[EM] SODA terminology: opinions wanted.

2012-05-25 Thread Jameson Quinn
I keep coming back to the basic question of terminology in SODA. If the
voters delegate their votes, what is the verb for the thing the candidates
do with those delegated votes? I want to be able to say: Candidate A is
first in the Xing order, so she Xs  for candidates B and C.
 is probably delegated approvals; what is ?

Assign? Cast? Commit? Fill in? Inject? Or is one word not enough, and you
need a phrase like delegated adding order?

I'd love it if someone could help me find a better option. Even if not, I
need more opinions before I can confidently choose one of the above options.

Jameson

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA terminology: opinions wanted.

2012-05-25 Thread Andy Jennings
On Fri, May 25, 2012 at 7:06 AM, Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.comwrote:

 I keep coming back to the basic question of terminology in SODA. If the
 voters delegate their votes, what is the verb for the thing the candidates
 do with those delegated votes? I want to be able to say: Candidate A is
 first in the Xing order, so she Xs  for candidates B and C.
  is probably delegated approvals; what is ?


How about: Candidate A is first in the sharing order, so she shares her
delegated votes with candidates B and C. ?

I know we had a discussion in August where we decided to change share to
add approvals to your vote on the wiki, and I agreed that I liked it
better.  Maybe I'm reconsidering...

I like the word share because A passing on votes doesn't diminish her
own.  (Similar to filesharing.)

~ Andy

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] SODA sometimes FBC-safe

2012-03-01 Thread MIKE OSSIPOFF

Jameson:

You wrote:

Actually,
 with SODA, it does help, because you can know ex ante (by looking at 
the predeclared preferences) when you are safe by FBC. That is, if you 
prefer AB, and B prefers A, or A prefers B, or A and B both prefer a
 certain viable C, then you are safe. Only if B prefers the most-viable 
third candidate C, but A is indifferent between B and C, then you might 
consider a favorite-betraying vote for B. And even then, it's only 
appropriate if A very nearly, but not quite, is able to win... not 
exactly the situation where favorite betrayal is the first thing on your
 mind.


This is a specific enough circumstance that 
favorite-betraying strategy would never take off and become a serious 
factor in SODA.
With
 SODA, you can give that as a solid ex-ante guarantee to most voters, 
just not quite all of them. This is unlike the situation in most voting 
systems, where you can make no solid guarantees before the vote unless 
you can make them to all voters.

[endquote]

Ok yes, as you say, that's a very different situation from the ordinary 
FBC-failure, because, for most people there is known to be no favorite-burial 
need. The favorite-burial problem really
exists when there's uncertainty for everyone, or for a large percentage of the 
voters, which isn't the case with SODA.

Mike Ossipoff



 
  
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA sometimes FBC-safe

2012-03-01 Thread Jameson Quinn
2012/3/1 MIKE OSSIPOFF nkk...@hotmail.com

  Jameson:

 You wrote:

 Actually, with SODA, it does help, because you can know ex ante (by
 looking at the predeclared preferences) when you are safe by FBC. That is,
 if you prefer AB, and B prefers A, or A prefers B, or A and B both prefer
 a certain viable C, then you are safe. Only if B prefers the most-viable
 third candidate C, but A is indifferent between B and C, then you might
 consider a favorite-betraying vote for B. And even then, it's only
 appropriate if A very nearly, but not quite, is able to win... not exactly
 the situation where favorite betrayal is the first thing on your mind.

 This is a specific enough circumstance that favorite-betraying strategy
 would never take off and become a serious factor in SODA.

 With SODA, you can give that as a solid ex-ante guarantee to most voters,
 just not quite all of them. This is unlike the situation in most voting
 systems, where you can make no solid guarantees before the vote unless you
 can make them to all voters.

 [endquote]

 Ok yes, as you say, that's a very different situation from the ordinary
 FBC-failure, because, for most people there is known to be no
 favorite-burial need. The favorite-burial problem really
 exists when there's uncertainty for everyone, or for a large percentage of
 the voters, which isn't the case with SODA.

 Thank you.

By the way, I left out one further circumstance in which you are FBC-safe.
Using the letters above, you are also safe if C declared a preference for
B. If C prefers A or is indifferent between A and B, then you might have to
worry (if all the other circumstances listed above also pertain.)

Jameson

Jameson

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA arguments

2012-02-18 Thread Jameson Quinn
  It seems to me that there would be a lot more candidates under SODA.
 It's pretty hard to spoil the race and there is benefit to
 be had in receiving some votes. It seems parliamentary that way. How many
 supporters is too few to consider running?


 Well, there is the 5% cutoff, below which your votes are automatically
 assigned for you.




 That's not really a punishment though. The candidate will probably get
 what they would've done anyway.

 I really think this is an issue that might need a rule of some kind. Why
 nominate one when you can nominate five? Anybody
 who appeals to some segment of the electorate could help bring in votes.
 Can you imagine if, for example, the Republicans
 were able to nominate every single one of their hopefuls for the
 presidency, with the knowledge that in the end all their votes
 would probably pool together? You don't have to like Gingrich, you can
 vote for Cain. And maybe your vote will end up
 with Gingrich, but without Cain you might not have cast it at all.


 That's a fair point


I've thought some more about the just nominate everyone problem, and I
think it may be worth making a SODA rule to deal with it. The problem with
the first  second + third rule is that it primarily focuses on the big
candidates, while the marginal choice of whether to throw one more hat in
the ring is made by the small candidates. So why not do something more
obvious: if a candidate gets less than 1%, they cannot use their delegated
votes at all.

Say candidates are naturally distributed by a modified form of Zipf's law,
with the top two candidates set to equal. That is to say, the top two
candidates have X% support; the next one has half that, X/2; the next, X/3;
etc.


It would take 21 candidates to get down to 1% support, and if all votes
were delegated or bullet votes, the top two would have 22% support each.
The minimum majority coalition would be 7 candidates.

If voters were a little more wary of wasting their vote, and left a safety
factor of 2 (that is, refused to vote for a candidate whose support was
under 2%), then there would be 12 candidates, and the top two would have
24% support each, and the minimum majority coalition would be 5 candidates.

And if voters had a safety factor of 2, but there were a 1/3 chance of
adding one more approval (that is, 2/9 of voters vote for 2 candidates,
2/27 vote for three, etc.; a total of 150% approvals) then there would be
14 candidates, the top two would have 35% support, and the minimum majority
coalition (using only the delegated, not the approval, votes of all but the
first coalition member) would be 3 candidates.

Of course, if you use a reasonable power law instead of Zipf's law, the
number of candidates would tend to be less, although the minimum majority
coalition might be slightly larger.

These numbers sound reasonable to me. I think the 1% cutoff would be a good
rule, and I'm considering adding it to the definition of the standard
version of SODA. What do others think?

Jameson

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] SODA arguments

2012-02-17 Thread Jameson Quinn
For those who feel that Bayesian Regret is the be-all-and-end-all measure
of voting system quality, that SODA's BR for 100% strategic voters will
beat all other systems, including Range/Approval.

For those who feel that Condorcet compliance is the be-all-and-end-all, a
majority Condorcet winner, or any Condorcet winner with 3 candidates and
full candidate preferences, is not just the winner with honest votes, but
in all cases the strategically-forced winner; this contrasts with Condorcet
systems, in which strategy can cause even majority- or 3-candidate- CWs to
lose.

For those who feel that strategic resistance is the most important, SODA is
unmatched. It meets FBC, solves the chicken dilemma, has no burial
incentive (ie, meets later-no-help), and even meets later-no-harm for the
two most-approved candidates (where it matters most). It's monotonic, and I
believe (haven't proven) that it meets consistency. It meets participation,
cloneproofness, and IIA for up to 4 candidates.

For those middlebrows who most value a system's acceptability to current
incumbents, SODA is top-of-the-line. It allows voters to vote
plurality-style and, if two parties are clearly favored by voters, allows
those two parties to prevent a weak centrist from winning, even if
polarization is so high that the centrist is an apparent Condorcet winner.

For those who want simplicity: while it's true that the SODA counting
process is more complicated than approval, the process of voting is
actually simpler than any other system, because you can just vote for your
favorite candidate. For the majority who agrees with their favorite
candidate's preferences, there is no strategic need to watch the polls and
figure out who the frontrunners are, and no nail-biting dilemma of whether
to rank others as equal to your favorite.

And for those who balk at delegation, SODA allows any voter to cast a
direct, undelegated ballot; and allows those voters who do delegate to know
how their vote will be used. Refusing to consider SODA because you don't
want to delegate, is like refusing to walk into a candy store because you
don't like chocolate; SODA allows, not requires, delegation.

I think pretty much everybody on this list falls into one or more of the
above categories. So, what's not to like about SODA?

Jameson

ps. I clarified the SODA
procedurehttp://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/SODA_voting_(Simple_Optionally-Delegated_Approval)#Full.2C_step-by-step_rules
on
the wiki, though there were no substantive changes. I improved the
formatting, marked the steps which are optional, and better explained that
winning candidates use their delegated votes first because precisely
because they will probably choose not to approve others.

Comments are welcome.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA arguments

2012-02-17 Thread Jameson Quinn


 For those who feel that strategic resistance is the most important, SODA
 is unmatched. It ... has no burial incentive (ie, meets later-no-help),


Oops. I got carried away. No burial incentive is arguably true, but it
doesn't universally meet later-no-help, only up to 4 candidates.

Jameson

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA arguments

2012-02-17 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Jameson,
 
Just a few thoughts.

De : Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
À : EM election-methods@lists.electorama.com; electionsciencefoundation 
electionscie...@googlegroups.com 
Envoyé le : Vendredi 17 février 2012 9h20
Objet : [EM] SODA arguments


For those who feel that Bayesian Regret is the be-all-and-end-all measure of 
voting system quality, that SODA's BR for 100% strategic voters will beat all 
other systems, including Range/Approval. 

I guess you will have a hard time arguing this, especially if you have multiple 
audiences. For instance, whether Range/Approval
are even all that great is controversial. But if you're an anti-majoritarian 
type or think it's unfair/unrealistic to propose that voters
are strategic, I guess that SODA looks like a step down.

Didn't you post an example where SODA declined to elect a weak CW that you 
said was actually a good thing? If that's
true, I guess some people won't agree with that.

It seems to me that there would be a lot more candidates under SODA. It's 
pretty hard to spoil the race and there is benefit to
be had in receiving some votes. It seems parliamentary that way. How many 
supporters is too few to consider running?

(I have a simple rule for cutting down the number of candidates. I don't think 
I've ever mentioned it because I know how 
idealistic you all are. Just say that the first-preference winner auto-wins if 
he has more first preferences than second and third
place combined. This can make it risky even to compete for third place. The 
idea is that voters should definitely then realize
which candidates are the top three in their race, which could amount to a 
viability/visibility boost for #3. My rule assumes 
there's no equal-ranking, but I bet something could be devised for other 
ballots.)

Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA arguments

2012-02-17 Thread Jameson Quinn
2012/2/17 Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr

 Hi Jameson,

 Just a few thoughts.

*De :* Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
 *À :* EM election-methods@lists.electorama.com;
 electionsciencefoundation electionscie...@googlegroups.com
 *Envoyé le :* Vendredi 17 février 2012 9h20
 *Objet :* [EM] SODA arguments

  For those who feel that Bayesian Regret is the be-all-and-end-all
 measure of voting system quality, that SODA's BR for 100% strategic voters
 will beat all other systems, including Range/Approval.


 I guess you will have a hard time arguing this, especially if you have
 multiple audiences. For instance, whether Range/Approval
 are even all that great is controversial. But if you're an
 anti-majoritarian type or think it's unfair/unrealistic to propose that
 voters
 are strategic, I guess that SODA looks like a step down.


I'm not sure that's true. Clay and Warren are the most hard-core BR
advocates, and probably I should let them speak for themselves, but... I
think their attitude is not that strategy is evil or Range voters will
be 100% honest, but rather, Some fraction of voters will be honest under
range, and that's good, so why not use range and let them? In that case,
the fact that range voting is strictly better (by BR, and for a pre-chosen
arbitrary strategic percentage) than [IRV, Condorcet, MJ, etc], is an
important foundation of their argument. Finding a system which, while it is
worse than range for 100% honest, is actually better than it in some cases
(100% strategy, and presumably 99%, who knows where it stops), is an
important qualitative difference in the situation.



 Didn't you post an example where SODA declined to elect a weak CW that
 you said was actually a good thing? If that's
 true, I guess some people won't agree with that.


Yes. The basic setup is two major candidates and a weak centrist. The
weaker of the two majors gets to decide which of the other two wins. So if
the weak CW is truly a CW, they will be preferred by the weaker major,
and thus win; but if they are more weak than CW, then the weaker major
would rather allow the stronger major to win than stake their reputation on
electing the weak CW.

So in the end, it's more a question of giving a last chance to realize that
someone isn't really the CW, rather than not electing someone who is the CW.


 It seems to me that there would be a lot more candidates under SODA. It's
 pretty hard to spoil the race and there is benefit to
 be had in receiving some votes. It seems parliamentary that way. How many
 supporters is too few to consider running?


Well, there is the 5% cutoff, below which your votes are automatically
assigned for you.



 (I have a simple rule for cutting down the number of candidates. I don't
 think I've ever mentioned it because I know how
 idealistic you all are. Just say that the first-preference winner
 auto-wins if he has more first preferences than second and third
 place combined. This can make it risky even to compete for third
 place. The idea is that voters should definitely then realize
 which candidates are the top three in their race, which could amount to a
 viability/visibility boost for #3. My rule assumes
 there's no equal-ranking, but I bet something could be devised for other
 ballots.)


That rule doesn't sound too bad to me. Most of the time, there'd be no risk
of it applying; but I think it would still be a gentle pressure in the
intended direction. Still, I think it should be considered separately from
SODA per se.

Jameson



 Kevin


 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA arguments

2012-02-17 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Jameson,
 


De : Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
À : Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr 
Cc : election-methods election-meth...@electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Vendredi 17 février 2012 19h53
Objet : Re: [EM] SODA arguments




 
For those who feel that Bayesian Regret is the be-all-and-end-all measure of 
voting system quality, that SODA's BR for 100% strategic voters will beat 
all other systems, including Range/Approval. 

I guess you will have a hard time arguing this, especially if you have 
multiple audiences. For instance, whether Range/Approval
are even all that great is controversial. But if you're an anti-majoritarian 
type or think it's unfair/unrealistic to propose that voters
are strategic, I guess that SODA looks like a step down.


I'm not sure that's true. Clay and Warren are the most hard-core BR 
advocates, and probably I should let them speak for themselves, but... I 
think their attitude is not that strategy is evil or Range voters will be 
100% honest, but rather, Some fraction of voters will be honest under 
range, and that's good, so why not use range and let them? In that case, the 
fact that range voting is strictly better (by BR, and for a pre-chosen 
arbitrary strategic percentage) than [IRV, Condorcet, MJ, etc], is an 
important foundation of their argument. Finding a system which, while it is 
worse than range for 100% honest, is actually better than it in some cases 
(100% strategy, and presumably 99%, who knows where it stops), is an 
important qualitative difference in the situation.

Alright. I guess I'll let them make their own arguments if they are so inclined.


Didn't you post an example where SODA declined to elect a weak CW that you 
said was actually a good thing? If that's
true, I guess some people won't agree with that.


Yes. The basic setup is two major candidates and a weak centrist. The weaker 
of the two majors gets to decide which of the other two wins. So if the weak 
CW is truly a CW, they will be preferred by the weaker major, and thus win; 
but if they are more weak than CW, then the weaker major would rather allow 
the stronger major to win than stake their reputation on electing the weak CW.


So in the end, it's more a question of giving a last chance to realize that 
someone isn't really the CW, rather than not electing someone who is the CW.


Concerns me a little. I'm not sure candidates would do the thing their 
supporters would want (or even that they themselves feel is 
best) due to pressures like staking their reputation. For instance, I can see 
a moderate liberal giving his votes to a more extreme
liberal even when he himself prefers a moderate conservative. A voter whose 
personal ranking crosses the line like that might
want to avoid delegating.




It seems to me that there would be a lot more candidates under SODA. It's 
pretty hard to spoil the race and there is benefit to
be had in receiving some votes. It seems parliamentary that way. How many 
supporters is too few to consider running?


Well, there is the 5% cutoff, below which your votes are automatically 
assigned for you.


That's not really a punishment though. The candidate will probably get what 
they would've done anyway.

I really think this is an issue that might need a rule of some kind. Why 
nominate one when you can nominate five? Anybody
who appeals to some segment of the electorate could help bring in votes. Can 
you imagine if, for example, the Republicans
were able to nominate every single one of their hopefuls for the presidency, 
with the knowledge that in the end all their votes
would probably pool together? You don't have to like Gingrich, you can vote for 
Cain. And maybe your vote will end up
with Gingrich, but without Cain you might not have cast it at all.
 



(I have a simple rule for cutting down the number of candidates. I don't 
think I've ever mentioned it because I know how 
idealistic you all are. Just say that the first-preference winner auto-wins 
if he has more first preferences than second and third
place combined. This can make it risky even to compete for third place. The 
idea is that voters should definitely then realize
which candidates are the top three in their race, which could amount to a 
viability/visibility boost for #3. My rule assumes 
there's no equal-ranking, but I bet something could be devised for other 
ballots.)


That rule doesn't sound too bad to me. Most of the time, there'd be no risk 
of it applying; but I think it would still be a gentle pressure in the 
intended direction. Still, I think it should be considered separately from 
SODA per se.
Maybe it would be gentle if you expect a lot of candidates but in general I 
don't think it is very gentle. For example, 
this election:

49 A
44 B
4 CB
3 DB

Would qualify, and auto-elect A.

Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA arguments

2012-02-17 Thread Jameson Quinn


 So in the end, it's more a question of giving a last chance to realize
 that someone isn't really the CW, rather than not electing someone who is
 the CW.




 Concerns me a little. I'm not sure candidates would do the thing their
 supporters would want (or even that they themselves feel is
 best) due to pressures like staking their reputation. For instance, I
 can see a moderate liberal giving his votes to a more extreme
 liberal even when he himself prefers a moderate conservative. A voter
 whose personal ranking crosses the line like that might
 want to avoid delegating.


This scenario is about whether to elect the squeezed centrist or the
opposite side. The extremist on your own side is already out of the
running. Moreover, as a voter, you can already see if your candidate
predeclared for a same-side exremist.



 It seems to me that there would be a lot more candidates under SODA. It's
 pretty hard to spoil the race and there is benefit to
 be had in receiving some votes. It seems parliamentary that way. How many
 supporters is too few to consider running?


 Well, there is the 5% cutoff, below which your votes are automatically
 assigned for you.




 That's not really a punishment though. The candidate will probably get
 what they would've done anyway.

 I really think this is an issue that might need a rule of some kind. Why
 nominate one when you can nominate five? Anybody
 who appeals to some segment of the electorate could help bring in votes.
 Can you imagine if, for example, the Republicans
 were able to nominate every single one of their hopefuls for the
 presidency, with the knowledge that in the end all their votes
 would probably pool together? You don't have to like Gingrich, you can
 vote for Cain. And maybe your vote will end up
 with Gingrich, but without Cain you might not have cast it at all.


That's a fair point. But look at the other side. Imagine Obama, with a
single votecatcher on his left, let's say Grayson. To me it's clear that
the two-person tag team (in this case, on the left) would be much better
off than the 6-person one (in this case, on the right). Too many people
would be tempted to approve just some subset of the Republicans. And
similarly, if it were just Romney and (pre-meltdown) Perry against
(non-incumbent) Obama, Clinton, (pre-scandal) Edwards, and Kucinich... I
think that Romney and Perry would have the advantage. That is to say, more
is not always better, even in SODA.

Jameson

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA criteria

2012-02-02 Thread Jameson Quinn
Example where SODA fails participation. To avoid the issue of ties, just
assume that the alphabetically first candidate wins all ties. (Otherwise,
you have to add votes in groups of two to make things clear).
25: A(BC)
5: B
5: C
25: D(CB)
40: E


As things are, A gets to delegate first, and approves only B. Now B is the
only candidate who can beat E, so D approves B as well, and B wins. But if
one approval-style vote is added for B and D, then D delegates first, and
approves only C. C wins by the same token. So a vote for B has made B lose.

I can prove this is impossible with 4 or fewer candidates. In particular,
the balance between the (AB) team and the (CD) team mean that such a
scenario can never work without a plausible-threat candidate E.

A similar scenario works for IIA, with the new candidate stealing votes
from A and sharing A's delegation order.

I find these scenarios very highly implausible; for 1 election every 4
years, it's literally not in a million years.

Jameson

2012/2/1 Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com



 2012/2/1 Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr

 Hi Jameson,

   *De :* Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
 *À :* Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr
 *Cc :* em election-meth...@electorama.com
 *Envoyé le :* Mercredi 1 février 2012 11h12
 *Objet :* Re: [EM] SODA criteria

   2012/2/1 Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr

  Hi Jameson,

 I expect that unpredictability (whatever there may be) of candidates'
 decisions can only hurt criteria compliance.
 At least with criteria that are generally defined on votes, because with
 such criteria you usually have to assume
 the worst about any other influences incorporated into the method.


 This is true.  For most of the criteria, I was implicitly talking about a
 version of SODA where all candidates use optimum strategy according to
 their predeclared preferences. This is well-defined and unique, but is not
 necessarily polytime-calculable. Still, even without being able to
 calculate results, you can prove criteria compliances for this version by
 contradiction.

 For a polytime-calculable version which satisfies most of the same
 criteria, assume that each candidate, when it is their turn to assign
 delegated votes, looks at the two distinct frontrunners; that is:
 Candidate X, their most-preferred member of the current Smith set
 and candidate Y, the candidate, of those whom they prefer differently
 from X, who does best pairwise (again, using current assignments and
 unassigned preferences) against X
 They approve as many candidates as possible without approving both X and
 Y.

