggested three slots as 
most practical.

So my example of two slots was only to disprove the statement the assertion 
that the method cannot be 
FBC compliant, since it is obviously compliant in that case.  

Furthermore something must be wrong with the quoted proof (of the 
incompatibility of the FBC and the 
CC) because the winner of the two slot case can be found entirely on the basis 
of the pairwise matrix.  
The other escape hatch is to say that two slots are not enough to satisfy 
anything but the voted ballots 
version of the Condorcet Criterion.  But this applies equally well to the three 
slot case.

Either way the cited therorem is not good enough to rule out compliance with 
the FBC by this new 
method.

Indeed, the three slot case does appear to satisfy the FBC as well.  It is an 
open question.  I did not 
assert that it does.  But I did say that IF it is strategically equivalent to 
Approval (as Range is, for 
example) then for practical purposes it satisfies the FBC.  Perhaps not the 
letter of the law, but the 
spirit of the law.  Indeed, in a non-stratetgical environment nobody worries 
about the FBC, i.e. only 
strategic voters will betray their favorite. If optimal strategy is approval 
strategy, and approval strategy 
requires you to top rate your favorite, then why would you do otherwise?

Forest

- Original Message -
From: Chris Benham 

Forest,
 
When the range ballots have only two slots, the method is  simply Approval, 
which does satisfy the 
FBC.
  
When you introduced the method you suggested that 3-slot ballots be used for 
simplicity.
 I thought you might be open to say 4-6 slots, but a complicated algorithm on 
2-slot ballots
 that is equivalent to Approval ??
  
Now consider the case of range ballots with three slots: and  suppose that 
optimal strategy requires the  
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] An ABE solution

2011-11-24 Thread Chris Benham


Jameson,
 
Your range scores are a little bit wrong,..

I've re-checked them and I don't see how. I gave each candidate 2 points for a 
top-rating, 1 for a middle-rating
and zero for a bottom rating (or truncation).
 
So in the initial sincere scenario for example C has 9 top-ratings and 1 
middle-rating to make a score of  19,
B has 8 top-ratings and 1 middle-rating to make a score of  17, and A has 5 
top-ratings and 2 middle-ratings
to make a score of 12.

Chris  Benham
 


From: Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
Sent: Friday, 25 November 2011 5:39 AM
Subject: Re: An ABE solution


Chris: 

Your range scores are a little bit wrong, so you have to add half a B vote for 
the example to work (or double all factions and add one B vote if you 
discriminate against fractional people), but yes, this is at heart a valid 
example where the method fails FBC. 

Note that in my tendentious terminology this is only a defensive failure, 
that is, it starts from a position of a sincere condorcet cycle, which I 
believe will be rare enough in real elections to be discountable. In 
particular, this failure does not result in a stable 
two-party-lesser-evil-strategy self-reinforcing equilibrium. 

Jameson


2011/11/24 Chris Benham cbenha...@yahoo.com.au

Forest,

In reference to your new Condorcet method suggestion (pasted at the bottom), 
which elects an
uncovered candidate and if there is none one-at-time disqualifies the Range 
loser until a remaining
candidate X covers all the other remaining candidates and then elects X, you 
wrote:

Indeed, the three slot case does appear to satisfy the FBC...

No. Here is my example, based on that Kevin Venke proof you didn't like.
 
Say sincere is
 
3: BA
3: A=C
3: B=C
2: AC
2: BA
2: CB
1: C
 
Range (0,1,2) scores: C19,   B17,   A12.

CB 8-5,   BA 10-5,   AC  7-6.
 
C wins.
 
Now we focus on the 3 BA preferrers. Suppose (believing the method meets the 
FBC)
they vote B=A.
 3: B=A  (sincere is BA)
3: A=C
3: B=C
2: AC
2: BA
2: CB
1: C
 Range (0,1,2) scores: C19,   B17,   A15.


CB 8-5,   BA 7-5,   AC  7-6.
 
C still wins.
 
Now suppose they instead rate their sincere favourite Middle:
 
3: AB  (sincere is BA)
3: A=C
3: B=C
2: AC
2: BA
2: CB
1: C
 Range (0,1,2) scores: C19,   A15,   B12.

AB  8-7,   AC  7-6,    CB  8-5
 
Now those 3 voters get a result they prefer, the election of their compromise
candidate A. Since it is clear they couldn't have got a result for themselves 
as
good or better by voting  BA or B=A or B or BC or B=C this is a failure
of the FBC.
 
Chris Benham
 
 


From: fsimm...@pcc.edu fsimm...@pcc.edu
Sent: Wednesday, 23 November 2011 9:01 AM 

Subject: Re: An ABE solution


You are right that although the method is defined for any number of slots, I 
suggested three slots as 
most practical.

So my example of two slots was only to disprove the statement the assertion 
that the method cannot be 
FBC compliant, since it is obviously compliant in that case.  

Furthermore something must be wrong with the quoted proof (of the 
incompatibility of the FBC and the 
CC) because the winner of the two slot case can be found entirely on the basis 
of the pairwise matrix.  
The other escape hatch is to say that two slots are not enough to satisfy 
anything but the voted ballots 
version of the Condorcet Criterion.  But this applies equally well to the 
three slot case.

Either way the cited therorem is not good enough to rule out compliance with 
the FBC by this new 
method.

Indeed, the three slot case does appear to satisfy the FBC as well.  It is an 
open question.  I did not 
assert that it does.  But I did say that IF it is strategically equivalent 
to Approval (as Range is, for 
example) then for practical purposes it satisfies the FBC.  Perhaps not the 
letter of the law, but the 
spirit of the law.  Indeed, in a non-stratetgical environment nobody worries 
about the FBC, i.e. only 
strategic voters will betray their favorite. If optimal strategy is approval 
strategy, and approval strategy 
requires you to top rate your favorite, then why would you do otherwise?

Forest

- Original Message -
From: Chris Benham 

Forest,
 
When the range ballots have only two slots, the method is  simply Approval, 
which does satisfy the 
FBC.
  
When you introduced the method you suggested that 3-slot ballots be used for 
simplicity.
 I thought you might be open to say 4-6 slots, but a complicated algorithm on 
2-slot ballots
 that is equivalent to Approval ??
  
Now consider the case of range ballots with three slots: and  suppose that 
optimal strategy requires the  
voters to avoid the middle slot.  Then the method reduces to Approval, which 
does satisfy the FBC.
  
The FBC doesn't stipulate that all the voters use optimal  strategy, so that 
isn't relavent.
 
http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/FBC
  
http://nodesiege.tripod.com/elections/#critfbc
 
Chris  Benham

Forest Simmons wrote (17 Nov 2011):


Here’s my current favorite

Re: [EM] An ABE solution

2011-11-21 Thread Chris Benham
Forest,
 
When the range ballots have only two slots, the method is simply Approval, 
which does satisfy the 
FBC.
 
When you introduced the method you suggested that 3-slot ballots be used for 
simplicity.
I thought you might be open to say 4-6 slots, but a complicated algorithm on 
2-slot ballots
that is equivalent to Approval ??
 
Now consider the case of range ballots with three slots: and suppose that 
optimal strategy requires the 
voters to avoid the middle slot.  Then the method reduces to Approval, which 
does satisfy the FBC.
 
The FBC doesn't stipulate that all the voters use optimal strategy, so that 
isn't relavent.

http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/FBC
 
http://nodesiege.tripod.com/elections/#critfbc

Chris  Benham
 
 
 
 



From: fsimm...@pcc.edu fsimm...@pcc.edu
To: C.Benham cbenha...@yahoo.com.au 
Cc: em election-meth...@electorama.com; MIKE OSSIPOFF nkk...@hotmail.com 
Sent: Tuesday, 22 November 2011 11:11 AM
Subject: Re: An ABE solution



From: C.Benham 

 
 Forest Simmons, responding to questions from Mike Ossipff, wrote 
 (19 Nov 
 2011):
 
   4. How does it do by FBC? And by the criteria that bother some
   people here about MMPO (Kevin's MMPO bad-example) and MDDTR 
  (Mono-Add-Plump)?
 
  I think it satisfies the FBC.
 
 Forest's definition of the method being asked about:
 
  Here’s my current favorite deterministic proposal: Ballots are 
 Range 
  Style, say three slot for simplicity.
 
  When the ballots are collected, the pairwise win/loss/tie 
 relations are
  determined among the candidates.
 
  The covering relations are also determined. Candidate X covers 
  candidate Y if X
  beats Y as well as every candidate that Y beats. In other 
 words row X 
  of the
  win/loss/tie matrix dominates row Y.
 
  Then starting with the candidates with the lowest Range 
 scores, they are
  disqualified one by one until one of the remaining candidates 
 X covers 
  any other
  candidates that might remain. Elect X.
 
 
 Forest,
 
 Doesn't this method meet the Condorcet criterion? Compliance 
 with 
 Condorcet is incompatible with FBC, so
 why do you think it satisfies FBC?

When the range ballots have only two slots, the method is simply Approval, 
which does satisfy the 
FBC.  Does Approval satisfy the Condorcet Criterion?  I would say no, but it 
does satisfy the votes only 
Condorcet Criterion. which means that the Approval winner X pairwise beats 
every other candidate Y 
according to the ballots, i.e. X is rated above Y on more ballots than Y is 
rated above X.

Now consider the case of range ballots with three slots: and suppose that 
optimal strategy requires the 
voters to avoid the middle slot.  Then the method reduces to Approval, which 
does satisfy the FBC.


 
 
 http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-
 electorama.com/2005-June/016410.html
 
  Hello,
 
  This is an attempt to demonstrate that Condorcet and FBC are 
 incompatible. I modified Woodall's proof that Condorcet and 
 LNHarm are incompatible.
  (Douglas R. Woodall, Monotonicity of single-seat preferential 
  election rules,
  Discrete Applied Mathematics 77 (1997), pages 86 and 87.)
 
  I've suggested before that in order to satisfy FBC, it must be 
 the case
  that increasing the votes for A over B in the pairwise matrix 
 can never
  increase the probability that the winner comes from {a,b}; 
 that is, it 
  must
  not move the win from some other candidate C to A. This is 
 necessary 
  because
  if sometimes it were possible to move the win from C to A by 
 increasing v[a,b], the voter with the preference order BAC 
 would have incentive to
  reverse B and A in his ranking (and equal ranking would be 
 inadequate).
  I won't presently try to argue that this requirement can't be 
 avoided 
  somehow.
  I'm sure it can't be avoided when the method's result is 
 determined solely
  from the pairwise matrix.

Note that in our method the Cardinal Ratings order (i.e. Range Order) is needed 
in addition to the 
pairwise matrix; the covering information comes from the pairwise matrix, but 
candidates are dropped 
from the bottom of the range order.

In the two slot case can the approval order be determined from the pairwise 
matrix?  If so, then this is a 
counterexample to the last quoted sentence above in the attempted proof of the 
incompatibility of the CC 
and the FBC.

Forest
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] IRV variants

2011-11-14 Thread Chris Benham
Forest,

the IRV- Condorcet you 
describe here is a simpler solution, as long as you allow equal rankings, and 
count them as whole (as 
opposed to fractional):
 
I am strongly opposed to allowing  equal ranking (except for truncation) in IRV 
or  IRV-like Condorcet
methods.  As I've explained more than once on EM, that just makes Push-over 
strategising much easier.
 
And in this respect the whole vote version is much worse than the 
fractional version. If you are confident
that your favourite will make the final runoff and that your favourite will 
have a pairwise win versus some
turkey with you being merely neutral (not supporting the turkey as you'd have 
to do in regular IRV) then
you should vote the turkey equal-top with your favourite.
 
You are still giving a whole vote to help your favourite make the top 2, so on 
the whole the strategy is 
much less risky and easier to carry out than with regular IRV and  to a lesser 
extent the Fractional version.
 
Chris



From: fsimm...@pcc.edu fsimm...@pcc.edu
To: C.Benham cbenha...@yahoo.com.au
Cc: em election-meth...@electorama.com
Sent: Thursday, 10 November 2011 5:54 AM
Subject: Re: IRV variants

 I don't get it. (I am confused by your explanation of the 
 algorithm).
 How do you think this is better than your latest version of 
 Enhanced DMC?

It takes care of the chicken problem.  But forget my confusing process; the 
IRV- Condorcet you 
describe here is a simpler solution, as long as you allow equal rankings, and 
count them as whole (as 
opposed to fractional):

 
 I think a good method is the IRV-Condorcet hybrid that differs 
 from IRV 
 only by before any and each elimination
 checks for an uneliminated candidate X that pairwise beats all 
 the other 
 uneliminated candidates and elects the
 first such X to appear.

Yes this is simpler.

 
 That of course gains Condorcet, and it keeps IRV's Mutual 
 Dominant Third 
 Burial Resistance property.
 So if a candidate X pairwise beats all the other candidates and 
 is 
 ranked above all the other candidates on more than
 a third of the ballots then (as with IRV) X must win and a rival 
 candidate Y's supporters can't get Y elected (assuming
 they can somehow change their ballots) by Burying X.
 
 Does your method share that property?
 
  49 C
  27 AB
  24 B
 
  Candidate A starts out as underdog, survives B, and is beaten 
 by C, so 
  C wins.
 
 
 From what I think I do understand of your algorithm 
 description, 
 doesn't candidate B start out as underdog?

Yes, I was in too much of a hurry when I wrote that.

Also contrary to my hopes the method turned out to be non-monotonic, because 
the IRV elimination 
order can eliminate a candidate earlier as a result of more first place 
support.  Only elimination orders 
without this defect can be used as a basis for a monotone method.

Forest
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Enhanced DMC (correction)

2011-10-06 Thread Chris Benham
I got the Woodall monotonicity criterion garbled.  Instead of  
mono-sub-delete and then
mono-raise-delete, in both instances I meant  *mono-sub-plump*.  (I've made 
the corrections
in the text below.)

It means that candidate x shouldn't be harmed (i.e. have his probability of 
election reduced)
by swapping some ballots that don't have x top-ranked for some that rank x 
alone in top place
and ignore (or vote equal-bottom) all the other candidates.

In the context of a universe of  ballots that allow only strict ranking from 
the top, with truncation
(but no other equal-ranking) allowed, Woodall defined it:

snip
A candidate x should not be harmed if:
(
are replaced by ballots that have 
choice;

snip


http://f1.grp.yahoofs.com/v1/4CSOTg18Jla8JeZD7lGf-L15LhewtDexi1BvIN9JQ79d6fDKQfZlI5ygNNqdMM_8b3XPbatc01XxYUjo1LgxMq9WirJdubA/wood1996.pdf

mono-sub-plump) some ballots that do not have x topx top with no second
Also I referred to Push-over strategy.  That refers to the strategy 
of raising some weak candidate to enable 
some other candidate to win (or to have a better chance of winning).
 
It was coined with methods like Top-Two Runoff and IRV in mind. Perhaps 
Push-over  *like* strategy was 
more apt for the methods I referred to.

 
Chris Benham
 
 
---
I  like this.  Regarding how approval is inferred, I'm also happy with Forest's 
idea of using Range 
(aka Score) type ballots (on which voters give their most preferred candidates 
the highest numerical 
scores) and interpreting any score above zero as approval and breaking approval 
ties as any score
above 1 etc.  Or any other sort of  multi-slot ratings ballot where all except 
the bottom-most slot is
interpreted as approval.
 
Another idea is to enter above-bottom equal-ranking between any 2 candidates in 
the pairwise matrix
as a whole vote for both candidates, and then take each candidate X's highest 
single pairwise score
as X's approval score.
 
Here are a couple of examples to demonstrate how this method varies from some 
other Condorcet
methods.

48: A
01: AD
24: BD
27: CBD
 
D is the most approved candidate and in the Smith set, and so Smith//Approval 
elects D.
Forest's Enhanced DMC or  Covering DMC  (and your suggested SARR 
implementation)
elects B.

B covers D and to me looks like a better winner. This method has a weaker 
truncation incentive 
than Smith//Approval.

25: AB
27: BC
26: CA
22: C

Approvals: C75,  B52, A51.    AB 51-49,   BC 52-48,   CA 75-25
 
Plain DMC and using MinMax or one of the algorithms that is equivalent to it 
when there are three
candidates (such as Schulze and Ranked Pairs and River) and weighing defeats 
either by Winning
Votes or Margins all elect B.
 
If  5 of  the 22 C voters change to A those methods all elect C (a failure of  
Woodall's mono-sub-plump
criterion).
 25: AB
27: BC
26: CA
17: C

05: A  (was C)
 
Approvals: C70,  A56,  B52.    AB 56-49,   BC 52-48,   CA 70-30.
 
In both cases our favoured method (like Smith//Approval) elects C, the  
positionally dominant candidate. It 
seems those other methods are more vulnerable to Push-over strategy.
 
(To be fair, Woodall has demonstrated that no Condorcet method can meet 
mono-sub-plump)
 
Chris Benham



From: Ted Stern araucaria.arauc...@gmail.com
To: election-methods@lists.electorama.com
Cc: Forest Simmons fsimm...@pcc.edu; Chris Benham cbenha...@yahoo.com.au
Sent: Wednesday, 5 October 2011 8:35 AM
Subject: Re: [EM] Enhanced DMC

After some private email exchanges with Forest and Chris, I'm
proposing a simple way of implementing Enhanced DMC, plus a new name,
Strong Approval Round Robin Voting (SARR Voting).

Ballot:

Ranked Voting, all explicitly ranked candidates considered approved.
Equal ranking allowed.  I'm basing this on recommendation from Chris
Benham.  I'm open to alternatives, but it seems to be the easiest way
to do it for now, and the most resistant to burying strategies.

Tallying:

Form the pairwise matrix, using the standard Condorcet procedure.  In
the diagonal entries, save total Approval votes.

For N candidates, the list of candidates in order from highest to
lowest approval is

  X_0, X_1, ..., X_k, X_{k+1}, ..., X_{N-1}

Initialize the Strong set to the empty set

Initialize the Weak set to the empty set.

For k = 0 to N-1,

  If X_k is already in the Weak set, continue iterating.  (X_k is
  defeated by a higher approved candidate.  This is called being
  strongly defeated.)

  If X_k loses to a member of the Weak set, continue iterating.  (X_k
  may defeat all higher approved candidates, but is weakly defeated
  by at least one of them.)
  
  If we're still here in the loop, X_k defeats all candidates in the
  Strong Set and all candidates in the Weak set.  (X_k covers all
  previously added members of the Strong set.)

  Add X_k to the Strong set and add all of X_k's defeats to the Weak
  set.

  Set the provisional winner to X_k.

The last provisional winner (the last candidate added to the Strong

Re: [EM] Enhanced DMC

2011-10-05 Thread Chris Benham
I  like this.  Regarding how approval is inferred, I'm also happy with Forest's 
idea of using Range 
(aka Score) type ballots (on which voters give their most preferred candidates 
the highest numerical 
scores) and interpreting any score above zero as approval and breaking approval 
ties as any score
above 1 etc.  Or any other sort of  multi-slot ratings ballot where all except 
the bottom-most slot is
interpreted as approval.
 
Another idea is to enter above-bottom equal-ranking between any 2 candidates in 
the pairwise matrix
as a whole vote for both candidates, and then take each candidate X's highest 
single pairwise score
as X's approval score.
 
Here are a couple of examples to demonstrate how this method varies from some 
other Condorcet
methods.

48: A
01: AD
24: BD
27: CBD
 
D is the most approved candidate and in the Smith set, and so Smith//Approval 
elects D.
Forest's Enhanced DMC or  Covering DMC  (and your suggested SARR 
implementation)
elects B.

B covers D and to me looks like a better winner. This method has a weaker 
truncation incentive 
than Smith//Approval.

25: AB
27: BC
26: CA
22: C

Approvals: C75,  B52, A51.    AB 51-49,   BC 52-48,   CA 75-25
 
Plain DMC and using MinMax or one of the algorithms that is equivalent to it 
when there are three
candidates (such as Schulze and Ranked Pairs and River) and weighing defeats 
either by Winning
Votes or Margins all elect B.
 
If  5 of  the 22 C voters change to A those methods all elect C (a failure of  
Woodall's mono-sub-delete
criterion).
 25: AB
27: BC
26: CA
17: C

05: A  (was C)
 
Approvals: C70,  A56,  B52.    AB 56-49,   BC 52-48,   CA 70-30.
 
In both cases our favoured method (like Smith//Approval) elects C, the  
positionally dominant candidate. It 
seems those other methods are more vulnerable to Push-over strategy.
 
(To be fair, Woodall has demonstrated that no Condorcet method can meet 
mono-raise-delete.)
 
 
Chris Benham
  



From: Ted Stern araucaria.arauc...@gmail.com
To: election-methods@lists.electorama.com
Cc: Forest Simmons fsimm...@pcc.edu; Chris Benham cbenha...@yahoo.com.au
Sent: Wednesday, 5 October 2011 8:35 AM
Subject: Re: [EM] Enhanced DMC

After some private email exchanges with Forest and Chris, I'm
proposing a simple way of implementing Enhanced DMC, plus a new name,
Strong Approval Round Robin Voting (SARR Voting).

Ballot:

Ranked Voting, all explicitly ranked candidates considered approved.
Equal ranking allowed.  I'm basing this on recommendation from Chris
Benham.  I'm open to alternatives, but it seems to be the easiest way
to do it for now, and the most resistant to burying strategies.

Tallying:

Form the pairwise matrix, using the standard Condorcet procedure.  In
the diagonal entries, save total Approval votes.

For N candidates, the list of candidates in order from highest to
lowest approval is

  X_0, X_1, ..., X_k, X_{k+1}, ..., X_{N-1}

Initialize the Strong set to the empty set

Initialize the Weak set to the empty set.

For k = 0 to N-1,

  If X_k is already in the Weak set, continue iterating.  (X_k is
  defeated by a higher approved candidate.  This is called being
  strongly defeated.)

  If X_k loses to a member of the Weak set, continue iterating.  (X_k
  may defeat all higher approved candidates, but is weakly defeated
  by at least one of them.)
  
  If we're still here in the loop, X_k defeats all candidates in the
  Strong Set and all candidates in the Weak set.  (X_k covers all
  previously added members of the Strong set.)

  Add X_k to the Strong set and add all of X_k's defeats to the Weak
  set.

  Set the provisional winner to X_k.

The last provisional winner (the last candidate added to the Strong
set) is the winner of the election.

Note:

The first member of the Strong Set will be X_0.

It is easiest to do this by hand if you first permute the pairwise
array so that it follows the same X_0, ..., X_{N-1} ordering.

As an example election, consider the one on this page:

  http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/Marginal_Ranked_Approval_Voting

Iterating through E, A, C, B, D, we find

  E:  Strong and Weak Sets are empty, so E has no losses to either.

      Strong set = {E};          Weak set = {C, D}
  
      Provisional winner set to E.

  A:  A defeats Strong set {E} and Weak set {C, D}.

    = Strong set = {E, A};      Weak set = {C, D}

      Provisional winner set to A.

  C:  in Weak set, not added to Strong set.

  B:  Defeats A, but is defeated by D from Weak set (and is therefore
      weakly defeated by A).

  D:  in Weak set, not added to Strong set.

A is the last candidate added to the Strong set, so A wins.

Ted
-- 
araucaria dot araucana at gmail dot com

On 26 Sep 2011 11:44:13 -0700, Chris Benham wrote:

 Forest,

 I think in general that if the approval scores are at all valid I
 would go for the enhanced DMC winner over any of the chain building
 methods we have considered. I think other considerations over-ride

Re: [EM] Enhanced DMC

2011-09-26 Thread Chris Benham
Forest,

I think in general that if the approval scores are at all valid I would go for 
the enhanced DMC winner over 
any of the chain building methods we have considered.  I think other 
considerations over-ride the 
importance of being uncovered.
 
I agree.  I think the chain building method in comparison seems a bit arbitrary 
and less philosophically justified.
 
Also the method has a fairly straight-forward description that doesn't need to 
mention Smith set or the Condorcet winner.
 
So of these similar methods (that include Smith//Approval and all elect the 
same winner if the Smith set contains 3 members or 1 member), 
I think this is my favourite. 
 
Maybe it could use a new name? :)

Chris
 
 
 

From: fsimm...@pcc.edu fsimm...@pcc.edu
To: C.Benham cbenha...@yahoo.com.au
Cc: election-methods-electorama@electorama.com
Sent: Monday, 12 September 2011 8:50 AM
Subject: Re: Enhanced DMC

Very good Chris.  

I tried to build a believable profile of ballots that would yield the approval 
order and defeats of this 
example without success, but I am sure that it is not impossible.

I think in general that if the approval scores are at all valid I would go for 
the enhanced DMC winner over 
any of the chain building methods we have considered.  I think other 
considerations over-ride the 
importance of being uncovered.

- Original Message -
From: C.Benham 
Date: Sunday, September 11, 2011 10:08 am
Subject: Enhanced DMC
To: election-methods-electorama@electorama.com
Cc: Forest W Simmons 

 Forest Simmons wrote (15 Aug 2011):
 
 Here's a possible scenario:
 
 Suppose that approval order is alphabetical from most approval 
 to least A, B, C, D.
 
 Suppose further that pairwise defeats are as follows:
 
 CADBA together with BCD .
 
 Then the set P = {A, B} is the set of candidates neither of 
 which is pairwise
 beaten by anybody with greater approval.
 
 Since the approval winner A is not covered by B, it is not 
 covered by any
 member of P, so the enhanced version of DMC elects A.
 
 But A is covered by C so it cannot be elected by any of the 
 chain building
 methods that elect only from the uncovered set.
 
 
 Forest,
 
 Is the Approval Chain-Building method the same as simply 
 electing the 
 most approved uncovered candidate?
 
 I surmise that the set of candidates not pairwise beaten by a 
 more 
 approved candidate (your set P, what I've
 been referring to as the Definite Majority set) and the 
 Uncovered set 
 don't necessarily overlap.
 
 If forced to choose between electing from the Uncovered set and 
 electing 
 from the DM set, I tend towards
 the latter.
 
 Since Smith//Approval always elects from the DM set, and your 
 suggested 
 enhanced DMC (elect the most
 approved member of the DM set that isn't covered by another 
 member) 
 doesn't necessarily elect from the Uncovered set;
 there doesn't seem to be any obvious philosophical case that 
 enhanced 
 DMC is better than Smith//Approval.
 
 (Also I would say that an election where those two methods 
 produce 
 different winners would be fantastically unlikely.)
 
 A lot of Condorcet methods are promoted as being able to give 
 the 
 winner just from the information contained in the
 gross pairwise matrix. I think that the same is true of these 
 methods 
 if we take a candidate X's highest gross pairwise
 score as X's approval score. Can you see any problem with that?
 
 
 Chris Benham
 
 
 
 
 - Original Message -
 From:
 Date: Friday, August 12, 2011 3:12 pm
 Subject: Enhanced DMC
 To: election-methods at lists.electorama.com,
 
   From: C.Benham
   To: election-methods-electorama.com at electorama.com
   Subject: [EM] Enhanced DMC
 
   Forest,
   The D in DMC used to stand for *Definite*.
 
  Yeah, that's what we finally settled on.
 
  
   I like (and I think I'm happy to endorse) this Condorcet method
   idea, and consider it to be clearly better than regular DMC
  
   Could this method give a different winner from the (Approval
   Chain Building ?) method you mentioned in the C//A thread 
 (on 11
   June 2011)?
 
  Yes, I'll give an example when I get more time. But for all 
 practical 
  purposes they both pick the highest approval Smith candidate.
 
 
 
 Here's a possible scenario:
 
 Suppose that approval order is alphabetical from most approval 
 to least 
 A, B, C, D.
 
 Suppose further that pairwise defeats are as follows:
 
 CADBA together with BCD .
 
 Then the set P = {A, B} is the set of candidates neither of 
 which is 
 pairwise
 beaten by anybody with greater approval.
 
 Since the approval winner A is not covered by B, it is not 
 covered by any
 member of P, so the enhanced version of DMC elects A.
 
 But A is covered by C so it cannot be elected by any of the 
 chain building
 methods that elect only from the uncovered set.
 
 
 Forest Simmons wrote (12 June 2011):
 
  I think the following complete description is simpler than anything
  possible for ranked pairs:
 
  1. Next to each candidate

[EM] Looking for the name of a Bucklin variant

2010-08-25 Thread Chris Benham
Michael,

The method you describe was invented by Douglas Woodall and is called 
Quota-Limited Trickle Down.

I don't think that anyone now claims that it is a very good single-winner 
method, but maybe you can
base an ok multi-winner method on it that meets Droop Proportionality.

Woodall had it meeting Majority for Solid Coalitions, his Plurality criterion, 
mono-raise,
mono-remove-bottom, mono-raise-delete, mono-sub-plump, mono-add-plump, 
mono-append and
Later-no-Help.

And failing Clone-Winner, Clone-Loser, Condorcet, mono-add-top, mono-sub-top 
and 
Later-no-Harm.


Chris Benham




Michael Rouse wrote (25 Aug 2010):
I was wondering if someone on the Election Methods list could give me the name 
(or better yet, a link to more information) on a particular variation of the 
Bucklin method.  In Bucklin, you check first place votes to see if a candidate 
has a majority. If not, you add second place votes, then third place votes and 
so on, until at least one candidate has a majority.  In the variation I'm 
thinking of, you look at first place votes. If one candidate has a majority, 
then he or she is the winner; otherwise, you start adding second place votes 
*one at a time* (rather than all at once), until you have majority candidate. 
If 
no candidate has a majority, you start adding third place votes one at a time, 
and so on. In other words, you find the candidate who needs the fewest added 
votes at a particular rank to be a majority winner. If candidate A needs only 2 
second-place votes to have a majority and candidate B needs 100, it wouldn't 
matter that candidate A has only 3 second place votes and B has 1000.  I know 
this has to have a name (or at least someone has looked at it and given a nice 
description of its properties), and I'm interested in seeing how it would apply 
to multi-winner elections without reinventing the wheel.  Thanks!  Michael 
Rouse 



  


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Irrelevant Ballots Independent Fallback Approval (IBIFA)

2010-06-16 Thread Chris Benham
 Irrelevant Ballots Independent Fallback Approval (IBIFA) is the name I've 
settled on for the method I proposed
in a May 2010 EM post titled Bucklin-like method meeting Favorite Betrayal and 
Irrelevant Ballots.

http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2010-May/026479.html

In that post I wrote that it uses multi-slot ratings ballots, and defined the 
4-slot version:


*Voters fill out 4-slot ratings ballots, rating each candidate as either Top, 
Middle1, Middle2
or Bottom. Default rating is Bottom, signifying least preferred and unapproved.


Any rating above Bottom is interpreted as Approval.


If any candidate/s X has a Top-Ratings score that is higher than any other 
candidate's approval
score on ballots that don't top-rate X, elect the X with the highest TR score.


Otherwise, if any candidate/s X has a Top+Middle1 score that is higher than 
any other candidate's
approval score on ballots that don't give X a Top or Middle1 rating, elect the 
X with the highest
Top+Middle1 score.


Otherwise, elect the candidate with the highest Approval score.*(Obviously 
other slot names are possible, such as 3 2 1 0 or  A B C D or  Top, High 
Middle, Low Middle, Bottom.)

The 3-slot version:


*Voters fill out 3-slot ratings ballots, rating each candidate as either Top, 
Middle
or Bottom. Default rating is Bottom, signifying least preferred and unapproved.

Any rating above Bottom is interpreted as Approval.

If any candidate/s X has a Top-Ratings score that is higher than any other 
candidate's approval
score on ballots that don't top-rate X, elect the X with the highest TR score.

Otherwise, elect the candidate with the highest Approval score.*


It can also be adapted for use with ranked ballots:


*Voters rank the candidates, beginning with those they most prefer. 
Equal-ranking and truncation
are allowed.

Ranking above at least one other candidate is interpreted as Approval.

The ballots are interpreted as multi-slot ratings ballots thus:
An approved candidate ranked below zero other candidates is interpreted as 
Top-Rated.
An approved candidate ranked below one other candidate is interpreted as being 
in the second-highest
ratings slot.
An approved candidate ranked below two other candidates is interpreted as being 
in the third-highest
ratings slot (even if this means the second-highest ratings slot is left empty).
An approved candidate ranked below three other candidates is interpreted as 
being in the fourth-highest
ratings slot (even if this means that a higher ratings slot is left empty).

And so on.
 

Say we label these ratings slot from the top A B C D etc. 
A candidate X's A score is the number of ballots on which it is A rated. 
A candidate X's A+B score is the number of ballots on which it is rated A or B.
A candidate X's A+B+C score is the number of ballots on which it is rated A or 
B or C.
And so on.


If any candidate X has an A score  that is greater than any other candidate's 
approval score on ballots
that don't A-rate X, then elect the X with the greatest A score.

Otherwise, if any candidate X has an A+B score that is greater than any other 
candidate's approval score
on ballots that don't A-rate of B-rate X, then elect the X with the greatest 
A+B score.

And so on as in the versions that use a fixed number of ratings slots, if 
necessary electing the most
approved candidate.*

This is analogous with ER-Bucklin(whole) on ranked ballots:
http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/ER-Bucklin





Chris Benham


  


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Condorcet question - why not bullet vote?

2010-06-16 Thread Chris Benham
Peter,

If I just bullet vote in a Condorcet election, then I increase the chances
of my candidate being elected.

Bullet voting in an election using a method that complies with the Condorcet 
criterion does I suppose
somewhat increase the chance of your candidate being the Condorcet winner.

But all Condorcet methods fail Later-no-Help, and in some this effect is 
sufficiently strong for the method
to have a random fill incentive.  That means that if you know nothing about 
how other voters will vote
you are probabilistically better off by strictly ranking all your least 
preferred candidates.

46: AB
44: B
10: C

Here A is the CW, but if the 44B voters change to BC then Schulze(Winning 
Votes) elects B.

Schulze (WV) also has a zero-info. equal-rank at the top incentive. So say you 
know nothing about
how other voters will vote and you have a big gap in your sincere ratings of 
the candidates, then your
best probabilistic strategy is to rank all the candidates in your preferred 
group (those above the big
gap in your ratings) equal-top and to strictly rank (randomly if necessarily) 
all the candidates below
the gap.

Your question seems to come with assumption that the voter doesn't care much 
who wins if her favourite
doesn't.

Q: In this case why should any voter not bullet-vote?

The voter might be mainly interested in preventing her least preferred 
candidate from winning. Bullet
voting is then a worse strategy than ranking that hated candidate strictly 
bottom.

Another Condorcet method is  Smith//Approval(ranking). That interprets ranking 
versus truncation as
approval and elects the member of the Smith set (the smallest subset S of 
candidates that pairwise beat
any/all non-S candidates) that has the highest approval score.

(Some advocate the even simpler Condorcet//Approval(ranking) that simply elects 
the most approved
candidate if there is no single Condorcet winner.)

In the example above the effect of the 44B voters changing to BC is with those 
methods to make C
the new winner.

Those methods do have a truncation incentive, so then many voters who are 
mainly interested in 
getting their strict favourites elected will and should bullet vote.

What is wrong with that?

Chris Benham



 


Dear all, dear Markus Schulze,I got a second question from one of our 
members (actually the same guy which  asked for the first time):  If I just 
bullet vote in a Condorcet election, then I increase the chances  of my 
candidate being elected.  If I have a second or third option, the chances of my 
prefered candidate to  win is lowered.  Q: In this case why should any voter 
not bullet-vote?  I have some clue on how to answer, but not enough for an 
exhaustive answer.My argument starts:  If I vote for a candidate who has 
50% of the votes, then it does not matter  if there is a second or third 
choice.  If my prefered candidate A gets 50%  of the votes, then it makes 
sense to  support a second choice candidate B.  However if the supporters of B 
only bullet vote, then maybe B's supporters  get an advantage over A?  ... at 
this point I realize, that I don't know enough about Condorcet and/or  Schulze 
to answer the question.Why is it not rational to
 bullet vote in a Condorcet election if you are  allowed not to rank some 
candidates?  I guess you have discussed this question a zillion of times, so 
please  forgive my ignorance.Maybe you could help me out with this one.
Peter  


  

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] methods based on cycle proof conditions

2010-06-04 Thread Chris Benham
 


I.  BDR or Bucklin Done Right: 

Use 4 levels, say, zero through three.  First eliminate all candidates 
defeated 
pairwise with a defeat ratio of 3 to 1.  Then collapse the top two levels, and 
eliminate all candidates that suffer a defeat ratio of 2 to 1.  If any 
candidates are left, among these elect the one with the greatest number of 
positive ratings. 
  

snip 

This seems to be even more Approvalish than normal Bucklin. 

65: A3, B2 
35: B3, A0 

(I assume that zero indicates least preferred) 

Forest's BDR method elects A, failing Majority Favourite. 

In response to the above, Abd Lomax-Smith wrote (3 June 2010):

snip

Now, who would use BDR with only two candidates? It's like using 
Range with only two candidates. Why would you care about majority 
favorite if you decide to use raw range. I wonder why the A faction 
even bothered to vote with that pattern of utilities (ratings). 
That's what is completely unrealistic about this kind of analysis.
snip

I was content to simply prove that the method simply fails Majority Favourite, 
but to appease 
Abd  here is a similar example with three candidates:

60: A3, B1, C0
35: B3, A0, C1
05: C3, A2, C0

A is the big majority favourite and the big voted  raw range winner, and yet  
B wins.

Chris Benham



  


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] methods based on cycle proof conditions

2010-06-03 Thread Chris Benham
 Forest Simmons wrote (1 June 2010):
snip

I.  BDR or Bucklin Done Right:

Use 4 levels, say, zero through three.  First eliminate all candidates defeated
pairwise with a defeat ratio of 3 to 1.  Then collapse the top two levels, and
eliminate all candidates that suffer a defeat ratio of 2 to 1.  If any
candidates are left, among these elect the one with the greatest number of
positive ratings.

snip

This seems to be even more Approvalish than normal Bucklin.

65: A3, B2
35: B3, A0

(I assume that zero indicates least preferred)

Forest's BDR method elects A, failing Majority Favourite. 


Chris Benham 


  


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Tanking advantage of cycle proof conditions

2010-06-01 Thread Chris Benham
 
Forest Simmons wrote (29 May 2010):


Here's a four slot method that takes advantage of the impossibility of beat
cycles under certain conditions:.


Use range style ballots with four levels: 0, 1, 2, and 3.

(1) First eliminate all candidates that are pairwise defeated by a ratio 
greater
than 3/1.


(2) Then eliminate all of the candidates that are pairwise defeated by a ratio
greater than 2/1 based on only those comparisons that involve an extreme 
rating,
i.e. 3 beats a 0, 1, or 2, while 1, 2, or 3 beats a 0, but don't count a 2 as
beating a 1, since neither 1 not 2 is an extreme rating on our four slot 
ballot.


(3) Finally, eliminate all of the candidates that are pairwise defeated by any
ratio greater than 1/1 on the basis of comparisons that involve a rating
difference of at least two, i.e. 3 vs. 0 or 1, and  2 or 3 vs. 0, while
considering 3 vs. 2,   2 vs. 1, and 1 vs. 0 to be too weak for this final
elimination decision that is based on a mere 1/1 defeat ratio cutoff.

The candidate that remains is the winner.



If there is a pairwise tie in step three, use the middle two levels to resolve
it, which is the same as electing the tied candidate with the greatest number 
of
ratings strictly above one.


None of the three elimination steps can eliminate all of the candidates because
the elimination conditions are cycle proof.  Furthermore, (with the tie breaker
in place) the third step will eliminate all of the remaining candidates except 
one. 

Notice that the ballot comparisons get progressively stronger as we go from 
step
one to step three, while the defeat ratio requirements get weaker, (from 3/1 to
2/1 to 1/1) but stay strong enough at each step to prevent cycles.

Isn't that cool?

Forest,

It is certainly elegant and interesting.

Wouldn't it be possible for step (2)  to eliminate a Condorcet winner?  If the 
method fails the Condorcet criterion,
does it meet Favourite Betrayal?

Does it ( like the Condorcet method Raynaud that also works by eliminating 
pairwise losers) fail mono-raise?

http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/Raynaud

I can't make an example of it failing the Plurality criterion.   Does it meet 
that criterion?

Chris Benham


  


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Bucklin-like method meeting Favorite Betrayal and Irrelevant Ballots

2010-05-28 Thread Chris Benham
 My so-far nameless  attempt at fixing Bucklin:

*Voters fill out 4-slot ratings ballots, rating each candidate as either Top, 
Middle1, Middle2
or Bottom. Default rating is Bottom, signifying least preferred and unapproved.

Any rating above Bottom is interpreted as Approval.

If any candidate/s X has a Top-Ratings score that is higher than any other 
candidate's approval
score on ballots that don't top-rate X, elect the X with the highest TR score.

Otherwise, if any candidate/s X has a Top+Middle1 score that is higher than any 
other candidate's
approval score on ballots that don't give X a Top or Middle1 rating, elect the 
X with the highest
Top+Middle1 score.

Otherwise, elect the candidate with the highest Approval score.*

 35: A
 10: A=B
 30: BC
 25: C

 Here (like SMD,TR) it elects B.  Bucklin elects C

Forrest Simmons wrote (28 May 2010):


It seems to me that this new method would elect A, since A has the most TR (45
versus 40 for B) and the greatest total of approvals below top is only 30 (by 
C).

Forest,

The pertinent phrase in the definition is any other candidate's approval score 
on ballots that don't
top-rate X.   A does have the highest TR score (45) but can't win in the first 
round because on ballots
that don't  top-rate A  (30BC, 25C)  C has an approval score of 55.

B's TR score is 40 and is allowed to win in the first round because on ballots 
that don't top-rate B
(35A, 25C) the highest approval score is only 35.

C's TR score is only 25  so of the candidates allowed to win in the first round 
B has the highest TR
score and so wins. And in any case on ballots that don't top-rate C  (35A, 
10A=B, BC)  A has
an approval score of  45 so B is the only candidate that is allowed to win in 
the first round.

Thanks for taking an interest 

Chris Benham


  


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] SMD,TR fails the Plurality criterion.

2010-05-27 Thread Chris Benham
My previous message contained a small blunder. The corrected version is below

A candidate X's  maximum approval oppostion score is the approval score of 
the most approved
candidate only on ballots on which X is not approved.

In the example election I mistakenly gave A's MAO score as 11.

The definition of SMD,TR:

*Voters fill out 3-slot ratings ballots, default rating is bottom-most
(indicating least preferred and not approved).

Interpreting top and middle rating as approval, disqualify all candidates
with an approval score lower than their maximum approval-opposition 
(MAO) score.
(X's  MAO score is the approval score of the most approved candidate on
ballots that don't approve X).

Elect the undisqualified candidate with the highest top-ratings score.*

http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2008-December/023530.html
Chris Benham


 
 Kevin Venzke has come up with an example that shows that my Strong Minimal 
Defense, Top Ratings 
(SMD,TR) method fails the Plurality criterion,contrary to what I've claimed. 

21: AC 
08: BA 
23: B 
11: C 

Approval scores:  A29,   B31,  C32 

Maximum Approval Opposition scores:  A23,   B32,  C31 

Top-Ratings scores:  A21,   B31,  C11. 

By the rules of SMD,TR  B is disqualified because B's MAO score (of 32, C's 
approval score on 
ballots that don't approve B) is greater than B's approval score. 

Then A (as the undisqualified candidate with the highest TR score) wins. 

But since B has more first-place votes than A has total votes, or in the 
language of this method 
B's TR score is greater than A's total approval score, the Plurality criterion 
says that A can't win. 

This seems to show that compliance with my Unmanipulable Majority criterion 
is a bit more 
expensive than I thought.  I still endorse SMD,TR as a good  Favourite Betrayal 
complying 
method, but with less enthusiasm. 

(My UM criterion says that if A is a winner and on more than half the ballots 
is voted above B, it 
is impossible to make B the winner by altering any ballots on which B is voted 
above A without 
raising on them B's ranking or rating.) 

I was wrong to claim that compliance with Strong Minimal Defense implies 
compliance with the 
Plurality criterion. 

Chris Benham 


  


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] The general form of Quick Runoff

2010-05-24 Thread Chris Benham
Kevin,

This new Quick Runoff (QR) method suggestion of yours does nothing to shake 
my opinion
that IRV is the best LNHarm method.

Monotonicity: We still have an unusual monotonicity problem in that a
candidate who lacks a majority over the candidate previous to him in
first-preference order, may wish he had received fewer first preferences
in order to sit behind a candidate that he did defeat (and who can
still provide the necessary majority beatpath to the top). He may also
wish he received *more* first preferences. Is it a wash?


Without bothering to make an example, it seems obvious that it fails 
Mono-add-Plump.

 
(It's conceivable that another way of ordering the candidates could
preserve all the properties plus clone independence, but I'm not very
optimistic at the moment.)

Why not order the candidates by DSC (the reverse of the DSC disqualification 
order)?

Wouldn't that version simply dominate (in terms of desirable criterion 
compliances) the QR 
you've defined (that uses the FPP order)?

Compared to plain DSC it seems to just gain compliance with Condorcet(Gross) 
Loser in
exchange for losing compliance with Irrelevant Ballots.

 
Chris Benham





Kevin Venzke wrote (22 May 2010):
Hello,

I realized that QR can be generalized for any number of candidates and
still retain LNHarm, Plurality, and resistance to the usual type of
burial strategy. To me this makes the method surprisingly good.

The philosophy is to elect the candidate with the fewest first-preferences
(think center-squeeze here) who has a very specific majority beatpath
to the first-preference winner.

Here is the new definition:

1. Rank the candidates. Truncation is allowed. Equal ranking is not 
planned for (but we could come up with something).
2. Label the candidates A, B, C, ... Z in descending order of first
preference count.
3. Let the current leader be A.
4. While the current leader has a majority pairwise loss to the very
next candidate, set the current leader to the latter candidate. (In
other words step 4 must be repeated until there is no loss or no other
candidates.)
5. Elect the current leader.

Proof of LNHarm satisfaction: Let's say you were voting BY (retaining
the meaning of the alphabetical ordering) and you consider changing
your ballot to BYM. The sole effect this may have is to create a
majority for ML, causing L to lose. You didn't rank L, so you didn't
harm any higher preferences. (And if you had ranked L, then adding the 
M preference could not have created a majority ML. Also note that
adding preferences cannot reverse or remove any majorities.)