 This version does not satisfy participation (though again, it's damn
 close) or IIA, and I'm not 100% sure about its cloneproofness (though I
 think it is). Otherwise, it satisfies the criteria I said.


 So I wonder, can you suggest a deterministic version of SODA, where the
 negotiations of SODA are instead
 calculated directly from the pre-announced preferences of the candidates?
 And if so, does it satisfy the same
 criteria in your view?

 I can say I would be skeptical of how a criterion is being applied, or
 how clearly it is being defined, if the
 satisfaction of it *depends* on the fact that candidates have
 post-voting decisions to make.


 Are you still suspicious of participation and [delegated] IIA, given that
 satisfying them depends on assuming optimal strategy?



 Hmm, I think so, just because optimal strategy is hard to define in
 general. Do you think that it will be possible to produce
 convincing proofs when somebody asks for one? Pretty daunting task I
 would think.


 The proofs for the condorcet-related properties using optimal strategy are
 pretty simple and obvious.

 The participation criterion only applies for delegated voters. The proof
 for that is a bit harder, but not too tough. For approval ballots, it is
 possible to fail the (voted) participation criterion only if the delegation
 order changes, and there are at least 5 candidates (in a delicate balance,
 and for voters whose ballots cannot make sense in a one-dimensional
 ideology space).

 I just discovered a hole in my proof for delegated IIA. It works if all
 votes for the new candidate are and were approval-style. It can fail if
 there are at least 4/5 candidates in a tricky balance and the 5th/extra
 candidate pulls delegated votes in a way that changes the delegation order.
 In that case, there is always still a rational strategy for those voters
 which would still preserve IIA. (This proof is tricky.)


 I find myself trying to suggest that it may never be necessary to
 delegate any power to the candidates. That would make it
 easier to analyze. But in that case the method is basically Approval and
 doesn't even satisfy Majority Favorite. Right?


 No. In my previous message, I suggested two versions which leave no
 freedom for the candidates, automatically assigning delegated ballots. The
 first – optimal strategy – is not polytime computable that I know of (I
 strongly suspect

Re: [EM] SODA criteria

2012-02-02 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Jameson,
 

De : Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
À : Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr 
Cc : em election-meth...@electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Mercredi 1 février 2012 18h35
Objet : Re: [EM] SODA criteria





In 
your criteria list you had Majority but for that you must actually be 
assuming the opposite of what I am trying, namely that
*everyone* is delegating, is that right?


Everyone who votes for the majority candidate is either delegating to them, 
or voting them above all other alternatives - that is, approving only them 
but checking do not delegate. This is the standard meaning of the majority 
criterion. For instance, by this meaning, approval meets the majority 
criterion.


For MMC, everyone in the mutual majority is either delegating to one of the 
candidates, or approving all of them and nobody else.

Oh, I missed that the voter can't rank at all. So you are good with FBC. But I 
don't regard Approval as satisfying what I
call MF and Woodall's Majority. It's possible to say it satisfies MF, but I 
prefer Woodall's treatment. (The criteria framework
I use doesn't have any way to say that Approval satisfies MMC. You can equate 
approval with equal-top, above-bottom, or
call it something external, but I can't say that voters stick to a limited 
number of slots. I understand the meaning of two-slot 
MMC or voted MMC but I see these as inferior versions.)

In response to your last line, if the majority set involves more than one 
candidate, the delegating voters are never part of it
and are unnecessary in getting one of these candidates elected. (I'm using your 
treatment that voters only have two rank 
levels.) If you don't agree, I'd like to hear how you are interpreting MMC, 
because I can't think of how else it would work.

Kevin
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA criteria

2012-02-02 Thread Jameson Quinn
2012/2/2 Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr

 Hi Jameson,


   *De :* Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
 *À :* Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr
 *Cc :* em election-meth...@electorama.com
 *Envoyé le :* Mercredi 1 février 2012 18h35

 *Objet :* Re: [EM] SODA criteria




In
 your criteria list you had Majority but for that you must actually be
 assuming the opposite of what I am trying, namely that
 *everyone* is delegating, is that right?


 Everyone who votes for the majority candidate is either delegating to
 them, or voting them above all other alternatives - that is, approving only
 them but checking do not delegate. This is the standard meaning of the
 majority criterion. For instance, by this meaning, approval meets the
 majority criterion.

 For MMC, everyone in the mutual majority is either delegating to one of
 the candidates, or approving all of them and nobody else.


 Oh, I missed that the voter can't rank at all. So you are good with FBC.
 But I don't regard Approval as satisfying what I
 call MF and Woodall's Majority. It's possible to say it satisfies MF, but
 I prefer Woodall's treatment.


I don't know what MF stands for. I agree that it fails Woodall's majority,
though not in the unique strong Nash equilibrium.


  (The criteria framework
 I use doesn't have any way to say that Approval satisfies MMC. You can
 equate approval with equal-top, above-bottom, or
 call it something external, but I can't say that voters stick to a limited
 number of slots. I understand the meaning of two-slot
 MMC or voted MMC but I see these as inferior versions.)


voted, because delegation means there's sometimes effectively more than
two slots.


 In response to your last line, if the majority set involves more than one
 candidate, the delegating voters are never part of it
 and are unnecessary in getting one of these candidates elected. (I'm using
 your treatment that voters only have two rank
 levels.) If you don't agree, I'd like to hear how you are interpreting
 MMC, because I can't think of how else it would work.


10: A(BC?...)
10: B(CA?...)
10: C(AB?...)
21: ABC
49: 

One of A, B, or C must win.

Jameson



 Kevin

 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA criteria

2012-02-02 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Jameson,


De : Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
À : Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr 
Cc : em election-meth...@electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Jeudi 2 février 2012 11h35
Objet : Re: [EM] SODA criteria









In 
your criteria list you had Majority but for that you must actually be 
assuming the opposite of what I am trying, namely that
*everyone* is delegating, is that right?


Everyone who votes for the majority candidate is either delegating to 
them, or voting them above all other alternatives - that is, approving 
only them but checking do not delegate. This is the standard meaning of 
the majority criterion. For instance, by this meaning, approval meets the 
majority criterion.


For MMC, everyone in the mutual majority is either delegating to one of 
the candidates, or approving all of them and nobody else.

Oh, I missed that the voter can't rank at all. So you are good with FBC. But 
I don't regard Approval as satisfying what I
call MF and Woodall's Majority. It's possible to say it satisfies MF, but I 
prefer Woodall's treatment.


I don't know what MF stands for. I agree that it fails Woodall's majority, 
though not in the unique strong Nash equilibrium.

(The criteria framework
I use doesn't have any way to say that Approval satisfies MMC. You can 
equate approval with equal-top, above-bottom, or
call it something external, but I can't say that voters stick to a limited 
number of slots. I understand the meaning of two-slot 
MMC or voted MMC but I see these as inferior versions.)


voted, because delegation means there's sometimes effectively more than two 
slots. 


In response to your last line, if the majority set involves more than one 
candidate, the delegating voters are never part of it
and are unnecessary in getting one of these candidates elected. (I'm using 
your treatment that voters only have two rank 
levels.) If you don't agree, I'd like to hear how you are interpreting MMC, 
because I can't think of how else it would work.


10: A(BC?...)
10: B(CA?...)
10: C(AB?...)
21: ABC
49: 


One of A, B, or C must win.

MF is Majority Favorite.

If I understand you correctly, you're treating voters as casting either an 
approval ballot, or else one of the predeclared
preference orders. I guess that makes sense though it's quite tricky to 
analyze. If a voter is counted as voting ABC, it's
not possible to raise C above only B. But when I analyze this, it has to result 
in something consistent with the desired ranking
unless that's completely impossible. I guess that could only be A, AC, or ACB 
approval ballots. I think that would result in 
some criteria problems. For instance, suppose that ABC elects C, but A=C=B 
elects B. Since I look at how the voter 
wanted to rank, and not the options the method made available, I would call 
that a Mono-raise failure.

You might think that's unfair, but I don't know what framework you can suggest 
that will be more apparent and also allow
you to fairly evaluate something like Mono-raise.

Personally I think it would be easier to assume voters have no idea what 
candidates predeclare. In that case MMC doesn't
apply in your scenario above.

Granted, this might make it hard for criteria that are supposed to deal with 
optimal strategy assumptions or equilibrium.
I just don't worry about those criteria because I don't know how to evaluate 
them.

I also wanted to note, here instead of in a separate post, that I wonder about 
the FBC. I was thinking it must satisfy
it because you could cast an approval ballot, but that's not good reasoning 
(see: any Condorcet method). What if it
is possible to get a superior result by delegating your vote to someone other 
than your favorite? It's not clear to me
that this is impossible.

Kevin
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA criteria

2012-02-02 Thread Jameson Quinn
2012/2/2 Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr

 Hi Jameson,

*De :* Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
 *À :* Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr
 *Cc :* em election-meth...@electorama.com
 *Envoyé le :* Jeudi 2 février 2012 11h35

 *Objet :* Re: [EM] SODA criteria






In
  your criteria list you had Majority but for that you must actually be
 assuming the opposite of what I am trying, namely that
 *everyone* is delegating, is that right?


 Everyone who votes for the majority candidate is either delegating to
 them, or voting them above all other alternatives - that is, approving only
 them but checking do not delegate. This is the standard meaning of the
 majority criterion. For instance, by this meaning, approval meets the
 majority criterion.

 For MMC, everyone in the mutual majority is either delegating to one of
 the candidates, or approving all of them and nobody else.


 Oh, I missed that the voter can't rank at all. So you are good with FBC.
 But I don't regard Approval as satisfying what I
 call MF and Woodall's Majority. It's possible to say it satisfies MF, but
 I prefer Woodall's treatment.


 I don't know what MF stands for. I agree that it fails Woodall's majority,
 though not in the unique strong Nash equilibrium.


   (The criteria framework
 I use doesn't have any way to say that Approval satisfies MMC. You can
 equate approval with equal-top, above-bottom, or
 call it something external, but I can't say that voters stick to a limited
 number of slots. I understand the meaning of two-slot
 MMC or voted MMC but I see these as inferior versions.)


 voted, because delegation means there's sometimes effectively more than
 two slots.


 In response to your last line, if the majority set involves more than one
 candidate, the delegating voters are never part of it
 and are unnecessary in getting one of these candidates elected. (I'm using
 your treatment that voters only have two rank
 levels.) If you don't agree, I'd like to hear how you are interpreting
 MMC, because I can't think of how else it would work.


 10: A(BC?...)
 10: B(CA?...)
 10: C(AB?...)
 21: ABC
 49: 

 One of A, B, or C must win.


 MF is Majority Favorite.

 If I understand you correctly, you're treating voters as casting either an
 approval ballot, or else one of the predeclared
 preference orders.


Yes.

 I guess that makes sense though it's quite tricky to analyze. If a voter
 is counted as voting ABC, it's
 not possible to raise C above only B. But when I analyze this, it has to
 result in something consistent with the desired ranking
 unless that's completely impossible. I guess that could only be A, AC, or
 ACB approval ballots. I think that would result in
 some criteria problems. For instance, suppose that ABC elects C, but
 A=C=B elects B. Since I look at how the voter
 wanted to rank, and not the options the method made available, I would
 call that a Mono-raise failure.


I guess I'd have to agree with that... well, if your vote for A=C causes C
to lose. So failing participation in this way – for which I recently posted
an example scenario, impossible with 4 candidates but possible with 5 –
means failing mono-raise.

My claim of monotonicity was based on comparing only approval ballots to
approval ballots, delegation preferences to delegation preferences, and
undelegated bullet votes to delegated votes. I did not consider this case.


 You might think that's unfair, but I don't know what framework you can
 suggest that will be more apparent and also allow
 you to fairly evaluate something like Mono-raise.


Well, you could do as I had done, and evaluate it when the candidate A
changes from BC to B=C.


 Personally I think it would be easier to assume voters have no idea what
 candidates predeclare. In that case MMC doesn't
 apply in your scenario above.


Easier, but I think less realistic. At that point, it's basically approval.



 Granted, this might make it hard for criteria that are supposed to deal
 with optimal strategy assumptions or equilibrium.
 I just don't worry about those criteria because I don't know how to
 evaluate them.

 I also wanted to note, here instead of in a separate post, that I wonder
 about the FBC. I was thinking it must satisfy
 it because you could cast an approval ballot, but that's not good
 reasoning (see: any Condorcet method). What if it
 is possible to get a superior result by delegating your vote to someone
 other than your favorite? It's not clear to me
 that this is impossible.


Say your favorite is W, but you delegate to some other X. They add
approvals Y and Z, so that your ballot is counted for X, Y, and Z; and Z
wins. You could have just voted for W, X, Y, and Z for the same result.
Your approval vote for X gives them the same boost in the delegation order
that a delegated vote would have given them.

In fact, if you don't like Y, you can probably leave them off.

Jameson



 Kevin

 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list

Re: [EM] SODA criteria

2012-02-01 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Jameson,
 
I expect that unpredictability (whatever there may be) of candidates' decisions 
can only hurt criteria compliance.
At least with criteria that are generally defined on votes, because with such 
criteria you usually have to assume
the worst about any other influences incorporated into the method.
 
So I wonder, can you suggest a deterministic version of SODA, where the 
negotiations of SODA are instead
calculated directly from the pre-announced preferences of the candidates? And 
if so, does it satisfy the same
criteria in your view?
 
I can say I would be skeptical of how a criterion is being applied, or how 
clearly it is being defined, if the 
satisfaction of it *depends* on the fact that candidates have post-voting 
decisions to make.
 
Kevin
 
 

De : Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
À : EM election-methods@lists.electorama.com 
Envoyé le : Mardi 31 janvier 2012 20h50
Objet : [EM] SODA criteria


SODA passes: 

Majority
MMC (as voted)
Condorcet (as voted, and in a strong Nash equilibrium as honest)
Condorcet loser (ditto)
Monotone
Participation (with the fix that delegation can be any fraction)
IIA (delegated version - that is, if a new candidate is added, the winner is 
either the same, or someone higher on the new candidate's delegation order.)
Cloneproof
Polytime (there is no guarantee that optimal delegated assignment strategy is 
polytime calculable, but it will be in any real case, and anyway, candidates 
can just choose some near-optimal strategy.)
Resolvable
Summable
Allows equal rankings
FBC

So, of the criteria in the wikipedia voting systems table, the only ones it 
out-and-out fails are:
Consistency (though it comes damn close)
Later-no-harm and later-no-help (though it does satisfy LNHarm for the one 
(two) candidate(s?) with the most voted approvals, and for other 
candidates, adding later preferences is probably strategically forced; so I'd 
say it fulfills the spirit of both of these. Similarly, it satisfies LNHelp for 
the last-to-delegate candidate, and nearly so for other late-delegating 
candidates, and the point of LNHelp is to prevent a weak candidate from winning 
through clever bottom filling, so again it satisfies the spirit.)
Allows later preferences (though delegation substitutes for this affordance in 
some cases.)

If we could just get some wikipedia-notable mention of SODA, we could put it in 
the table, and I think it would graphically stand out as the most 
criteria-compliant method there.

I'm working on an academic article on SODA, which would not be focused on these 
criteria or even on SODA, but would quickly state the above. But if anyone can 
make an article happen in a wikipedia reliable source, that would be great.

Jameson


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA criteria

2012-02-01 Thread Jameson Quinn
2012/2/1 Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr

 Hi Jameson,

 I expect that unpredictability (whatever there may be) of candidates'
 decisions can only hurt criteria compliance.
 At least with criteria that are generally defined on votes, because with
 such criteria you usually have to assume
 the worst about any other influences incorporated into the method.


This is true.  For most of the criteria, I was implicitly talking about a
version of SODA where all candidates use optimum strategy according to
their predeclared preferences. This is well-defined and unique, but is not
necessarily polytime-calculable. Still, even without being able to
calculate results, you can prove criteria compliances for this version by
contradiction.

For a polytime-calculable version which satisfies most of the same
criteria, assume that each candidate, when it is their turn to assign
delegated votes, looks at the two distinct frontrunners; that is:
Candidate X, their most-preferred member of the current Smith set
and candidate Y, the candidate, of those whom they prefer differently from
X, who does best pairwise (again, using current assignments and unassigned
preferences) against X
They approve as many candidates as possible without approving both X and Y.

This version does not satisfy participation (though again, it's damn close)
or IIA, and I'm not 100% sure about its cloneproofness (though I think it
is). Otherwise, it satisfies the criteria I said.


 So I wonder, can you suggest a deterministic version of SODA, where the
 negotiations of SODA are instead
 calculated directly from the pre-announced preferences of the candidates?
 And if so, does it satisfy the same
 criteria in your view?

 I can say I would be skeptical of how a criterion is being applied, or how
 clearly it is being defined, if the
 satisfaction of it *depends* on the fact that candidates have post-voting
 decisions to make.


Are you still suspicious of participation and [delegated] IIA, given that
satisfying them depends on assuming optimal strategy?

Jameson


 Kevin



   *De :* Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
 *À :* EM election-methods@lists.electorama.com
 *Envoyé le :* Mardi 31 janvier 2012 20h50
 *Objet :* [EM] SODA criteria

 SODA passes:

 Majority
 MMC (as voted)
 Condorcet (as voted, and in a strong Nash equilibrium as honest)
 Condorcet loser (ditto)
 Monotone
 Participation (with the fix that delegation can be any fraction)
 IIA (delegated version - that is, if a new candidate is added, the winner
 is either the same, or someone higher on the new candidate's delegation
 order.)
 Cloneproof
 Polytime (there is no guarantee that optimal delegated assignment strategy
 is polytime calculable, but it will be in any real case, and anyway,
 candidates can just choose some near-optimal strategy.)
 Resolvable
 Summable
 Allows equal rankings
 FBC

 So, of the criteria in the wikipedia voting systems 
 tablehttp://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Voting_system#Compliance_of_selected_systems_.28table.29,
 the only ones it out-and-out fails are:
 Consistency (though it comes damn close)
 Later-no-harm and later-no-help (though it does satisfy LNHarm for the one
 (two) candidate(s?) with the most voted approvals, and for other
 candidates, adding later preferences is probably strategically forced; so
 I'd say it fulfills the spirit of both of these. Similarly, it satisfies
 LNHelp for the last-to-delegate candidate, and nearly so for other
 late-delegating candidates, and the point of LNHelp is to prevent a weak
 candidate from winning through clever bottom filling, so again it satisfies
 the spirit.)
 Allows later preferences (though delegation substitutes for this
 affordance in some cases.)

 If we could just get some wikipedia-notable mention of SODA, we could put
 it in the table, and I think it would graphically stand out as the most
 criteria-compliant method there.

 I'm working on an academic article on SODA, which would not be focused on
 these criteria or even on SODA, but would quickly state the above. But if
 anyone can make an article happen in a wikipedia reliable source, that
 would be great.

 Jameson


 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info



 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA criteria

2012-02-01 Thread Jameson Quinn
2012/2/1 Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr

 Hi Jameson,

   *De :* Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
 *À :* Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr
 *Cc :* em election-meth...@electorama.com
 *Envoyé le :* Mercredi 1 février 2012 11h12
 *Objet :* Re: [EM] SODA criteria

   2012/2/1 Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr

  Hi Jameson,

 I expect that unpredictability (whatever there may be) of candidates'
 decisions can only hurt criteria compliance.
 At least with criteria that are generally defined on votes, because with
 such criteria you usually have to assume
 the worst about any other influences incorporated into the method.


 This is true.  For most of the criteria, I was implicitly talking about a
 version of SODA where all candidates use optimum strategy according to
 their predeclared preferences. This is well-defined and unique, but is not
 necessarily polytime-calculable. Still, even without being able to
 calculate results, you can prove criteria compliances for this version by
 contradiction.

 For a polytime-calculable version which satisfies most of the same
 criteria, assume that each candidate, when it is their turn to assign
 delegated votes, looks at the two distinct frontrunners; that is:
 Candidate X, their most-preferred member of the current Smith set
 and candidate Y, the candidate, of those whom they prefer differently from
 X, who does best pairwise (again, using current assignments and unassigned
 preferences) against X
 They approve as many candidates as possible without approving both X and Y.

 This version does not satisfy participation (though again, it's damn
 close) or IIA, and I'm not 100% sure about its cloneproofness (though I
 think it is). Otherwise, it satisfies the criteria I said.


 So I wonder, can you suggest a deterministic version of SODA, where the
 negotiations of SODA are instead
 calculated directly from the pre-announced preferences of the candidates?
 And if so, does it satisfy the same
 criteria in your view?

 I can say I would be skeptical of how a criterion is being applied, or how
 clearly it is being defined, if the
 satisfaction of it *depends* on the fact that candidates have post-voting
 decisions to make.


 Are you still suspicious of participation and [delegated] IIA, given that
 satisfying them depends on assuming optimal strategy?



 Hmm, I think so, just because optimal strategy is hard to define in
 general. Do you think that it will be possible to produce
 convincing proofs when somebody asks for one? Pretty daunting task I would
 think.


The proofs for the condorcet-related properties using optimal strategy are
pretty simple and obvious.

The participation criterion only applies for delegated voters. The proof
for that is a bit harder, but not too tough. For approval ballots, it is
possible to fail the (voted) participation criterion only if the delegation
order changes, and there are at least 5 candidates (in a delicate balance,
and for voters whose ballots cannot make sense in a one-dimensional
ideology space).

I just discovered a hole in my proof for delegated IIA. It works if all
votes for the new candidate are and were approval-style. It can fail if
there are at least 4/5 candidates in a tricky balance and the 5th/extra
candidate pulls delegated votes in a way that changes the delegation order.
In that case, there is always still a rational strategy for those voters
which would still preserve IIA. (This proof is tricky.)


 I find myself trying to suggest that it may never be necessary to delegate
 any power to the candidates. That would make it
 easier to analyze. But in that case the method is basically Approval and
 doesn't even satisfy Majority Favorite. Right?