Who wins instead? Let's talk about burial. Typically the concern is that
voters for a strong candidate will rank a weak candidate insincerely
high in an effort to make a strong competitor lose. For example, you
would vote AC to confuse the method into defeating B and electing A.
In QR your added C preference can only help elect a candidate who was
even weaker (in first preferences) than C. This makes burial a useless
strategy for the largest factions.

Proof of Plurality satisfaction (a second advantage over MMPO): If X has
more first preferences than Y has votes total, then Y can't have a
majority win over anybody and can never be the current leader.

Monotonicity: We still have an unusual monotonicity problem in that a
candidate who lacks a majority over the candidate previous to him in
first-preference order, may wish he had received fewer first preferences
in order to sit behind a candidate that he did defeat (and who can
still provide the necessary majority beatpath to the top). He may also
wish he received *more* first preferences. Is it a wash?

In any case, getting additional second or third (etc) preferences can't
hurt a candidate.

QR doesn't satisfy Condorcet(gross) (i.e. a candidate with a majority
over every other candidate is not guaranteed to win unless he is one
of the top two candidates in first-preference order) but it does satisfy
Condorcet(gross) Loser.

It doesn't satisfy minimal defense in general. A candidate barred
according to minimal defense can only win if he places first (since he
will be unable to take the win from any other candidate) and he does
not lose by a majority to second-place. (If the latter candidate is the
majority's common candidate under minimal defense, then the barred
candidate will lose.)

It doesn't satisfy SFC generally (because a majority win is only enforced
against one other candidate) but it does work when the involved candidates
place first and second in some order. (If the suspected sincere CW is
A, then A has a majority over B and wins immediately; if the suspected
sincere CW is B, then B takes the win from A and B cannot lose it to
anybody.)

Fairly obviously it satisfies Majority Favorite and Majority Last
Preference. It doesn't satisfy Majority for Solid Coalitions due to the
possibility that the majority's first preferences are so fragmented that
none of their candidates place first or second

[EM] Proposal: Majority Enhanced Approval (MEA)

2010-05-12 Thread Chris Benham
Forest,

This MEA method you have suggested would nearly always give the same winner as 
Smith//Approval (ranking), one of the methods I endorse.

Where they do give different winners, would it be the case that the 
Smith//Approval winner
is the more approved?  But outside the Uncovered set?

What is the most realistic example you can give of the two methods giving 
different winners?

A feature of both methods that I am going off is that voters can be punished 
for failing to truncate
their least preferred of the viable candidates.

49: A1A2
24: B
27: CBA1

A1 is uncovered and most approved, so both methods elect A1. But the presence 
of the weakly
pareto-dominated clone A2 on the ballot caused the C supporters to not truncate 
A1. If they had
done so then B would have won.

This type of example is what motivated me to recently propose that a 
candidate's 'biggest gross
pairwise score in a pairwise victory over an uncovered candidate' be used as a 
quasi-approval score.
B then wins whether the C voters truncate A1 or not.

(The other motivation was that I was looking for something that used nothing 
but the normal gross
pairwise matrix.)

I recognize that this can cause failure of mono-raise, but probably only in a 
complicated not very
likely example.

Chris Benham



Forest Simmons wrote (8 May 2010):

I have a proposal that uses the same pairwise win/loss/tie information that 
Copeland is based on, along with 
the complementary information that Approval is based on.  It’s a simple and 
powerful Condorcet/Approval 
hybrid which, like Copeland, always elects an uncovered candidate, but without 
the indecisiveness or clone 
dependence of Copeland.

I used to call it UncAAO, but for better name recognition, I’m changing the 
name to Majority Enhanced 
Approval (MEA).

The method is extremely easy to understand once you get the simple concept of 
covering.  Candidate X 
covers candidate Y if candidate X pairwise beats both Y and every candidate 
that Y beats pairwise.

MEA elects the candidate A1 that is approved on the greatest number of ballots 
if A1 is uncovered. 
Otherwise it elects the highest approval candidate A2 that covers A1 if A2 is 
uncovered.  Otherwise it elects 
the highest approval candidate A3 that covers A2 if A3 is uncovered.  
Otherwise, etc. until we arrive at an 
uncovered candidate An, which is elected.

MEA satisfies Monotonicity, Clone Independence, Independence from Pareto 
Dominated Alternatives, and 
Independence from Non-Smith Alternatives, as well as all of the following:

1.  It elects the same member of a clone set as the method would when 
restricted to the clone set.

2.  If a candidate that beats the winner is removed, the winner is unchanged.

3.  If an added candidate covers the winner, the new candidate becomes the new 
winner.

4.  If the old winner covers an added candidate, the old winner still wins.

5.  It always chooses from the uncovered set.

6.  It is easy to describe:  Initialize L to be an empty list.  While there 
exists some alternative that covers 
every member of L,  add to L the one (from among those) with the greatest 
approval.  Elect the last 
candidate added to L. 

What other deterministic method (based on ranked ballots with truncations 
allowed) satisfies all of these 
criteria?

Forest



  


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Scenario where IRV and Asset outperform Condorcet, Range, Bucklin, Approval.

2010-05-12 Thread Chris Benham


Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote (12 May 2010):
One idea of mine, although extremely complex, would be to select the two 
candidates for a runoff by two Condorcet methods - one that's resistant 
to strategy (like Smith,IRV), and one that's not but provides better 
results in the honest vote case (e.g. Schulze, uncovered methods). Since 
the second round is honest - a two-candidate election where a majority 
wins is strategy-proof - it should lower the chances of ending up with a 
very bad candidate.

If the two methods agree, the candidate would win outright.
These sorts of schemes (a runoff between the winners of methods A and B)
invariably fail mono-raise and are vulnerable to Pushover strategy.

The voters may also end up arguing that because the two methods agree so often 
(if they do), there's no need to have the runoff in the first place; if the 
method 
deters organized strategy, the organized strategy wouldn't appear and so the 
actual 
runoff mechanism would appear superfluous.
 
 
So the threat of a runoff (that is never needed to be held) is deterring 
organised
strategy is somehow an argument for abolishing the threat??
 
A better 2-round scheme would be to have all the members of the Smith set 
eligible
for the second round, which uses simple Approval.
 

Chris Benham


  


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] MinMax(AWP) and Participation

2010-04-23 Thread Chris Benham
 Forest wrote:

..MinMax is the only commonly known Condorcet method that satisfies the 
following weak form of Participation:
If A wins and then another ballot with A ranked unique first is added to the 
count, A still wins.


That is Mono-add-Top, I think coined by Douglas Woodall. It is met by IRV.


Beatpath, River, Ranked Pairs, etc. fail this weak participation criterion, 
but they do 
satisfy this even weaker version:
If A wins and then another ballot with only A ranked is added to the count, 
then A still wins.

That is Mono-add-Plump.

Forest,

Is there some method that you like or take seriously that actually fails this 
criterion?


Chris Benham





Forest Simmons wrote (21 April 2010):


I don't know if Juho is still cheering for MinMax as a public proposal.  I used 
to be against it because of its clone dependence, 
but now that I realize that measuring defeat strength by AWP (Approval Weighted 
Pairwise) solves that problem, I'm starting to 
warm up more to the idea. 
MinMax elects the candidate that suffers no defeats if there is one, else it 
elects the one whose maximum strength defeat is 
minimal.
There are various ways of measuring defeat strength.  James Green Armytage has 
advocated one called AWP as making Condorcet 
methods less vulnerable to strategic manipulation.
If all ranked candidates on a ballot are considered approved, then the AWP 
strength of a defeat of B by A is the number of ballots 
on which A is ranked but B is not.
Then more recently I was reading a paper by Joaquin Pérez in which he shows 
that MinMax is the only commonly known Condorcet method 
that satisfies the following weak form of Participation:
If A wins and then another ballot with A ranked unique first is added to the 
count, A still wins.
Beatpath, River, Ranked Pairs, etc. fail this weak participation criterion, but 
they do satisfy this even weaker version:
If A wins and then another ballot with only A ranked is added to the count, 
then A still wins.
Proof:  First add a ballot in which no candidate is ranked.  The above 
mentioned methods allow this, and it doesn't affect their 
outcome since no mention of absolute majority is made in any of them.  Then 
raise A while leaving the other candidates unranked.  
This cannot hurt A since all of the above mentioned methods are monotone.
Knowing that Beatpath satisfies the weaker version but not the weak version may 
be an inducement for voters to bullet vote candidate 
A to make sure that they avoid the no show paradox.  But MinMax is free of this 
temptation; they wouldn't have to truncate the other 
candidates.



  


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Classifying 3-cand scenarios. LNHarm methods again.

2010-04-21 Thread Chris Benham
Dave Ketchum wrote 17 April 2010:

First, quoting Wikipedia:
 A Condorcet method is any single-winner election method that meets  
 the Condorcet criterion, that is, which always selects the Condorcet  
 winner, the candidate who would beat each of the other candidates in  
 a run-off election, if such a candidate exists. In modern examples,  
 voters rank candidates in order of preference. There are then  
 multiple, slightly differing methods for calculating the winner, due  
 to the need to resolve circular ambiguities—including the Kemeny- 
 Young method,Ranked Pairs, and the Schulze method. Almost all of  
 these methods give the same result if there are fewer than 4  
 candidates in the circularly-ambiguous Smith set and voters  
 separately rank all of them.


I have heard this complaint before, so am listening for help.

WHAT should I say when I want EXACTLY what is described as Condorcet  
above?
 
Dave,
The Wikiipedia piece you quote doesn't say *the* Condorcet method. It
says A Condorcet method...

So you couuld say that, or a Condorcet-complying method. 
You asked Will not Condorcet attend to clones with minimum pain?
Plain Condorcet won't do anything except elect a voted CW if
there is one.
Some Condorcet-complying methods are clone-proof and some aren't.
Chris Benham


 
On Apr 17, 2010, at 9:25 PM, Markus Schulze wrote:
 Hallo,

 Dave Ketchum wrote (18 April 2010):

 Why IRV? Have we not buried that deep enough?
 Why not Condorcet which does better with about
 the same voting?

 Why TTR?  Shouldn't that be avoided if trying
 for a good method? TTR requires smart deciding
 as to which candidates to vote on.

 Will not Condorcet attend to clones with minimum
 pain? Voters can rank them together (with equal
 or adjacent ranks).

 Does not Condorcet properly attend to symmetric
 with a voted cycle?

 In my opinion, Condorcet refers to a criterion
 rather than to an election method.

 Markus Schulze


  


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Multiwinner Bucklin - proportional, summable (n^3), monotonic (if fully-enough ranked)

2010-03-28 Thread Chris Benham
Jameson Quinn wrote (26 March 2010):

snip
Right now, I think MCV - that is, two-rank, equality-allowed Bucklin, with
top-two runoffs if no candidate receives a majority of approvals in those
two ranks - is my favorite proposal for practical implementation.
snip


Jameson,

What does MCV stand for?  

Does top-two runoffs mean a second trip to the polls?

How are the candidates scored to determine the top two? Is it based on the
candidates' scores after the second Bucklin round?

Chris Benham


  

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Smith, FPP fails Minimal Defense and Clone-Winner

2010-03-10 Thread Chris Benham
Robert Bristow-Johnson  wrote (9 March 2010):

snip
so, keeping RP, Schulze in mind for later, what would be a good  
scheme for resolving cycles by use of elimination of candidates?   
what would be a good (that is resistant to more anomalies) and  
simple method to identify the weakest candidate (in the Smith set)  
to eliminate and run the beats-all tabulation again? i'm not saying  
elimination is a good way to do it, but it might be easier to sell to  
neanderthal voters.

r b-j

I recommend Smith//Approval(ranking):
 
*Voters rank from the top candidates they approve. Equal-ranking is allowed. 
Interpreting being ranked above at least one other candidate as approval, elect 
the most 
approved member of the Smith set (the smallest non-empty set  S of candidates 
that pairwise
beat all the outside-S candidates).*

I don't think this is very hard to explain or sell.


Who do you think should win this election?

25: AB
26: BC
23: CA
26: C

CA 75-25,  AB 49-26,  BC 51-49
 
 
Chris Benham


  


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Simple monotonicity question

2010-02-20 Thread Chris Benham
Kristofer Munsterhjelm  wrote:

Does nonmonotonicity in three-candidate IRV only happen when the 
Condorcet winner is eliminated?
 
No.

47: ACB
26: BA
02: CAB
25: CB
 
There is no Condorcet winner. 
 
IRV elects A but if the two CAB ballots are changed to ACB then
there is still no Condorcet winner and now IRV elects B, a failure of
mono-raise.
 
49: ACB
26: BA
25: CB

 
Chris Benham


  
__
Yahoo!7: Catch-up on your favourite Channel 7 TV shows easily, legally, and for 
free at PLUS7. www.tv.yahoo.com.au/plus7


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] good method ? , was IRV ballot pile count (proof of closed form)

2010-02-12 Thread Chris Benham
Rob LeGrand wrote (11 Feb 2010):

snip

35:A
32:BC
33:C,

by which I mean

35:AB=C
32:BCA
33:CA=B.

In this example, C is the Condorcet winner even though C does not have a
majority over B.  I can see how this example could be seen as an
embarrassment to the Condorcet criterion, in that a good method might not
choose C as the winner.

end quoted message

Rob,

Well I can't. Electing A would be a violation of the Minmal Defense criterion,
and electing B would violate Woodall's Plurality criterion and Condorcet Loser.

What good method do you have in mind that might not elect C?

And what's good about it?

Chris Benham



  


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] IRV vs Plurality

2010-01-26 Thread Chris Benham
Juho wrote (26 Jan 2010):

snip
It may well be that this method can be characterized as not fully  
Condorcet and Approval strategy added. I'm not quite sure that the  
intended idea of mostly Condorcet with core support rewarded (= do  
what the IRV core support idea is supposed to do) works well enough to  
justify this characterization and the use of this method (when core  
support is required). There is however some tendency to reward the  
large parties or other core support (as intended) and the behaviour is  
quite natural with some more common sets of votes.
snip

Juho,

I don't see the IRV core support idea as a serious part of IRV's motivation.

Rather I see it as reasonable propaganda to on the one hand offer some
vague philosophical excuse for not meeting the Condorcet criterion, and 
on the other reassure those who are wary of too radical a change (from 
Plurality)
that this method will not elect a candidate with very few first preferences.

The proper criterion that I see it as being most closely positively linked to 
is 
Mutual Dominant Third, a weakened version of  Condorcet that says that if more
than a third of the voters vote all the members of subset S of candidates above
all the non-member candidates and all the members of S pairwise beat all
the non-members, then the winner must come from S.

Also of course it seeks to put a positive spin on the fact that the candidate
with the fewest first preferences can't win, even if that candidate is the big
pairwise beats-all winner.

snip
 51: ABC
 41: BCA
 08: CAB

 BA 61.5 - 59,  BC 112.5 - 12,  AC 76.5 - 53

51% voted A as their unique favourite and 59% voted A above B, and  
yet B wins.

Yes, and I believe there are more criteria that the method fails. We  
should however from some point of view be happy since the method  
elected B that seems to have 92% core support (maybe this is how I  
defined core support in this method).
snip

Defining as you do core support as approval, what is your objection to
simpler methods that don't allow ranking among unapproved candidates
(and so just interpret ranking above bottom as approval) such as the
Smith//Approval(ranking) method I endorse?

Or if you think that it is justified for a candidate with a very big approval
score to beat a majority favourite with less approval, why not simply
promote the plain Approval method?

Chris Benham


  
__
Yahoo!7: Catch-up on your favourite Channel 7 TV shows easily, legally, and for 
free at PLUS7. www.tv.yahoo.com.au/plus7


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] IRV vs Plurality

2010-01-25 Thread Chris Benham
Juho  wrote (25 Jan 2010):

I reply to myself since I want to present one possible simple method  
that combines Condorcet and added weight to first preferences  
(something that IRV offers in its own peculiar way).

Let's add an approval cutoff in the Condorcet ballots. The first  
approach could be to accept only winners that have some agreed amount  
of approvals. But I'll skip that approach and propose something  
softer. A clear approval cutoff sounds too black and white to me  
(unless there is already some agreed level of approval that must be  
met).

The proposal is simply to add some more strength to opinions that  
cross the approval cutoff. Ballot ABCD would be counted as 1 point  
to pairwise comparisons AB and CD but some higher number of points  
(e.g. 1.5) to comparisons AC, AD, BC and BD. This would introduce  
some approval style strategic opportunities in the method but basic  
ranking would stay as sincere as it was. I don't believe the approval  
related strategic problems would be as bad in this method as in  
Approval itself.
snip

The  some higher number of points (e.g. 1.5)  looks arbitrary and results
in the method failing Majority Favourite, never mind Condorcet etc.

51: ABC
41: BCA
08: CAB

BA 61.5 - 59,  BC 112.5 - 12,  AC 76.5 - 53

51% voted A as their unique favourite and 59% voted A above B, and yet B wins.

Chris Benham


  
__
Yahoo!7: Catch-up on your favourite Channel 7 TV shows easily, legally, and for 
free at PLUS7. www.tv.yahoo..com.au/plus7


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Strong Minmal Defense, Top Ratings

2010-01-21 Thread Chris Benham
In a recent EM post in another thread, I defined and recommended the
Strong Minimal Defense, Top Ratings method  (that I first proposed
in 2008) as the best of the methods that meet the Favourite Betrayal
criterion, and also the best 3-slot ballot method:

*Voters fill out 3-slot ratings ballots, default rating is bottom-most
(indicating least preferred and not approved).

Interpreting top and middle rating as approval, disqualify all candidates
with an approval score lower than their maximum approval-opposition 
(MAO) score.
(X's  MAO score is the approval score of the most approved candidate on
ballots that don't approve X).

Elect the undisqualified candidate with the highest top-ratings score.*

I gather from one off-list response that this sentence of mine could have
been more clear:

'Unlike MCA/Bucklin this fails Later-no-Help (as well as LNHarm) so the voters 
have a less
strong incentive to truncate..'

I neglected to mention that I think it is desirable that after top-voting X, 
ranking Y below X
(but above bottom) should be about equally likely to help X as to harm X.

This implies that if one of the the two LNhs are failed, it is desirable that 
the other is also.

MCA/Bucklin meets Later-no-Help while failing Later-no-Harm. The voters have a 
big incentive
to truncate, and to equal-rank at the top, so with strategic voters it tends to 
look like  plain Approval.

In SMD,TR after top-rating X, middle-rating Y may harm X or may help X.

As discussed in 2008, it fails Mono-add-Top  (and so Participation).

8: C
3: F
2: XF
2: YF
2: ZF

F wins after all other candidates are disqualified, but if  2 FC ballots are
added C wins.

Of course it is far from uniquely bad in that respect. A big plus for it is 
that it is virtually alone
in meeting my proposed  Unmanipulable Majority strategy criterion:

Regarding my proposed Unmanipulable Majority criterion:

*If (assuming there are more than two candidates) the ballot 
rules don't constrain voters to expressing fewer than three 
preference-levels, and A wins being voted above B on more 
than half the ballots, then it must not be possible to make B 
the winner by altering any of the ballots on which B is voted 
above A without raising their ranking or rating of B.*

http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2008-December/023530.html

In common with MCA it meets mono-raise (aka ordinary monotonicity) and a 3-slot 
ballot version of
Majority for Solid Coaltions, which says that if  majority of the voters rate a 
subset S of the candidates
above all the outside-S candidates, the winner must come from S.


From the post that introduced SMD,TR:


It is more Condorcetish and has a less severe later-harm problem than MCA, 
Bucklin,
or  Cardinal Ratings (aka Range, Average Rating, etc.)

40: AB
35: B
25: C

Approval scores:    A40,   B75,   C25 
Approval Opp.:  A35,   B25,   C75
Top-ratings scores: A40,   B35,   C25 

They elect B, but SMD,TR elects the Condorcet winner A.


Chris Benham


  
__
See what's on at the movies in your area. Find out now: 
http://au.movies.yahoo.com/session-times/


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Two simple alternative voting methods that are fairer than IRV/STV and lack most IRV/STV flaws

2010-01-20 Thread Chris Benham
Dave Ketchum wrote (18 Jan 2010):

In response I will pick on LNH for not being a serious reason for  
rejecting Condorcet - that such failure can occur with reasonable  
voting choices for which the voter knows what is happening.  Quoting  
from Wikipedia:

For example in an election conducted using the Condorcet compliant  
method Ranked pairs the following votes are cast:
49: A
25: B
26: CB
B is preferred to A by 51 votes to 49 votes. A is preferred to C by  
49 votes to 26 votes. C is preferred to B by 26 votes to 25 votes.
There is no Condorcet winner and B is the Ranked pairs winner.
Suppose the 25 B voters give an additional preference to their  
second choice C.
The votes are now:
49: A
25: BC
26: CB
C is preferred to A by 51 votes to 49 votes. C is preferred to B by  
26 votes to 25 votes. B is preferred to A by 51 votes to 49 votes.
C is now the Condorcet winner and therefore the Ranked pairs winner.
By giving a second preference to candidate C the 25 B voters have  
caused their first choice to be defeated.


Pro-A is about equal strength with anti-A.  For this it makes sense  
for anti-A to give their side the best odds with the second vote  
pattern, not caring about LNH (B and C may compete with each other,  
but clearly care more about trouncing A).
snip

Dave,
Your assumption that  B and C may compete with each other, but clearly 
care more about trouncing A  is based on what?

The ballots referred to contain only the voters' rankings, with no indications
about their relative preference strengths.

If you read my entire post you will see that in it I endorse three methods,
one of which is a Condorcet method.

Chris Benham


  
__
See what's on at the movies in your area. Find out now: 
http://au.movies.yahoo.com/session-times/


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] IRV vs Plurality ( Kristofer Munsterhjelm )

2010-01-17 Thread Chris Benham
Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote (17 Jan 2010):

To me, it seems that the method becomes Approval-like when (number of 
graduations) is less than (number of candidates). When that is the case, 
you *have* to rate some candidates equal, unless you opt not to rate 
them at all.

That won't make much of a difference when the number of candidates is 
huge (100 or so), but then, rating 100 candidates would be a pain. I'd 
say it would be better to just have plain yes/no Approval for a first 
round, then pick the 5-10 most approved for a second round (using 
Range, Condorcet, whatever). Or use minmax approval or PAV or somesuch, 
as long as it homes in on the likely winners of a full vote.

Simply using plain Approval to reduce the field to the top x point scorers
who then compete in the final round seems unsatifactory to me because
of the  Rich Party incentive (clone problem) for parties to field x 
candidates;
and because of the tempting Push-over (turkey raising) strategy incentive.

Chris Benham


  
__
See what's on at the movies in your area. Find out now: 
http://au.movies.yahoo.com/session-times/


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Two simple alternative voting methods that are fairer than IRV/STV and lack most IRV/STV flaws

2010-01-17 Thread Chris Benham
Abd Lomax wrote (17 Jan 2010):

snip

Chris is Australian, and is one of a rare breed: someone who actually 
understands STV and supports it for single-winner because of LNH 
satisfaction. Of course, LNH is a criterion disliked by many voting 
system experts, and it's based on a political concept which is, quite 
as you say, contrary to sensible negotiation process.
 snip

I endorse IRV (Alternative Vote, with voters able to strictly rank from the top 
however 
many candidates they choose) as a good method, much better than Plurality or 
TTR,
and the best of the methods that are invulnerable to Burial and meet 
Later-no-Harm.

Some of us see elections as primarily a contest and not a negotiation process.

I endorse IRV because it has a maximal set of  (what I consider to be) 
desirable
criterion compliances:

Majority for Solid Coalitions (aka Mutual Majority)
Woodall's Plurality criterion
Mutual Dominant Third
Condorcet Loser 

Burial Invulnerability
Later-no-Harm
Later-no-Help

Mono-add-Top
Mono-add-Plump  (implied by mono-add-top)
Mono-append
Irrelevant Ballots

Clone-Winner
Clone-Loser  (together these two add up to Clone Independence)

As far as I can tell, the only real points of dissatisfaction with IRV in 
Australia are
(a) that in some jurisdictions the voter is not allowed to truncate (on pain of 
his/her
vote  being binned as invalid) and (b) that it isn't multi-winner PR so that 
minor
parties can be fairly represented.

I gather the Irish are also reasonably satisfied with it for the election of 
their President.

snip
I've really come to like Bucklin, because it allows voters to 
exercise full power for one candidate at the outset, then add, *if 
they choose to do so*, alternative approved candidates.
snip

The version of Bucklin Abd advocates (using ratings ballots with voters able to 
give
as many candidates they like the same rating and also able to skip slots) tends
to be strategically equivalent to Approval  but entices voters to play silly 
strategy
games sitting out rounds.

It would be better if 3-slot ballots are used, in which case it is the same 
thing as
(one of the versions of) Majority Choice Approval (MCA).

IMO the best method that meets  Favourite Betrayal (and also the best 3-slot 
ballot method)
is Strong Minimal Defence, Top Ratings:

*Voters fill out 3-slot ratings ballots, default rating is bottom-most
(indicating least preferred and not approved).

Interpreting top and middle rating as approval, disqualify all candidates
with an approval score lower than their maximum approval-opposition 
(MAO) score.
(X's  MAO score is the approval score of the most approved candidate on
ballots that don't approve X).

Elect the undisqualified candidate with the highest top-ratings score.*

Unlike MCA/Bucklin this fails Later-no-Help (as well as LNHarm) so the voters 
have a less
strong incentive to truncate.

Unlike MCA/Bucklin this meets Irrelevant Ballots. In MCA candidate X could be 
declared the
winner in the first round, and then it is found that a small number of voters 
had been wrongly
excluded and these new voters choose to openly bullet-vote for nobody (perhaps 
themselves
as write-ins) and then their additional ballots raise the majority threshold 
and trigger a second 
round in which X loses.

I can't take seriously any method that fails Irrelevant Ballots.

Compliance with Favourite Betrayal is incompatible with Condorcet. If you are 
looking for a 
relatively simple Condorcet method, I recommend Smith//Approval (ranking):

*Voters rank from the top candidates they approve. Equal-ranking is allowed. 
Interpreting being ranked above at least one other candidate as approval, elect 
the most 
approved member of the Smith set (the smallest non-empty set  S of candidates 
that pairwise
beat all the outside-S candidates).*


Chris Benham


  
__
See what's on at the movies in your area.. Find out now: 
http://au.movies.yahoo.com/session-times/


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Two simple alternative voting methods that are fairer than IRV/STV and lack most IRV/STV flaws

2010-01-15 Thread Chris Benham
Abd ul-Rahman Lomax wrote  (14 Jan 2010):

snip
Why does Kathy elsewhere defend Top Two Runoff which isn't monotonic?

This opinion, stated as fact, is false. Top Two Runoff is a two-step 
system, and monotonicity doesn't refer to such. It refers to the 
effect of a vote on a single ballot as to the result of that ballot 
only. A vote for a candidate on a primary ballot in TTR will always 
help the candidate supported to make it either to a majority and a 
win, or to make it into the runoff. It never hurts that candidate. 
snip

A vote for any candidate X in any given IRV  counting round will likewise 
help X to a majority win or to make it into the next round.

The contention that a two-step system (meaning requiring voters to make
two trips to the polls) to elect a single candidate isn't allowed to be judged
in aggregate is absurd.

snip
Did supporters of the Lizard vote for the Wizard in order to create the Lizard 
vs. Wizard election in Louisiana? I rather doubt it. But this wouldn't create a 
monotonicity violation, and the problem is created by eliminations, 
it doesn't exist with repeated balloting.
snip

With repeated balloting there are no eliminations?  As I undersatnd it, in
Top Two Runoff all but the top two first-round vote getters are eliminated
if no candidate gets more than half the votes in the first round.

Chris Benham


  
__
See what's on at the movies in your area. Find out now: 
http://au.movies.yahoo.com/session-times/


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Two simple alternative voting methods that are fairer than IRV/STV and lack most IRV/STV flaws

2010-01-14 Thread Chris Benham
 than satisfying  Majority Favorite?

Why does Kathy elsewhere defend Top Two Runoff which isn't monotonic?


Chris Benham


  
__
See what's on at the movies in your area. Find out now: 
http://au.movies.yahoo.com/session-times/

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] IRV vs Plurality

2010-01-14 Thread Chris Benham
Dave Ketchum wrote (9 Jan 2010):

 
For a quick look at IRV: 35A, 33BC, 32C

A wins for being liked a bit better than B - 3533.

That C is liked better than A is too trivial for IRV to notice - 6535.

Let one BC voter change to C and C would win over A - 6535.

Let a couple BC voters switch to A and C would win over A - 6337.

Point is that IRV counting often ignores parts of votes.

Dave Ketchum


Yes. 

The implicit assumption seems to be that ignoring parts of votes is 
always a pure negative but not doing so can cause failure of Later-no-Harm
and Later-no-Help, and vulnerability to Burial.

All Condorcet methods fail those criteria, while IRV meets them.

Note that I wrote that IRV is my favourite of the methods that are
invulnerable to Burial strategy and meet Later-no-Harm.

I didn't write that it was necessarily preferable to to all of the methods
that meet the Condorcet criterion.

 
Chris Benham


  
__
See what's on at the movies in your area. Find out now: 
http://au.movies.yahoo.com/session-times/


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] IRV vs Plurality

2010-01-11 Thread Chris Benham
Kathy Dopp wrote (11 Jan 2010):

snip

Plurality is far better than IRV for many many reasons including:

1. preserves the right to cast a vote that always positively affects
the chances of winning of the candidate one votes for

2. allows all voters the right to participate in the final counting
round in the case of top two runoff or primary/general elections

snip

IRV satisfies both of these. 

Regarding the first,assuming that the candidate one votes for refers 
to the candidate the voter top-ranks, then top-ranking X in an IRV election 
has the same positive effect on X's chance of winning as does voting for
X in a Plurality election.

It is true that sometimes in an IRV election a subset of X's sincere 
supporters may be able to do better for X by top-ranking some non-X,
whereas in Plurality the best strategy for all of X's supporters is always 
just to vote for X; but that is different.

IRV meets Mono-add-top, which means that a voter who top-ranks X
would never have done better for X by staying home.

Having arrived at the voting booth, the X supporter's overwhelmingly 
best probabilistic IRV strategy is to top-rank X.

Regarding Kathy's second point, IRV voters should be allowed to
strictly rank from the top as many candidates as they wish. 
The voter is then free to ensure that s/he participates in the final
counting round by simply ranking all the candidates (or alternatively
if the likely front-runners are known then just make it very likely by
ranking among them).


Chris Benham


  
__
See what's on at the movies in your area. Find out now: 
http://au.movies.yahoo.com/session-times/


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] IRV is best method meeting 'later no harm'?

2009-11-27 Thread Chris Benham
Steve Eppley wrote (26 Nov 2009):
Can it be said that Later No Harm (LNH) is satisfied by the variation of
IRV that allows candidates to withdraw from contention after the votes are
cast?

No. Take this classic (on EM) scenario:

49: A
24: B
27: CB

A is the normal IRV winner, but in the variation you describe C presumably
withdraws causing B to win.

49: A
24: BC
27: CB

If the B supporters instead of truncating vote BC then C wins. Assuming
C accepts the win the B voters have caused B to lose by not truncating, a 
clear failure of Later-no-Harm.

Steve wrote:
Since IRV is said to satisfy LNH, then one must say Plurality Rule
satisfies LNH too, because Plurality Rule can be viewed as just a
variation of IRV with a smaller limit (one candidate per voter).

Yes, and I did. I listed FPP (First-Preference Plurality or more traditionally
First Past the Post) as a method that meets Later-no-Harm.

I understand that in the US the Alternative Vote is called IRV, but that 
sometimes
various inferior approximations are given the same label.

Chris Benham


  
__
Win 1 of 4 Sony home entertainment packs thanks to Yahoo!7.
Enter now: http://au.docs.yahoo.com/homepageset/

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-25 Thread Chris Benham
Robert Bristow-Johnson wrote (9 Nov 2009):

Of course IRV, Condorcet, and Borda use different methods to tabulate  
the votes and select the winner and my opinion is that IRV (asset  
voting, i might call it commodity voting: your vote is a  
commodity that you transfer according to your preferences) is a  
kabuki dance of transferred votes.  and there is an *arbitrary*  
evaluation in the elimination of candidates in the IRV rounds: 2nd- 
choice votes don't count for shit in deciding who to eliminate (who  
decided that?  2nd-choice votes are as good as last-choice?  under  
what meaningful and consistent philosophy was that decided?), then  
when your candidate is eliminated your 2nd-choice vote counts as much  
as your 1st-choice.

Regarding IRV's philosophy: each voter has single vote that is transferable
according to a rule that meets Later-no-Harm, Later-no-Help and Majority
for Solid Coalitions.

I rate IRV (Alternative Vote with unlimited strict ranking from the top) as the
best of the single-winner methods that meet Later-no-Harm.

Chris Benham


  
__
Win 1 of 4 Sony home entertainment packs thanks to Yahoo!7.
Enter now: http://au.docs.yahoo.com/homepageset/

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] 'Shulze (Votes For)' definition?

2009-08-14 Thread Chris Benham
Marcus,

I have some questions about your draft (dated  23 June 2009)  Shulze method
paper, posted:

http://m-schulze.webhop.net/schulze1.pdf

On page 13 you define some of the ways of measuring defeat strengths,
two of which are  Votes For and  Votes Against:

snip

Example 5 (
then the strength is measured primarily by the absolute number N[e,f] of votes 
for candidate e.
(N[e,f],N[f,e]) for (N[g,h],N[h,g]) if and only if at least one of the 
following conditions is satisfied: 
1. N[e,f]  N[g,h]. 2. N[e,f] = N[g,h] and N[f,e]  N[h,g]. 
 
Example 6 (votes against): When the strength of the pairwise defeat ef is 
measured by votes against, 
then the strength is measured primarily by the absolute number N[f,e] of votes 
for candidate f. 
(N[e,f],N[f,e]) against (N[g,h],N[h,g]) if and only if at least one of the 
following conditions is satisfied: 
1. N[f,e]  N[h,g]. 2. N[f,e] = N[h,g] and N[e,f]  N[g,h].
 
snip
 
I am a little bit confused as to the exact meaning of the phrase the absolute 
number ..of 
votes for candidate E.
 
Does the number of votes for E mean 'the number of ballots on which E is 
ranked above
at least one other candidate'?
 
Or does it mean something that can be read purely from the pairwise matrix?

Does it mean 'the sum of all the entries in the pairwise matrix that represent 
pairwise votes for E'?

Do the two methods 'Schulze(Votes For)' and  'Shulze(Votes Against)'  meet  
Independence
of  Clones?

I look forward to hearing your clarification.


Chris  Benham
 votes for): When the strength of the pairwise defeat ef is measured by votes 
for, 


  
__
Find local businesses and services in your area with Yahoo!7 Local.
Get started: http://local.yahoo.com.au
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] 'Shulze (Votes For)' definition?

2009-08-14 Thread Chris Benham
Kevin,

Or does it mean something that can be
read purely from the pairwise matrix?

It's the latter, read from the matrix. Absolute number is in contrast to
using margin or ratio.

Thanks for that, but it isn't the concept of absolute number that I'm having
trouble with.

What I don't understand is the difference between winning votes (which I'm
familiar with) and votes for,  as they are both defined on page 13 of Marcus
Shulze's paper, pasted below.


http://m-schulze.webhop.net/schulze1.pdf

snip

Example 3 (
by winning votes, then the strength is measured primarily by the absolute 
number 
N[e,f] of votes for the winner of this pairwise defeat. 

 
snip
 Example 5 (
votes for candidate e. votes for): When the strength of the pairwise defeat ef 
is measured by 
votes for, then the strength is measured primarily by the absolute number 
N[e,f] of winning votes): When the strength of the pairwise defeat ef is 
measured 
 
snip
Chris Benham


  
__
Find local businesses and services in your area with Yahoo!7 Local.
Get started: http://local.yahoo.com.au
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Electowiki relicensed to Creative Commons Share Alike 3.0

2009-07-27 Thread Chris Benham
In the Electowiki article on the River method, none of  these 
links work properly:

* First proposal 
* 
* slight refinement 
* 
* More concise definition. In this last version, River is defined 
very similarly to ranked pairs. 
* 
* Example using 2004 baseball scores. This shows how a 
* 14-candidate election winner can be determined much more 
* quickly using River than with RP or Schulze. 

* Early criticism of the River method. This shows that the River 
* method violates mono-add-top and mono-remove-bottom 
 
One is broken and the rest go to the wrong EM post.
 
http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/River

 
Also, some of my EM posts in the Electorama archive have links 
to other EM posts which also go to the wrong one.
 
 
Chris Benham


  

Access Yahoo!7 Mail on your mobile. Anytime. Anywhere.
Show me how: http://au.mobile.yahoo.com/mail
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Condorcet/Range DSV

2009-07-01 Thread Chris Benham
Jameson,

Sorry to be so tardy in replying.

 
That is not a bad suggestion; I like both systems. Yours gives less of a 
motivation for 
honest rating: In most cases, it makes A100 B99 C0 equivalent to A100 B51 C0.

No, mine gives more motivation for honest rating (in the sense that it gives 
less incentive 
for dishonest rating).   If  A, B, C  are the three Smith-set members then 
it makes both
A100, B99, C0 and  A100, B51, C0  equivalent to A100, B100, C0.

I guess you'd give exactly half an approval if B were at exactly 50?

Yes.

49: A100,  B0,  C0
24: B100,  A0,  C0
27: C100,  B80, A0

More than half the voters vote A not above equal-bottom and below B, and yet
A wins.

True. Yet B could win if the C voters rated B 99, which would still be 
Condorcet-honest.

That isn't really in principle relevant because your suggested method doesn't 
guarantee to a
section of the voters comprising more than half  who rate/rank A bottom that 
they can ensure
that A loses while still expressing all their sincere pairwise preferences.

4999: A100,  B0,  C0
2500: B100,  A0,  C0
2501: C100,  B99, A0

BA 5001- 4999,  AC,  CB. 

In this modified version of my demonstration that your suggested method fails 
Minimal Defense,
the majority that prefer B to A cannot ensure that B loses and still be 
Condorcet-honest.

Anyway, the main motivations for a DSV-type proposal like this is to make it 
really rare for voters 
to have enough information to strategize without it backfiring. I think that 
including full range information 
(that is, my proposal as opposed to yours) makes the voter's analysis harder, 
and so makes the system  
more resistant to strategy. 

I don't think the type of examples I've given would be really rare, and in 
them I don't think the C
supporters have to very well-informed or clever to work out that their 
candidate can't beat A and
so they have incentive to falsely vote B (at least) equal to their favourite.

Favorite Betrayal in this case means, honest ABC voters who know that A's 
losing and that CBA 
and ACB votes are both relatively common, can vote BAC to cause a Condorcet 
tie and perhaps 
get B to win ...

Not necessarily, no. You seem to be assuming that Favourite Betrayal strategy 
is only about falsely creating
a  Condorcet tie when one's favourite isn't the (presumed to be) sincere 
Condorcet winner. It can
also be the case that the strategist fears that if she votes sincerely there 
will be no Condorcet winner,
so she order-reverse compromises to try to make her compromise the voted 
Condorcet winner.


Chris  Benham







Jameson Quinn wrote  (26 June 2009) :


This Condorcet-Range hybrid you suggest seems to me to inherit a couple of
the problems with Range Voting.

Fair enough.



It fails the Minimal Defense criterion.

49: A100,  B0,  C0
24: B100,  A0,  C0
27: C100,  B80, A0

More than half the voters vote A not above equal-bottom and below B, and yet
A wins.

True. Yet B could win if the C voters rated B 99, which would still be 
Condorcet-honest.



Also I don't like the fact that the result can be affected just by varying the 
resolution
of  ratings ballots used, an arbitrary feature.

I think it would be better if the method derived approval from the ballots, 
approving all
candidates the voter rates above the voter's average rating of  the Smith set 
members.

That is not a bad suggestion; I like both systems. Yours gives less of a 
motivation for honest rating: In most cases, it makes A100 B99 C0 equivalent to 
A100 B51 C0. I guess you'd give exactly half an approval if B were at exactly 
50?

Anyway, the main motivations for a DSV-type proposal like this is to make it 
really rare for voters to have enough information to strategize without it 
backfiring. I think that including full range information (that is, my proposal 
as opposed to yours) makes the voter's analysis harder, and so makes the system 
 more resistant to strategy. Under honest range votes, it also helps improve 
the utility.




For strategies which don't change the content
of the Smith set, it does very well on other criteria, fulfilling
Participation, Consistency, and Local IIA. 

Sorry, I wasn't clear. If the content of the smith set DOES change, this method 
fails all those criteria. See below for argument of why that's not too bad.



And because it uses Range ballots as an input but encourages
more honest voting than Range,..

That is more true of the automated approval version I suggested, and also it 
isn't
completely clear-cut because Range meets Favourite Betrayal which is 
incompatible
with Condorcet.

Favorite Betrayal in this case means, honest ABC voters who know that A's 
losing and that CBA and ACB votes are both relatively common, can vote 
BAC to cause a Condorcet tie and perhaps get B to win (if A would win that tie, 
then A would be winning already, so they can't get their favorite through 
betrayal. In other words, at least it's monotonic

[EM] Condorcet/Range DSV

2009-06-26 Thread Chris Benham
Jameson,

This Condorcet-Range hybrid you suggest seems to me to inherit a couple of
the problems with Range Voting. 

It fails the Minimal Defense criterion.

49: A100,  B0,  C0
24: B100,  A0,  C0
27: C100,  B80, A0

More than half the voters vote A not above equal-bottom and below B, and yet
A wins.

Also I don't like the fact that the result can be affected just by varying the 
resolution
of  ratings ballots used, an arbitrary feature.

I think it would be better if the method derived approval from the ballots, 
approving all
candidates the voter rates above the voter's average rating of  the Smith set 
members.


For strategies which don't change the content
of the Smith set, it does very well on other criteria, fulfilling
Participation, Consistency, and Local IIA. 


The criteria you mention only apply (as a strict pass/fail test) to voting 
methods, not 
strategies (and  have nothing to do with strategy).

We know that Condorcet is incompatible with Participation  (and so I suppose 
also with
the similar Consistency).  I don't see how a method that fails Condorcet Loser 
can meet
Local IIA.

And because it uses Range ballots as an input but encourages
more honest voting than Range,..

That is more true of the automated approval version I suggested, and also it 
isn't
completely clear-cut because Range meets Favourite Betrayal which is 
incompatible
with Condorcet.

 
Chris Benham


Jameson Quinn wrote (25 June 2009) wrote:


 
I believe that using Range ballots, renormalized on the Smith set as a
Condorcet tiebreaker, is a very good system by many criteria. I'm of course
nothttp://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2005-January/014469.htmlthe
first one to propose this method, but I'd like to justify and analyze
it further.

I call the system Condorcet/Range DSV because it can be conceived as a kind of
Declared Strategy Voting system, which rationally strategizes voters' ballots 
for them assuming that
they have correct but not-quite-complete information about all other voters.
Let me explain.

I have been looking into fully-rational DSV methods using Range ballots both
as input and as the underlying method in which strategies play out. It turns
out to be impossible, as far as I can tell, to get a stable, deterministic,
rational result from strategy when there is no Condorcet winner. (Assume
there's a stable result, A. Since A is not a cond. winner, there is some B
which beats A by a majority. If all BA voters bullet vote for B then B is a
Condorcet winner, and so wins. Thus there exists an offensive strategy. This
proof is not fully general because it neglects defensive strategies, but in
practice trying to work out a coherent, stable DSV which includes defensive
strategies seems impossible to me.) Note that, on the other hand, there MUST
exist a stable probabilistic result, that is, a Nash equilibrium.

Let's take the case of a 3-candidate Smith set to start with. (This
simplifies things drastically and I've never seen a real-world example of a
larger set.) In the Nash equilibrium, all three candidates have a nonzero
probability of winning (or at least, are within one vote of having such a
probability). Voters are dissuaded from using offensive strategy by the real
probability that it would backfire and result in a worse candidate winning.
This Nash equilibrium is in some sense the best result, in that all voters
have equal power and no voter can strategically alter it. However, it is
both complicated-to-compute and unnecessarily probabilistic. Forest Simmons has
proposed an interesting
methodhttp://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2003-October/011028.htmlfor
artificially reducing the win probability of the less-likely
candidates,
but this method increases computational complexity without being able to
reach a single, fully stable result. (Simmons proposed simply selecting the
most-probable candidate, which is probably the best answer, but it does
invalidate the whole strategic motivation).
There's an easier way. Simply assume that any given voter has only
near-perfect information, not perfect information. That is, each voter knows
exactly which candidates are in the Smith set, but makes an ideosyncratic
(random) evaluation of the probability of each of those candidates winning.
That voter's ideal strategic ballot is an approval style ballot in which all
candidates above their expected value are rated at the top and all
candidates below at the bottom. However, averaging over the different
ballots they'd give for different subjective win probabilities, you get
something very much like a range ballot renormalized so that there is at
least one Smith set candidate at top and bottom. (It's not exactly that, the
math is more complex, especially when the Smith set is bigger than 3; but
it's a good enough approximation and much simpler than the exact answer).

Let's look at a few scenarios to see how this plays out

[EM] voting strategy with rank-order-with-equality ballots

2009-06-09 Thread Chris Benham
Warren,

How true is it that approval-style voting is strategic for Schulze?

Not very true. It depends on the voter's information and  sincere ratings.
Schulze, being a Condorcet method fails Favourite Betrayal.

Is Schulze with approval-style ballots a better or worse voting system 
than plain approval?

If approval-style ballots are compelled than Schulze is the same as plain
Approval.  If they are merely allowed  (as Marcus Schulze and other 
proponents favour) then in my opinion it is better than Approval.

In the zero-information case, the voter with a big enough gap in hir sincere 
ratings
does best to rank all the candidates above the gap equal top and to strictly
rank all those below it  (random-filling if necessary in the absence of a 
sincere
full ranking).

I find it preferable that the zero-info. strategy for a ranked-ballot method be 
either
full sincere ranking regardless of  relative ratings (as in IRV and Margins) 
or  sincere
ranking above the big ratings gap and truncation below it  (as in 
Smith//Approval).