No. In my previous message, I suggested two versions which leave no freedom
for the candidates, automatically assigning delegated ballots. The first –
optimal strategy – is not polytime computable that I know of (I strongly
suspect it's NP-complete in theory, though in practical cases it will be
easy to compute). The second – vote-one-frontrunner – is easy to compute,
but it causes violations of IIA and participation.


  In
 your criteria list you had Majority but for that you must actually be
 assuming the opposite of what I am trying, namely that
 *everyone* is delegating, is that right?


Everyone who votes for the majority candidate is either delegating to them,
or voting them above all other alternatives - that is, approving only them
but checking do not delegate. This is the standard meaning of the
majority criterion. For instance, by this meaning, approval meets the
majority criterion.

For MMC, everyone in the mutual majority is either delegating to one of the
candidates, or approving all of them and nobody else.



 Kevin

 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] SODA is monotonic. Earlier failure/fix was actually for participation, not monotononicity.

2012-01-31 Thread Jameson Quinn
A week or two ago, I sent a message to the list with a scenario which I
claimed was an example of nonmonotonicity in SODA as defined; and mentioned
a natural fix for this problem (allowing partial assignment of delegated
votes).

I was mistaken. It was not an example of nonmonotonicity, but rather an
example of failure of the participation criterion. The rest of what I said,
including the simple fix for the problem, still applies.

Jameson

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] SODA criteria

2012-01-31 Thread Jameson Quinn
SODA passes:

Majority
MMC (as voted)
Condorcet (as voted, and in a strong Nash equilibrium as honest)
Condorcet loser (ditto)
Monotone
Participation (with the fix that delegation can be any fraction)
IIA (delegated version - that is, if a new candidate is added, the winner
is either the same, or someone higher on the new candidate's delegation
order.)
Cloneproof
Polytime (there is no guarantee that optimal delegated assignment strategy
is polytime calculable, but it will be in any real case, and anyway,
candidates can just choose some near-optimal strategy.)
Resolvable
Summable
Allows equal rankings
FBC

So, of the criteria in the wikipedia voting systems
tablehttp://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Voting_system#Compliance_of_selected_systems_.28table.29,
the only ones it out-and-out fails are:
Consistency (though it comes damn close)
Later-no-harm and later-no-help (though it does satisfy LNHarm for the one
(two) candidate(s?) with the most voted approvals, and for other
candidates, adding later preferences is probably strategically forced; so
I'd say it fulfills the spirit of both of these. Similarly, it satisfies
LNHelp for the last-to-delegate candidate, and nearly so for other
late-delegating candidates, and the point of LNHelp is to prevent a weak
candidate from winning through clever bottom filling, so again it satisfies
the spirit.)
Allows later preferences (though delegation substitutes for this affordance
in some cases.)

If we could just get some wikipedia-notable mention of SODA, we could put
it in the table, and I think it would graphically stand out as the most
criteria-compliant method there.

I'm working on an academic article on SODA, which would not be focused on
these criteria or even on SODA, but would quickly state the above. But if
anyone can make an article happen in a wikipedia reliable source, that
would be great.

Jameson

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] SODA

2012-01-22 Thread MIKE OSSIPOFF




Jameson: SODA can be described to someone in a brief way that people accept. In 
a recent convefrsation, I described SODA, and the person considered it 
acceptable. You're speciflying the rules in too much detail. The 
street-description, and the petition-language, needn't be the legal language 
(though that should be available upon request). Likewise, for MTAOC or MCAOC, 
or AOC, people won't demandto see the computer program, but it will be 
available to the person who wants to look at it. The person who wouldn't accept 
a computer program also wouldn't ask to read it. So here's how I described SODA 
to that person: It's like Approval, but, if you vote only for one person, you 
can optionally check a box indicating that you want that personto be able to 
add approval votes to your ballot, on your behalf, if s/he doesn't win. S/he 
will have previously published a rankingof candidates to show the order in 
which s/he would give such delegated approvals. That's it. That brief 
descriptionl tells how the method works. As I said yesterday, it seems to me 
that it would be much more publicly-accepable if the default assumption is 
non-delegation.If someone wants to delegate, they can check the box to indicate 
that. I'd like SODA to be a bit fancier: Why should delegation only b e 
available to the person who has only voted for one candidate? Say you vote for 
several candidates. Each candidate has a delegation box by hir name. If you 
want to, you can designate as delegate anycandidate for whom you've voted. (but 
you can only deleglate just one candidate) As in your version, s/he can add to 
your ballot approvals for candidates for whom you haven't voted, as long as 
your resulting approval set doesn't skip any candidates in hir publicized 
ranking. Disadvantage: It loses some of SODA's simplicity. I understand that 
the S in SODA is for simple. As you said, the optional-ness of the 
delegation should avoid any complaint of undemocratic-ness. But of couise 
opponentswill still try to use that complaint. I'll mention SODA (simple or 
more elaborate) along with the other FBC/ABE methods, any time I suggest new 
methods more complicated than Approval.  Of course sometimes you only have time 
to mention Approval. (The problem causing the lack of linebreaks was probably 
opposite to what I'd believed it was. I should make sure that I let my text 
editor do the linebreaks automatically. That will probably be more l ikely to 
be transmitted in e-mail than my carriage-returncharacters.) Mike Ossipoff  
    
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA

2012-01-22 Thread Jameson Quinn
2012/1/22 MIKE OSSIPOFF nkk...@hotmail.com

  Jameson:

 SODA can be described to someone in a brief way that people accept. In a
 recent convefrsation, I described SODA, and the person considered it
 acceptable. You're speciflying the rules in too much detail. The
 street-description, and the petition-language, needn't be the legal
 language (though that should be available upon request). Likewise, for
 MTAOC or MCAOC, or AOC, people won't demand
 to see the computer program, but it will be available to the person who
 wants to look at it. The person who wouldn't accept a
 computer program also wouldn't ask to read it.

 So here's how I described SODA to that person:

 It's like Approval, but, if you vote only for one person, you can
 optionally check a box indicating that you want that person
 to be able to add approval votes to your ballot, on your behalf, if s/he
 doesn't win. S/he will have previously published a ranking
 of candidates to show the order in which s/he would give such delegated
 approvals.


Good description.



 That's it. That brief descriptionl tells how the method works.

 As I said yesterday, it seems to me that it would be much more
 publicly-accepable if the default assumption is non-delegation.
 If someone wants to delegate, they can check the box to indicate that.


One main advantage of SODA is that the laziest possible voter, the one who
just checks one candidate and goes home, has a vote which is essentially as
strategically powerful as any. Thus, I prefer delegation by default. But I
certainly wouldn't fight about it, and I'd happily embrace your version.



 I'd like SODA to be a bit fancier: Why should delegation only b e
 available to the person who has only voted for one candidate? Say you vote
 for several candidates. Each candidate has a delegation box by hir name. If
 you want to, you can designate as delegate any
 candidate for whom you've voted. (but you can only deleglate just one
 candidate)

 As in your version, s/he can add to your ballot approvals for candidates
 for whom you haven't voted, as long as your resulting approval set doesn't
 skip any candidates in hir publicized ranking.

 Disadvantage: It loses some of SODA's simplicity. I understand that the
 S in SODA is for simple.


Exactly. In particular, it loses the ballot simplicity, and thus becomes
arguably worse than plurality in that way (ie, more rather than less
possible to unintentionally spoil a ballot in some way). Also, the
summability, and the complexity of strategic possibilities in the
delegation phase (although not, I think, the outcome; but I'm not sure)
both suffer significantly.



 As you said, the optional-ness of the delegation should avoid any
 complaint of undemocratic-ness. But of couise opponents
 will still try to use that complaint.

 I'll mention SODA (simple or more elaborate) along with the other FBC/ABE
 methods, any time I suggest new methods more complicated than Approval.  Of
 course sometimes you only have time to mention Approval.


Thank you.

Jameson

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] SODA posting with run-on lines (hopefully) fixed.

2012-01-22 Thread MIKE OSSIPOFF




This is a test, to find out if I can get rid of the run-on lines by re-typing 
the posting with automatic linebreaks at the right margin instead of using the 
carriage-return. But does that mean that if I try to make a paragraph division, 
I'll instead end up with an endless line? Sorry, but I'm having difficulty 
sending readable e-mail wth my new computer system. Now let's try a paragraph 
and find out if that works: I'm copying the posting here, and will then rewrite 
it without the carriage-returns. What is sent will be the verion without the 
carriage-returns.(except for new paragraphs). One problem is that the zoom 
scale keeps changing, which could make nonsense of the automatic linebreaks. 
SODA can be described to someone in a brief way that people accept. In a recent 
convefrsation, I described SODA, and the person considered it acceptable. 
You're specifying the rules in too much detail. The initiative 
street-descrliption needn't be legal language, though that should be available 
upon request. Likewise, for the computer program of MTAOC, MCAOC and AOC.
So here's how I described SODA to that person: It's like Approval, but, if you 
vote only for one person, you can optionally check a box indicating that you 
want that candidate to be able to add approval votes to your ballot on your 
behalf if s/he doesn't win. S/he will have previously published a ranking of 
candidates to indicate the order in which s/he would give such designated 
approvals. 
That's it. That brief descriptionl tells how the method works.
 
As I said yesterday, it seems to me that it would be much more 
publicly-accepable if the default assumption is non-delegation. If someone 
wants to delegate, they can check the box. I'd better send this before the 
system finds a way to mess it up more, or freeze the computer, etc. (more when 
I can fix the remaining run-on lines in the posting) Mike Ossipoff. 
more complicated than Approval.  Of course sometimes you only have time to 
mention Approval.
 
(The problem causing the lack of linebreaks was probably opposite to what I'd 
believed it was. I should make sure that I let my text editor do the linebreaks 
automatically. That will probably be more l ikely to be transmitted in e-mail 
than my carriage-return
characters.)
 
Mike Ossipoff
 
 
  
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA posting with run-on lines (hopefully) fixed.

2012-01-22 Thread Dave Ketchum

Looks like your new system is teaching you properly.

I tried printing with smaller characters - and each line filled out  
properly.


I tried making the page wider or narrower - still properly got as many  
words on each line as would fit.


On Jan 22, 2012, at 10:30 PM, MIKE OSSIPOFF wrote:

This is a test, to find out if I can get rid of the run-on lines by  
re-typing the posting with automatic linebreaks at the right margin  
instead of using the carriage-return. But does that mean that if I  
try to make a paragraph division, I'll instead end up with an  
endless line? Sorry, but I'm having difficulty sending readable e- 
mail wth my new computer system. Now let's try a paragraph and find  
out if that works:


I'm copying the posting here, and will then rewrite it without the  
carriage-returns. What is sent will be the verion without the  
carriage-returns.(except for new paragraphs). One problem is that  
the zoom scale keeps changing, which could make nonsense of the  
automatic linebreaks.


SODA can be described to someone in a brief way that people accept.  
In a recent convefrsation, I described SODA, and the person  
considered it acceptable. You're specifying the rules in too much  
detail. The initiative street-descrliption needn't be legal  
language, though that should be available upon request. Likewise,  
for the computer program of MTAOC, MCAOC and AOC.


So here's how I described SODA to that person:

It's like Approval, but, if you vote only for one person, you can  
optionally check a box indicating that you want that candidate to be  
able to add approval votes to your ballot on your behalf if s/he  
doesn't win. S/he will have previously published a ranking of  
candidates to indicate the order in which s/he would give such  
designated approvals.


That's it. That brief descriptionl tells how the method works.

As I said yesterday, it seems to me that it would be much more  
publicly-accepable if the default assumption is non-delegation. If  
someone wants to delegate, they can check the box.


I'd better send this before the system finds a way to mess it up  
more, or freeze the computer, etc.


(more when I can fix the remaining run-on lines in the posting)

Mike Ossipoff.


more complicated than Approval. Of course sometimes you only have  
time to mention Approval.


(The problem causing the lack of linebreaks was probably opposite to  
what I'd believed it was. I should make sure that I let my text  
editor do the linebreaks automatically. That will probably be more l  
ikely to be transmitted in e-mail than my carriage-return

characters.)

Mike Ossipoff




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for  
list info



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] SODA: polls via like/+1/reddit; resulting nonmonotonicity; natural fix

2012-01-10 Thread Jameson Quinn
I'm designing a SODA poll that would use facebook like, google+ +1,
and/or reddit upvotes, along with automated delegated vote assignment, to
give live-updated results. In thinking about this, I've realized that SODA
can be nonmonotonic in the following (highly contrived) scenario:

(delegated preferences in parentheses)

35: A(C)
30: B
25: C
10-n: X
n: Y(BA)

With n=4, A wins. With n=6, Y's votes are enough to make B win, so A
approves C to prevent that from happening, and C wins; a worse result from
the perspective of the Y voters.

The natural fix is to allow A to approve C with only some of their
delegated votes. Then, when n=6, A can approve C with 12 votes. Now Y's
votes cannot make B win, so Y approves A, and the nonmonotonicity is gone.

Of course, in order for this to work like that in a live poll, I have to
make the logic for automatically updating assigned approvals much, much
more complex. In fact, off the top of my head, I can't even prove that the
general problem isn't NP-hard. But in real life, it's very unlikely that
the scenario would be even this complex, so I'm not too worried about that.

Jameson

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] SODA description adjustment

2012-01-07 Thread Jameson Quinn
I adjusted the description of the process on the SODA
pagehttp://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/SODA_voting_(Simple_Optionally-Delegated_Approval)to
integrate two of the minor optional rules (slightly modified) and
discard the third optional rule. Thus there is now only one official
version of SODA.

Input on the new method description is welcome.

Jameson

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] SODA, negotiation, and weak CWs (Jameson Quinn)

2011-12-25 Thread fsimmons
Jameson,

could you please submit this again in a plain text format that doesn't put in 
extra form feeds?

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA might be the method we've been looking for.

2011-12-15 Thread Jameson Quinn
2011/12/15 Andrew Myers an...@cs.cornell.edu

 On 7/22/64 2:59 PM, Andy Jennings wrote:

 I don't see any huge theoretical downsides.  Do others still have
 reservations about SODA?  I realize that some people may be opposed to
 delegation, in principle.  And others think delegable systems just don't
 have a chance of getting implemented.  So I think these debates about which
 is the best voting system in the standard (non-delegable) model are still
 useful.  I also think it's useful for Jameson to inject a plug about SODA
 every now and then.

 I will repeat what I've written before:

  I have to agree. SODA to me seems quite complex. It appears to pose
 difficult strategic decisions for candidates and even for voters.

 Thanks for the honest response.

What do you think would help alleviate this largely-false appearance? Voter
strategy is limited to a few cases:

1. Correct approval strategy in case your favorite candidate's preferences
differ significantly from yours. People on this list understand approval
strategy; in my opinion, it's not ideal, but it's no worse than plurality
strategy, which most people tolerate. And I estimate that perhaps a third
or fewer voters will differ significantly from their favorite candidates.
If significantly only counts differences in the order between the two
frontrunner candidates, that kind of number makes sense.

2. Attempts at chicken strategy in a few cases. In the classic A+B vs C
case, such strategy can only work if C has no preference between A and B.
(Under one rule variant of SODA, even an honest preference that wasn't
predeclared would be sufficient to avoid a chicken dilemma). Note that,
unlike in approval/Range/MJ, the only way a chicken strategy can work for A
is by making it impossible for B to win the election; chicken strategy is *
always* either ineffective or dangerous. So it seems to me that in SODA,
unlike those systems, there is no slippery slope to a chicken dilemma.

As for candidate strategy, that comes in two flavors:

1. Preference declaration strategies. Again, these mainly come down to
chicken strategies, and there are several restraints even on such
strategies. If A truncates B, B can retaliate; this should keep it from
happening unless A is clearly a second-string candidate, in which case it
may be a good thing. Also, C could intervene to avoid the dilemma.

2. Post-election strategy. This is a sequential, perfect-information game;
there's a single optimal strategy, and in any real election it's pretty
easy to calculate. (I can imagine artificially-balanced situations with
dozens or hundreds of candidates which might be NP-hard; but in real life,
it basically comes down to finding the delegated CW).

Also note that journalists would quickly work out and publish the optimal
strategy and all plausible variations thereof, so the candidates would not
have to work it out on their own.

So, I can't quite give a blanket denial that strategy matters, but I can
give a qualified one: in real life SODA elections, it is not worth worrying
about strategy. Having read the above, can you see any way I could say that
better? I want to be able to allay this concern; strategy issues are an
outstanding strength of SODA, not a weakness.

Jameson

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA might be the method we've been looking for.

2011-12-15 Thread Jameson Quinn
One kind of SODA strategy which I didn't discuss is candidate
preference-declaration strategy aimed, not at directly attaining a better
result, but at attracting votes. This would basically take two forms:
established candidates truncating upstarts to try to minimize their
importance, and a candidate altering their true preference order to better
conform to some important fraction (probably the majority) of their voters.
In both cases, these phenomena would tend to have a bandwagon effect
which is arguably socially beneficial - minimizing the chances that a weak
Condorcet winner will win the election, while strengthening the margin of
true Condorcet winners. So I'm not worried about this sort of strategy
being a problem.

Jameson

2011/12/15 Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com



 2011/12/15 Andrew Myers an...@cs.cornell.edu

 On 7/22/64 2:59 PM, Andy Jennings wrote:

 I don't see any huge theoretical downsides.  Do others still have
 reservations about SODA?  I realize that some people may be opposed to
 delegation, in principle.  And others think delegable systems just don't
 have a chance of getting implemented.  So I think these debates about which
 is the best voting system in the standard (non-delegable) model are still
 useful.  I also think it's useful for Jameson to inject a plug about SODA
 every now and then.

 I will repeat what I've written before:

  I have to agree. SODA to me seems quite complex. It appears to pose
 difficult strategic decisions for candidates and even for voters.

 Thanks for the honest response.

 What do you think would help alleviate this largely-false appearance?
 Voter strategy is limited to a few cases:

 1. Correct approval strategy in case your favorite candidate's preferences
 differ significantly from yours. People on this list understand approval
 strategy; in my opinion, it's not ideal, but it's no worse than plurality
 strategy, which most people tolerate. And I estimate that perhaps a third
 or fewer voters will differ significantly from their favorite candidates.
 If significantly only counts differences in the order between the two
 frontrunner candidates, that kind of number makes sense.

 2. Attempts at chicken strategy in a few cases. In the classic A+B vs C
 case, such strategy can only work if C has no preference between A and B.
 (Under one rule variant of SODA, even an honest preference that wasn't
 predeclared would be sufficient to avoid a chicken dilemma). Note that,
 unlike in approval/Range/MJ, the only way a chicken strategy can work for A
 is by making it impossible for B to win the election; chicken strategy is
 *always* either ineffective or dangerous. So it seems to me that in SODA,
 unlike those systems, there is no slippery slope to a chicken dilemma.

 As for candidate strategy, that comes in two flavors:

 1. Preference declaration strategies. Again, these mainly come down to
 chicken strategies, and there are several restraints even on such
 strategies. If A truncates B, B can retaliate; this should keep it from
 happening unless A is clearly a second-string candidate, in which case it
 may be a good thing. Also, C could intervene to avoid the dilemma.

 2. Post-election strategy. This is a sequential, perfect-information game;
 there's a single optimal strategy, and in any real election it's pretty
 easy to calculate. (I can imagine artificially-balanced situations with
 dozens or hundreds of candidates which might be NP-hard; but in real life,
 it basically comes down to finding the delegated CW).

 Also note that journalists would quickly work out and publish the optimal
 strategy and all plausible variations thereof, so the candidates would not
 have to work it out on their own.

 So, I can't quite give a blanket denial that strategy matters, but I can
 give a qualified one: in real life SODA elections, it is not worth worrying
 about strategy. Having read the above, can you see any way I could say that
 better? I want to be able to allay this concern; strategy issues are an
 outstanding strength of SODA, not a weakness.

 Jameson


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] SODA strategy

2011-12-15 Thread fsimmons
If voters think that SODA is complex, then it's because they have been exposed 
unnecessarily or 
prematurely to the niceties of strategy considerations.

Let's take a lesson from IRV supporters.  They don't get anybody worried about 
IRV's monotonicity 
failure or FBC failure by bringing them up to unsophisticated voters.

We need to emphasize the simplicity of SODA voting to the public, and answer 
the strategy questions 
to the experts.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA strategy

2011-12-15 Thread Jameson Quinn
2011/12/15 fsimm...@pcc.edu

 If voters think that SODA is complex, then it's because they have been
 exposed unnecessarily or
 prematurely to the niceties of strategy considerations.

 Let's take a lesson from IRV supporters.  They don't get anybody worried
 about IRV's monotonicity
 failure or FBC failure by bringing them up to unsophisticated voters.


In fact, they disingenuously use IRV's LNH compliance to claim that no
strategy is needed.

Is there some criterion we could use to more-honestly say that strategy is
practically-speaking irrelevant in SODA? Unfortunately, SODA does not meet
the letter of the SFC, which has the best name of any criterion. (Though
I'd argue that SODA meets the spirit of the SFC. It fails both because
non-delegated votes don't allow full preferences, and because large
clonesets can obscure a true CW and trip up the delegated-assignment order
algorithm. But both of these are technicalities in my opinion.)

For instance, the unique-FBC for 3 serious candidates is a guarantee that
it is safe to bullet vote (delegate). But if we're going to make a big deal
out of that criterion, it definitely needs a better name.



 We need to emphasize the simplicity of SODA voting to the public, and
 answer the strategy questions
 to the experts.
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA might be the method we've been looking for.

2011-12-14 Thread Andy Jennings
Jameson,

Believe me, I'm on board with SODA.  I think I, too, like it better than
LRV, but I'm still trying to get a handle on LRV to make sure.

In my opinion (and my wording), SODA's advantages are:

1. The laziest possible voter, who just bullet votes for his favorite, is
still casting a (nearly?) optimal vote that is fair to him and to the rest
of society.