By  Shulze  I have been meaning  Shulze(Winning Votes), the 'standard version'
favoured by Marcus himself and other proponents. 

In January this year I suggested a different version I prefer:

http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2009-January/023959.html


Chris Benham


 
 Warren Smith wrote (8 June 2009):

One problem is nobody really has a good understanding of what good strategy is.

If one believes that range voting becomes approval voting in the
presence of strategic voters (often, anyhow)...

One might similarly speculate that
strategic voters in a system such as Schilze beatpaths ALLOWING ballots
with both  and = (e.g. AB=C=DE=F is a legal ballot)  usually the
strategic vote
is approval style i.e. of form A=B=CD=E=F, say, with just ONE .
One might then speculate that Schulze, just like range, then becomes
equivalent to approval voting for strategic voters.

Well...  how true or false is that?   Is Schulze with approval-style ballots
a better or worse voting system than plain approval?

How true is it that approval-style voting is strategic for Schulze?

I'd like to hear people's ideas on this question.  (And not
necessarily just for Schulze -- substitute other methods too, if you
prefer.)

The trouble is, range voting is simple. Simple enough that you can
reach a pretty full understanding of what strategic range voting is.
  (Which is not at all trivial,
but it can pretty much be done.) In contrast, a lot of Condorcet
systems including Schulze are complicated. Complicated enough that
making confident statements
about their behavior with strtagic voters (or even undertsnading what
strtagy IS) is
hard.

Frankly, I've heard various vague but confident claims about strategy
for Schulze  the like, and my impression is those making the claims
know very little about what they
are talking about.  I also know very little on this, the difference is
I admit it :)


  Need a Holiday? Win a $10,000 Holiday of your choice. Enter 
now.http://us.lrd.yahoo.com/_ylc=X3oDMTJxN2x2ZmNpBF9zAzIwMjM2MTY2MTMEdG1fZG1lY2gDVGV4dCBMaW5rBHRtX2xuawNVMTEwMzk3NwR0bV9uZXQDWWFob28hBHRtX3BvcwN0YWdsaW5lBHRtX3BwdHkDYXVueg--/SIG=14600t3ni/**http%3A//au.rd.yahoo.com/mail/tagline/creativeholidays/*http%3A//au.docs.yahoo.com/homepageset/%3Fp1=other%26p2=au%26p3=mailtagline
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] voting strategy with rank-order-with-equality ballots

2009-06-09 Thread Chris Benham
Kevin,

I have found that Schulze(wv) had little favorite betrayal incentive. In 
simulations I mentioned in June 05, out of 50,000 trials, Schulze(wv) showed 
incentive 7 times, compared to 251 for Schulze(margins), 363 for 
Condorcet//Approval, and 625 for my erroneous interpretation of 
ERBucklin(whole).

What was this erroneous interpretation?  How can a method that meets 
Favourite Betrayal, such as ER-Bucklin(whole) ever show favourite
betrayal incentive?

Chris Benham


 

Kevin Venzke wrote (9 June 2009):

Hello,

I think in Schulze(wv) and similar, decent methods, you shouldn't rank the 
worse of two frontrunners or below. I don't think that's a big problem though.

I have found that Schulze(wv) had little favorite betrayal incentive. In 
simulations I mentioned in June 05, out of 50,000 trials, Schulze(wv) showed 
incentive 7 times, compared to 251 for Schulze(margins), 363 for 
Condorcet//Approval, and 625 for my erroneous interpretation of 
ERBucklin(whole).

The simulation worked by examining the effects of introducing a strict ranking 
between two candidate ranked tied at the top. So a method showed favorite 
betrayal incentive when introducing a strict ranking AB moved the win to one 
of these candidates from a third candidate.

You can look at incentive to compress at the top, but it's not as informative. 
There is compression incentive where introducing the AB strict ranking moves 
the win e.g. from B to a third candidate. This happened hundreds of times for 
the methods I looked at (1200 for ICA).

I guess you could look at the odds that a strict ranking will help or hurt 
compared to an equal ranking, overall. I'm not sure that would be very 
informative either though. For one thing, it would only tell you about the 
zero-info case. And it wouldn't consider utility, which should be important: 
Whether or not you should compress at the top probably depends on how much you 
like those candidates compared to the other candidates.

Kevin Venzke


  Need a Holiday? Win a $10,000 Holiday of your choice. Enter 
now.http://us.lrd.yahoo.com/_ylc=X3oDMTJxN2x2ZmNpBF9zAzIwMjM2MTY2MTMEdG1fZG1lY2gDVGV4dCBMaW5rBHRtX2xuawNVMTEwMzk3NwR0bV9uZXQDWWFob28hBHRtX3BvcwN0YWdsaW5lBHRtX3BwdHkDYXVueg--/SIG=14600t3ni/**http%3A//au.rd.yahoo.com/mail/tagline/creativeholidays/*http%3A//au.docs.yahoo.com/homepageset/%3Fp1=other%26p2=au%26p3=mailtagline
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Beatpath GMC compliance a mistaken standard?

2009-01-26 Thread Chris Benham
Kevin,

You wrote (25 Jan 2009):

I think there ought to be a clear distinction between criteria whose
violation is absurd no matter what the circumstances, and criteria
whose violation is absurd due to other available options.

I don't see why (particularly).

There are very few (named) criteria whose failure I'd call absurd no
matter what.

Of those criteria, which is the one you consider to be the least absurd?
(Or if you can't say, just name some.)

 Does your question mean that this really is how you view the
 difference between CDTT and Mutual Majority, is in terms of
 the candidates of the winning set sharing a probability pie?
 
 Not exactly. No-one has ever suggested  MM,Random Ballot as a 
 good method and few have suggested  that sometimes the clearly most
 appropriate winner is not in the MM set (as I have regarding the CDTT set).

I think that either isn't relevant or doesn't help your case.

Then you can regard that as a rhetorical aside. To answer your question again
I would say that way of putting it seems too mild to me, but I can't see that 
it's
irrational.

The question is about why you view MM's behavior as qualitatively different
from CDTT's behavior, when in practice, in a real method, it's exactly the same 
behavior.

In a previous message I think I made it clear that I don't accept that it is 
exactly
the same behavior.

[I don't accept that 'being tossed out of the favoured (not excluded from 
winning)
set' is exactly the same phenomenon as 'being joined by others in the 
favoured set'.]

Well, supposing that the public decided to accept a method that failed
a positional criterion, I guess at that time I would drop that criterion.

Does that mean that you think all positional criteria have no value other 
than to appease
misguided members  of  the public?

Hypothetically if the public were willing to accept any method I would
propose to them, and not question any of its results, then I wouldn't care
about appearances. I would just give them the method that I felt would
perform the best.

In this context, what  do you mean by appearances?  How can a method that you 
feel 
performs the best have (in your eyes) anything wrong with its appearance?

Chris Benham



Hi Chris,

--- En date de : Ven 23.1.09, Chris Benham cbenha...@yahoo.com.au a écrit :
 I can't see what's so highly absurd about
 failing mono-append. It's
 basically a limited case of mono-raise, and one that
 doesn't seem
 especially more important. Is it absurd to fail
 mono-raise?
 
 The absurdity of failing mono-append is compounded by the
 cheapness of
 meeting it. As with mono-add-plump the quasi-intelligent
 device is given
 simple and pure new information. Being confused by it is
 simply unforgivable
 *stupidity* on the part of  the
 quasi-intelligent device.

I find it unclear how to decide whether something is unforgivably stupid
in your view, or instead mitigated by something like this:

 Regards mono-raise, I would say that failing it is
 obviously 'positionally absurd'
 and 'pairwise absurd' but perhaps not  'LNH
 absurd'.  We know that it isn't 
 absurd in the sense that mono-add-plump and
 mono-append is, because it is 
 failed by a method that has a maximal set of 
 (IMO) desirable criterion compliances .

It seems to me like a real problem that the absurdity of failing a
criterion can depend on whether better criteria require that it be
failed. I think this is just cheapness again. Failing mono-raise
isn't absurd, because mono-raise is relatively expensive.

I think there ought to be a clear distinction between criteria whose
violation is absurd no matter what the circumstances, and criteria
whose violation is absurd due to other available options.

There are very few (named) criteria whose failure I'd call absurd no
matter what.

  Can I take it then that you no longer like 
  CDTT,Random Ballot, which does award
  a probability pie?
 
 Sure. Does your question mean that this really is how
 you view the
 difference between CDTT and Mutual Majority, is in terms of
 the candidates
 of the winning set sharing a probability pie?
 
 Not exactly. No-one has ever suggested  MM,Random
 Ballot as a good method and few
 have suggested  that sometimes the clearly most
 appropriate winner is not in the MM set
 (as I have regarding the CDTT set).

I think that either isn't relevant or doesn't help your case. The
question is about why you view MM's behavior as qualitatively different
from CDTT's behavior, when in practice, in a real method, it's exactly
the same behavior. If the important thing is how many people suggest
that the clearly best winner is not in the MM or CDTT sets, then there
doesn't seem to be a good reason to bring up mono-add-plump.

  The criterion/standard is an end in itself.  Not
  everything is about the strategy game.
  Higer SU with sincere voting and sparing the method
  common-sense  (at least) difficult -to-counter
 complaints 
  from the positional-minded are worthwhile
 accomplisments

Re: [EM] Beatpath GMC compliance a mistaken standard?

2009-01-23 Thread Chris Benham
Kevin,

I can't see what's so highly absurd about failing mono-append. It's
basically a limited case of mono-raise, and one that doesn't seem
especially more important. Is it absurd to fail mono-raise?

The absurdity of failing mono-append is compounded by the cheapness of
meeting it. As with mono-add-plump the quasi-intelligent device is given
simple and pure new information. Being confused by it is simply unforgivable
*stupidity* on the part of  the quasi-intelligent device.

Regards mono-raise, I would say that failing it is obviously 'positionally 
absurd'
and 'pairwise absurd' but perhaps not  'LNH absurd'.  We know that it isn't 
absurd in the sense that mono-add-plump and mono-append is, because it is 
failed by a method that has a maximal set of  (IMO) desirable criterion 
compliances .

 Can I take it then that you no longer like 
 CDTT,Random Ballot, which does award
 a probability pie?

Sure. Does your question mean that this really is how you view the
difference between CDTT and Mutual Majority, is in terms of the candidates
of the winning set sharing a probability pie?

Not exactly. No-one has ever suggested  MM,Random Ballot as a good method and 
few
have suggested  that sometimes the clearly most appropriate winner is not in 
the MM set
(as I have regarding the CDTT set).

 The criterion/standard is an end in itself.  Not
 everything is about the strategy game.
 Higer SU with sincere voting and sparing the method
 common-sense  (at least) difficult -to-counter complaints 
 from the positional-minded are worthwhile accomplisments.

This strikes me as an unusual amount of paranoia that the method's
results can't be explained to the public's satisfaction unless it's
similar to Approval.

It isn't just the public. It is myself wearing my common-sense positional 
hat. And it isn't just
Approval, it's  'Approval and/or FPP'.


Chris Benham








Hi Chris,

--- En date de : Jeu 15.1.09, Chris Benham cbenha...@yahoo.com.au a écrit :
 Kevin,
 
 You wrote (12 Jan 2009):
 
 Why do we *currently* ever bother to satisfy
 difficult criteria? What do 
 we mean when we say we value a criterion? Surely not just
 that we feel 
 it's cheap?
 
 When simultaneously a criterion's satisfaction's
 cost falls below a certain 
 level and  its failure reaches a certain level of 
 absurdity/silliness  I start to
 lose sight of  the distinction between important for
 its own sake and very
 silly not to have because it's so cheap.
 Mono-add-plump (like mono-append)
 is way inside that territory.  

I see. I don't think I value criteria for this sort of reason. If I insist
on a criterion like Plurality, it's because I don't think the public
will accept the alternative. And these two criteria are relative, so
that in order to complain about a violation you have to illustrate a
hypothetical scenario in addition to what really occurred.

I can't see what's so highly absurd about failing mono-append. It's
basically a limited case of mono-raise, and one that doesn't seem
especially more important. Is it absurd to fail mono-raise?

 If you need to identify majorities, then the fact
 that a ballot shows
 no preference between Y and Z, is relevant
 information.
 
 In my view a voting method *doesn't* need to
 specifically identify majorities, so it
 isn't. (The voting method can and should meet
 majority-related criteria 'naturally'
 and obliquely.)

But we aren't even talking about voting methods, we're talking about
sets. You have basically criticized Schulze(wv) even though it naturally 
and obliquely satisfies majority-related criteria.

 But even if  the quasi-intelligent device is mistaken
 in treating them as
 relevant, then that is a much more understandable  and
 much less serious a 
 blunder than the mono-add-plump failure.
 
 Ok. I still don't really see why, or what makes
 the difference.
 
 Imagine the quasi-intelligent device is the captain of  a
 democracy bus that takes
 on passengers and then decides on its course/destination
 after polling the passengers.
 
 Imagine that as in situation 1 it
 provisionally decides to go to C, and then as in 
 situation 2 a group of new passengers get on
 (swelling the total by about 28%) and 
 they are openly polled and they all say we want to go
 to C, and have nothing else to say
 and then the captain announces in that case I'll
 take the bus to B.
 
 Would you have confidence that that captain made rational
 decisions on the most
 democratic (best representing the
 passengers' expressed wishes) decisions?
 I and I think many others would not, and would conclude
 that  the final B decision
 can only be right if the original C decision
 was completely ridiculous. Or would you
 be impressed by the captain's wisdom in being properly
 swayed by the new passengers'
 indecision between A and B?

However I answer doesn't make any difference, because the question is
why this crosses the boundary of clear badness while failures of 
mono-add-top

[EM] Schulze (Approval-Domination prioritised Margins)

2009-01-18 Thread Chris Benham
I have an idea for a new defeat-strength measure for the Schulze algorithm
(and  similar such as Ranked Pairs and River), which I'll call:

Approval-Domination prioritised Margins:

*Voters rank from the top however many candidates they wish.
Interpreting ranking (in any position, or alternatively above at least one other
candidate) as approval, candidate A is considered as approval dominating
candidate B if  A's approval-opposition to B (i.e. A's approval score on ballots
that don't approve B) is greater than B's total approval score.

All pairwise defeats/victories where the victor approval dominates the loser
are considered as stronger than all the others.

With that sole modification, we use Margins  as the measure of  defeat 
strength.*

This aims to meet  SMD  (and so Plurality and Minimal Defense, criteria failed
by regular Margins) and my recently suggested Smith- Comprehensive 3-slot
Ratings Winner criterion (failed by Winning Votes).

http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2008-December/023595.html

Here is an example where the result differs from regular Margins, Winning Votes
and  Schwartz//Approval.

44: A
46: BC
07: CA
03: C

AB  51-46 =  5 * 
BC  46-10 = 36 
CA  56-44 = 12

Plain Margins would consider B's defeat to be the weakest and elect B, but that 
is the only
one of the three pairwise results where the victor approval-dominates the 
loser.  A's approval
opposition to B is 51, higher than B's total approval score of 46.

So instead my suggested alternative considers A's defeat (with the next 
smallest margin) to be
the weakest  and elects A.  Looking at it from the point of view of the Ranked 
Pairs algorithm
(MinMax, Schulze, Ranked Pairs, River are all equivalent with three 
candidates), the AB result
is considered strongest  and so locked, followed by the BC result (with the 
greatest margin)
to give the final order ABC.

Winning Votes  considers C's defeat to be weakest and so elects C.  
Schwartz//Approval also
elects C.

Margins election of  B is a failure of  Minimal Defense. Maybe the B supporters 
are Burying
against A and A is the sincere Condorcet winner.

I have a second suggestion for measuring defeat strengths which I think is 
equivalent to
Schwartz//Approval, and that is simply Loser's Approval (interpreting ranking 
as approval as
above, defeats where the loser's total approval score is higher are considered 
to be weaker than
those where the loser's total approval score is lower).

Some may see this as more elegant than Schwartz//Approval, and maybe in some 
more complicated
example it can give a different result.


Chris Benham


  Stay connected to the people that matter most with a smarter inbox. Take 
a look http://au.docs.yahoo.com/mail/smarterinbox
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Beatpath GMC compliance a mistaken standard?

2009-01-11 Thread Chris Benham
Kevin,

You wrote (10 Jan 2009):

26 AB
25 BA
49 C

Mutual Majority elects {A,B}

Now add 5 A bullet votes:

26 AB
25 BA
49 C
5 A

Now Mutual Majority elects {A,B,C}.

Oops!  (I knew that!)  Sorry for falsely contradicting you.

Why is mono-add-plump important?

Because as an election method algorithm that fails it
simply can't have any credibility as a quasi-intelligent 
 device (which is what it is supposed to be) and because 
 satisfying it should be (and is) very cheap.

I feel that cheapness isn't relevant to whether a criterion is important,
and certainly not to whether failing it is absurd. I save the term 
absurd for ideas that are bad regardless of what else is available.

Well I don't. If none of the election criteria were incompatible with each
other, wouldn't we say that nearly all of them are important?

Regarding your first reason: Why is it acceptable to fail mono-add-top
or Participation, but not acceptable to fail mono-add-plump? I guess
that you based this distinction almost entirely on the relative cheapness
of the criteria.

No. With mono-add-top and Participation, the quasi-intelligent device in
reviewing its decision to elect X gets (possibly relevant) information about
other candidates besides X. With mono-add-plump it gets nothing but information
about and purely in favour of X, so it has no excuse at all for changing its 
mind
about electing X.

 If we view CDTT somehow as an election method, then when it fails 
 mono-add-plump, the bullet votes for X are not simply strengthening
X, they are also *weakening* some pairwise victory of Y over Z, which X
had relied upon in order to have a majority beatpath to Z.

That just testifies to the absurdity of an algorithm  specifically putting 
some  
 special significance on majority beatpaths versus other beatpaths.

You're saying it's absurd, but what is absurd about it?

It's absurd that ballots that plump for X should in any way be considered 
relevant
to the strength of the pairwise comparison between two other candidates.
This absurdity only arises from the algorithm specifically using (and relying 
on) a
majority threshold.   

It would be better, as in less arbitrary, if you simply criticized that 
beatpath GMC is 
incompatible with ratings summation.

So is Condorcet. I don't think it's particularly arbitrary  to value electing 
a voted
Shwartz winner. I'm still a bit confused as to why anyone would be interested in
beatpath GMC.

So essentially, Schwartz//Approval is preferable to any method that satisfies 
SMD, 
Schwartz, and beatpath GMC.

Yes, much preferable to any method that satisfies beatpath GMC period

I don't feel there's an advantage to tending to elect candidates with more 
approval, because 
in turn this should just make voters approve fewer candidates when they doubt 
how the method 
will use their vote.

And why is that a negative?  I value LNHarm as an absolute guarantee, but in 
inherently- 
vulnerable-to-Burial  Condocet methods, I think it is better if they have a 
watch who you rank
because you could help elect them Approval flavour.

From your earlier post:
In the three-candidate case, at least, I think it's a problem to elect a 
candidate who isn't in the 
CDTT.

Why?

25: AB
26: BC
23: CA
26: C

In this situation 2 election from my demonstration, can you seriously contend 
(with a straight face)
that electing C is a problem?   Refresh my memory: who first suggested  Max. 
Approval Opposition 
as a way of measuring a candidate's strength?


Chris Benham


  Stay connected to the people that matter most with a smarter inbox. Take 
a look http://au.docs.yahoo.com/mail/smarterinbox
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Beatpath GMC compliance a mistaken standard?

2009-01-11 Thread Chris Benham
Kevin,

You wrote (11 Jan 2009):

There are reasons for criteria to be important other than how easy they are 
to satisfy. 
Otherwise why would we ever bother to satisfy the difficult criteria?

Well, if  as I said none of the criteria were incompatible with each other 
then
presumably none of the criteria would be difficult.

With mono-add-top and Participation, the quasi-intelligent device in
reviewing its decision to elect X gets (possibly relevant) information 
about other candidates besides X.

How can it be relevant? X was winning and X is the preferred candidate
on the new ballots.

You know that Condorcet is incompatible with mono-add-top (and so of course
Participation), so if we value compliance with the Condorcet criterion 
information
about candidates ranked below X must sometimes be relevant. But even if  the 
quasi-intelligent device is mistaken in treating them as relevant, then that is 
a much
more understandable  and much less serious a blunder than the mono-add-plump
failure.

It's absurd that ballots that plump for X should in any way be considered 
 relevant to the strength of the pairwise comparison between two other 
 candidates.
This absurdity only arises from the algorithm specifically using (and relying 
on) 
 a majority threshold.
 
We have Mutual Majority and beatpath GMC displaying the same phenomenon.
 
No. I don't accept that 'being tossed out of the favoured (not excluded from 
winning)
set' is exactly the same phenomenon as 'being joined by others in the 
favoured set'.
The latter is obviously far less serious.

I don't feel there's an advantage to tending
to elect candidates with more approval, because 
in turn this should just make voters approve fewer
candidates when they doubt how the method 
will use their vote.

And why is that a negative?  I value LNHarm as an absolute
guarantee, but in inherently- vulnerable-to-Burial  Condocet 
 methods, I think it is better if they have a watch who you rank
because you could help elect them Approval flavour.

This is a negative because it suggests that your positional criterion
will be self-defeating.
 
How can it possibly be self-defeating?  What is there to defeat?

From your earlier post:
In the three-candidate case, at least, I think it's a problem to elect a 
 candidate who isn't in the CDTT.

Why?

Because in the three-candidate case this is likely to be a failure of MD or 
SFC, 
or close to it.
 
I'm happy to have MD, and I don't care about SFC or close failures of  MD.
 
 I'm still a bit confused as to why anyone would be interested in
beatpath GMC.

Well, it's a majority-rule criterion that is compatible with clone
independence and monotonicity.
 
Other majority-rule criteria with those same properties will suffice. 

In the three-candidate case it's also compatible with LNHarm. By adding a vote 
for 
your second choice, you can't inadvertently remove your first preference from 
the CDTT.
 
Well since Condorcet is incompatible with LNHarm, that doesn't explain why 
Condorcet
fans should like it.  Also I think this is mainly just putting a positive spin 
on gross unfairness
to truncators and the related silly random-fill incentive.
 
25: AB
26: BC
23: CA
26: C
100 ballots (majority threshold = 51)

BC 51-27,   CA 75-25,   AB 48-26.
 
In Schulze(Winning Votes), and I think also in any method that meets beatpath 
GMC
and mono-raise, the 26C truncators can virtually guarantee that C be elected by 
using
the random-fill strategy. That is silly and unfair.
 
Also, by artificially denying  the clearly strongest candidate  any method that 
doesn't
elect C must be vulnerable to Pushover, certainly much more than those that do 
elect C.

http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2008-December/023590.html
 
(not that that is a very relevant strategy problem for the methods like WV that 
have the
much easier and safer random-fill strategy for the C(B=C) voters.)
 

Chris  Benham


  Stay connected to the people that matter most with a smarter inbox. Take 
a look http://au.docs.yahoo.com/mail/smarterinbox
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Beatpath GMC compliance a mistaken standard? (was GMC compliance...)

2009-01-09 Thread Chris Benham
Marcus,

You wrote (8 Jan 2009):

Statement #1: Criterion X does not imply criterion Y.
Statement #2: Criterion X and criterion Y are incompatible.

Statement #1 does not imply statement #2. But in your
29 Dec 2008 mail, you mistakenly assume that statement #1
implies statement #2.

No I didn't. That is just your mistaken impression.

You proved only that beatpath GMC does not imply mono-add-plump;
but then you mistakenly concluded that this means that beatpath
GMC and mono-add-plump were incompatible (spectacularly
vulnerable to mono-add-plump, spectacular failure of
mono-add-plump).

No,  I only wrote that the beatpath GMC *concept* is vulnerable to 
Mono-add-Plump.  

However, the fact, that Schulze(winning votes) satisfies beatpath GMC 
and mono-add-plump, demonstrates that these two criteria are not incompatible.

Yes, that is obvious. I explicitly acknowledged this in my last post.

I think that all methods that fail Independence from Irrelevant Ballots are 
silly and
that methods should meet the Majority criterion.  The Majority *concept* is 
vulnerable to Irrelevant Ballots because candidate A can be the only candidate
allowed to win by the Majority criterion and then we add a handful of ballots 
that
all plump for nobody and candidate A no longer has a majority.

But of course I don't suggest that those two criteria are incompatible.

The point of my  Dec.29 demonstration was to refute any notion or assumption
that all candidates in the CDTT (i.e. those not excluded by Beatpath GMC) must
be stronger (i.e. more representative of the voters and so more deserving of 
victory)
than any of the candidates outside the CDTT. 

This was only the first part of my argument that  Beatpath GMC [compliance] is a
mistaken standard. What other criterion/standard says that the winner must 
come
from set S, with S being a set that a candidate X can be kicked out of by an 
influx
of new ballots that all plump (bullet-vote) for X?

I put it to you that the answer is none, and that that makes Beatpath GMC 
uniquely
weird and suspect. By itself that isn't conclusively damning because it doesn't 
prove
that Beatpath GMC can exclude the strongest candidate. 

25: AB
26: BC
23: CA
26: C

But I contend that here in my situation 2 election Beatpath GMC does exclude
the clearly strongest candidate C.  You ignored the last few paragraphs of my 
last post:

.. I don't accept your suggestion that compliance with beatpath GMC is 
acceptably cheap 
(let alone free), because it isn't compatible with my recently suggested 
Smith- Comprehensive 
3-slot Ratings Winner criterion, which I value much more.

http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2008-December/023595.html

In other words the CDTT set can fail to include the candidate that on 
overwhelming 
common-sense (mostly positional) grounds is the strongest candidate (e.g. C in 
Situation # 2).
 
So given a method that meets what I've been recently calling Strong Minimal 
Defense  
(and so Minimal Defense and Plurality) and Schwartz (and so fails LNHarm and 
meets Majority 
for Solid Coalitions), I consider the addition of compliance with beatpath 
GMC a negative if 
without it the method can meet Smith- Comprehensive 3-slot Ratings Winner 
(which
should be very very easy).

Chris Benham




Dear Chris Benham,

you wrote (29 Dec 2008):

 I think that compliance with GMC is a mistaken standard
 in the sense that the best methods should fail it.

 The GMC concept is spectacularly vulnerable to Mono-add-Plump!

 [Situation #1]

 25: AB
 26: BC
 23: CA
 04: C
 78 ballots (majority threshold = 40)

 BC 51-27,  CA 53-25,  AB 48-26.

 All three candidates have a majority beat-path to each other,
 so GMC says that any of them are allowed to win.

 [Situation #2]

 But say we add 22 ballots that plump for C:

 25: AB
 26: BC
 23: CA
 26: C
 100 ballots (majority threshold = 51)

 BC 51-49,  CA 75-25,  AB 48-26.

 Now B has majority beatpaths to each of the other candidates
 but neither of them have one back to B, so the GMC says that
 now the winner must be B.

 The GMC concept is also naturally vulnerable to Irrelevant
 Ballots. Suppose we now add 3 new ballots that plump for an
 extra candidate X.

 [Situation #3]

 25: AB
 26: BC
 23: CA
 26: C
 03: X
 103 ballots (majority threshold = 52)

 Now B no longer has a majority-strength beat-path to C,
 so now GMC says that C (along with B) is allowed to win
 again.

 (BTW this whole demonstration also applies to Majority-Defeat
 Disqualification(MDD) and if we pretend that the C-plumping
 voters are truncating their sincere preference for B over A
 then it also applies to Eppley's Truncation Resistance
 and Ossipoff's SFC and GFSC criteria.)

I wrote (29 Dec 2008):

 Your argumentation is incorrect. Example:

    In many scientific papers, the Smith set is criticized
    because the Smith set can contain Pareto-dominated
    candidates. However, to these criticisms I usually
    reply that the fact

[EM] Beatpath GMC compliance a mistaken standard? (was GMC compliance...)

2009-01-08 Thread Chris Benham
Marcus,
 
You wrote (29 Dec,2008):
 
You wrote: All three candidates have a majority beatpath
to each other, so GMC says that any of them are allowed to
win. No! Beatpath GMC doesn't say that any of them are
allowed to win; beatpath GMC only doesn't exclude any of
them from winning. 


I can't see that the distinction between allowed to win and 
not excluded from winning is anything more than that between
the glass is half full and the glass is half empty, so I reject your
semantic quibble. Any candidate that a criterion C doesn't exclude
from winning is (as far as C is concerned) allowed to win.
 
You didn't demonstrate that the GMC concept is spectacularly
vulnerable to mono-add-plump. 
 
Well, I think I did. Perhaps you misunderstand my use of the 
word concept.

Beatpath GMC says that the winner must come from a certain set
S, but a candidate X can fall out of  S if a relatively large number
of new ballots are added, all plumping (bullet-voting) for X.
 
Is there any other criterion with that absurd feature?

However, the fact, that Schulze(winning votes) satisfies
mono-add-plump and always chooses from the CDTT set and
isn't vulnerable to irrelevant ballots, shows that these
properties are not incompatible.

Yes, and I never meant to suggest otherwise.  In your previous post
you (referring to beatpath GMC as the CDTT criterion) wrote:
 
When Woodall's CDTT criterion is violated, then this
means that casting partial individual rankings could
needlessly lead to the election of a candidate B who
is not a Schwartz candidate; needlessly because
Woodall's CDTT criterion is compatible with the
Smith criterion, independence of clones, monotonicity,
reversal symmetry, Pareto, resolvability, etc..

The Schwartz criterion doesn't imply beatpath GMC, so
by a Schwartz candidate you mean a '[presumed] sincere 
Schwartz candidate' instead of a  'voted Schwartz candidate'.
 
I don't accept that this stated aim is necessarily so desirable
partly because it isn't the case that (assuming sincere voting
and no strategic nominations) a Schwartz candidate is the
one that is mostly likely to be the SU winner (as evidenced by
my suggested Comprehensive 3-slot Ratings Winner criterion's
incompatibility with Condorcet).

Secondly I don't accept your suggestion that compliance with
beatpath GMC is acceptably cheap (let alone free) because it
isn't compatible with recently suggested Smith- Comprehensive 3-slot
Ratings Winner criterion, which I value much more.

In other words the CDTT set can fail to include the candidate that on
overwhelming common-sense (mostly positional) grounds is the strongest
candidate (e.g. C in Situation # 2).
 
So given a method that meets what I've been recently calling Strong
Minimal Defense  (and so Minimal Defense and Plurality) and Schwartz
(and so fails LNHarm and meets Majority for Solid Coalitions), I consider
the addition of compliance with beatpath GMC a negative if without it the
method can meet Smith- Comprehensive 3-slot Ratings Winner (which
should be very very easy).


Chris Benham


 

Dear Chris Benham,

you wrote (29 Dec 2008):

The  Generalised Majority Criterion says in effect that
the winner must come from Woodall's CDTT set, and is
defined by Markus Schulze thus (October 1997):

 Definition (Generalized Majority Criterion):

 X  Y means, that a majority of the voters prefers    X to Y.

    There is a majority beat-path from X to Y, means,
    that X  Y or there is a set of candidates
    C[1], ..., C[n] with X  C[1]  ...  C[n]  Y.

    A method meets the Generalized Majority
    Criterion (GMC) if and only if:
    If there is a majority beat-path from A to B, but
    no majority beat-path from B to A, then B must not
    be elected.

With full strict ranking this implies Smith, and obviously 
Candidates permitted to win by GMC (i.e.CDTT), Random
Candidate is much better than plain Random Candidate.
Nonetheless I think that compliance with GMC is a mistaken
standard in the sense that the best methods should fail it.

The GMC concept is spectacularly vulnerable to Mono-add-Plump!

[Situation #1]

25: AB
26: BC
23: CA
04: C
78 ballots (majority threshold = 40)

BC 51-27,   CA 53-25,   AB 48-26.

All three candidates have a majority beat-path to each other,
so GMC says that any of them are allowed to win.

[Situation #2]

But say we add 22 ballots that plump for C:

25: AB
26: BC
23: CA
26: C
100 ballots (majority threshold = 51)

BC 51-49,   CA 75-25,   AB 48-26.

Now B has majority beatpaths to each of the other candidates
but neither of them have one back to B, so the GMC says that
now the winner must be B.

The GMC concept is also naturally vulnerable to Irrelevant
Ballots. Suppose we now add 3 new ballots that plump for an
extra candidate X.

[Situation #3]

25: AB
26: BC
23: CA
26: C
03: X
103 ballots (majority threshold = 52)

Now B no longer has a majority-strength beat-path to C,
so now GMC says that C (along with B) is allowed to win
again.

(BTW this whole demonstration

[EM] CDTT criterion compliance desirable?

2008-12-29 Thread Chris Benham
Marcus,
You wrote (25 Dec. 2008):

Dear Chris Benham,

you wrote (25 Dec 2008):

I had already proposed this criterion in 1997.
Why then do you list it as Woodall's CDTT criterion
instead of your own Generalised Majority Criterion?

Did, as far as you know, Woodall ever actually proposethe CDTT criterion as 
something that is desirable for
methods to meet (instead of just defining the CDTT set)?

Woodall's main aims are to describe and to investigate
the different election methods. Compared to the
participants of this mailing list, Woodall is very
reluctant to say that some election method was good/bad
or that some property was desirable/undesirable.
 
That is true, but nonetheless the short answer to my second question
is 'no'. To quote  Douglas Woodall (with his permission) from a recent
email (19 Dec 2008):
 
I defined the CDTT set as a means towards constructing election methods 
with certain mathematical properties.  My memory for such things is not good, 
and I am open to correction, but as far as I recall I never suggested that for 
the 
winner to belong to the CDTT was particularly desirable, and I never suggested 
this as a criterion. So although calling it Woodall's CDTT criterion is an
understandable shorthand, it is somewhat misleading.

So can we agree that there isn't really such a thing as Woodall's CDTT 
criterion
and what you have  given that label to is your own Generalised Majority 
Criterion 
(GMC) that is equivalent to the winner must come from the  defined-by-Woodall
CDTT set?
 
I'm sorry if this seems excessively nitpicking, and I'm not suggesting you 
intended
to mislead with your understandable shorthand.
 
In my soon-to-follow next post I will explain why I think the GMC is a mistaken
standard.

Chris Benham


  Stay connected to the people that matter most with a smarter inbox. Take 
a look http://au.docs.yahoo.com/mail/smarterinbox
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] GMC compliance a mistaken standard? (was CDTT criterion...)

2008-12-29 Thread Chris Benham
The  Generalised Majority Criterion says in effect that the winner
must come from Woodall's CDTT set, and is defined by Marcus Schulze
thus (October 1997):

Definition (Generalized Majority Criterion):

   X  Y means, that a majority of the voters prefers
   X to Y.

   There is a majority beat-path from X to Y, means,
   that X  Y or there is a set of candidates
   C[1], ..., C[n] with X  C[1]  ...  C[n]  Y.

   A method meets the Generalized Majority
   Criterion (GMC) if and only if:
   If there is a majority beat-path from A to B, but
   no majority beat-path from B to A, then B must not
   be elected.

With full strict ranking this implies Smith, and obviously 
Candidates permitted to win by GMC (i.e.CDTT), Random Candidate
is much better than plain Random Candidate. Nonetheless I think that compliance
with GMC is a mistaken standard in the sense that the best methods should
fail it.

The GMC concept is spectacularly vulnerable to Mono-add-Plump!

25: AB
26: BC
23: CA
04: C
78 ballots (majority threshold = 40)

BC 51-27,   CA 53-25,   AB 48-26.

All three candidates have a majority beat-path to each other, so GMC says that
any of them are allowed to win. 

But say we add 22 ballots that plump for C:

25: AB
26: BC
23: CA
26: C
100 ballots (majority threshold = 51)

BC 51-27,   CA 75-25,   AB 48-26.

Now B has majority beatpaths to each of the other candidates but neither of them
have one back to B, so the GMC says that now the winner must be B.

The GMC concept is also naturally vulnerable to Irrelevant Ballots. Suppose we 
now
add 3 new ballots that plump for an extra candidate X.

25: AB
26: BC 
23: CA
26: C
03: X
103 ballots (majority threshold = 52)

Now B no longer has a majority-strength beat-path to C, so now GMC says that C
(along with B) is allowed to win again.

(BTW this whole demonstration also applies to Majority-Defeat 
Disqualification(MDD)
and if we pretend that the C-plumping voters are trucating their sincere 
preference for B
over A then it also applies to Eppley's Truncation Resistance and Ossipoff's 
SFC and
GFSC criteria.)

If  the method uses 3-slot ratings ballots and we assume that the voted 3-slot 
ratings are
sincere, then the GMC can bar the plainly highest SU candidate from winning as 
evidenced
by its incompatibility with my recently suggested  Smith-Comprehensive 3-slot 
Ratings
Winner criterion:

*If no voter expresses more than three preference-levels and the ballot 
rules allow the expression of 3 preference-levels when there are 3 (or 
more) candidates, then (interpreting candidates that are voted above one
or more candidates and below none as top-rated, those voted above
one or more candidates but below all the top-rated candidates as 
middle-rated and those not voted above any other candidate and below
at least one other candidate as bottom-rated, and interpreting above-
bottom rating as approval) it must not be possible for candidate X to
win if there is some candidate Y which has a beat-path to X and  
simultaneously higher Top-Ratings and Approval scores and a lower  
Maximum Approval-Opposition score.*

http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2008-December/023548.html

25: AB
26: BC 
23: CA
26: C

TR scores:  C49,   B26,    A25
App. scores:   C75,   B51,    A48
MAO scores: C25,   B49,A52

That criterion says that C  must win here. GMC says only B can win.

Frankly I think any method needs a much better excuse than any that Winning 
Votes
can offer for not electing C here. As I discuss in another recent post, any 
method
that doesn't elect C here must be vulnerable to Push-over. So another reason not
to be in love with GMC is that it is incompatible with Pushover 
Invulnerability.

http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2008-December/023543.html

As I hope some may have guessed from the spectacular failure of Mono-add-Plump, 
the GMC 
concept is grossly unfair to truncators.  And Winning Votes  (as a GMC 
complying method) is
unfair to truncators. 

Say the 26C we're just here to elect C and don't care about any other 
candidate voters use a 
random-fill strategy, each tossing a fair coin to decide between voting CB or 
CA; then even if as
few as 4 of them vote CA they will elect C. Their chance making C the decisive 
winner is  99.9956% 
(according to an online calculator http://stattrek.com/Tables/Binomial.aspx  ).

I have some sympathy with the idea of giving up something so as to counter 
order-reversing buriers,
but not with the idea that electing a CW is obviously so wonderful that when 
there is no voted CW
we must guess that there is a sincere CW and if we can infer that that can 
only (assuming no voters
are order-reversing) be X then we must elect X.


Chris Benham


  Stay connected to the people that matter most with a smarter inbox. Take 
a look http://au.docs.yahoo.com/mail/smarterinbox
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Why I think IRV isn't a serious alternative KD

2008-12-21 Thread Chris Benham
Kristofer,
Woodall's DAC and  DSC and  Bucklin and Woodall's similar QLTD
all meet mono-raise and Mutual Majority (aka Majority for Solid Coalitions).

DSC meets LNHarm and the rest meet LNHelp.

Chris Benham

 
Kristofer Munsterhjelm  wrote (Sun.Dec.21):
snip
In any case, it may be possible to have one of the LNHs and be monotonic 
and have mutual majority. I'm not sure, but perhaps (doesn't one of DAC 
or DSC do this?). If so, it would be possible to see (at least) whether 
people strategize in the direction of early truncation by looking at 
methods that fail LNHarm but pass LNHelp; that is, Bucklin.
snip


  Stay connected to the people that matter most with a smarter inbox. Take 
a look http://au.docs.yahoo.com/mail/smarterinbox
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Push-over Invulnerability criterion

2008-12-12 Thread Chris Benham
Part of  my demonstration of  many methods' failure of the Unmanipulable 
Majority
criterion has inspired me to suggest another strategy criterion: 

Push-over Invulnerability:
*It must not be possible to change the winner from candidate X to candidate Y by
altering some ballots (that vote Y above both candidates  X and  Z) by raising 
Z above
Y without changing their relative rankings among other (besides X and Z) 
candidates.*

I might later suggest a more elegant re-wording, and/or suggest a simplified 
approximation
that is easier to test for.

25: AB
26: BC
23: CA
26: C

BC 51-49,   CA 75-25,  AB 48-26

Schulze/RP/MM/River (WV) and Approval-Weighted Pairwise and DMC and MinMax(PO)
and MAMPO and IRV elect B.

Now say 4 of the 26C change to AC (trying a Push-over strategy):

25: AB
04: AC
26: BC
23: CA
22: C

BC 51-49,   CA 71-29,  AB 52-26

Now Schulze/RP/MM/River (WV) and  AWP and DMC and MinMax(PO) and MAMPO
and IRV all elect C. 

For a long time I thought that only non-monotonic methods like IRV and  
Raynaud (that
fail mono-raise) were vulnerable to Push-over, so therefore there was no need 
for a separate
Push-over Invulnerability criterion.

But now we see that the Schulze, Ranked Pairs, MinMax, River algorithms (all 
equivalent with 3
candidates)  using Winning Votes are all vulnerable  to Push-over (as my 
suggested criterion
defines it).

Now I know that Winning Votes' failure can be seen as functionally really a 
failure of  Later-no-help,
because those C-supporting strategists could more safely achieve the same end 
just by changing
their votes from C to CA instead of from C to AC. But that is hardly a 
bragging point for WV.

I think this Pushover criterion  can be seen as a kind of  monotonicity 
criterion, in the sense that all
else being equal methods that meet it must be in some way more monotonic than 
those that don't.

I have shown that WV fails Pushover Invulnerability. I strongly suspect (but 
not at present up to
proving) that both Margins and  Schwartz//Approval (ranking) meet it.

Can anyone please give an example (or examples) that show that either or both 
of  Margins and
S//A(r)  fail my suggested Push-over Invulnerability criterion?

Chris Benham



  Start your day with Yahoo!7 and win a Sony Bravia TV. Enter now 
http://au.docs.yahoo.com/homepageset/?p1=otherp2=aup3=tagline
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Why I Prefer IRV to Condorcet

2008-12-10 Thread Chris Benham
Kristofer,

You wrote (Sun.Nov.23):
Regarding number two, simple Condorcet methods exist. Borda-elimination 
(Nanson or Raynaud) is Condorcet. Minmax is quite simple, and everybody 
who's dealt with sports knows Copeland (with Minmax tiebreaks). I'll 
partially grant this, though, since the good methods are complex, but 
I'll ask whether you think MAM (Ranked Pairs(wv)) is too complex. In 
MAM, you take all the pairwise contests, sort by strength, and affirm 
down the list unless you would contradict an earlier affirmed contest. 
This method is cloneproof, monotonic, etc...

Raynaud isn't  Borda-elimination.  It is  Pairwise Elimination, i.e. eliminate
the loser of  the most decisive or strongest pairwise result (by one measure or
another) until one candidate remains.  You may have instead meant to write 
Baldwin,though some sources just talk about 2 different versions of  Nanson.

Simpler and much better than any of those methods are  Condorcet//Approval
and  Smith//Approval and  Schwartz//Approval ,in each case interpreting 
ranking as approval and so not allowing ranking among unapproved candidates.

Chris Benham


  Start your day with Yahoo!7 and win a Sony Bravia TV. Enter now 
http://au.docs.yahoo.com/homepageset/?p1=otherp2=aup3=tagline
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Unmanipulable Majority strategy criterion (Kristofer)

2008-12-10 Thread Chris Benham
Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote (Sat.Nov.29):

-snip-

I don't know of any method that meets  the MDQBR you refer to that isn't 
completely invulnerable to Burial (do you?), so I don't see how that criterion 
is 
presently useful.

That's odd, because the example I gave in a reply to Juho was yours.
http://listas.apesol.org/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2006-December/019097.html

Note that the method of that post (which I've been referring to as first 
preference Copeland) ...

-snip-

Kristofer,
Yes,sorry, that was a not-well-considered posting of mine that I'd forgotten.

That method, the basic version of which was introduced by Forest Simmons as 
Clone-proofed
Copeland, doesn't meet  Mutual Dominant Quarter Burial Resistance (MDQBR).

26: AB
25: CA
02: CB
25: BA
22: BC

AB 51-49,   AC 51-49,   BC  73-27.  

FPs: A26,  B47,  C27.  A is the CW and wins with the penalty score of  total 
FPs of candidates
pairwise beaten by of  zero. With over a quarter of the FPs A is a mutual 
dominant quarter 
candidate.

Say two of the 25 BA change to BC:

26: AB
25: CA
02: CB
23: BA
24: BC

AB 51-49,   CA 51-49,   BC  73-27

Now the penalty scores are  A27,  B26,  C47.  The Burial has worked, the new 
winner is B.

Chris Benham



  Start your day with Yahoo!7 and win a Sony Bravia TV. Enter now 
http://au.docs.yahoo.com/homepageset/?p1=otherp2=aup3=tagline
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] IRV's Squeeze Feature

2008-12-07 Thread Chris Benham
Forest,
You wrote, setting up your attack on IRV:
Suppose that the voters are distributed uniformly on a disc with center C, and 
that they are voting to 
choose from among several locations for a community center.

(a) That is quite a big suppose, and  (b) I agree that IRV would not be among 
the best methods
to use to vote to choose the location of a community centre.

The center C of any distribution of voters with central symmetry through C 
will be a Universal Condorcet 
Option for that distribution.

Yes, that is almost a tautology (and to the extent that it isn't it seems to 
be just a semantic point).

And what justification for winning does the IRV winner have?

I agree that if we suddenly have unfettered access to all the voters' sincere 
pairwise preferences and that
each voter's different pairwise preferences are all at least approximately as 
strong as each other, then yes
electing the Condorcet winner is nicer and philosophically more justified 
than electing the IRV winner. 

However the IRV winner could have as its justification simply the criterion 
compliances of the IRV method.
You, as the election-method salesman, could say to the polity/voters  
'customer':
This Condorcet method is definitely best for choosing the most central 
community centre with sincere voting. 
I recommend it. 

but they could reply: 
Does it meet Burial Invulnerability and Later-no-Harm and Later-no-Help as 
well as Mutual Dominant Third 
and Mutual Majority and  Condorcet Loser and Woodall's Plurality criterion and 
Clone Independence?