2. Voters can vote approval style, instead, if they want.

3. The only people who have to rank all the candidates are the candidates
themselves, who should be willing to do the work to come up with a full
honest ranking.  Their ratings are public, so we can call them out if they
try to use turkey-raising or other dishonest strategies.

4. There is a delegation phase after the election where the candidates
can negotiate an outcome, but their ability to negotiate back-room deals is
severely limited because they have to use their pre-declared rankings and
they have to play in an order determined by the votes.  In fact, there will
be a game-theory dominant equilibrium and the candidates will probably have
very little power to change the outcome.  Chicken scenarios are avoided
because they know the play order, the other candidates' rankings, and
exactly how much voting weight each one has.

5. If there is some super-weak Condorcet winner that is totally unfit to
govern, then the others can indeed block him in the delegation phase.

I don't see any huge theoretical downsides.  Do others still have
reservations about SODA?  I realize that some people may be opposed to
delegation, in principle.  And others think delegable systems just don't
have a chance of getting implemented.  So I think these debates about which
is the best voting system in the standard (non-delegable) model are still
useful.  I also think it's useful for Jameson to inject a plug about SODA
every now and then.

My main reservation about SODA at this point is that I see no practical
path to adoption.  It would be perfect for a large primary, like the
current Republican presidential field, but there's no way to start at that
level.  We have to start small.  But for small political elections,
professional societies, open source decisions, elementary school elections
etc. it seems too complicated.  I had a long discussion with a party
district chairman here.  He's interested in alternative voting systems to
fill his party positions but skeptical of complexity.  I don't even think
I've pitched him on SODA because he's still thinking about Approval Voting.

And with SODA, you can't just run a straw poll to show it off like you can
with so many other voting systems.  You need the participation of the
actual candidates to choose their rankings beforehand and to do their
delegation afterwards.

I know we haven't traditionally discussed implementation strategy on this
list (though that has changed some recently), but if you see a good
strategy for SODA adoption, please tell.

~ Andy



On Tue, Dec 13, 2011 at 6:55 PM, Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.comwrote:

 I believe that LRV (Least Resentment Voting) is indeed quite a clever
 solution to the chicken dilemma. But once more, I'd like to remind people
 that there is a way to solve the chicken dilemma without risking a victory
 by the plurality winner/condorcet loser. I'm speaking of course of SODA.

 First, SODA meets the FBC. In fact, in any 3-candidate scenario, and I
 believe in any 4-candidate one, it is strategically optimal to bullet vote
 for a candidate if you agree with their declared preferences. This ability,
 not just to vote your favorite equal-top, but unique-top, is not shared by
 any other method I know of. (Perhaps we could call this UFBC3, unique FBC
 for 3 candidates.)

 How does it do with chicken dilemma scenarios? For the following, I'll
 give honest ratings, then discuss the likely strategic implications under
 SODA.

 40 C
 25 AB
 35 BA

 If this is the honest situation, then candidates A and B have every reason
 to find a way to include each other in their predeclared preference lists.
 These predeclared lists are made openly, and so one side cannot betray the
 other without giving the other side a chance to retaliate. The chance for
 retaliation will make betrayal a losing strategy.

 40 C
 25 A
 35 BA

 If the A camp is honestly indifferent between B and C, and candidate B
 finds this indifference credible, then B can still decide not to retaliate,
 that is, to ignore A's truncation and nonetheless declare a preference for
 A. This enables A to win without B spoiling the election.

 (Any single-round method which elects A here is subject to the chicken
 dilemma; electing B is, in my mind, crazy; and any method which elects C
 here has been spoiled by candidate B, and so encourages shenanigans of the
 republicans-funding-greens sort. Any method I know of except SODA fails in
 one of these ways.)

 40 C
 25 AB
 35 B

 This is like the above situation, but since A had no chance of winning
 anyway, they have even less 

Re: [EM] SODA might be the method we've been looking for.

2011-12-14 Thread Jameson Quinn
Thanks, Andy, for the SODA endorsement. I agree with the advantages you
list, but I would add the avoidance of the chicken dilemma (that is, the
lack of either a self-reinforcing truncation incentive or hard-to-defend
mindreadingresults that give a burial incentive) as an important
advantage. Compromising favorite betrayal, truncation, and burial are the
basic forms of strategy; and I don't know of any other system which is so
resistant (and yet also resiliant) to all of these.

Jameson

ps. I realize I'm repeating myself a bit, but as Andy said, an occasional
plug for SODA is worthwhile.

2011/12/14 Andy Jennings electi...@jenningsstory.com

 Jameson,

 Believe me, I'm on board with SODA.  I think I, too, like it better than
 LRV, but I'm still trying to get a handle on LRV to make sure.

 In my opinion (and my wording), SODA's advantages are:

 1. The laziest possible voter, who just bullet votes for his favorite, is
 still casting a (nearly?) optimal vote that is fair to him and to the rest
 of society.

 2. Voters can vote approval style, instead, if they want.

 3. The only people who have to rank all the candidates are the candidates
 themselves, who should be willing to do the work to come up with a full
 honest ranking.  Their ratings are public, so we can call them out if they
 try to use turkey-raising or other dishonest strategies.

 4. There is a delegation phase after the election where the candidates
 can negotiate an outcome, but their ability to negotiate back-room deals is
 severely limited because they have to use their pre-declared rankings and
 they have to play in an order determined by the votes.  In fact, there will
 be a game-theory dominant equilibrium and the candidates will probably have
 very little power to change the outcome.  Chicken scenarios are avoided
 because they know the play order, the other candidates' rankings, and
 exactly how much voting weight each one has.

 5. If there is some super-weak Condorcet winner that is totally unfit to
 govern, then the others can indeed block him in the delegation phase.

 I don't see any huge theoretical downsides.  Do others still have
 reservations about SODA?  I realize that some people may be opposed to
 delegation, in principle.  And others think delegable systems just don't
 have a chance of getting implemented.  So I think these debates about which
 is the best voting system in the standard (non-delegable) model are still
 useful.  I also think it's useful for Jameson to inject a plug about SODA
 every now and then.

 My main reservation about SODA at this point is that I see no practical
 path to adoption.  It would be perfect for a large primary, like the
 current Republican presidential field, but there's no way to start at that
 level.  We have to start small.  But for small political elections,
 professional societies, open source decisions, elementary school elections
 etc. it seems too complicated.  I had a long discussion with a party
 district chairman here.  He's interested in alternative voting systems to
 fill his party positions but skeptical of complexity.  I don't even think
 I've pitched him on SODA because he's still thinking about Approval Voting.

 And with SODA, you can't just run a straw poll to show it off like you can
 with so many other voting systems.  You need the participation of the
 actual candidates to choose their rankings beforehand and to do their
 delegation afterwards.

 I know we haven't traditionally discussed implementation strategy on this
 list (though that has changed some recently), but if you see a good
 strategy for SODA adoption, please tell.

 ~ Andy



 On Tue, Dec 13, 2011 at 6:55 PM, Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.comwrote:

 I believe that LRV (Least Resentment Voting) is indeed quite a clever
 solution to the chicken dilemma. But once more, I'd like to remind people
 that there is a way to solve the chicken dilemma without risking a victory
 by the plurality winner/condorcet loser. I'm speaking of course of SODA.

 First, SODA meets the FBC. In fact, in any 3-candidate scenario, and I
 believe in any 4-candidate one, it is strategically optimal to bullet vote
 for a candidate if you agree with their declared preferences. This ability,
 not just to vote your favorite equal-top, but unique-top, is not shared by
 any other method I know of. (Perhaps we could call this UFBC3, unique FBC
 for 3 candidates.)

 How does it do with chicken dilemma scenarios? For the following, I'll
 give honest ratings, then discuss the likely strategic implications under
 SODA.

 40 C
 25 AB
 35 BA

 If this is the honest situation, then candidates A and B have every
 reason to find a way to include each other in their predeclared preference
 lists. These predeclared lists are made openly, and so one side cannot
 betray the other without giving the other side a chance to retaliate. The
 chance for retaliation will make betrayal a losing strategy.

 40 C
 25 A
 35 BA

 If the A camp is honestly 

Re: [EM] SODA might be the method we've been looking for.

2011-12-14 Thread Jameson Quinn
Further responses to Andy's advantage list:

2011/12/14 Andy Jennings electi...@jenningsstory.com

 Jameson,

 Believe me, I'm on board with SODA.  I think I, too, like it better than
 LRV, but I'm still trying to get a handle on LRV to make sure.

 In my opinion (and my wording), SODA's advantages are:

 1. The laziest possible voter, who just bullet votes for his favorite, is
 still casting a (nearly?) optimal vote that is fair to him and to the rest
 of society.


It is less than optimal in only two cases that I know of:
1. In certain circumstances when there's a set of 3 or more clones facing a
candidate who has more first-preferences than any of them.
2. When there is a chicken dilemma which is NOT resolved by the opposing
candidate; that is, the candidate opposing the chicken cloneset has no
honest preference between the chicken candidates.* *(In this case the lazy
vote is individually suboptimal, but socially optimal; so I actually hope
that there will be enough lazy and/or altruistic voters to overwhelm the
optimal strategic voters.)


 2. Voters can vote approval style, instead, if they want.

 3. The only people who have to rank all the candidates are the candidates
 themselves, who should be willing to do the work to come up with a full
 honest ranking.  Their ratings are public, so we can call them out if they
 try to use turkey-raising or other dishonest strategies.


Actually, turkey-raising is a meaningless/useless strategy in SODA. The
main thing you have to worry about is chicken-style truncation. And in
that case, it's not just the voters who can call them out (and vote
approval-style); it's the other clone candidate, who can respond by
retaliatory truncation, which gives the truncating a candidate a chance to
de-truncate. That is to say: there is a way to back down, even after one
candidate has attempted truncation.




 4. There is a delegation phase after the election where the candidates
 can negotiate an outcome, but their ability to negotiate back-room deals is
 severely limited because they have to use their pre-declared rankings and
 they have to play in an order determined by the votes.  In fact, there will
 be a game-theory dominant equilibrium and the candidates will probably have
 very little power to change the outcome.  Chicken scenarios are avoided
 because they know the play order, the other candidates' rankings, and
 exactly how much voting weight each one has.

 5. If there is some super-weak Condorcet winner that is totally unfit to
 govern, then the others can indeed block him in the delegation phase.

 I don't see any huge theoretical downsides.  Do others still have
 reservations about SODA?  I realize that some people may be opposed to
 delegation, in principle.  And others think delegable systems just don't
 have a chance of getting implemented.  So I think these debates about which
 is the best voting system in the standard (non-delegable) model are still
 useful.  I also think it's useful for Jameson to inject a plug about SODA
 every now and then.

 My main reservation about SODA at this point is that I see no practical
 path to adoption.  It would be perfect for a large primary, like the
 current Republican presidential field, but there's no way to start at that
 level.  We have to start small.  But for small political elections,
 professional societies, open source decisions, elementary school elections
 etc. it seems too complicated.  I had a long discussion with a party
 district chairman here.  He's interested in alternative voting systems to
 fill his party positions but skeptical of complexity.  I don't even think
 I've pitched him on SODA because he's still thinking about Approval Voting.


 And with SODA, you can't just run a straw poll to show it off like you can
 with so many other voting systems.  You need the participation of the
 actual candidates to choose their rankings beforehand and to do their
 delegation afterwards.


You've hit on SODA's biggest weak point, I think. All I can respond is that
there's no reason not to use SODA in local political elections. (For
internal elections of private groups... yeah, it may be overkill; but even
in that case, the benefits for dealing with lazy voters are significant)


 I know we haven't traditionally discussed implementation strategy on this
 list (though that has changed some recently), but if you see a good
 strategy for SODA adoption, please tell.


Step one is to make an online tool for running SODA elections smoothly...
which I'll do if I ever get enough free time from my day job...

I also plan (again, if I can find the time) to run an Amazon Turk-based
behavioral-economics experiment to see which system allows the electorate
to extract the most (small) monetary rewards (from me, the experimenter) in
various chicken-dilemma and weak-condorcet situations. I don't expect SODA
to do best at that (it may elect slightly more WCW than it should, and the
experimental setup may make SODA look a bit worse 

Re: [EM] SODA might be the method we've been looking for.

2011-12-14 Thread fsimmons
Like Andy I prefer SODA as well, especially for a deterministic method.  In 
some settings I prefer certain 
stochastic methods to deterministic methods.  But my curiosity impels me to see 
what can be done 
while ignoring or putting aside the advantages of both chance and delegation.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] SODA might be the method we've been looking for.

2011-12-13 Thread Jameson Quinn
I believe that LRV (Least Resentment Voting) is indeed quite a clever
solution to the chicken dilemma. But once more, I'd like to remind people
that there is a way to solve the chicken dilemma without risking a victory
by the plurality winner/condorcet loser. I'm speaking of course of SODA.

First, SODA meets the FBC. In fact, in any 3-candidate scenario, and I
believe in any 4-candidate one, it is strategically optimal to bullet vote
for a candidate if you agree with their declared preferences. This ability,
not just to vote your favorite equal-top, but unique-top, is not shared by
any other method I know of. (Perhaps we could call this UFBC3, unique FBC
for 3 candidates.)

How does it do with chicken dilemma scenarios? For the following, I'll give
honest ratings, then discuss the likely strategic implications under SODA.

40 C
25 AB
35 BA

If this is the honest situation, then candidates A and B have every reason
to find a way to include each other in their predeclared preference lists.
These predeclared lists are made openly, and so one side cannot betray the
other without giving the other side a chance to retaliate. The chance for
retaliation will make betrayal a losing strategy.

40 C
25 A
35 BA

If the A camp is honestly indifferent between B and C, and candidate B
finds this indifference credible, then B can still decide not to retaliate,
that is, to ignore A's truncation and nonetheless declare a preference for
A. This enables A to win without B spoiling the election.

(Any single-round method which elects A here is subject to the chicken
dilemma; electing B is, in my mind, crazy; and any method which elects C
here has been spoiled by candidate B, and so encourages shenanigans of the
republicans-funding-greens sort. Any method I know of except SODA fails in
one of these ways.)

40 C
25 AB
35 B

This is like the above situation, but since A had no chance of winning
anyway, they have even less of a motivation to retaliate against B, whether
or not B's truncation is honest.

40 CA
25 AB
35 BA

In this situation, it's difficult to say who's the correct winner;
depending on the underlying utilities, it could easily be any of the three,
so I'd have no problem with a method that elected any. Still, ideally a
method would give similar results here as in the situations above, so that
candidates and voters are not motivated to be conciliatory, rather than
projecting an image of someone who's inclined to truncate.

Strategically, it is in B's interest to truncate, to reduce the chance of
10 CA voters voting CA and thus giving A the all-important second move in
the vote delegation stage. Then, candidate A will declare a preference for
B, in order to present C with a credible threat. And candidate C will
declare a preference for A to prevent B from winning.

40 CA???
25 AB
35 BA???

This is the weak condorcet winner situation. The question marks denote a
preference for the dark-horse candidate A which would evaporate in a
runoff, when people took a hard look at A without being distracted by the
C/B rivalry. If that is the case, A should not win. And indeed, even if C
predeclares a preference for A, when C is faced with the morning-after
reality of the choice to throw the election to A or allow it to go to B,
they have a chance to leave it with B if A is really such a bad candidate.
Sure, C may prefer a weak winner who owes them a favor to a stronger
opponent, and so elect A even if B would be socially-optimal; but at least
SODA gives B a chance in this situation. Any Condorcet method would simply
elect A and not look back.

I think that the situations above show that SODA always allows honest
truncation without a strategic penalty, but does not encourage strategic
truncation.

I know that some people on this list dislike SODA for its delegation.
Obviously, I disagree. Consider:
- SODA delegation is optional and eyes-open. Because of pre-declaration,
you know what kinds of result your delegated vote could and could not
promote, and if you don't like those results, you don't delegate.
- SODA delegation allows results that seem to me to be obviously better
than other methods in the above scenarios.
- SODA delegation allows for unmatched simplicity from the average voter's
perspective. If you like your favorite's declared preferences, just vote
for them, and you're done.
- SODA delegation allows significant minority candidates a moment of
personal power, which they can use to extract (non-binding) promises before
throwing their votes behind someone. I believe that this transitory moment
of minority power is a healthy compromise between the stability and
leadership in winner-take-all systems and the broader accommodation of
minority interests in parliamentary systems.

Of course, there are cases where SODA is not ideal. For instance, for a
pre-election poll, SODA cannot be used unless the inter-candidate
preferences can be somehow known or inferred. Still, I think SODA is
overall a standout good method for most 

[EM] SODA false claim

2011-09-07 Thread Warren Smith
It is simply false to say SODA's simplicity (for either the voter, or
the counters)
beats any other system I know of.

It is less simple than plain approval voting.  Full stop.

If you persist in making ludicrous statements, then you will hurt your
credibility.

-- 
Warren D. Smith

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA false claim

2011-09-07 Thread Andrew Myers

On 7/22/64 2:59 PM, Warren Smith wrote:

It is simply false to say SODA's simplicity (for either the voter, or
the counters)
beats any other system I know of.

It is less simple than plain approval voting.  Full stop.

If you persist in making ludicrous statements, then you will hurt your
credibility.

I have to agree. SODA to me seems quite complex. It appears to pose 
difficult strategic decisions for candidates and even for voters.


-- Andrew
attachment: andru.vcf
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA false claim

2011-09-07 Thread Jameson Quinn
Claim: SODA is simpler for voters than any system I know of, and
specifically simpler for voters than approval.

Justification:

Simplest algorithm for voting Approval that is reasonably close to
strategically optimal:

Find the two frontrunners. Vote for one of them plus any candidate that's
better.


Simplist algorithm for voting SODA that's reasonably close to strategically
optimal:

Vote for your favorite.


I understand that there is room for debate on this claim, and I'm not asking
you to accept it at face value. But certainly I have a basis for making it.

JQ

2011/9/7 Andrew Myers an...@cs.cornell.edu

 On 7/22/64 2:59 PM, Warren Smith wrote:

 It is simply false to say SODA's simplicity (for either the voter, or
 the counters)
 beats any other system I know of.

 It is less simple than plain approval voting.  Full stop.

 If you persist in making ludicrous statements, then you will hurt your
 credibility.

  I have to agree. SODA to me seems quite complex. It appears to pose
 difficult strategic decisions for candidates and even for voters.

 -- Andrew

 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA unfairly hobbles nonparanoid voters.

2011-09-05 Thread Jameson Quinn
Basically, ⸘Ŭalabio‽'s objection is that SODA does not allow non-bullet
votes to be delegable. The reason that SODA is designed that way is not
paranoia, as ⸘Ŭalabio‽ claims, but rather simplicity.

To see why multiple delegable votes would be confusing, consider the
following scenario. Let us say that I vote for A and B. After the votes are
counted, it turns out that all the other voters voted for X or Y, in a 50/50
proportion. My delegated vote could be decisive. But A approves X, and B
approves Y. So both of these approvals are added to my delegated vote, which
ends up being useless in deciding between X and Y.

Also, making multiply-delegated votes possible would entirely ruin SODA's
summability. This would make a number of useful anti-fraud measures
impossible, including precinct-level counting, sampled count audits, and
voter-auditable cryptographic ballot receipts like those of heliosvoting.org
.

⸘Ŭalabio‽, I understand and sympathize with your desire for multiple
delegation, but I do not see how a SODA-like system could meet that desire
without too high a cost in complexity and insecurity. If you think that you
can resolve these issues, please propose a specific solution and explore its
implications. As you know, voting system design often involves trade-offs,
and so doing P has disadvantage Q is not a good objection against a system
unless it's accompanied by alternative S avoids Q without causing any other
disadvantages as serious.

Jameson

2011/9/4 ⸘Ŭalabio‽ wala...@macosx.com

¡Hello!

¿How fare you?

I do not believe in attacking the ideas of others, so I refrained
 from making this post from the remainder of July and all of August.  I gave
 others months to develop SODA without criticism:

The problem with most traditional voting systems is that one must
 choose between jacks-of-all-trades-but-master-of-none and idiot-savants:

Let us suppose that the greatest living Agronomist who studied under
 Professor Norman Ernest Borlaug (if you do not know who Professor Norman
 Ernest Borlaug was, please kill yourself immediately), and a
 Renaissance-Politician who served in the military, thus got to see the
 world, on the GI-Bill, got a score of degrees, but the most advanced of
 which are A.Scs  and A.As, who went on to a score of careers before becoming
 a politician.

One can vote for depth or breadth.

With Asset-voting, one can have both:

Let us suppose that we have an Asset-Election where each voter gets
 9 votes.  I chose 9 votes because it gives voters choice, but is easy for
 the voters to error-check:

In Base-10, make certain that the number of Asset-votes is a
 single-digit-number.  Make certain that the number in Base-10 is 9.

I could vote for 9 different Nobel-Lauriets who promise to transfer
 their votes to Renaissance-Politicians who promise to call on their
 expertise when needed.  In other words, with Asset-Voting, one can have
 one’s cake and eat it too.

SODA-Voting is a version of Asset-Voting.  SODA is based on the fear
 of being screwed by those who receive the Asset.  It is impossible eliminate
 the possibility of getting screwed.  This holds for politicians in
 nontransferable elections too.  The logical thing to do is not vote for
 backstabbing politicians again.

The paranoia of SODA is that it allows voters to make votes
 nontransferable so that the politicians cannot screw the voter during
 transfer negotiations.  This means 2 things:

*   One risks loss of voting power due to ballot-exhaustion (I
 suspect that SODA is susceptible to voting-splitting and Duverger’s Law).
*   Politicians can still screw over voters in the legislature.

SODA is a solution that does not work and it lets paranoid voters
 disenfranchise themselves.  I do not mind paranoid voters disenfranchising
 themselves because that means more voting power for me, but soda hobbles
 everyone to prevent that:

If one votes for more than 1 person in SODA makes the votes
 nontransferable.  That means that nonparanoid voters cannot vote for exports
 who then transfer their votes to jacks-of-all-trades under the condition
 that the Renaissance-Politicians call upon the experts when appropriate.
  One must choose between the 2.