To which you must reply No, and then the 'customer' says Then which is the 
best method that does?, to
which you reply IRV and make the sale.

IRV has some more-or-less unique problems but they are the unavoidable price 
of  a unique set of  strengths,
so I don't consider it justified to focus on its problems in isolation. Often 
this is done, comparing (sometimes
implicitly) IRV with the best features of several other methods. 

But as you know, I am also supportively interested in Condorcet methods and 
also Favourite Betrayal 
complying methods such as 3-slot SDC,TR.

Chris Benham



Forest Simmons wrote (Fri. Dec.5):
Suppose that the voters are distributed uniformly on a disc with center C, and 
that they are voting to 
choose from among several locations for a community center.

Then no matter how many locations on the ballot, if the voters rank them from 
nearest to furthest, the 
location nearest to C will be the Condorcet Option.

Therefore, if C itself is one of the options, it will be the Condorcet Option 
no matter what the other 
options are.  So C is more than just a regular run of the mill Condorcet 
Option, it is a kind of Universal 
Condorcet Option for this distribution of voters.

The center C of any distribution of voters with central symmetry through C will 
be a Universal Condorcet 
Option for that distribution.

But no matter how peaked that distribution might be (even like the roof of a 
Japanese pagoda) the center 
C is not immune from the old IRV squeeze play.

If the good and bad cop team gangs up on C, one on each side, they can reduce 
C's first choice region 
to a narrow band perpendicular to the line connecting the two team mates, thus 
forcing C out in the first 
round of the runoff.

If the team mates are not perfectly coordinated, then instead of a narrow band, 
C's first choice region 
becomes a long narrow pie piece shaped wedge, roughly perpendicular to the line 
determined by the two 
team mates.

This squeeze play can be used against any candidate no matter the shape of the 
distribution, symmetric 
or not.  But my point is that even in a sharply peaked unimodal symetrical 
distribution, the center C, 
which is the Universal Condorcet Option, can easily be squeezed out under IRV.  
And what justification 
for winning does the IRV winner have?  Merely that it was the closer of the two 
team mates to the ideal 
location C.

Now leaving the concrete setting of voting for a physical location for a 
community center, and getting 
back to a more abstract political issue space: It doesn't really matter if the 
good cop and bad cop are 
really even anywhere near to opposite sides of a targeted candidate (say a 
strong third party challenger) 
as long as they can make it appear that way.

The two corporate parties are very good at this good cop / bad cop game, 
especially since the major 
media manipulators of public opinion are completely beholden to the giant 
corporations.


  Start your day with Yahoo!7 and win a Sony Bravia TV. Enter now 
http://au.docs.yahoo.com/homepageset/?p1=otherp2=aup3=tagline
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Unmanipulable Majority strategy criterion

2008-12-06 Thread Chris Benham
Kristofer,
You wrote addressing me:
You have some examples showing that RP/Schulze/etc fail the criterion.

By my lazy etc. I just meant  'and the other Condorcet methods that are 
all equivalent to MinMax when there are just 3 candidates and Smith//Minmax
when there are not more than 3 candidates in the Smith set'.

Do they show that Condorcet and UM is incompatible? Or have they just 
been constructed on basis of some Condorcet methods, with differing 
methods for each?

My intention was to show that all the methods that take account of more than 
one possible voter preference-level (i.e. not Approval or FPP) (and are 
well-known and/or advocated by anyone on EM) are vulnerable to UM except 
SMD,TP.

I think I remember that you said Condorcet implies some vulnerability to 
burial. Is that sufficient to make it fail UM?

Probably yes, but I haven't  tried to prove as much. 

Returning to this demonstration:


93: A
09: BA
78: B
14: CB
02: CA
04: C
200 ballots

BA  101-95,  BC 87-20,  AC 102-20.
All Condorcet methods, plus MDD,X  and  MAMPO and  ICA elect B.

B has a majority-strength pairwise win against A, but say 82 of the 93A change 
to
AC  thus:

82: AC
11: A
09: BA
78: B
14: CB
02: CA
04: C

BA  101-95,  CB 102-87,  AC 102-20
Approvals: A104, B101, C102
TR scores: A93,   B87,   C 20

Now MDD,A and MDD,TR and MAMPO and ICA and  Schulze/RP/MinMax etc. using 
WV or Margins elect A.  So all those methods fail the UM criterion.

Working in exactly the same way as ICA (because no ballots have voted more than 
one candidate
top), this also applies to  Condorcet//Approval and Smith//Approval and 
Schwartz//Approval.
So those methods also fail UM.

I did a bit of calculation and it seems my FPC (first preference 
Copeland) variant elects B here, as should plain FPC. Since it's 
nonmonotonic, it's vulnerable to Pushover, though, and I'm not sure 
whether that can be fixed at all.

My impression is/was that in 3-candidates-in-a-cycle examples that method 
behaves just like IRV.
The demonstration that I gave of  IRV failing UM certainly also applies to it. 


Chris Benham



Kristofer Munsterhjelm  wrote (Thurs.Dec.4):
Chris Benham wrote:
Regarding my proposed Unmanipulable Majority criterion:
  
*If (assuming there are more than two candidates) the ballot
rules don't constrain voters to expressing fewer than three
preference-levels, and A wins being voted above B on more
than half the ballots, then it must not be possible to make Bthe winner by 
altering any of the ballots on which B is voted
above A without raising their ranking or rating of B.*
  
To have any point a criterion must be met by some method.
  
It is met by my recently proposed SMD,TR method, which I introduced
as 3-slot SMD,FPP(w):

*Voters fill out 3-slot ratings ballots, default rating is bottom-most
(indicating least preferred and not approved).

Interpreting top and middle rating as approval, disqualify all candidates
with an approval score lower than their maximum approval-opposition
(MAO) score.
(X's  MAO score is the approval score of the most approved candidate on
ballots that don't approve X).

Elect the undisqualified candidate with the highest top-ratings score.*
  
[snip examples of methods failing the criterion]

You have some examples showing that RP/Schulze/etc fail the criterion. 
Do they show that Condorcet and UM is incompatible? Or have they just 
been constructed on basis of some Condorcet methods, with differing 
methods for each?

I think I remember that you said Condorcet implies some vulnerability to 
burial. Is that sufficient to make it fail UM? I wouldn't be surprised 
if it is, seeing that you have examples for a very broad range of 
election methods.

93: A
09: BA
78: B
14: CB
02: CA
04: C
200 ballots

BA  101-95,  BC 87-20,  AC 102-20.
All Condorcet methods, plus MDD,X  and  MAMPO and  ICA elect B.

B has a majority-strength pairwise win against A, but say 82 of the 93A 
change to
AC  thus:

82: AC
11: A
09: BA
78: B
14: CB
02: CA
04: C
  
BA  101-95,  CB 102-87,  AC 102-20
Approvals: A104, B101, C102
TR scores: A93,   B87,   C 20
  
Now MDD,A and MDD,TR and MAMPO and ICA and  Schulze/RP/MinMax etc. using
WV or Margins elect A.  So all those methods fail the UM criterion.

I did a bit of calculation and it seems my FPC (first preference 
Copeland) variant elects B here, as should plain FPC. Since it's 
nonmonotonic, it's vulnerable to Pushover, though, and I'm not sure 
whether that can be fixed at all.



  Start your day with Yahoo!7 and win a Sony Bravia TV. Enter now 
http://au.docs.yahoo.com/homepageset/?p1=otherp2=aup3=tagline
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Why I think IRV isn't a serious alternative

2008-12-03 Thread Chris Benham
Forest,
What nicer distribution can  you think of..

Nice (and nicer) is a fuzzy emotional/aesthetic term that I might apply to 
food, music, people etc.
but seems unscientific and out-of-place here (and I'm not sure exactly what 
it's supposed to mean). 

I can see that such a distribution is more comfortable for methods that try to 
elect the centrist candidate.

I see IRV as FPP that trades most of its monotonicity criteria (including 
mono-raise and Participation but 
not mono-add-top, mono-add-plump or mono-append) to gain Clone-Winner and 
Majority for Solid
Coalitions (and Mutual Dominat Third and Condorcet Loser).

It keeps FPP's compliances with Woodall's Plurality criterion, Later-no-Harm, 
Later-no-Help and Clone-Loser.

The representativeness criteria it meets generally allow for a bigger set of 
allowable winners than say
the Smith set, and its monotonity failures mean that it chooses a winner from 
this set a bit erratically.
But I think your use of  the term pathology (comparing it to a disease and so 
something  that is self-evidently
unacceptable) is biased and out of place.

I also think that the argument that IRV makes a good stepping-stone to  PR is 
strong. Truly proportional 
multi-winner methods meet  Droop Proportionality for Solid Coalitions 
(equivalent in the single-winner 
case to Majority for Solid Coalitions, aka Mutual Majority.)

Single-winner STV's  virtues of  Later-no-Harm and Clone Independence survive 
into the multi-winner 
version (which of course meets Droop Proportionality SC), while for 
multi-winner methods the Condorcet 
criterion and Favourite Betrayal  are both incompatible with Droop PSC.  Also I 
think Later-no-Harm 
compliance is more valuable for multi-winner methods than for single-winner 
methods.

Chris Benham



Forest Simmons wrote (Sat. Nov.29):

From: Chris Benham 
  Forest,
 Given IRV's compliance with the representativeness criteria  Mutual 
 Dominant Third, Majority for
 Solid Coalitions, Condorcet Loser and? Plurality; why should the  bad look of 
 its erratic behaviour
 be sufficient to condemn IRV in spite of these and other  positive criterion 
 compliances such as
 Later-no-Harm and Burial Invulnerability?
 
A picture is worth a thousand words.  It shows the actual behavior, including 
the extent of the pathology.

  in the best of all possible worlds, namely normally distributed voting 
  populations in no more 
 than two dimensional issue space.
 CB: Why does that situation you refer to qualify as the best of all  
 possible worlds ?
 Three points determine a plane, so we cannot expect a lower dimension than 
 two. What nicer 
distribution can you think of. than normal?  But any distribution whose 
density only depends on distance 
from the center of the distribution would give exactly the same results for 
any Condorcet method, without 
making the IRV results any nicer. 

Forest


  Start your day with Yahoo!7 and win a Sony Bravia TV. Enter now 
http://au.docs.yahoo.com/homepageset/?p1=otherp2=aup3=tagline
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Unmanipulable Majority strategy criterion (newly amended version)

2008-12-03 Thread Chris Benham
Regarding my proposed Unmanipulable Majority criterion:

*If (assuming there are more than two candidates) the ballot 
rules don't constrain voters to expressing fewer than three 
preference-levels, and A wins being voted above B on more 
than half the ballots, then it must not be possible to make B 
the winner by altering any of the ballots on which B is voted 
above A without raising their ranking or rating of B.*

To have any point a criterion must be met by some method.

It is met by my recently proposed SMD,TR method, which I introduced
as 3-slot SMD,FPP(w):

*Voters fill out 3-slot ratings ballots, default rating is bottom-most
(indicating least preferred and not approved).

Interpreting top and middle rating as approval, disqualify all candidates
with an approval score lower than their maximum approval-opposition 
(MAO) score.
(X's  MAO score is the approval score of the most approved candidate on
ballots that don't approve X).

Elect the undisqualified candidate with the highest top-ratings score.*

Referring to the UM criterion: (a) if candidate A has a higher TR score than B
then the BA strategists can only make B win by causing A to be disqualified.
But in this method it isn't possible to vote x above y without approving x, so
we know that just on the AB ballots A has majority approval. It isn't possible
for a majority-approved candidate to be disqualified, and the strategists can't
cause A's approval to fall below majority-strength. And the criterion specifies
that none of the BA voters who don't top-rate B can raise their rating of B to
increase B's TR score.

(b) if on the other hand B has a higher TR score than A but B is disqualified
there is nothing the BA strategists can do to undisqualify B.

So SMD,TR meets the UM criterion.

93: A
09: BA
78: B
14: CB
02: CA
04: C
200 ballots

BA  101-95,  BC 87-20,  AC 102-20.
All Condorcet methods, plus MDD,X  and  MAMPO and  ICA elect B.

B has a majority-strength pairwise win against A, but say 82 of the 93A change 
to
AC  thus:

82: AC
11: A
09: BA
78: B
14: CB
02: CA
04: C

BA  101-95,  CB 102-87,  AC 102-20
Approvals: A104, B101, C102
TR scores: A93,   B87,   C 20

Now MDD,A and MDD,TR and MAMPO and ICA and  Schulze/RP/MinMax etc. using 
WV or Margins elect A.  So all those methods fail the UM criterion.

25: AB
26: BC
23: CA
26: C

BC 51-49,   CA 75-25,  AB 48-26

Schulze/RP/MM/River (WV) and Approval-Weighted Pairwise and DMC and MinMax(PO)
and MAMPO and IRV elect B.

Now say 4 of the 26C change to AC (trying a Push-over strategy):


25: AB
04: AC
26: BC
23: CA
22: C

BC 51-49,   CA 71-29,  AB 52-26

Now Schulze/RP/MM/River (WV) and  AWP and DMC and MinMax(PO) and MAMPO
and IRV all elect C. Since B had/has a majority-strength pairwise win against 
C, all these
methods also fail  Unmanipulable Majority. If  scoring ballots were used and 
all voters score
their most preferred candidate 10 and any second-ranked candidate 5 and 
unranked candidates
zero, then this demonstration also works for IRNR so it also fails.

Who knew that such vaunted  monotonic methods as WV and  MinMax(PO) and MAMPO
were vulnerable to Push-over?!

48: AB
01: A
03: BA
48: CB

BA 51-49.  Bucklin and MCA elect B, but if the 48 AB voters truncate the 
winner changes
to A.  So those methods also fail UM.

49: A9, B8, C0
24: B9, A0, C0
27: C9, B8, A0

Here Range/Average Ratings/Score/CR elects B and on more than half the ballots 
B is voted 
above A, but if  the 49 A9, B8, C0 voters change to  A9, B0, C0  the winner 
changes to A.
So this method fails UM.

48: ABCD
44: BADC
04: CBDA
03: DBCA

Here Borda elects B and B is voted above A on more than half the ballots, but 
if the 48 
ABCD ballots are changed to ACDB the  Borda winner changes to A, so
Borda fails UM.

This  Unmanipulable Majority criterion is failed by all well known and 
currently advocated
methods, except  3-slot SMD,TR!

Given its other criterion compliances and simplicity, that is my favourite 
3-slot s-w method
and my favourite Favourite Betrayal complying method.


Chris Benham


  Start your day with Yahoo!7 and win a Sony Bravia TV. Enter now 
http://au.docs.yahoo.com/homepageset/?p1=otherp2=aup3=tagline
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Unmanipulable Majority strategy criterion definition amended

2008-12-01 Thread Chris Benham
I propose to amend my suggested  Unmanipulable Majority
criterion by simply adding a phrase beginning with without.. 
so that it now reads:

*If (assuming there are more than two candidates) the ballot 
rules don't constrain voters to expressing fewer than three 
preference-levels, and A wins being voted above B on more 
than half the ballots, then it must not be possible to make B 
the winner by altering any of the ballots on which B is voted 
above A without raising their ranking or rating of B.*

(Later I might rephrase it just to make it more succinct and
polished).

The effect of  the alteration is to preclude Compromise strategy.
When I first suggested the original version I knew that many methods
fail it due to Burial and/or  Push-over, but I mistakenly thought that
my recent 3-slot method suggestion (defined below) meets it.


*Voters fill out 3-slot ratings ballots, default rating is bottom-most
(indicating least preferred and not approved).

Interpreting top and middle rating as approval, disqualify all candidates
with an approval score lower than their maximum approval-opposition (MAO) 
score.
(X's  MAO score is the approval score of the most approved candidate on
ballots that don't approve X).

Elect the undisqualified candidate with the highest top-ratings score.*

My preferred name for that method is now Strong Minimal Defense, Top
Ratings (SMD,TR). 

45: A
03: AB
47: BA
02: XB
03: YA

Approvals:   A98,  B52,  Y3,   X2
Max. AO:    A2,    B48,  Y95, X95
Top Ratings: A48, B47,   Y3,  X2.

X and Y are disqualified, and  A wins.

A  is voted above B on more than half the ballots, but if all the ballots on
which B is voted above A are altered so that they all plump for B (top-rate B
and approve no other candidates) then B wins.


45: A
03: AB
49: B 
03: YA

Approvals:   A51,  B52,  Y3,   X0
Max. AO:    A49,  B48,  Y52, X52
Top Ratings: A48, B49,   Y3,  X0

As before only X and Y are disqualified, but now B has the highest Top Ratings
score.

I will soon post more on the subject of  which methods meet or fail the (newly
amended)  Unmanipulable Majority criterion.

Chris Benham


  Start your day with Yahoo!7 and win a Sony Bravia TV. Enter now 
http://au.docs.yahoo.com/homepageset/?p1=otherp2=aup3=tagline
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Unmanipulable Majority strategy criterion

2008-11-29 Thread Chris Benham
Kristofer,

...your Dominant Mutual Quarter Burial Resistance property.

I don't  remember reading or hearing about anything like that with Quarter in 
the title
anywhere except in your EM  posts. 

A few years ago  James Green-Armytage coined the Mutual Dominant Third 
criterion
but never promoted it.  I took it up, but sometimes mistakenly reversed the 
order of the first 
two words. I now think the original order is better, because MDT is analogous 
with the 
better-known older Mutual Majority criterion.

I do remember suggesting  what is in effect MDT Burial Resistance, because 
there is an
ok method that meets it while failing Burial Invulnerability: namely Smith,IRV.

I don't know of any method that meets  the MDQBR you refer to that isn't 
completely in
invulnerable to Burial (do you?), so I don't see how that criterion is 
presently useful.

In response to my question is Unmanipulative Majority desirable?  you wrote:

In isolation (not affecting anything else), sure. It's desirable because  it 
limits the burying 
tricks that can be done.

I'm glad you think so.

The mention of pushover strategy there would mean that the method would 
have to have some degree of monotonicity, I assume.

Yes.

If AX voters can cause A to win by rearranging  their ballots, then that 
would be a 
form of constructive burial. If, for instance, some subset of the voters who 
place X 
fifth can keep X from winning by rearranging their first-to-fourth preferences, 
then that 
would be destructive burial.

If those voters are sincere in ranking X fifth, i.e they sincerely prefer all 
the candidates
they rank above X to X; then I can't see that that qualifies as Burial 
strategy at all.

Normally the strategy you refer to would qualify as some form of  Compromise 
strategy.
(Do you have an example that doesn't?)

Chris Benham





Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote (Fri.Nov.28) wrote:

Chris Benham wrote:
  
 Kristofer,
 Thanks for at least responding.
  
 ...I won't say anything about the desirability because I  don't know 
 what it implies;..
 
 Only judging criteria by how they fit in with other criteria is 
 obviously circular.

That's true. If we're going to judge criteria by how they fit in with 
other criteria, we should have an idea of how relatively desirable they are.

It may also be the case that it the tradeoff would be too great, by 
reasoning similar to what I gave in the reply to Juho about your 
Dominant Mutual Quarter Burial Resistance property. But if we consider 
this in more detail, we don't really know whether such tradeoffs are too 
great for, for instance, cloneproof criteria (though I think they are not).

 Do you (or anyone) think that judged in isolation this strategy 
 criterion is desirable?
 It is true that some desirable/interesting criteria are so restrictive 
 (as you put it) that
 IMO  compliance with them can only be a redeeming feature of  a method 
 that isn't
 one of the best.  (I  put Participation in that category.)

In isolation (not affecting anything else), sure. It's desirable because 
it limits the burying tricks that can be done.

If you're asking whether I think it's more important than being, say, 
cloneproof, I don't think I can answer at the moment. I haven't thought 
about the relative desirability of criteria, though I prefer Condorcet 
methods to be both Smith and cloneproof.

 Maybe some people would like me to paraphrase this suggested criterion 
 in language
 that is more EM-typical:
 
 'If candidate A majority-strength pairwise beats candidate B, then it 
 must not be possible for B's
 supporters (pairwise versus A) to use Burial or Pushover strategy to 
 change the winner from A
 to B.'

The mention of pushover strategy there would mean that the method would 
have to have some degree of monotonicity, I assume.

 Destructive burial would be trying to make X not win,...
  
 Your destructive burial  looks  almost synonymous with *monotonicity*.

Hm, not necessarily. Without qualifications on the criterion, 
destructive burial would be constructive burial for *any* candidate, but 
also more than that. If AX voters can cause A to win by rearranging 
their ballots, then that would be a form of constructive burial. If, for 
instance, some subset of the voters who place X fifth can keep X from 
winning by rearranging their first-to-fourth preferences, then that 
would be destructive burial.



  Start your day with Yahoo!7 and win a Sony Bravia TV. Enter now 
http://au.docs.yahoo.com/homepageset/?p1=otherp2=aup3=tagline
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Why I think IRV isn't a serious alternative

2008-11-27 Thread Chris Benham
Forest,
Given IRV's compliance with the representativeness criteria Mutual Dominant 
Third, Majority for
Solid Coalitions, Condorcet Loser and  Plurality; why should the bad look of  
its erratic behaviour
be sufficient to condemn IRV in spite of these and other positive criterion 
compliances such as
Later-no-Harm and  Burial Invulnerability?

in the best of all possible worlds, namely normally distributed voting 
populations in no more 
than two dimensional issue space.

Why does that situation you refer to qualify as the best of all possible 
worlds ?

Chris  Benham



Forrest Simmons wrote  (Wed. Nov.26):
Greg,

When someone asks for examples of IRV not working well in practice, they are 
usually protesting against 
contrived examples of IRV's failures.  Sure any method can be made to look 
ridiculous by some unlikely 
contrived scenario.

I used to sympathize with that point of view until I started playing around 
with examples that seemed natural 
to me, and found that IRV's erratic behavior was fairly robust.  You could vary 
the parameters quite a bit 
without shaking the bad behavior.

But I didn't expect anybody but fellow mathematicians to be able to appreciate 
how generic the pathological 
behavior was, until ...

... until the advent of the Ka-Ping Lee and B. Olson diagrams, which show 
graphically the extent of the 
pathology even in the best of all possible worlds, namely normally distributed 
voting populations in no more 
than two dimensional issue space.

These diagrams are not based upon contrived examples, but upon 
benefit-of-a-doubt assumptions.  Even 
Borda looks good in these diagrams because voters are assumed to vote sincerely.

Each diagram represents thousands of elections decided by normally distributed 
sincere voters.

I cannot believe that anybody who supports IRV really understands these 
diagrams.  Admittedly, it takes 
some effort to understand exactly what they represent, and I regret that the 
accompaning explanations are 
too abstract for the mathematically naive.  They are a subtle way of displaying 
an immense amount of 
information.

One way to make more concrete sense out of these diagrams is to pretend that 
each of the candidate 
dots actually represents a proposed building site, and that the purpose of each 
simulated election is to 
choose the site from among these options.

Each of the other pixels in the diagram represents (by its color) the outcome 
the election would have (under 
the given method) if a normal distribution of voters were centered at that 
pixel.