I do not like being hobbled because other voters are paranoid.  If
 other voters want to make their votes nontransferable, that is fine by me,
 but they should have to live with reduced voting power due to exhaustion
 rather than hobbling everyone else.  This is how I would do it:

*   Paranoid voters can indicate that their ballots are
 nontransferable by marking on the ballots that the ballots are
 nontransferable by marking them nontranferable, but must live with loss of
 voting power due to ballot-exhaustion.
*   Nonparanoid voters can choose 9 Nobel-Lauriets who then
 transfer the votes to Renaissance-Politicians 

Re: [EM] SODA unfairly hobbles nonparanoid voters.

2011-09-05 Thread ⸘Ŭalabio‽
2011-09-05T09:28:14Z, “Jameson Quinn” jameson.qu...@gmail.com:

0thly, I recommend that you read this article:


http://web.archive.org/web/20080113211450/http://www.greenend.org.uk/rjk/2000/06/14/quoting.html

   Basically, ⸘Ŭalabio‽'s objection is that SODA does not allow non-bullet 
 votes to be delegable. The reason that SODA is designed that way is not 
 paranoia, as ⸘Ŭalabio‽ claims, but rather simplicity.

Simplicity is in the eye of the beholder.  What is simple for me is 
choosing people whom I trust to represent my interests in the 
Asset-Negotiations and leave them to their work.  If some of them screw me 
during Asset-Negotiations, I shall never vote for the bad 1s again.  As far as 
simplicity goes, SODA seems more complex to me than Asset-Voting.

   To see why multiple delegable votes would be confusing, consider the 
 following scenario. Let us say that I vote for A and B. After the votes are 
 counted, it turns out that all the other voters voted for X or Y, in a 50/50 
 proportion. My delegated vote could be decisive. But A approves X, and B 
 approves Y. So both of these approvals are added to my delegated vote, which 
 ends up being useless in deciding between X and Y.

Either A or B would eventually by won over to the other side by 
policy-concessions.

   Also, making multiply-delegated votes possible would entirely ruin 
 SODA's summability. This would make a number of useful anti-fraud measures 
 impossible, including precinct-level counting, sampled count audits, and 
 voter-auditable cryptographic ballot receipts like those of heliosvoting.org.

Just make the allowable votes a fixed number.  This is required in 1 
form or another in proportional systems.  Indeed, most of the problems with 
SODA is that it is based on a system designed for creating a proportional 
legislature, but is modified for both creating proportional legislatures and 
for single-winner.  These are 2 different domains and should use different 
systems.  The simplest methods for these domains are:

Single-Winner:
Approval-Voting

Proportional Legislature:
Asset-Voting

SODA should just forget about single-winner.  Because it is based on a 
proportional-voting system, it is ilsuited for single winner.

If voters want to make their votes in an Asset-Election 
nontransferable, that is fine by me, but we should tell them that they run a 
real risk of disenfranchising themselves.

   ⸘Ŭalabio‽, I understand and sympathize with your desire for multiple 
 delegation, but I do not see how a SODA-like system could meet that desire 
 without too high a cost in complexity and insecurity. If you think that you 
 can resolve these issues, please propose a specific solution and explore its 
 implications. As you know, voting system design often involves trade-offs, 
 and so doing P has disadvantage Q is not a good objection against a system 
 unless it's accompanied by alternative S avoids Q without causing any other 
 disadvantages as serious.

My solution is to scrap SODA SODA as being fundamentally flawed and use 
Approval for single-winner and Asset with 9 votes for proportional with an 
option to makes the votes nontransferable with the understanding that one 
_“*PROBABLY*”_ will disenfranchise oneself if one makes the votes 
nontransferable.

FairVote started wanting STV for a new house of proportional 
representation or turning the House of Representatives into an house of 
proportional representation using STV.  FairVote settled for using STV for 
single-winner which is IRV.  We all know how lousy IRV turned out.  SODA 
repeats the mistakes of IRV:

One tries to use Asset for single winner, but it does not work well, so 
one modifies it into SODA which instead of working well for single-winner and 
proportional, works well for neither proportional nor single-winner.

The fact is that Asset works better than SODA for proportional 
representation and Approval works better than SODA for single-winner.  SODA 
just is not a good tool for the job:

Let is suppose that we tell steelworkers to build a skyscraper using 
only the tool Allen-Wrench.  The steelworkers are the voters, SODA is the 
Allen-Wrench, and the pile of rubble which is supposed to be a skyscraper is 
the legislature.  SODA is good for neither proportional representation nor 
single-winner.

   Jameson

“⸘Ŭalabio‽”

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA unfairly hobbles nonparanoid voters.

2011-09-05 Thread Jameson Quinn
SODA was initially designed as a single-winner system. I believe that as
such, it has four independent advantages, three of which are unmatched by
any other good system.

1. It is the easiest possible system for voters. No spoiled ballots, bullet
voting works, and no need to defensively strategize.
2. It is later-no-harm enough to satisfy political incumbents who don't
want to be defeated by centrist nonentities. (This is also true of IRV, but
IRV has other problems)
3. It resolves the chicken problem better than any other system I know of.
4. I believe it would give good results overall - like Approval, Condorcet,
MJ, or Range.

So if you are thinking of SODA as just being Asset shoehorned into a
single-winner case, then you don't understand the motivation, and either you
don't understand the system or I don't.

JQ

2011/9/5 ⸘Ŭalabio‽ wala...@macosx.com

2011-09-05T09:28:14Z, “Jameson Quinn” jameson.qu...@gmail.com:

0thly, I recommend that you read this article:


 http://web.archive.org/web/20080113211450/http://www.greenend.org.uk/rjk/2000/06/14/quoting.html

Basically, ⸘Ŭalabio‽'s objection is that SODA does not allow
 non-bullet votes to be delegable. The reason that SODA is designed that way
 is not paranoia, as ⸘Ŭalabio‽ claims, but rather simplicity.

 Simplicity is in the eye of the beholder.  What is simple for me is
 choosing people whom I trust to represent my interests in the
 Asset-Negotiations and leave them to their work.  If some of them screw me
 during Asset-Negotiations, I shall never vote for the bad 1s again.  As far
 as simplicity goes, SODA seems more complex to me than Asset-Voting.

To see why multiple delegable votes would be confusing, consider
 the following scenario. Let us say that I vote for A and B. After the votes
 are counted, it turns out that all the other voters voted for X or Y, in a
 50/50 proportion. My delegated vote could be decisive. But A approves X, and
 B approves Y. So both of these approvals are added to my delegated vote,
 which ends up being useless in deciding between X and Y.

 Either A or B would eventually by won over to the other side by
 policy-concessions.

Also, making multiply-delegated votes possible would entirely ruin
 SODA's summability. This would make a number of useful anti-fraud measures
 impossible, including precinct-level counting, sampled count audits, and
 voter-auditable cryptographic ballot receipts like those of
 heliosvoting.org.

 Just make the allowable votes a fixed number.  This is required in
 1 form or another in proportional systems.  Indeed, most of the problems
 with SODA is that it is based on a system designed for creating a
 proportional legislature, but is modified for both creating proportional
 legislatures and for single-winner.  These are 2 different domains and
 should use different systems.  The simplest methods for these domains are:

 Single-Winner:
Approval-Voting

 Proportional Legislature:
Asset-Voting

SODA should just forget about single-winner.  Because it is based on
 a proportional-voting system, it is ilsuited for single winner.

If voters want to make their votes in an Asset-Election
 nontransferable, that is fine by me, but we should tell them that they run a
 real risk of disenfranchising themselves.

⸘Ŭalabio‽, I understand and sympathize with your desire for
 multiple delegation, but I do not see how a SODA-like system could meet that
 desire without too high a cost in complexity and insecurity. If you think
 that you can resolve these issues, please propose a specific solution and
 explore its implications. As you know, voting system design often involves
 trade-offs, and so doing P has disadvantage Q is not a good objection
 against a system unless it's accompanied by alternative S avoids Q without
 causing any other disadvantages as serious.

 My solution is to scrap SODA SODA as being fundamentally flawed and
 use Approval for single-winner and Asset with 9 votes for proportional with
 an option to makes the votes nontransferable with the understanding that one
 _“*PROBABLY*”_ will disenfranchise oneself if one makes the votes
 nontransferable.

FairVote started wanting STV for a new house of proportional
 representation or turning the House of Representatives into an house of
 proportional representation using STV.  FairVote settled for using STV for
 single-winner which is IRV.  We all know how lousy IRV turned out.  SODA
 repeats the mistakes of IRV:

One tries to use Asset for single winner, but it does not work well,
 so one modifies it into SODA which instead of working well for single-winner
 and proportional, works well for neither proportional nor single-winner.

The fact is that Asset works better than SODA for proportional
 representation and Approval works better than SODA for single-winner.  SODA
 just is not a good tool for the job:


Re: [EM] SODA unfairly hobbles nonparanoid voters.

2011-09-05 Thread Toby Pereira
I'm not sure that three of those are unmatched by other systems. Point 1 - I 
don't think it is the simplest system. I certainly don't think it's any simpler 
than straight approval, and they've also got to decide whether to delegate or 
not and they've also got to understand that their vote can be delegated only if 
they vote for one candidate. You say they don't need to defensively strategize, 
but I'm not sure how well the benefits of SODA would get across to the general 
public. So it's not clear whether voters will see the strategy as simpler. Even 
if the task of voting is relatively simple, understanding the system and why it 
works like it does is not simple, and I think you have to include that in the 
simplicity of a system. Overall I'd say it's an above averagely complex system. 
And I don't know about in America (although I can't imagine it would be much 
different from the UK), but in the UK I simply canot see people ever accepting 
this idea of
 delegating votes. It's a major paradigm shift and I think it renders it a 
non-starter as a serious system to elect parliaments, if I'm being honest 
(along with any other asset system).
 
Also, if it is better for a voter to bullet vote and allow delegation (from 
their point of view), then voters who like a candidate but don't like their 
delegation list are presumably at a disadvantage to begin with, which they may 
perceive as unfair.
 
Point 2 - You've said yourself that IRV satisifes this, but then I notice 
you've qualifed this earlier by saying any good system. Clever.
 
Point 3 - The chicken problem - yeah maybe. I'd have to get back to you.
 
Point 4 - I imagine this is the one where it isn't unmatched by other good 
systems.
 
So if we're allowing point 2 on this technicality, I still think it's only 2 
out of 4, because I think it fails simplicity, and fails it badly.
 
Toby
 
 

From: Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
To: ⸘Ŭalabio‽ wala...@macosx.com
Cc: EM election-methods@lists.electorama.com
Sent: Monday, 5 September 2011, 19:31
Subject: Re: [EM] SODA unfairly hobbles nonparanoid voters.


SODA was initially designed as a single-winner system. I believe that as such, 
it has four independent advantages, three of which are unmatched by any other 
good system. 

1. It is the easiest possible system for voters. No spoiled ballots, bullet 
voting works, and no need to defensively strategize.
2. It is later-no-harm enough to satisfy political incumbents who don't want 
to be defeated by centrist nonentities. (This is also true of IRV, but IRV has 
other problems)
3. It resolves the chicken problem better than any other system I know of.
4. I believe it would give good results overall - like Approval, Condorcet, MJ, 
or Range.

So if you are thinking of SODA as just being Asset shoehorned into a 
single-winner case, then you don't understand the motivation, and either you 
don't understand the system or I don't.

JQ


2011/9/5 ⸘Ŭalabio‽ wala...@macosx.com

       2011-09-05T09:28:14Z, “Jameson Quinn” jameson.qu...@gmail.com:

       0thly, I recommend that you read this article:

       
http://web.archive.org/web/20080113211450/http://www.greenend.org.uk/rjk/2000/06/14/quoting.html


       Basically, ⸘Ŭalabio‽'s objection is that SODA does not allow 
 non-bullet votes to be delegable. The reason that SODA is designed that way 
 is not paranoia, as ⸘Ŭalabio‽ claims, but rather simplicity.

       Simplicity is in the eye of the beholder.  What is simple for me is 
choosing people whom I trust to represent my interests in the 
Asset-Negotiations and leave them to their work.  If some of them screw me 
during Asset-Negotiations, I shall never vote for the bad 1s again.  As far as 
simplicity goes, SODA seems more complex to me than Asset-Voting.


       To see why multiple delegable votes would be confusing, consider the 
 following scenario. Let us say that I vote for A and B. After the votes are 
 counted, it turns out that all the other voters voted for X or Y, in a 50/50 
 proportion. My delegated vote could be decisive. But A approves X, and B 
 approves Y. So both of these approvals are added to my delegated vote, which 
 ends up being useless in deciding between X and Y.

       Either A or B would eventually by won over to the other side by 
policy-concessions.


       Also, making multiply-delegated votes possible would entirely ruin 
 SODA's summability. This would make a number of useful anti-fraud measures 
 impossible, including precinct-level counting, sampled count audits, and 
 voter-auditable cryptographic ballot receipts like those of heliosvoting.org.

       Just make the allowable votes a fixed number.  This is required in 1 
form or another in proportional systems.  Indeed, most of the problems with 
SODA is that it is based on a system designed for creating a proportional 
legislature, but is modified for both creating proportional legislatures and 
for single-winner.  These are 2 different domains and should use

Re: [EM] SODA unfairly hobbles nonparanoid voters.

2011-09-05 Thread Jameson Quinn
I think voter/strategic simplicity, and system-description simplicity, are
two different aspects. I certainly don't claim that SODA is any great shakes
in system-description simplicity, though there are worse. But it's no more
complex than the electoral college, and a giant leap more simple than how
Obama beat Clinton. That is to say, there are a lot of people who are OK
with not fully understanding a system. System-description simplicity is
definitely good, but not in my opinion a non-negotiable necessity.

As to voter/strategic simplicity... sure, it's not perfect, but I still
think it beats any other system I know of.

Jameson Quinn

2011/9/5 Toby Pereira tdp2...@yahoo.co.uk

 I'm not sure that three of those are unmatched by other systems. Point 1 -
 I don't think it is the simplest system. I certainly don't think it's any
 simpler than straight approval, and they've also got to decide whether to
 delegate or not and they've also got to understand that their vote can be
 delegated only if they vote for one candidate. You say they don't need to
 defensively strategize, but I'm not sure how well the benefits of SODA would
 get across to the general public. So it's not clear whether voters will see
 the strategy as simpler. Even if the task of voting is relatively simple,
 understanding the system and why it works like it does is not simple, and I
 think you have to include that in the simplicity of a system. Overall I'd
 say it's an above averagely complex system. And I don't know about in
 America (although I can't imagine it would be much different from the UK),
 but in the UK I simply canot see people ever accepting this idea of
 delegating votes. It's a major paradigm shift and I think it renders it a
 non-starter as a serious system to elect parliaments, if I'm being honest
 (along with any other asset system).

 Also, if it is better for a voter to bullet vote and allow delegation (from
 their point of view), then voters who like a candidate but don't like their
 delegation list are presumably at a disadvantage to begin with, which
 they may perceive as unfair.

 Point 2 - You've said yourself that IRV satisifes this, but then I notice
 you've qualifed this earlier by saying any good system. Clever.


Actually, I even suspect that MJ may satisfy point 2, but for this point,
not having clear evidence that a system is satisfactory is almost as bad as
it definitely not being satisfactory.


 Point 3 - The chicken problem - yeah maybe. I'd have to get back to you.

 Point 4 - I imagine this is the one where it isn't unmatched by other good
 systems.

 So if we're allowing point 2 on this technicality, I still think it's only
 2 out of 4, because I think it fails simplicity, and fails it badly.


Didn't say there weren't points where it failed :).

Jameson


 Toby



   *From:* Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
 *To:* ⸘Ŭalabio‽ wala...@macosx.com
 *Cc:* EM election-methods@lists.electorama.com
 *Sent:* Monday, 5 September 2011, 19:31
 *Subject:* Re: [EM] SODA unfairly hobbles nonparanoid voters.

 SODA was initially designed as a single-winner system. I believe that as
 such, it has four independent advantages, three of which are unmatched by
 any other good system.

 1. It is the easiest possible system for voters. No spoiled ballots, bullet
 voting works, and no need to defensively strategize.
 2. It is later-no-harm enough to satisfy political incumbents who don't
 want to be defeated by centrist nonentities. (This is also true of IRV, but
 IRV has other problems)
 3. It resolves the chicken problem better than any other system I know of.
 4. I believe it would give good results overall - like Approval, Condorcet,
 MJ, or Range.

 So if you are thinking of SODA as just being Asset shoehorned into a
 single-winner case, then you don't understand the motivation, and either you
 don't understand the system or I don't.

 JQ

 2011/9/5 ⸘Ŭalabio‽ wala...@macosx.com

2011-09-05T09:28:14Z, “Jameson Quinn” jameson.qu...@gmail.com:

0thly, I recommend that you read this article:


 http://web.archive.org/web/20080113211450/http://www.greenend.org.uk/rjk/2000/06/14/quoting.html

Basically, ⸘Ŭalabio‽'s objection is that SODA does not allow
 non-bullet votes to be delegable. The reason that SODA is designed that way
 is not paranoia, as ⸘Ŭalabio‽ claims, but rather simplicity.

Simplicity is in the eye of the beholder.  What is simple for me is
 choosing people whom I trust to represent my interests in the
 Asset-Negotiations and leave them to their work.  If some of them screw me
 during Asset-Negotiations, I shall never vote for the bad 1s again.  As far
 as simplicity goes, SODA seems more complex to me than Asset-Voting.

To see why multiple delegable votes would be confusing, consider
 the following scenario. Let us say that I vote for A and B. After the votes
 are counted, it turns out that all the other voters voted for X or Y, in a
 50/50 proportion. My

Re: [EM] SODA unfairly hobbles nonparanoid voters.

2011-09-05 Thread ⸘Ŭalabio‽
2011-09-05T18:31:16Z, “Jameson Quinn” jameson.qu...@gmail.com:

   SODA was initially designed as a single-winner system.

Sorry but it looks like a terrible degraded form of Asset-Voting.

   I believe that as such, it has four independent advantages, three of 
 which are unmatched by any other good system.

[snip/]

I just do not see any of those advantages.  As far as simplicity, one 
cannot beat approval:

Approve:
+1

Neutral or no opnion:
0

Reject:
-1

+1  0   -1  Name

[ ] [ ] [ ] Alpha
[ ] [ ] [ ] Bravo
[ ] [ ] [ ] Charlie
[ ] [ ] [ ] Delta
[ ] [ ] [ ] Echo
[ ] [ ] [ ] Foxtrot
[ ] [ ] [ ] Golf
[ ] [ ] [ ] Hotel
[ ] [ ] [ ] India
[ ] [ ] [ ] Juliet
[ ] [ ] [ ] Kilo
[ ] [ ] [ ] Mike
[ ] [ ] [ ] November
[ ] [ ] [ ] Oscar
[ ] [ ] [ ] Papa
[ ] [ ] [ ] Quebec
[ ] [ ] [ ] Romeo
[ ] [ ] [ ] Sierra
[ ] [ ] [ ] Tango
[ ] [ ] [ ] Uniform
[ ] [ ] [ ] Victor
[ ] [ ] [ ] Whiskey
[ ] [ ] [ ] X-Ray
[ ] [ ] [ ] Yankee
[ ] [ ] [ ] Zulu

Since I cannot find anything nice to say about SODA, after this reply 
and 1 to  “Toby Pereira” tdp2...@yahoo.co.uk, I shall drop the subject.

   JQ

“⸘Ŭalabio‽”

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA unfairly hobbles nonparanoid voters.

2011-09-05 Thread ⸘Ŭalabio‽
2011-09-05T208:05:13Z, “Toby Pereira” tdp2...@yahoo.co.uk:

This is an article you should read:


http://web.archive.org/web/20080113211450/http://www.greenend.org.uk/rjk/2000/06/14/quoting.html

 Point 1 - I don't think it is the simplest system.

I agree:

Soda is more complex than simple approval.

   So if we're allowing point 2 on this technicality, I still think it's 
 only 2 out of 4, because I think it fails simplicity, and fails it badly.

I generally agree with you, but I do not see SODA as winning on any 
front.

Since, I have nothing nice to say, I shall make this my last post about 
SODA.

   Toby

“⸘Ŭalabio‽”


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] SODA unfairly hobbles nonparanoid voters.

2011-09-04 Thread ⸘Ŭalabio‽
¡Hello!

¿How fare you?

I do not believe in attacking the ideas of others, so I refrained from 
making this post from the remainder of July and all of August.  I gave others 
months to develop SODA without criticism:

The problem with most traditional voting systems is that one must 
choose between jacks-of-all-trades-but-master-of-none and idiot-savants:

Let us suppose that the greatest living Agronomist who studied under 
Professor Norman Ernest Borlaug (if you do not know who Professor Norman Ernest 
Borlaug was, please kill yourself immediately), and a Renaissance-Politician 
who served in the military, thus got to see the world, on the GI-Bill, got a 
score of degrees, but the most advanced of which are A.Scs  and A.As, who went 
on to a score of careers before becoming a politician.

One can vote for depth or breadth.

With Asset-voting, one can have both:

Let us suppose that we have an Asset-Election where each voter gets 9 
votes.  I chose 9 votes because it gives voters choice, but is easy for the 
voters to error-check:

In Base-10, make certain that the number of Asset-votes is a 
single-digit-number.  Make certain that the number in Base-10 is 9.

I could vote for 9 different Nobel-Lauriets who promise to transfer 
their votes to Renaissance-Politicians who promise to call on their expertise 
when needed.  In other words, with Asset-Voting, one can have one’s cake and 
eat it too.

SODA-Voting is a version of Asset-Voting.  SODA is based on the fear of 
being screwed by those who receive the Asset.  It is impossible eliminate the 
possibility of getting screwed.  This holds for politicians in nontransferable 
elections too.  The logical thing to do is not vote for backstabbing 
politicians again.

The paranoia of SODA is that it allows voters to make votes 
nontransferable so that the politicians cannot screw the voter during transfer 
negotiations.  This means 2 things:

*   One risks loss of voting power due to ballot-exhaustion (I 
suspect that SODA is susceptible to voting-splitting and Duverger’s Law).
*   Politicians can still screw over voters in the legislature.

SODA is a solution that does not work and it lets paranoid voters 
disenfranchise themselves.  I do not mind paranoid voters disenfranchising 
themselves because that means more voting power for me, but soda hobbles 
everyone to prevent that:

If one votes for more than 1 person in SODA makes the votes 
nontransferable.  That means that nonparanoid voters cannot vote for exports 
who then transfer their votes to jacks-of-all-trades under the condition that 
the Renaissance-Politicians call upon the experts when appropriate.  One must 
choose between the 2.

I do not like being hobbled because other voters are paranoid.  If 
other voters want to make their votes nontransferable, that is fine by me, but 
they should have to live with reduced voting power due to exhaustion rather 
than hobbling everyone else.  This is how I would do it:

*   Paranoid voters can indicate that their ballots are 
nontransferable by marking on the ballots that the ballots are nontransferable 
by marking them nontranferable, but must live with loss of voting power due to 
ballot-exhaustion.
*   Nonparanoid voters can choose 9 Nobel-Lauriets who then 
transfer the votes to Renaissance-Politicians who promise to call upon the 
expertise of the Nobel-Lauriets when appropriate.

Paranoid voters who are so afraid of being screwed that they make their 
ballots nontransferable just screw themselves.

¡Peace!

-- 

“⸘Ŭalabio‽” wala...@macosx.com

Skype:
Walabio

An IntactWiki:
http://intactipedia.org/

“You are entitled to your own opinion, but you are not entitled to your 
own facts.”
——
Senator Daniel Patrick Moynihan

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] SODA strategy

2011-08-09 Thread Jameson Quinn
SODA is not strategy free. Even if you make the assumption that candidate
preferences are honest because dishonesty will be detected and punished by
voters -- an assumption which puts the system beyond the reach of the
Gibbard-Satterthwaite proof -- the fact remains that you can construct
strategic scenarios.

However, it seems to me that SODA is not just a less-strategic system than
most others, but radically so. Unlike Approval, semi-honest approval
strategy is not something voters must deal with at least implicitly. But
like approval, non-semi-honest strategy is relegated to a tiny minority of
voters in a tiny minority of cases. The system can deal with all the
commonly-discussed strategic problems, including chicken, center squeeze,
and honest cycle. I honestly suspect that strategy under SODA would be
favored less than half as often as any other good deterministic system I
know of, including Approval, Asset, Condorcet (various), IRV, Median, and
Range.

So, how would you set out to make this idea demonstrable or falsifiable?
What rigorous statement about strategy and SODA could I make that would be
testable, preferably using simulated elections or mathematical
demonstration/counterexamples? What voter model could capture enough of the
sophisticated strategic thinking of which humans are capable?

How about SODA requires no self-reinforcing or defensive strategy?

These are honest, not rhetorical questions. I appreciate good responses,
good research questions, from anyone, whatever you expect that the results
of that research would be.

Thanks,
JQ

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA strategy

2011-08-09 Thread Juho Laatu
I checked the definition of SODA at the wiki page. Since the method consists of 
multiple phases and has many rules, it was difficult to find a simple mapping 
from that to one simple claim that could be proved or falsified. I also had 
some problems with terms semi-honest, non-semi-honest, self-reinforcing and 
defensive strategy below.

I had multiple thoughts on where SODA might be vulnerable and where not, but on 
the other hand I didn't know which phases were supposed to be strategy free 
and which way (the phases whose role I wondered were nomination, preference 
order declaration, voting and vote transfer). Maybe one could do this in 
smaller pieces, like handling separately the chicken problem for one of the 
phases etc. Another approach would be simply to list all identified possible 
vulnerabilities and then prove that all those cases are harmless. Is there one 
major claim that could sum it all (at least the claims) in one sentence or 
should we start from smaller pieces?

Juho


On 9.8.2011, at 16.14, Jameson Quinn wrote:

 SODA is not strategy free. Even if you make the assumption that candidate 
 preferences are honest because dishonesty will be detected and punished by 
 voters -- an assumption which puts the system beyond the reach of the 
 Gibbard-Satterthwaite proof -- the fact remains that you can construct 
 strategic scenarios.
 
 However, it seems to me that SODA is not just a less-strategic system than 
 most others, but radically so. Unlike Approval, semi-honest approval strategy 
 is not something voters must deal with at least implicitly. But like 
 approval, non-semi-honest strategy is relegated to a tiny minority of voters 
 in a tiny minority of cases. The system can deal with all the 
 commonly-discussed strategic problems, including chicken, center squeeze, and 
 honest cycle. I honestly suspect that strategy under SODA would be favored 
 less than half as often as any other good deterministic system I know of, 
 including Approval, Asset, Condorcet (various), IRV, Median, and Range.
 
 So, how would you set out to make this idea demonstrable or falsifiable? What 
 rigorous statement about strategy and SODA could I make that would be 
 testable, preferably using simulated elections or mathematical 
 demonstration/counterexamples? What voter model could capture enough of the 
 sophisticated strategic thinking of which humans are capable?
 
 How about SODA requires no self-reinforcing or defensive strategy?
 
 These are honest, not rhetorical questions. I appreciate good responses, good 
 research questions, from anyone, whatever you expect that the results of that 
 research would be.
 
 Thanks,
 JQ
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA strategy

2011-08-09 Thread Jameson Quinn
2011/8/9 Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk

 I checked the definition of SODA at the wiki page. Since the method
 consists of multiple phases and has many rules, it was difficult to find a
 simple mapping from that to one simple claim that could be proved or
 falsified. I also had some problems with terms semi-honest, non-semi-honest,
 self-reinforcing and defensive strategy below.

 I had multiple thoughts on where SODA might be vulnerable and where not,
 but on the other hand I didn't know which phases were supposed to be
 strategy free and which way (the phases whose role I wondered were
 nomination, preference order declaration, voting and vote transfer). Maybe
 one could do this in smaller pieces, like handling separately the chicken
 problem for one of the phases etc. Another approach would be simply to list
 all identified possible vulnerabilities and then prove that all those cases
 are harmless. Is there one major claim that could sum it all (at least the
 claims) in one sentence or should we start from smaller pieces?


I think starting small is probably the best way to go.

I believe that there are worthwhile strategy-proofness claims to be made
about each of the phases except preference order declaration. For that
phase, the principal defense against strategy is the assumption that
dishonesty in this phase would be detected and punished by the voters,
either by voters withdrawing support, or in a weaker way by their turning
delegated votes into non-delegated votes.

The system I want to use for strategy considerations is SODA-DAC with
candidate preferences completed to strict rankings by approval order. This
differs in two ways from the simplest basic SODA version, but I believe that
the latter is close enough to share most advantage.

I'll try to develop a list of clear sub-claims in a later message.

JQ



 Juho


 On 9.8.2011, at 16.14, Jameson Quinn wrote:

  SODA is not strategy free. Even if you make the assumption that candidate
 preferences are honest because dishonesty will be detected and punished by
 voters -- an assumption which puts the system beyond the reach of the
 Gibbard-Satterthwaite proof -- the fact remains that you can construct
 strategic scenarios.
 
  However, it seems to me that SODA is not just a less-strategic system
 than most others, but radically so. Unlike Approval, semi-honest approval
 strategy is not something voters must deal with at least implicitly. But
 like approval, non-semi-honest strategy is relegated to a tiny minority of
 voters in a tiny minority of cases. The system can deal with all the
 commonly-discussed strategic problems, including chicken, center squeeze,
 and honest cycle. I honestly suspect that strategy under SODA would be
 favored less than half as often as any other good deterministic system I
 know of, including Approval, Asset, Condorcet (various), IRV, Median, and
 Range.
 
  So, how would you set out to make this idea demonstrable or falsifiable?
 What rigorous statement about strategy and SODA could I make that would be
 testable, preferably using simulated elections or mathematical
 demonstration/counterexamples? What voter model could capture enough of the
 sophisticated strategic thinking of which humans are capable?
 
  How about SODA requires no self-reinforcing or defensive strategy?
 
  These are honest, not rhetorical questions. I appreciate good responses,
 good research questions, from anyone, whatever you expect that the results
 of that research would be.
 
  Thanks,
  JQ
  
  Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list
 info

 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] SODA

2011-08-08 Thread Warren Smith
http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/SODA

SODA is slightly more complicated for the voter since voter needs to
check box saying she delegates her vote, or not.  Also more
complicated in the sense that there is more information shoved in the
voter's face.
But those deficits are probably amply compensated for...

I think this is a very nice voting method.

It also can be used both as a single-winner method, and as a PR
multiwinner method
(in the sense it acts like asset voting), right?
Another very elegant point.  It also has ideas in common with DYN
   http://www.rangevoting.org/DynDefn.html

It is not entirely clear to me some other mental hybrid of asset and
dyn ideas, might
not be superior to SODA.  Specifically, SODA
only delegates if you vote plurality style.  But you could also have a
ballot like this:

YES.NO.Candidate
___ .___A who prefers BCD
___ .___B who prefers ACD
___ .___C who prefers BAD
___ .___D who prefers BCA

and if you put down exactly one yes and an arbitrary number of nos,
then your blank entries get delegated to the candidate you voted yes on.

Is that an improvement or a worsening versus the SODA rules?

I definitely think SODA is a good idea, and I'd like to add a SODA
page or two to the
CRV website.

On the sample ballot on the SODA web page, I do not like the use of
the word share.
I think that word is not the right word.  But I admit I'm unsure how
best to re-word it.
Delegate your remaining approvals is not the same as share, is my
linguistic point.


-- 
Warren D. Smith
http://RangeVoting.org  -- add your endorsement (by clicking
endorse as 1st step)
and
math.temple.edu/~wds/homepage/works.html

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA

2011-08-08 Thread Andy Jennings
On Mon, Aug 8, 2011 at 6:35 AM, Warren Smith warren@gmail.com wrote:

 http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/SODA

 SODA is slightly more complicated for the voter since voter needs to
 check box saying she delegates her vote, or not.  Also more
 complicated in the sense that there is more information shoved in the
 voter's face.
 But those deficits are probably amply compensated for...

 I think this is a very nice voting method.

 It also can be used both as a single-winner method, and as a PR
 multiwinner method
 (in the sense it acts like asset voting), right?
 Another very elegant point.  It also has ideas in common with DYN
   http://www.rangevoting.org/DynDefn.html



SODA is definitely a descendant of DYN.  In my opinion, it comes down to
three improvements that are basically orthogonal.

1. Ballot design - The most important thing here is that the ballot
basically looks like it always has and that voters who bullet vote like they
always have are casting a delegated vote for one candidate, which is an
effective vote.  (Yes there is one extra question at the bottom, but I find
that preferable to forcing people to write in Do not delegate.)

2. Candidates must exercise their ballots in a way consistent with a
preference order they declared before the election - Helps voters understand
how their ballot might get extended and vastly decreases opportunities for
strategy in the delegation phase.

3. Candidates exercise their ballots one-at-a-time in a specific order -
Avoids candidates trying to mislead each other about how they will exercise
their delegated ballots (if they all go simultaneously).  Can eliminate the
chicken paradox.

You could apply these improvements to DYN in isolation or in other
combinations, or even mix in other improvements, but together I think they
make quite a strong system.



 On the sample ballot on the SODA web page, I do not like the use of
 the word share.
 I think that word is not the right word.  But I admit I'm unsure how
 best to re-word it.
 Delegate your remaining approvals is not the same as share, is my
 linguistic point.



I agree.  At one point I reworded it to candidates exercise their delegated
ballots.  But I don't think this is perfect.  Jameson wanted to unify the
language on the whole page, which is good, and went with share likely
because it is the most succinct, but I do think it can be confusing for
someone learning about SODA for the first time.

~ Andy

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] SODA and the Condorcet criterion

2011-08-05 Thread fsimmons
Jameson, 

as you say, it seems that SODA will always elect a candidate that beats every 
other candidate majority 
pairwise.  If rankings are complete, then all pairwise wins will be by 
majority.  So at least to the degree 
that rankings are complete, SODA satisfies the Condorcet Criterion.

Also, as I mentioned briefly in my last message under this subject heading, 
SODA seems to completely 
demolish the chicken problem.

To review for other readers, we're talking about the scenario

48 A
27 CB
25 BC

Candidates B and C form a clone set that pairwise beats A, and in fact C is the 
Condorcet Winner, but 
under many Condorcet methods, as well as for Range and Approval, there is a 
large temptation for the 
25 B faction to threaten to truncate C, and thereby steal the election from C.  
Of course C can counter 
the threat to truncate B, but then A wins.  So it is a classical game of 
chicken.

Some methods like IRV cop out by giving the win to A right off the bat, so 
there is no game of chicken.  
But is there a way of really facing up to  the problem?  i.e. a way that elects 
from the majority clone set 
by somehow diffusing the game of chicken?

The problem is that in most methods both factions must decide more or less 
simultaneously.  However, 
if the decisions can be made sequentially, then the faction that plays first 
can safely forestall the 
chicken threat of the other.  That's one reason that it makes sense for SODA to 
have the candidates 
play sequentially, and to have the strongest candidate of a clone (or near 
clone) set go before the other 
candidate or candidates in the clone set.

Since DAC is designed to pick out the strongest candidate in the plurality 
winner clone set, it is a 
natural for setting the order of play (in the sophisticated version of SODA).

Another way to solve the chicken problem is to not allow truncations.  But in 
SODA it seems essential 
to allow the candidates to truncate.  However there is a pressure  for the 
candidates to not truncate too 
high up in the rankings; if they do, they lose credibility with their 
supporters, so fewer of them will 
delegate their approval decisions to them.  

Since having complete rankings helps both in chicken and with regard to the 
Condorcet Criterion, it 
might be worth using the implicit order in the approval ballots of the 
supporters of candidate X to 
complete X's rankings by using that implicit order to rank the candidates 
truncated by X (or otherwise 
ranked equal by X).

This would discourage X from too much truncation, and would make it more likely 
that the true CW was 
elected in the (usual?) case where there is one.

Forest



 From: Jameson Quinn 
 To: EM 
 Subject: [EM] SODA and the Condorcet criterion
 Here's the new text on the SODA
 page Delegated_Approval#Criteria_Compliancerelatingto the Condorcet 
 criterion:
 It fails the Condorcet
 criterion,
 although the majority Condorcet winner over the ranking-
 augmented ballots is
 the unique strong, subgame-perfect equilibrium winner. That is 
 to say that,
 the method would in fact pass the *majority* Condorcet winner 
 criterion,assuming the following:
 
 - *Candidates are honest* in their pre-election rankings. 
 This could be
 because they are innately unwilling to be dishonest, because 
 they are unable
 to calculate a useful dishonest strategy, or, most likely, 
 because they fear
 dishonesty would lose them delegated votes. That is, voters 
 who disagreed
 with the dishonest rankings might vote approval-style instead 
 of delegating,
 and voters who perceived the rankings as dishonest might 
 thereby value the
 candidate less.
 - *Candidates are rationally strategic* in assigning their 
 delegated vote. Since the assignments are sequential, game 
 theory states that there is
 always a subgame-perfect Nash equilibrium, which is always 
 unique except in
 some cases of tied preferences.
 - *Voters* are able to use the system to *express all relevant
 preferences*. That is to say, all voters fall into one of two 
 groups: those who agree with their favored candidate's 
 declared preference order and
 thus can fully express that by delegating their vote; or 
 those who disagree
 with their favored candidate's preferences, but are aware of 
 who the
 Condorcet winner is, and are able to use the approval-style 
 ballot to
 express their preference between the CW and all second-place 
 candidates. Second place means the Smith set if the 
 Condorcet winner were removed from
 the election; thus, for this assumption to hold, each voter 
 must prefer the
 CW to all members of this second-place Smith set or vice 
 versa. That's
 obviously always true if there is a single second-place CW.
 
 The three assumptions above would probably not strictly hold 
 true in a
 real-life election, but they usually would be close enough to 
 ensure that
 the system does elect the CW.
 
 SODA does even better than this if there are only 3 candidates, 
 or if the
 Condorcet winner goes

Re: [EM] SODA and the Condorcet criterion

2011-08-05 Thread Jameson Quinn
 the implicit order in the approval ballots of the
 supporters of candidate X to
 complete X's rankings by using that implicit order to rank the candidates
 truncated by X (or otherwise
 ranked equal by X).


Ugh. The big problem with this is that approval-style votes for a candidate
will be, by definition, from voters who disagree with that candidate's
actual ordering. Also, as a small group, it would be very vulnerable to
hijacking, at little cost.



 This would discourage X from too much truncation, and would make it more
 likely that the true CW was
 elected in the (usual?) case where there is one.


Yes, I sympathize with the goal. But I can't see how to achieve it without
inventing CODA.

JQ



 Forest



  From: Jameson Quinn
  To: EM
  Subject: [EM] SODA and the Condorcet criterion
  Here's the new text on the SODA
  page Delegated_Approval#Criteria_Compliancerelatingto the Condorcet
  criterion:
  It fails the Condorcet
  criterion,
  although the majority Condorcet winner over the ranking-
  augmented ballots is
  the unique strong, subgame-perfect equilibrium winner. That is
  to say that,
  the method would in fact pass the *majority* Condorcet winner
  criterion,assuming the following:
 
  - *Candidates are honest* in their pre-election rankings.
  This could be
  because they are innately unwilling to be dishonest, because
  they are unable
  to calculate a useful dishonest strategy, or, most likely,
  because they fear
  dishonesty would lose them delegated votes. That is, voters
  who disagreed
  with the dishonest rankings might vote approval-style instead
  of delegating,
  and voters who perceived the rankings as dishonest might
  thereby value the
  candidate less.
  - *Candidates are rationally strategic* in assigning their
  delegated vote. Since the assignments are sequential, game
  theory states that there is
  always a subgame-perfect Nash equilibrium, which is always
  unique except in
  some cases of tied preferences.
  - *Voters* are able to use the system to *express all relevant
  preferences*. That is to say, all voters fall into one of two
  groups: those who agree with their favored candidate's
  declared preference order and
  thus can fully express that by delegating their vote; or
  those who disagree
  with their favored candidate's preferences, but are aware of
  who the
  Condorcet winner is, and are able to use the approval-style
  ballot to
  express their preference between the CW and all second-place
  candidates. Second place means the Smith set if the
  Condorcet winner were removed from
  the election; thus, for this assumption to hold, each voter
  must prefer the
  CW to all members of this second-place Smith set or vice
  versa. That's
  obviously always true if there is a single second-place CW.
 
  The three assumptions above would probably not strictly hold
  true in a
  real-life election, but they usually would be close enough to
  ensure that
  the system does elect the CW.
 
  SODA does even better than this if there are only 3 candidates,
  or if the
  Condorcet winner goes first in the delegation assignment order,
  or if there
  are 4 candidates and the CW goes second. In any of those
  circumstances,under the assumptions above, it passes the
  *Condorcet* criterion, not just
  the majority Condorcet criterion. The important difference
  between the
  Condorcet criterion (beats all others pairwise) and the majority
  Condorcetcriterion (beats all others pairwise by a strict
  majority) is that the
  former is clone-proof while the latter is not. Thus, with few
  enough strong
  candidates, SODA also passes the independence of clones
  criterion
  .
 
  Note that, although the circumstances where SODA passes the Condorcet
  criterion are hemmed in by assumptions, when it does pass, it
  does so in a
  perfectly strategy-proof sense. That is *not* true of any actual
  Condorcetsystem (that is, any system which universally passes
  the Condorcet
  criterion). Therefore, for rationally-strategic voters who
  believe that the
  above assumptions are likely to hold, *SODA may in fact pass the
  Condorcetcriterion more often than a Condorcet system*.
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] SODA and the Condorcet criterion

2011-08-04 Thread Jameson Quinn
Here's the new text on the SODA
pagehttp://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/Simple_Optionally-Delegated_Approval#Criteria_Compliancerelating
to the Condorcet criterion:

It fails the Condorcet
criterionhttp://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/Condorcet_criterion,
although the majority Condorcet winner over the ranking-augmented ballots is
the unique strong, subgame-perfect equilibrium winner. That is to say that,
the method would in fact pass the *majority* Condorcet winner criterion,
assuming the following:

   - *Candidates are honest* in their pre-election rankings. This could be
   because they are innately unwilling to be dishonest, because they are unable
   to calculate a useful dishonest strategy, or, most likely, because they fear
   dishonesty would lose them delegated votes. That is, voters who disagreed
   with the dishonest rankings might vote approval-style instead of delegating,
   and voters who perceived the rankings as dishonest might thereby value the
   candidate less.
   - *Candidates are rationally strategic* in assigning their delegated
   vote. Since the assignments are sequential, game theory states that there is
   always a subgame-perfect Nash equilibrium, which is always unique except in
   some cases of tied preferences.
   - *Voters* are able to use the system to *express all relevant
   preferences*. That is to say, all voters fall into one of two groups:
   those who agree with their favored candidate's declared preference order and
   thus can fully express that by delegating their vote; or those who disagree
   with their favored candidate's preferences, but are aware of who the
   Condorcet winner is, and are able to use the approval-style ballot to
   express their preference between the CW and all second-place candidates.
   Second place means the Smith set if the Condorcet winner were removed from
   the election; thus, for this assumption to hold, each voter must prefer the
   CW to all members of this second-place Smith set or vice versa. That's
   obviously always true if there is a single second-place CW.

The three assumptions above would probably not strictly hold true in a
real-life election, but they usually would be close enough to ensure that
the system does elect the CW.