So each pixel of the diagram represents a different election, but with the same 
candidates (i.e. proposed 
construction sites).

Different digrams explore the effect of moving the candidates around relative 
to each other, as well as 
increasing the number of candidates.

With a little practice you can get a good feel for what each diagram 
represents, and what it says about the 
method it is pointed at (as a kind of electo-scope).

On result is that IRV shows erratic behavior even in those diagrams where every 
pixel represents an election 
in which there is a Condorcet candidate.

My Best,

Forest


  Start your day with Yahoo!7 and win a Sony Bravia TV. Enter now 
http://au.docs.yahoo.com/homepageset/?p1=otherp2=aup3=tagline
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Unmanipulable Majority strategy criterion

2008-11-26 Thread Chris Benham
I have a suggestion for a new strategy criterion I might call  
Unmanipulable Majority.

*If (assuming there are more than two candidates) the ballot 
rules don't constrain voters to expressing fewer than three 
preference-levels, and A wins being voted above B on more 
than half the ballots, then it must not be possible to make B 
the winner by altering any of the ballots on which B is voted 
above A.*

Does anyone else think that this is highly desirable?

Is it new?

Chris Benham


  Start your day with Yahoo!7 and win a Sony Bravia TV. Enter now 
http://au.docs.yahoo.com/homepageset/?p1=otherp2=aup3=tagline
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Why I Prefer IRV to Condorcet

2008-11-20 Thread Chris Benham
Greg,
I generally liked your essay. I rate IRV as the best of the single-winner 
methods that
meet Later-no-Harm, and a good method (and a vast improvement on FPP).

But I think you made a couple of technical errors.

However, because bullet voting can help and never backfire against one's top 
choice under
Condorcet, expect every campaign with a shot at winning to encourage its 
supporters to 
bullet vote. 

Bullet voting can backfire against one's top choice under Condorcet because 
Condorcet
methods, unlike IRV, fail Later-no-Help. 

http://groups.yahoo.com/group/election-methods-list/files/wood1996.pdf

In this 1996 Douglas Woodall paper, see Election 6 and the accompanying 
discussion on
page 5/6 of the pdf (labelled on the paper as Page 13).

Quoting again from your paper:
As mentioned, every voting system is theoretically vulnerable to strategic 
manipulation, and IRV 
is no exception. However, under IRV, there is no strategy that can increase the 
likelihood of 
electing one's first choice beyond the opportunity offered by honest rankings. 
While there are 
strategies for increasing the chances of less preferred candidates under IRV, 
like push-over, 
they are counter-intuitive.

The Push-over strategy is certainly not limited to improving the chance of 
electing a lower 
[than first] choice. Say sincere is:

49: A 
27: BA
24: CB

B is the IRV winner, but if  4-21 (inclusive) of the A voters change to C or 
C? then the winner
changes to A.

But as you say the strategy isn't intuitive , and backfires if too many of 
the A supporters try it.
Some IRV opponents claim to like Top-Two Runoff, but that is more vulnerable to 
Push-over 
than IRV (because the strategists can support their sincere favourite in the 
second round).

The quite intuitive strategy that IRV is vulnerable to is Compromise, like any 
other method that
meets Majority. But voters' incentive to compromise (vote one's front-runner 
lesser-evil in first
place to reduce the chance of front-runner greater-evil winning) is generally 
vastly vastly less
than it is under FPP.

(There are methods that meet both Majority and Favourite Betrayal, and in them 
compromisers
can harmlessly vote their sincere favourites in equal-first place.)

But some Condorcet advocates are galled  by the Compromise incentive that can 
exist where
there is a sincere CW who is not also a sincere Mutual Dominant Third winner.

49: AB
02: BA
22: B
27: CB

On these votes B is the CW, but IRV elects A.  If the CB voters change to B 
then B will be 
the voted majority favourite, so of course IRV like Condorcet methods and FPP 
will elect B.

Chris Benham

 
Greg wrote (Wed.Nov.19, 2008):
I have written up my reasons for preferring IRV over Condorcet methods
in an essay, the current draft of which is available here:
  http://www.gregdennis.com/voting/irv_vs_condorcet.html

I welcome any comments you have.

Thanks,
Greg



  Make the switch to the world#39;s best email. Get Yahoo!7 Mail! 
http://au.yahoo.com/y7mail
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] New MN court affidavits by those defending non-Monotonic voting methods IRV/STV

2008-11-07 Thread Chris Benham
Greg wrote (Th.Nov.6):
Those documents make a good case. If you rule IRV/STV unconstitutional
due to non-monotonicity, you have to be prepared to rule open
primaries and top-two primaries unconstitutional as well.

Note also that other arguments by the MN Voter's Alliance would, if
successful, would render *any* voting method that involves putting
marks next to multiple candidates -- IRV, Bucklin, Approval,
Condorcet, Range -- by its nature unconstitutional.

-snip-

That anti-IRV group explicitly say as much:

Additional note:  There are several other non-traditional voting methods 
currently being advocated around the country. Among these are Range Voting
and Approval Voting. (See the NYU report linked above) While these schemes
are better in some ways than IRV, they retain some of the same fatal flaws which
 make IRV unconstitutional.

http://www.mnvoters.org/IRV.htm


Chris Benham



  Find your perfect match today at the new Yahoo!7 Dating. Get Started 
http://au.dating.yahoo.com/?cid=53151pid=1012
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] In defense of the Electoral College (was Re: Making a Bad Thing Worse)

2008-11-07 Thread Chris Benham


Kevin Venzke wrote (Fri.Nov.7):
Hi,

--- En date de : Ven 7.11.08, Markus Schulze markus.schulze at 
alumni.tu-berlin.de a écrit :
Second: It makes it possible that the elections
are run by the governments of the individual
states and don't have to be run by the central
government.

I especially agree with this second point, or at least that it has been
a good thing that the elections have not been conducted by a single
authority.

It's possible to imagine a different American history, if the federal
government had been in a position to cancel or postpone or manipulate the 
presidential election.

Kevin Venzke

 
Kevin,
Why does having elections for national office run by a central authority
like a federal electoral commission  necessarily mean that the federal
government (presumably you refer here to partisan office-holders with
a stake in the election outcome) would have the power to cancel or
postpone or manipulate the presidential election?

Can you please support your point by comparing the US with other
First World countries, perhaps just focussing on the last few decades?

Chris Benham



  Find your perfect match today at the new Yahoo!7 Dating. Get Started 
http://au.dating.yahoo.com/?cid=53151pid=1012
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] New MN court affidavits by those defending non-Monotonic voting methods IRV/STV

2008-11-07 Thread Chris Benham
Dave,
Are you really comfortable supporting and supplying ammunition to a 
group of avowed FPP supporters in their effort to have IRV declared
unconstitutional?

Will have any complaint when in future they are trying to do the same
thing to some Condorcet method you like and IRV supporters help
them on grounds like it fails Later-no-Harm, Later-no-Help, and 
probably  mono-add-top?

Chris Benham

 



Dave Ketchum wrote (Fri.Nov.7):
Perhaps this could get some useful muscle by adding such as:
  9 BA

Now we have 34 voting BA.  Enough that they can expect to win and may have 
as strong a preference between these two as might happen anywhere.

C and D represent issues many feel strongly about - and can want to assert 
to encourage action by B, the expected winner.  If ONE voter had voted BA 
rather than DBA, IRV would have declared B the winner.

Note that Condorcet would have declared B the winner any time the BA count 
exceeded the AB count (unless C or D got many more votes).

DWK

On Fri, 7 Nov 2008 14:05:03 -0700 Kathy Dopp wrote:
Dave,

I agree with you -that is important too, but the attorneys and
judge(s) have their own criteria for judging importance as compared to
existing laws.

Your example IMO does show unequal treatment of voters, so perhaps
I'll include it as one of many ways to show how IRV unequally treats
voters and see if the attorneys use it or not.

Thanks.

Kathy


  Find your perfect match today at the new Yahoo!7 Dating. Get Started 
http://au.dating.yahoo.com/?cid=53151pid=1012
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] In defense of the Electoral College (was Re: Making a Bad Thing Worse)

2008-11-06 Thread Chris Benham
Steve Eppley wrote (Th. Nov.6):
Hi,

Greg Nisbet wrote on 10/18/08:
-snip-
The Electoral College:
This is generally regarded as a bad thing. No one really appears to
support it except as an adhoc version of asset voting.
-snip-

I don't believe the EC is generally accepted as a bad thing. (I picked 
the Subject line above to cite a book by the same name.)  Although I may 
have been the person who came up with the idea for how to get rid of the 
EC without a constitutional amendment (posted in EM many years ago), I 
later concluded the EC is better than a national popular vote.
-snip-

One widespread argument against the EC is that it flouts the commonsense
fairness axiom that all votes should be weighted equally.

A national popular vote would exacerbate polarization, since candidates 
could/would focus on voter turnout of their base instead of having to 
appeal to swing voters in a few close states.

I don't see how preventing the supposed evil of  exacerbating polarisation
anything like justifiies the unfairness evil of weighting votes unequally.

And in any case I don't accept the argument. Why wouldn't candidates
have incentive to appeal to swing voters  *across the whole country*??

Why would anyone go to the trouble of elaborating and proposing a 
relatively complicated ranked-ballot method that is justified by meeting
the Condorcet criterion and Majority for Solid Coalitions and so on,
and then turn around and suggest that it is desirable that weighting votes
unequally should be maintained, thus ensuring that any voting method
cannot meet those criteria or even  Majority Favourite or Majority
Loser?

A national popular vote would exacerbate the candidates' need for 
campaign money, since they would not be able to focus on the few states 
that are close.  That would make them more beholden to wealthy special 
interests.

A national popular vote would make for a nightmare when recounting a 
close election.  The recounting wouldn't be confined to a few close states.

Plenty of other countries directly elect their presidents without any EC,
and yet it is the US that has these problems (more severely).

I think the counting problems would be less likely with a national popular
vote, simply because it is very unlikely to be very close. The scenario
that it is very close in some (using the the EC)  critical states but not
close in the overall popular vote is much more likely than it being very
close in both.

 
Chris Benham


  Search 1000's of available singles in your area at the new Yahoo!7 
Dating. Get Started http://au.dating.yahoo.com/?cid=53151pid=1011
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Re : About Condorcet//Approval

2008-10-30 Thread Chris Benham
Kevin,
I've always thought that the main value of  mono-raise is that methods that 
fail it are 
vulnerable to Pushover strategy and those that meet it aren't. 

push-over 
The strategy of ranking a weak alternative higher than one's preferred 
alternative, which may be useful in a method that violates monotonicity.
http://condorcet.org/emr/defn.shtml

But now you are proposing an interpretation of  mono-raise (aka monotonicity) 
that can 
be met by a method that is clearly vulnerable to Pushover strategy.
 
25: AB
26: BC
23: CA
26: C

What is the value/use of a criterion that does that and moreover can be met by 
a method
that fails to elect C in the above election?   
 
The method under discussion that you say meets mono-raise, Definite Majority 
Choice
(Whole), elects B.
 
 
All candidates are in the top cycle, but by our 3-slot ratings ballot 
interpretation C has
the highest TR score, the highest  approval score, and the lowest 
approval-opposition
score.
 
Would you agree then that there is a need for an  Invulnerability to Pushover 
strategy
criterion, that is more important than mono-raise?
 
Chris Benham
 

 

Hi Chris,

--- En date de : Jeu 23.10.08, Chris Benham cbenhamau at yahoo.com.au a 
écrit :
Kevin,
I think the version of  DMC  that allows voters to rank among unapproved
candidates fails mono-raise, and both versions are vulnerable to Pushover
strategy. 

Would you say that that the plain all ranked are
approved version doesn't properly fail mono-raise but instead fails
mono-raise-delete?

I think it definitely fails the latter. I think it only fails the former
if you can't rank all the candidates (for approval purposes).

http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2007-March/019824.html

I wrote in March 2007:
With the approval cutoffs, DMC  (and AWP) come close to
failing mono-raise.

31: AB
04: AC
32: BC
33: CA

ABCA   Approvals: A35,  B32,   C33. 
A eliminates (doubly defeats) B, and C wins. (AWP measures 
defeat-strengths by the number of ballots on the winning
side that approve the 
winner and not the loser, and so says C's defeat is the
weakest and so also
elects C.)

Now change the 4 AC ballots to CA

To my mind you aren't allowed to move C over both A and the cutoff at
the same time, unless the method for some reason doesn't allow it any
other way (such as if this is the bottom of the ballot and you can't
approve all candidates).

Kevin Venzke

I misstated something:

--- En date de : Dim 26.10.08, Kevin Venzke stepjak at yahoo.fr a écrit :
 Now change the 4 AC ballots to CA

To my mind you aren't allowed to move C over both A and
the cutoff at
the same time, unless the method for some reason
doesn't allow it any
other way (such as if this is the bottom of the ballot and
you can't
approve all candidates).

You can move C over both at the same time, but you can't, at this same
time, move A and the cutoff relative to each other, according to my
opinion.

Kevin Venzke


  Search 1000's of available singles in your area at the new Yahoo!7 
Dating. Get Started http://au.dating.yahoo.com/?cid=53151pid=1011
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] About Condorcet//Approval

2008-10-23 Thread Chris Benham
Kevin,
I think the version of  DMC  that allows voters to rank among unapproved
candidates fails mono-raise, and both versions are vulnerable to Pushover
strategy. 

Would you say that that the plain all ranked are approved version
doesn't properly fail mono-raise but instead fails mono-raise-delete?

http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2007-March/019824.html

I wrote in March 2007:
With the approval cutoffs, DMC  (and AWP) come close to failing mono-raise.

31: AB
04: AC
32: BC
33: CA

ABCA   Approvals: A35,  B32,   C33. 
A eliminates (doubly defeats) B, and C wins. (AWP measures 
defeat-strengths by the number of ballots on the winning side that approve the 
winner and not the loser, and so says C's defeat is the weakest and so also
elects C.)

Now change the 4 AC ballots to CA

31: AB
32: BC
37: CA (4 were AC)

ABCA   Approvals: C37,   B32,  A31
Now C doubly defeats A, and B wins. (AWP also elects B)

http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2008-October/023017.html


Chris Benham




Kevin Venzke wrote (Mon.Oct.20):
Hi Kristofer,

--- En date de : Lun 20.10.08, Kristofer Munsterhjelm km-elmet at 
broadpark.no a écrit :
You could also have the approval version of Smith,IRV. Call
it 
Condorcet,Approval. I think it's Smith (so it would be
Smith,Approval), 
but I'm not sure. The method is this: Drop candidates,
starting with the 
Approval loser and moving upwards, until there's a CW.
Then that one is 
the winner.

This method has been invented from scratch a few times; most recently
it was called Definite Majority Choice.

I don't think it can be described using double-slash or comma notation...

For instance Smith//FPP would mean that you eliminate all non-Smith
candidates and elect the FPP winner pretending that the eliminated
candidates never existed. Whereas Smith,FPP would mean that you elect
that Smith candidate who had the most first preferences to start with.

When Condorcet is the first or Approval is the second component, it's
not likely to make a difference which punctuation is used.

Is Condorcet,Approval (Smith,Approval?) nonmonotonic? If
not, and it is 
Smith, then you have a simple Smith-compliant
Condorcet/approval method.

It satisfies Smith and monotonicity.

Kevin Venzke


Send instant messages to your online friends http://au.messenger.yahoo.com 
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] About Condorcet//Approval

2008-10-21 Thread Chris Benham
Kristofer Munsterhjelm  wrote (Sat.Oct.18):
Because Smith is more complex to explain, my current favorite election 
method is Condorcet//Approval. We don't need complex algorithms to find a 
winner.

You could also have the approval version of Smith,IRV. Call it 
Condorcet,Approval. I think it's Smith (so it would be Smith,Approval), 
but I'm not sure. The method is this: Drop candidates, starting with the 
Approval loser and moving upwards, until there's a CW. Then that one is 
the winner.

 
Kristofer,
The method you describe isn't Smith,Approval (which is the same thing as
Smith//Approval).  Smith,Approval elects the member of the Smith set
highest-ordered by Approval on the original ballots, Smith//Approval first
eliminates (drops from the ballots) all non-members of the Smith set and
applies Approval to the remaining candidates. 

Since approval is treated as 'absolute' it doesn't make a difference like it 
does 
between Smith,IRV and Smith//IRV.
 
The method you describe has IRV-like mono-raise failure and Pushover 
strategy vulnerability.
 
31: AB
32: BC
31: CA
06: C
 
All ranked candidates are approved, and all candidates are in the Smith set.
AB 62-32,   BC 63-31,  CA 69-31.   
Approval scores:  A62,  B63,  C69.

A is eliminated and B wins, but if  2 of  the 6 C votes change to A then C 
wins. 
 
31: AB
32: BC
31: CA
04: C
02: A
 
The Approval winner C is the clearly strongest candidate (the most first 
preferences 
and the most second preferences) in both cases.
 
These methods would obviously need approval cutoff ballots (unless you 
go with the MDDA assumption, that the approval cutoff is where the voter 
truncates, but I don't think that would be a good idea here).

Here I agree with Kevin Venzke. Allowing voters to rank among candidates they
don't approve just makes the method more vulnerable to Burial strategy and makes
the proposal much more complex.
 
 
Chris Benham

Send instant messages to your online friends http://au.messenger.yahoo.com 
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] 3-slot SMD,ER-FPP(w)

2008-10-20 Thread Chris Benham

--- En date de : Dim 19.10.08, Chris Benham cbenhamau at yahoo.com.au a 
écrit :
I have an idea for a new 3-slot voting method:

*Voters fill out 3-slot ratings ballots, default rating is
bottom-most (indicating least preferred and not approved).

Interpreting top and middle rating as approval, disqualify
all candidates with an approval score lower than their approval-opposition
(AO) score.
(X's  AO score is the approval score of the most approved candidate on
ballots that don't approve X).

Elect the undisqualified candidate with the highest
top-ratings score.*
 Kevin Venzke wrote (Mon.Oct.20):


Interesting method, but I'm concerned that rating a candidate in the 
middle can disqualify other candidates, but can't help this candidate 
win, except by preventing him from being disqualified himself. It seems
like a burial risk.

With two major factions supporting A and B, and a third candidate C,
if A faction buries B under C, I believe A will often win. Does B faction
have a defensive strategy that isn't the same as the offensive strategy?
I don't think they do.

Actually, this method isn't that far from MDD,FPP.

CB: Except that method fails Irrelevant Ballots and I think meets LNHarm.

This clearly meets Favourite Betrayal, Participation,
mono-raise, mono-append,
3-slot Majority for Solid Coalitions, Strong Minimal
Denfense (and so Minimal
Defense and  Woodall's Plurality criterion),
Independence of  Irrelevant Ballots.

I don't think it satisfies Participation, because your favorite candidate
could be winning, and when your vote is added, you add sufficient
approval to your compromise choice that they are no longer disqualified,
and are able to win instead of your favorite.

CB: Oops!.. you are right. It fails Participation and even Mono-add-Top.

8: C
3: F
2: XF
2: YF
2: ZF

F wins after all other candidates are disqualified, but if  2 FC ballots are
added C wins in exactly the way you describe.

It looks like the Strong Minimal Defense mechanism is incompatible with
Participation, so I was also wrong in suggesting that my recent Range-Approval
hybrid method suggestion meets Participation.

I still like this 3-slot SMD,FPP(w) method however and am confident the other
criterion compliances I claimed for it hold up.


Chris Benham

Send instant messages to your online friends http://au.messenger.yahoo.com 
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] 3-slot SMD,ER-FPP(w)

2008-10-19 Thread Chris Benham
I have an idea for a new 3-slot voting method:

*Voters fill out 3-slot ratings ballots, default rating is bottom-most
(indicating least preferred and not approved).

Interpreting top and middle rating as approval, disqualify all candidates
with an approval score lower than their approval-opposition (AO) score.
(X's  AO score is the approval score of the most approved candidate on
ballots that don't approve X).

Elect the undisqualified candidate with the highest top-ratings score.*

This clearly meets Favourite Betrayal, Participation, mono-raise, mono-append,
3-slot Majority for Solid Coalitions, Strong Minimal Denfense (and so Minimal
Defense and  Woodall's Plurality criterion), Independence of  Irrelevant 
Ballots.

This  3-slot Strong Minimal Defense, Equal-Ranking First-Preference Plurality 
(Whole) method is my new clear favourite 3-slot single-winner method.

One small technical disadvantage it has compared to Majority Choice Approval 
(MCA)
and  ER-Bucklin(Whole) and maybe Kevin Venzke's ICA method is that it fails
what I've been calling Possible Approval Winner (PAW).

35: A
10: A=B
30: BC
25: C

Approval scores:  A45,   B40,  C55
Approval Opp.:    A55,  B35,   C45
Top-ratings score: A45,  B40,   C25.  

C's approval opposition to A is 55, higher than A's approval score of 45, so A 
is
disqualified.  The undisqualified candidate with the highest top-ratings score 
is B,
so B wins.  But if we pretend that on each ballot there is an invisible approval
threshold that makes some distinction among the candidates but not among those
with the same rank, then B cannot have an approval score as high a A's.

This example is from Kevin Venzke, which he gave to show that Schulze (also) 
elects
B and so fails this criterion.  It doesn't bother me very much. MCA and  
Bucklin elect
C.

It is more Condorcetish and has a less severe later-harm problem than MCA, 
Bucklin,
or  Cardinal Ratings (aka Range, Average Rating, etc.)

40: AB
35: B
25: C

Approval scores:    A40,   B75,   C25 
Approval Opp.:  A35,   B25,   C75
Top-ratings scores: A40,   B35,   C25 

They elect B, but SMD,FPP(w) elects the Condorcet winner A.

It seems a bit less vulnerable to Burial strategy than Schulze.

46: AB
44: BC  (sincere is BA)
05: CA
05: CB

Approval scores:    A51,   B95,   C54 
Approval Opp.:  A49,   B05,   C46
Top-ratings scores: A46,   B44,   C10.  

In this admittedly not very realistic scenario, no candidate is disqualified 
and so A
wins. Schulze elects the buriers' favourite B.


Chris  Benham

Send instant messages to your online friends http://au.messenger.yahoo.com 
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Worst Voting Method

2008-10-17 Thread Chris Benham


Very bad is the Supplementary Vote used to elect some
mayors in the  UK.   It is like the Contingent Vote  (one trip to 
the polls TTR) except voters are only allowed to rank 2 candidates.


Kevin Venzke wrote:

I don't see how this is very bad. I could see how you might think it
is easily improved. But is this method better or worse than Approval? Is 
it better or worse than FPP?

Kevin,
The question of the precise ranking of  the worst single-winner methods
doesn't interest me very much. I just mentioned it as a method in use with
absurd arbitrary features/restrictions that is dominated (in terms of useful 
criterion 
compliances) by IRV.

To reluctantly answer your question I suppose it isn't worse than FPP  and
is probably worse than Approval.

I'd be much more interested in your reaction to my recent Range-Approval
hybrid suggested methods, which after all use the concept of  Approval
Opposition which you invented.

Chris Benham

Send instant messages to your online friends http://au.messenger.yahoo.com 
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


  1   2   >