SODA does even better than this if there are only 3 candidates, or if the
Condorcet winner goes first in the delegation assignment order, or if there
are 4 candidates and the CW goes second. In any of those circumstances,
under the assumptions above, it passes the *Condorcet* criterion, not just
the majority Condorcet criterion. The important difference between the
Condorcet criterion (beats all others pairwise) and the majority Condorcet
criterion (beats all others pairwise by a strict majority) is that the
former is clone-proof while the latter is not. Thus, with few enough strong
candidates, SODA also passes the independence of clones
criterionhttp://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/index.php?title=Independence_of_clones_criterionaction=editredlink=1
.

Note that, although the circumstances where SODA passes the Condorcet
criterion are hemmed in by assumptions, when it does pass, it does so in a
perfectly strategy-proof sense. That is *not* true of any actual Condorcet
system (that is, any system which universally passes the Condorcet
criterion). Therefore, for rationally-strategic voters who believe that the
above assumptions are likely to hold, *SODA may in fact pass the Condorcet
criterion more often than a Condorcet system*.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] SODA and the Condorcet criterion

2011-08-04 Thread fsimmons
I want to thank Jameson for taking the ball and running with it on SODA.  I 
really appreciate his talented 
and energetic work on elaborating, explaining, and selling the method.

It's exciting to me to see the possibilities.

Here's more evidence of monotonicity:

With a three candidate cycle

x ABC
y BCA
z CAB

if xyz, then A plays first, but B wins the election.

If the B faction increases at the expense of the x faction so that  yxz, then 
B goes first, and still wins! 
(because ACB is opposite the cyclic order of the beat cycle)

The other nice thing about SODA and strong first play order is that it makes 
the game of chicken go 
away.



 Date: Thu, 4 Aug 2011 08:01:30 -0500
 From: Jameson Quinn 
 To: EM 
 Subject: [EM] SODA and the Condorcet criterion
 Message-ID:
 
 Content-Type: text/plain; charset=iso-8859-1
 
 Here's the new text on the SODA
 page Delegated_Approval#Criteria_Compliancerelatingto the Condorcet 
 criterion:
 It fails the Condorcet
 criterion,
 although the majority Condorcet winner over the ranking-
 augmented ballots is
 the unique strong, subgame-perfect equilibrium winner. That is 
 to say that,
 the method would in fact pass the *majority* Condorcet winner 
 criterion,assuming the following:
 
 - *Candidates are honest* in their pre-election rankings. 
 This could be
 because they are innately unwilling to be dishonest, because 
 they are unable
 to calculate a useful dishonest strategy, or, most likely, 
 because they fear
 dishonesty would lose them delegated votes. That is, voters 
 who disagreed
 with the dishonest rankings might vote approval-style instead 
 of delegating,
 and voters who perceived the rankings as dishonest might 
 thereby value the
 candidate less.
 - *Candidates are rationally strategic* in assigning their 
 delegated vote. Since the assignments are sequential, game 
 theory states that there is
 always a subgame-perfect Nash equilibrium, which is always 
 unique except in
 some cases of tied preferences.
 - *Voters* are able to use the system to *express all relevant
 preferences*. That is to say, all voters fall into one of two 
 groups: those who agree with their favored candidate's 
 declared preference order and
 thus can fully express that by delegating their vote; or 
 those who disagree
 with their favored candidate's preferences, but are aware of 
 who the
 Condorcet winner is, and are able to use the approval-style 
 ballot to
 express their preference between the CW and all second-place 
 candidates. Second place means the Smith set if the 
 Condorcet winner were removed from
 the election; thus, for this assumption to hold, each voter 
 must prefer the
 CW to all members of this second-place Smith set or vice 
 versa. That's
 obviously always true if there is a single second-place CW.
 
 The three assumptions above would probably not strictly hold 
 true in a
 real-life election, but they usually would be close enough to 
 ensure that
 the system does elect the CW.
 
 SODA does even better than this if there are only 3 candidates, 
 or if the
 Condorcet winner goes first in the delegation assignment order, 
 or if there
 are 4 candidates and the CW goes second. In any of those 
 circumstances,under the assumptions above, it passes the 
 *Condorcet* criterion, not just
 the majority Condorcet criterion. The important difference 
 between the
 Condorcet criterion (beats all others pairwise) and the majority 
 Condorcetcriterion (beats all others pairwise by a strict 
 majority) is that the
 former is clone-proof while the latter is not. Thus, with few 
 enough strong
 candidates, SODA also passes the independence of clones
 criterion
 .
 
 Note that, although the circumstances where SODA passes the Condorcet
 criterion are hemmed in by assumptions, when it does pass, it 
 does so in a
 perfectly strategy-proof sense. That is *not* true of any actual 
 Condorcetsystem (that is, any system which universally passes 
 the Condorcet
 criterion). Therefore, for rationally-strategic voters who 
 believe that the
 above assumptions are likely to hold, *SODA may in fact pass the 
 Condorcetcriterion more often than a Condorcet system*.
 -- next part --
 An HTML attachment was scrubbed...
 URL:  electorama.com/attachments/20110804/d8f85fc2/attachment-0001.htm
 

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA and the Condorcet criterion

2011-08-04 Thread Jameson Quinn
2011/8/4 fsimm...@pcc.edu

 I want to thank Jameson for taking the ball and running with it on SODA.  I
 really appreciate his talented
 and energetic work on elaborating, explaining, and selling the method.


Thank you.

More stuff I've added to the SODA page recently:

-I tried to unify the terminology. Voters can delegate their votes;
Candidates receive delegated votes (not ballots), which they then use (I
had been using assign, exercise, or share) by approving other
candidates, who in turn receive these shared votes.

I'd be open to suggestions to improve any of those terms, though I think
consistency is more important than perfection.

-I revamped the section on Advantages, and added a section on Electoral
College compatibility. The latter contains proposed rules for using with the
EC, for which I'm open to refinements or suggestions.

Here are the sections as they stand:

Advantages

SODA has advantages for many groups. In fact, most of the advantages would
fit in more than one of the categories below, so the division is somewhat
arbitrary. Also, on the talk page (click discussion above) there are also
two hard sell SODA pitches for two different audiences, which restate
these advantages in more-opinionated terms.
 
[edithttp://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/index.php?title=Simple_Optionally-Delegated_Approvalaction=editsection=10
]For voters

   1. SODA is extremely easy for the voters; in fact, *no voting system is
   simpler to vote*. (Plurality, by restricting you to only one vote, also
   makes it possible to mistakenly overvote, spoiling your ballot. There is
   no such way to accidentally invalidate your ballot under SODA. Also, both
   Plurality and Approval require a conscientious voter to consider strategy
   and polling status; SODA allows a simple bullet vote to still be
   strategically as strong as possible, regardless of the candidate standings.)
   2. Under SODA, there is *no need for dishonesty* from individual voters.
   A voter can safely vote for any candidate that they honestly agree with,
   without fear of that vote being wasted; or safely vote an honest
   approval-style ballot, if they do not agree with any candidate's preference
   order. This is drastically different from plurality, where voters must
   dishonestly spurn spoiler candidates as a matter of course.
   3. SODA *does not require you to trust any politician*. Any vote
   delegation is both safe (you can see where your delegated vote will go) and
   entirely optional. Any voter who dislikes the idea of their vote being
   delegated in a smoke-filled room, need not allow that to happen.

[edithttp://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/index.php?title=Simple_Optionally-Delegated_Approvalaction=editsection=11
]For society (results)

   1. SODA is far *more likely to arrive at a majority result* than
   Plurality (or even IRV). Winners will thus have a clearer mandate.
   2. SODA may be *more likely to elect the Condorcet winner* (aka pairwise
   champion, the candidate who could beat all others one-on-one) than *any
   other system* (except SODA-DAC http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/DAC).
   See the technical discussion in the prior section for the assumptions that
   would make this true.
   3. However, unexpected, relatively unknown or *unqualified winners will
   be as rare or rarer under SODA* than under Approval or a Condorcet
   system. In a polarized society, Condorcet can have such a strong tendency to
   elect centrists that even unqualified, largely-unknown centrists have an
   advantage over better-known candidates; SODA will not have such a tendency
   unless the stronger candidates consciously choose this as a compromise.

[edithttp://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/index.php?title=Simple_Optionally-Delegated_Approvalaction=editsection=12
]For society (process)

   1. Leaders of *minority factions would have an appropriate voice for
   their concerns*, although power would ultimately reside with any majority
   coalition which exists. In fact, you could say that SODA combines the best
   of both worlds - the negotiated, everyone-gets-a-voice coalitions of
   parliamentary government, with the decisive, buck-stops-here clear winner of
   a US-style system.
   2. SODA would *reduce negative campaigns*. A negative attack against
   opponent A would often just shift votes to another opponent B who would end
   up sharing them back with A in the delegation round. Meanwhile, the
   candidate carrying out the attacks could also suffer with voters.
   3. Like many other voting reforms, SODA would *reduce the influence of
   money* in political campaigns. Plurality, with its overriding need to be
   a frontrunner, exaggerates the importance of money. SODA in particular, by
   encouraging meaningful campaigns and get-out-the-vote operations by minor
   candidates, while still ensuring that the extra turnout those generated
   would have an effective impact in deciding between the major candidates,
   would help substitute grassroots 

[EM] SODA rationale, part 1 of 4: Undecided voters (was: Record activity on the EM list?)

2011-08-03 Thread Jameson Quinn


 but, as a peripheral actor here, i haven't been participating too much in
 this SODA thing or any other asset voting systems.  i have to admit that my
 attitude toward such is why bother?.  i still don't get it.  maybe in an
 election in an organization or corporation, but i just can't see such in a
 governmental election.  people who complain about IRV or a ranked ballot as
 complicated will feel no different about an proxy-assignable contingency
 vote.  toss in the option to not assign the contingency vote to a proxy
 (with an additional check box) and these people will all the more so say
 hunh?.


It's a fair criticism. So let me try to explain why I think SODA is
especially promising from a practical standpoint.

I think SODA would be better than other good systems from the perspective of
several constituencies who are typically skeptical about voting reform. RBJ
speaks of people who complain about IRV, but I think it's worth being more
specific.

-

First off, there's the typical undecided voters, whom I'd recast as being
mostly more like *disengaged voters*. My thinking about such people has been
influenced by this 2004 article from the New
Republichttp://www.csus.edu/indiv/f/friedman/spring2011/govt1/schedule/g/g2/undecided.htm.
Basically it argues that undecided voters are not so much the centrists that
pundits like to make up just-so stories about, but rather, they're just
people who view politics as an unappealing chore. They accept voting as
their civic duty, but see it as a boring and distasteful requirement to
choose between a bunch of people they don't know and probably wouldn't like
or even trust if they did. A person like that really does not care about how
the ballot-counting process works, any more than they want to have to think
about where their electricity comes from. And they don't want anyone coming
around to tell them later that they should have spent more effort to make a
strategically optimal vote (whatever that means).

SODA's advantages for this group are clear. They want to vote-for-one and
forget about it. And they don't care about the rest. Sure, they may express
their skepticism about IRV in terms of how the inner workings seem to
complex, but in reality they don't care about the inner workings.

Note that, even though it adds undesirable complexity, the optional part
of SODA, the ability not to delegate, is also important in convincing this
group of people. They don't trust politicians, and so any system which
forces voters to delegate and trust is a non-starter. So it's important to
have the option not to delegate, even if these voters will rarely use it.

Why even worry about such people, if they're so disengaged? It's not as if
they'll ever become political activists for your cause. But still, ignore
them at your peril. It's easy for a negative campaign to bring to the
forefront these people's simmering distrust, and while they are the weakest
of allies, you do not want them as enemies. Disengaged they may be, but they
are still voters. (They might have plenty in common with non-voters, but
that's not who I'm talking about).

(By the way, I have friends like this, as I'm sure most of you do. I
certainly hope I'm not being insulting. They are just as smart as anyone
else on average. The difference between the kind of person who'd be on an
election methods mailing list, and the kind of person who views voting as
about as fun as cleaning the toilet, isn't that the former is necessarily
more capable of understanding voting systems, it's that they're more
interested.)

*(to be continued)*

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] SODA page updated with SODA-PR

2011-07-24 Thread Jameson Quinn
Just to alert those who may be interested, I've added SODA-PR to the SODA
page on 
electowikihttp://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/Simple_Optionally-Delegated_Approval#SODA-PR_.28proportional_representation_version_of_SODA.29
.

It includes some minor adjustments since the last time I expounded it here:

Simplifying the ballot by including same-district candidates in a larger
font, nearby-district candidates in a smaller font, and far-away candidates
as write-ins only, is now part of the system by default.
Random discards are repeated until the next candidate to be elected is the
same twice in a row. That is intended as a compromise between the
mathematical simplicity of ballot discarding and the deterministic nature of
fractional reweighting. In most cases, it will not affect the result.
Intercandidate can be conditional on being mutual, but not conditional on
anything else. That should allow a reasonable, but not excessive, level of
party discipline.

It also notes the circumstances when this will give the same results as
plurality, to argue that existing plurality winners will find this to be a
relatively-good PR system.

JQ

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA

2011-07-21 Thread Jameson Quinn


  For generic SODA, the current rule is: candidates exercise their
  ballots in
  descending order of current approval score.

 By current approval score do you mean the non-delegated scores?  If so,
 what do we do when
 everbody delegates?


 No, I mean total votes - including non-delegated approval from voters,
delegated bullet votes from voters, and assigned delegated votes from other
candidates. Yes, these totals increase as the game is played, so
descending order is a bit of a misnomer; perhaps I should say the next
player is always the candidate with the highest current votes.

JQ

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA

2011-07-21 Thread fsimmons
I like it!

- Original Message -
From: Jameson Quinn 
Date: Thursday, July 21, 2011 4:11 am
Subject: Re: [EM] SODA
To: fsimm...@pcc.edu
Cc: election-methods@lists.electorama.com

 
 
   For generic SODA, the current rule is: candidates exercise their
   ballots in
   descending order of current approval score.
 
  By current approval score do you mean the non-delegated 
 scores? If so,
  what do we do when
  everbody delegates?
 
 
 No, I mean total votes - including non-delegated approval from 
 voters,delegated bullet votes from voters, and assigned 
 delegated votes from other
 candidates. Yes, these totals increase as the game is played, so
 descending order is a bit of a misnomer; perhaps I should say 
 the next
 player is always the candidate with the highest current votes.
 
 JQ
 

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] SODA

2011-07-20 Thread fsimmons
In our SODA development we came to something of an impasse for determining the 
order of play for 
the candidates casting their approval cutoffs.

Here's a suggestion:

Let the DSC winner go first, because the DSC winner is easily calculated, 
satisfies Later-No-Harm (so 
does not unduly encourage truncation), and can be thought of as the minimal 
acceptable modification of 
plurality, namely de-cloning it without destroying its montonicity.  In a way, 
DSC elegantly 
accomplishes what IRV attempts but botches. 

[In the context of SODA where there is only one faction for each of the n 
candidates, the DSC method 
has to score at most n*(n-1) subsets, and it takes no more than the order of 
n^2 steps to determine the 
DSC score of each of these subsets.  So the whole thing can be done in the 
order of n^4 steps at worst.]

From then on the next player in the sequence is the candidate that ranked the 
previous player X the 
highest. If there is a tie, say Y1, Y2, and Y3 each ranks X equally high (and 
higher than anybody else 
does) then the member of {Y1, Y2, Y3} ranked highest by X is the next player.

This order is clone consistent, i.e. if Y is replaced by a clone set, then the 
entire clone set will be 
intercalated into the order in place of Y.

This order discourages burial, because if X is first in the order, and Y buries 
X,  then Y will not follow X, 
unless all of the other candidates bury X, too, in which case X could not have 
been first.

Note that we could reverse the roles of X and Y in determining the order and 
breaking ties:  The 
remaining candidate Y that X ranks the highest is next, and if X ranks no 
remaining candidate, then the 
candidate that ranks X the highest is next.  My intuition is that this order 
might not be quite as burial 
resistant, but it would be better at discouraging what we could call fawning, 
namely ranking the 
presumed DSC winner artificially high for the sole purpose of getting into the 
order earlier.

Another option would be to use the DSC winner's rankings for all of the rest of 
the players, and passing 
to the second player's rankings to resolve any equal rankings made by the DSC 
winner, etc.

We need to experiment to see if any of these is adequate, and if so, which is 
best.

What are some good scenarios to test?



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA

2011-07-20 Thread fsimmons
Sounds good.

- Original Message -
From: Jameson Quinn 
 I would like to keep generic SODA as simple as possible, to make 
 it easier
 to promote for practical use. However, I am still interested in 
 figuring out
 the best possible SODA+ method, using DSC or whatever.
 
 For generic SODA, the current rule is: candidates exercise their 
 ballots in
 descending order of current approval score.
 
By current approval score do you mean the non-delegated scores?  If so, what 
do we do when 
everbody delegates?
 
 This will correctly 
 get the CW
 in all 3-candidate scenarios (including non-delegable votes), 
 and I suspect
 in all 4-candidate scenarios without delegable votes and full 
 ranking. (I
 can get a very fragile non-CW scenario for 5 candidates, all-delegable
 votes, and full ranking, in a (1+*2*)v(2) clone scenario, where 
 the CW is
 one of the starred 2.) Note that, simple as it is, this rule 
 tends to
 follow clone sets down, as Forest's proposed rules do, because 
 if A
 delegates to B, then B is almost certain to go next. Thus, this 
 rule is
 highly clone resistant, for reasonable numbers of clones, 
 although not
 perfectly clone-proof. It is also clone-proof (ie, IIA) for 1D 
 scenarios.
 I'd like to make some Yee diagrams for SODA with this rule. Does 
 anybodyknow what algorithms I could use? It would be pretty easy 
 if you assumed
 that all voters gave a delegable vote; but I think that a more 
 realisticrule would be that voters give a delegable vote iff 
 they agree with their
 preferred candidate's first delegation, and approves the top max(2
 candidates or 1/3 of all candidates) if not. That, plus the delegation
 order, is getting a bit hairy for calculating Yee diagrams from, 
 so I'd
 appreciate any tips on algorithmic short cuts. (eg, is there 
 some way to
 prove that this voting rule in a 2-dimensional space always 
 gives a
 ballot-CW under SODA, and that therefore I can avoid dealing 
 with delegation
 order?). If the diagrams can be calculated relatively quickly, 
 I'd be
 interested in doing this using a real-time web tool (as an 
 excercise in
 programming in go with GAE); otherwise, I could do it in 
 whatever language,
 offline.
 
 As for Forest's DSC rule for SODA+: how about starting with the 
 DSC winner,
 then proceeding to the DSC winner among those who got votes from 
 the last
 player, or the DSC winner among the remainder if the last player 
 did not
 assign votes? It's in effect similar to the higest ranking from the
 previous player rule, but closer to the generic SODA rule.
 
 JQ
 
 ps. I vaguely know how DSC works, but I'd appreciate a refresher.
 
Here's a link:
 
http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/Descending_Solid_Coalitions
 
It's quite fun to play with.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA

2011-07-09 Thread fsimmons


From: Jameson Quinn 
 Here's the scenario you used to first show your tree method of 
 determiningdelegation order.
 
 16 A1A2B
 12 A2A1B
 24 BA1=A2
 48 C
 
 What if some candidate outside the A1 A2 faction had an A2A1 
 preference? I
 mean either:
 Scenario S
 16 A1A2B
 12 A2A1B
 24 BA2A1
 48 C
 
 Or:
 Scenario T
 16 A1A2B
 12 A2A1B
 24 BA1=A2
 43 C
 5 CA2
 
 Or even:
 Scenario U
 16 A1A2B
 12 A2A1B
 24 BA1=A2
 43 C
 5 A2C
 
 I believe that A2 should go first in all of the above scenarios. 

I agree, and my coalition tree/DAG idea doesn't work, so let's scrap it.

However, before we settle on a quick and dirty way of deciding the player 
order, I suggest that we do find 
an ideal way as a standard of comparison for competing approximations.

The ideal way should generate a clone consistent monotonic list from ballot 
rankings.

Short of CSSD itself, note that DAC (Descending Acquiescing Coalitions) elects 
A2 in all three of the 
scenarios S, T, and U above, and A! in the original.  So use DAC to get the 
first player, and then to get 
the next player use DAC to choose from the remaining candidates, etc.

DAC is easy to describe and easy to do in O(n*m) steps where n is the number of 
candidates, and m is 
the number of factions, which in our case is also n.

On another note,  I think it is important to get a fairly complete ranking for 
each faction to avoid the 
temptation of playing chicken before the approval stage by truncating the 
rankings.  I'm not saying that 
the candidates have to submit a complete rankings, but we need a way of more or 
less completing the 
ballots that have truncations and equal rankings.

Here's what I suggest.  To complete (or nearly complete) the ranking submitted 
by candidate X, take a 
weighted average of all of the approval ballots (i.e. non-delegating ballots) 
that approve X, with the weight 
of each such ballot being the reciprocal of the number of candidates approved 
by that ballot.  Use this 
weighted average of approval ballots to break as many ties as possible in the 
ranking submitted by X.

Note that if candidate C bullet votes, then the supporters of candidate C who 
have strong opinions about 
second and third choices will have significant incentive to submit approval 
ballots.

Once the approval ballots have been used in this way to help fill out the 
rankings, we restore full weight 
to each of them for the final approval count..

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA clarification

2011-07-08 Thread Andy Jennings
On Thu, Jul 7, 2011 at 8:33 AM, Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.comwrote:

 Andy, I like both of your suggestions. Why don't you try putting them on the
 pagehttp://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/Simple_Optionally-Delegated_Approvalyourself?
  I don't want this system or that page to be mine, I just want
 them to be good.


Okay, I changed the Wiki.  I'll try to give it a second look tomorrow to see
if I want to re-word anything.




 2011/7/7 Andy Jennings electi...@jenningsstory.com

 Jameson,

 I'm really liking the SODA method that is evolving.  I have a couple of
 cosmetic suggestions:

 First, in the description of SODA, I dislike using the term delegate for
 step 3, candidate-to-candidate transfers.  I would only use the word
 delegate for step 2, the bullet voters' votes getting delegated to their
 candidates.  I prefer to think of step 3 as the candidates casting their
 votes (which includes all the delegated votes they control).  It's a much
 simpler mental model for me.  Since they aren't passing anything on to
 another candidate which can be changed or controlled, I don't consider it
 delegation.  Also, it decreases the implication of smoke-filled rooms (for
 me) to have as little delegation as possible.  I think this terminology
 was why I was confused about step 3 in a prior email.

 Second, I find it incredibly confusing to say you have to write in do not
 delegate if you bullet vote and you don't want your vote delegated.  I
 realize that you want delegation to be the default for bullet voters.  Why
 not organize the ballot with that as a separate question (as follows)?

 
 Vote for as many candidates as you approve:

 [ ] Candidate A
 [ ] Candidate B
 [ ] Candidate C
 [ ] Candidate D
 [ ] ___(write-in)_
 [ ] ___(write-in)_
 [ ] ___(write-in)_

 If you only vote for one candidate, he can choose to transfer his vote to
 one or more alternate candidates in the event that he cannot win, UNLESS you
 check the box below:

 [ ] Do not let the candidate I voted for transfer my vote to other
 candidates
 

 Andy




 On Wed, Jul 6, 2011 at 8:54 AM, Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.comwrote:



 2011/7/6 Andy Jennings electi...@jenningsstory.com

 Jameson,

 I have become confused about one point of operation in SODA.  Take this
 scenario:

 35 ABC
 34 BCA
 31 CAB

 If A delegates to A,B then does B have 69 votes he can delegate to B,C
 or does he have only 34 he can play with?

 In other words, can votes delegated from one candidate to another be
 re-delegated to a third candidate?


 B has 34. Delegable votes are only bullet votes. In fact, a real SODA
 scenario would probably be more like:

 25 A (B)
 5 A,X
 5 A,B
  26 B (C)
 4 B,X
 4 B, C
 29 C (A)
 1 C,X
 1 C,A
 Initial totals: 36A, 39B, 35C
 Delegable: 25A, 26B, 29C

 Note that in this example, C has the most delegable votes and would
 decide delegation first, even though B has the most total initial votes. In
 this case - a Condorcet cycle - the result would be the same no matter who
 delegates first, as long as all candidates use correct strategy. But there
 are cases where it wouldn't be:

 25: Left (X)
 15: Left, Center
 5: Left, Right
 25: Center (Right)
 30: Right (Center)

 The candidate Left has not declared any delegable preferences, but the
 left voters clearly tend to prefer Center over Right. Center is the
 Condorcet winner, but Right would get the chance to delegate before Center,
 and thus would be the strategic winner under SODA. If delegation order went
 in order of total votes instead of delegable votes, Center would win.

 Hmm... now that I look at this scenario in black and white, I'm starting
 to think that delegation order should be in order of total, not delegable,
 votes. Not that there isn't a case to be made for Right in this election; if
 Center were really a better result, then they should get either Left's
 delegation or more delegable votes from the nominally voters who chose
 [Left, Center] here. This argument like FairVote's handwaving arguments
 about strength of support - which is not necessarily invalid just because
 it's imprecise and easy to reduce ad absurdem. But... I think that having
 this scenario go to Right puts too much of a burden of strategic calculation
 on the [Left, Center] voters.

 So, yet another adjustment to SODA, I think. Delegation choice goes in
 descending order of total votes; the person with the most total votes gets
 the first move. If my grounded intuition is correct, this should not
 matter when there's a 3-way cycle, only when there's a pairwise champion
 (CW).

 Hopefully this will be the last time I have to adjust SODA. Also note
 that all the adjustments so far have been minor tweaks; any of the versions
 so far would work well, though I believe they have been steadily improving.
 Current rules, as always, are at
 http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/Simple_Optionally-Delegated_Approval

 JQ


 I looked at the wiki and still am unclear on this.  I 

Re: [EM] SODA

2011-07-08 Thread Andy Jennings
This is not an answer to the question of how to arrange them into a tree,
but here is an idea for how to compare factions of different sizes:

If there are N total candidates, then the score of a faction (a subset of
candidates) of size M could be the voter count of that faction (the number
of voters who ranked those candidates strictly above all other candidates)
divided by the expected size of a faction of size M (total number of voters
divided by N choose M).

Then you could identify the weakest candidate in the strongest faction and
make him go first, or something like that.


In general, since it seems like an disadvantage to go first, to me it
doesn't seem right to make the strongest candidate go first.  Jameson, is
the main thing you're trying to avoid the game of chicken between two
clones?  Or are you trying to avoid the game of chicken and the kingmaker
problem at the same time?

Andy

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA

2011-07-08 Thread Andy Jennings
Here's an off-the-wall idea.  Haven't fully thought through the strategic
implications, but here goes:

What if, instead of requiring the candidates to vote sequentially, they all
have to go at the same time, but we introduce another level between
approve and don't approve which is conditional approval or approve
this candidate only if he approves me.  (I don't yet know how this fits in
with the candidates' pre-specified rankings.)

These are resolved on a pairwise basis.  If A approves B and B conditionally
approves A, then that is converted into full approval.  If A and B both
conditionally approve each other, then that should be converted into mutual
full approval.

Thoughts?

Andy

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA

2011-07-08 Thread fsimmons
You're right, the same example dawned on me last night after I used up all of 
my computer time.

But the Hasse diagram of the partial order does yield a weighted DAG (directed 
acyclic graph) where the 
weight of each coalition is the sum of the weights of the factions that are 
included in it.  If we agree that 
edges are directed from coalition to subcoalition, then the only source is the 
set of all factions. [A 
source is a node that has at least one edge leaving it, but no edge entering 
it; i.e. indegree=0, 
outdegree0.]

Here's how to order the factions:

While there remains at least one edge in the graph ..
remove the heaviest edge leaving the most recently exposed source.
EndWhile

The factions play in the order that they are exposed.

[The weight of an edge is the weight of the node that it enters.  A node is 
exposed at the stage its 
indegree reaches zero. In the original DAG the only source is considered to be 
the most recently 
exposed source.]

This generalizes the order that I gave for trees, i.e.if the DAG is a tree, 
this order agrees with the order 
that I gave for that case.

It is clear that this algorithm takes O(n) steps where n is the number of edges 
in the DAG.



- Original Message -
From: Jameson Quinn 
  The Hasse diagram for a partially ordered set is a tree.
 
 
 No, it's not. Or at least, not if I understand your terms 
 correctly. If
 there are three candidates [ABC], and all vote types exist, then 
 is [A] a
 leaf on the [AB] branch or on the [AC] branch?
 
 JQ
 

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA

2011-07-07 Thread Jameson Quinn
Here's the scenario you used to first show your tree method of determining
delegation order.

16 A1A2B
12 A2A1B
24 BA1=A2
48 C

What if some candidate outside the A1 A2 faction had an A2A1 preference? I
mean either:
Scenario S
16 A1A2B
12 A2A1B
24 BA2A1
48 C

Or:
Scenario T
16 A1A2B
12 A2A1B
24 BA1=A2
43 C
5 CA2

Or even:
Scenario U
16 A1A2B
12 A2A1B
24 BA1=A2
43 C
5 A2C

I believe that A2 should go first in all of the above scenarios. Thus, you'd
use the worst relevant pairwise WV totals over the whole electorate to
determine order within a coalition. For two-member coalitions, that's just
the pairwise WV between them; for a three-member, cycled coalition, it's
minimax WV; and for a coalition of two multi-member subcoalitions, it's the
worst WV of a member of subcoalition X over a member of subcoalition Y and
vice versa. That is, in all cases, lower-bounded by the coalition size, but
it can go higher, as it does in the three scenarios I gave above.



I like this coalition tree method as a theoretical way of making a
cloneproof SODA. However, for SODA as a practical proposal, it's too much
complication for too little benefit. SODA is already proof against simple
pairs of clones, and I don't think that larger clouds of clones without one
stand-out winner will ever be a factor in a real election. Certainly I can't
think of any historical election where this would have mattered, even
including serious 4-way elections like US 1860 or Romania 2009.

JQ

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA

2011-07-07 Thread Andy Jennings
On Wed, Jul 6, 2011 at 6:06 PM, fsimm...@pcc.edu wrote:


 Of course, with too many factions, the optimal strategy computation would
 be intractable.


With twenty candidates, there are about a million different possible subsets
to consider.  Seems like it could be tractable.

I'm not exactly following how the tree is organized.  If there are N
candidates and every voter ranks all candidates, then the biggest N-1 size
faction will be the one that omits the candidate who is ranked last by the
most voters, right?  Can't you apply that recursively to build the tree?

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA clarification

2011-07-07 Thread Andy Jennings
Jameson,

I'm really liking the SODA method that is evolving.  I have a couple of
cosmetic suggestions:

First, in the description of SODA, I dislike using the term delegate for
step 3, candidate-to-candidate transfers.  I would only use the word
delegate for step 2, the bullet voters' votes getting delegated to their
candidates.  I prefer to think of step 3 as the candidates casting their
votes (which includes all the delegated votes they control).  It's a much
simpler mental model for me.  Since they aren't passing anything on to
another candidate which can be changed or controlled, I don't consider it
delegation.  Also, it decreases the implication of smoke-filled rooms (for
me) to have as little delegation as possible.  I think this terminology
was why I was confused about step 3 in a prior email.

Second, I find it incredibly confusing to say you have to write in do not
delegate if you bullet vote and you don't want your vote delegated.  I
realize that you want delegation to be the default for bullet voters.  Why
not organize the ballot with that as a separate question (as follows)?


Vote for as many candidates as you approve:

[ ] Candidate A
[ ] Candidate B
[ ] Candidate C
[ ] Candidate D
[ ] ___(write-in)_
[ ] ___(write-in)_
[ ] ___(write-in)_

If you only vote for one candidate, he can choose to transfer his vote to
one or more alternate candidates in the event that he cannot win, UNLESS you
check the box below:

[ ] Do not let the candidate I voted for transfer my vote to other
candidates


Andy




On Wed, Jul 6, 2011 at 8:54 AM, Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.comwrote:



 2011/7/6 Andy Jennings electi...@jenningsstory.com

 Jameson,

 I have become confused about one point of operation in SODA.  Take this
 scenario:

 35 ABC
 34 BCA
 31 CAB

 If A delegates to A,B then does B have 69 votes he can delegate to B,C or
 does he have only 34 he can play with?

 In other words, can votes delegated from one candidate to another be
 re-delegated to a third candidate?


 B has 34. Delegable votes are only bullet votes. In fact, a real SODA
 scenario would probably be more like:

 25 A (B)
 5 A,X
 5 A,B
  26 B (C)
 4 B,X
 4 B, C
 29 C (A)
 1 C,X
 1 C,A
 Initial totals: 36A, 39B, 35C
 Delegable: 25A, 26B, 29C

 Note that in this example, C has the most delegable votes and would decide
 delegation first, even though B has the most total initial votes. In this
 case - a Condorcet cycle - the result would be the same no matter who
 delegates first, as long as all candidates use correct strategy. But there
 are cases where it wouldn't be:

 25: Left (X)
 15: Left, Center
 5: Left, Right
 25: Center (Right)
 30: Right (Center)

 The candidate Left has not declared any delegable preferences, but the left
 voters clearly tend to prefer Center over Right. Center is the Condorcet
 winner, but Right would get the chance to delegate before Center, and thus
 would be the strategic winner under SODA. If delegation order went in order
 of total votes instead of delegable votes, Center would win.

 Hmm... now that I look at this scenario in black and white, I'm starting to
 think that delegation order should be in order of total, not delegable,
 votes. Not that there isn't a case to be made for Right in this election; if
 Center were really a better result, then they should get either Left's
 delegation or more delegable votes from the nominally voters who chose
 [Left, Center] here. This argument like FairVote's handwaving arguments
 about strength of support - which is not necessarily invalid just because
 it's imprecise and easy to reduce ad absurdem. But... I think that having
 this scenario go to Right puts too much of a burden of strategic calculation
 on the [Left, Center] voters.

 So, yet another adjustment to SODA, I think. Delegation choice goes in
 descending order of total votes; the person with the most total votes gets
 the first move. If my grounded intuition is correct, this should not
 matter when there's a 3-way cycle, only when there's a pairwise champion
 (CW).

 Hopefully this will be the last time I have to adjust SODA. Also note that
 all the adjustments so far have been minor tweaks; any of the versions so
 far would work well, though I believe they have been steadily improving.
 Current rules, as always, are at
 http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/Simple_Optionally-Delegated_Approval

 JQ


 I looked at the wiki and still am unclear on this.  I still have the
 original SODA proposal in my head (where votes could not be delegated
 multiple times) and I can't remember if we've changed this detail at some
 point.

 Thanks,

 Andy



 On Tue, Jul 5, 2011 at 12:39 PM, Jameson Quinn 
 jameson.qu...@gmail.comwrote:

 Russ, you said that SODA was too complicated. In my prior message, I
 responded by saying that it was actually pretty simple. But thanks for your
 feedback; I realize that the SODA page was not conveying that simplicity
 well. I've changed the 

Re: [EM] SODA clarification

2011-07-07 Thread Jameson Quinn
Andy, I like both of your suggestions. Why don't you try putting them on the
page 
http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/Simple_Optionally-Delegated_Approvalyourself?
I don't want this system or that page to be mine, I just want
them to be good.

2011/7/7 Andy Jennings electi...@jenningsstory.com

 Jameson,

 I'm really liking the SODA method that is evolving.  I have a couple of
 cosmetic suggestions:

 First, in the description of SODA, I dislike using the term delegate for
 step 3, candidate-to-candidate transfers.  I would only use the word
 delegate for step 2, the bullet voters' votes getting delegated to their
 candidates.  I prefer to think of step 3 as the candidates casting their
 votes (which includes all the delegated votes they control).  It's a much
 simpler mental model for me.  Since they aren't passing anything on to
 another candidate which can be changed or controlled, I don't consider it
 delegation.  Also, it decreases the implication of smoke-filled rooms (for
 me) to have as little delegation as possible.  I think this terminology
 was why I was confused about step 3 in a prior email.

 Second, I find it incredibly confusing to say you have to write in do not
 delegate if you bullet vote and you don't want your vote delegated.  I
 realize that you want delegation to be the default for bullet voters.  Why
 not organize the ballot with that as a separate question (as follows)?

 
 Vote for as many candidates as you approve:

 [ ] Candidate A
 [ ] Candidate B
 [ ] Candidate C
 [ ] Candidate D
 [ ] ___(write-in)_
 [ ] ___(write-in)_
 [ ] ___(write-in)_

 If you only vote for one candidate, he can choose to transfer his vote to
 one or more alternate candidates in the event that he cannot win, UNLESS you
 check the box below:

 [ ] Do not let the candidate I voted for transfer my vote to other
 candidates
 

 Andy




 On Wed, Jul 6, 2011 at 8:54 AM, Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.comwrote:



 2011/7/6 Andy Jennings electi...@jenningsstory.com

 Jameson,

 I have become confused about one point of operation in SODA.  Take this
 scenario:

 35 ABC
 34 BCA
 31 CAB

 If A delegates to A,B then does B have 69 votes he can delegate to B,C or
 does he have only 34 he can play with?

 In other words, can votes delegated from one candidate to another be
 re-delegated to a third candidate?


 B has 34. Delegable votes are only bullet votes. In fact, a real SODA
 scenario would probably be more like:

 25 A (B)
 5 A,X
 5 A,B
  26 B (C)
 4 B,X
 4 B, C
 29 C (A)
 1 C,X
 1 C,A
 Initial totals: 36A, 39B, 35C
 Delegable: 25A, 26B, 29C

 Note that in this example, C has the most delegable votes and would decide
 delegation first, even though B has the most total initial votes. In this
 case - a Condorcet cycle - the result would be the same no matter who
 delegates first, as long as all candidates use correct strategy. But there
 are cases where it wouldn't be:

 25: Left (X)
 15: Left, Center
 5: Left, Right
 25: Center (Right)
 30: Right (Center)

 The candidate Left has not declared any delegable preferences, but the
 left voters clearly tend to prefer Center over Right. Center is the
 Condorcet winner, but Right would get the chance to delegate before Center,
 and thus would be the strategic winner under SODA. If delegation order went
 in order of total votes instead of delegable votes, Center would win.

 Hmm... now that I look at this scenario in black and white, I'm starting
 to think that delegation order should be in order of total, not delegable,
 votes. Not that there isn't a case to be made for Right in this election; if
 Center were really a better result, then they should get either Left's
 delegation or more delegable votes from the nominally voters who chose
 [Left, Center] here. This argument like FairVote's handwaving arguments
 about strength of support - which is not necessarily invalid just because
 it's imprecise and easy to reduce ad absurdem. But... I think that having
 this scenario go to Right puts too much of a burden of strategic calculation
 on the [Left, Center] voters.

 So, yet another adjustment to SODA, I think. Delegation choice goes in
 descending order of total votes; the person with the most total votes gets
 the first move. If my grounded intuition is correct, this should not
 matter when there's a 3-way cycle, only when there's a pairwise champion
 (CW).

 Hopefully this will be the last time I have to adjust SODA. Also note that
 all the adjustments so far have been minor tweaks; any of the versions so
 far would work well, though I believe they have been steadily improving.
 Current rules, as always, are at
 http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/Simple_Optionally-Delegated_Approval

 JQ


 I looked at the wiki and still am unclear on this.  I still have the
 original SODA proposal in my head (where votes could not be delegated
 multiple times) and I can't remember if we've changed this detail at some
 point.

 Thanks,

 Andy



 On 

Re: [EM] SODA

2011-07-07 Thread Jameson Quinn
2011/7/7 Andy Jennings electi...@jenningsstory.com

 On Wed, Jul 6, 2011 at 6:06 PM, fsimm...@pcc.edu wrote:


 Of course, with too many factions, the optimal strategy computation would
 be intractable.


 With twenty candidates, there are about a million different possible
 subsets to consider.  Seems like it could be tractable.

 I'm not exactly following how the tree is organized.  If there are N
 candidates and every voter ranks all candidates, then the biggest N-1 size
 faction will be the one that omits the candidate who is ranked last by the
 most voters, right?  Can't you apply that recursively to build the tree?


But wouldn't you prefer to find the biggest faction of a size around N/2? I
must admit, I'm also confused. It's easy with toy examples, but I can't
understand what Forest means for a broad set of candidates.

Here's one rule that might work: to divide a coalition, take the broadest
(most candidates) strict sub-coalition that is larger (more voters) than any
strict sub-coalition which is as broad or broader. That will be N-1 in a
non-partisan, clone-free election, but I think it will still find any
natural coalitions.

JQ

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA

2011-07-07 Thread fsimmons


- Original Message -
From: Andy Jennings 
 
  Of course, with too many factions, the optimal strategy 
 computation would
  be intractable.
 
 
 With twenty candidates, there are about a million different 
 possible subsets
 to consider. Seems like it could be tractable.

Building the tree and finding the order of play is tractable, but computing the 
optimal strategy is 
intractable.

Suppose there are twenty candidates, then each candidate has 19 choices of 
where to put her approval 
cutoff in her ranking of the candidates.  That makes 19^20 possibilities.  
Precisely one of these will be 
optimal for the given order of play.   So Jameson is right; it is better to not 
compute the optimal strategy 
automatically; just let the candidates play the chess game the best they can.

However, when it gets down to the last five players, there will be only 19^5 
possibilities left, and these 
could be done automatically in order to completely remove the temptation for a 
potential kingmaker to 
throw the election for some personal gain.



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA

2011-07-07 Thread Jameson Quinn
2011/7/7 fsimm...@pcc.edu



 - Original Message -
 From: Andy Jennings
  
   Of course, with too many factions, the optimal strategy
  computation would
   be intractable.
  
 
  With twenty candidates, there are about a million different
  possible subsets
  to consider. Seems like it could be tractable.

 Building the tree and finding the order of play is tractable,


That may be so, but I still don't understand what algorithm you're
proposing.


 but computing the optimal strategy is
 intractable.


 Suppose there are twenty candidates, then each candidate has 19 choices of
 where to put her approval
 cutoff in her ranking of the candidates.  That makes 19^20 possibilities.
  Precisely one of these will be
 optimal for the given order of play.   So Jameson is right; it is better to
 not compute the optimal strategy
 automatically; just let the candidates play the chess game the best they
 can.

 However, when it gets down to the last five players, there will be only
 19^5 possibilities left, and these
 could be done automatically in order to completely remove the temptation
 for a potential kingmaker to
 throw the election for some personal gain.


Actually, if you assume only the top five vote-getters are viable -
generally justified from the outset in real elections - then there are only
5^19 possibilities, and some good chess-playing algorithms could prune that
tree to tractability.

But the reason I said we should let the candidates do it rather than
computing wasn't computability; it was to prevent pre-election strategy
(principally burial) for candidates.

JQ

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA

2011-07-07 Thread fsimmons
A correction below at ***

- Original Message -
From: 
Date: Thursday, July 7, 2011 5:16 pm
Subject: Re: [EM] SODA
To: Jameson Quinn ,
Cc: Andy Jennings , election-methods@lists.electorama.com,

 
 
 - Original Message -
 From: Jameson Quinn 
  2011/7/7 Andy Jennings 
  
   On Wed, Jul 6, 2011 at 6:06 PM, wrote:
  
  
   Of course, with too many factions, the optimal strategy 
  computation would
   be intractable.
  
  
   With twenty candidates, there are about a million different 
 possible  subsets to consider. Seems like it could be tractable.
  
   I'm not exactly following how the tree is organized. If 
 there 
  are N
   candidates and every voter ranks all candidates, then the 
  biggest N-1 size
   faction will be the one that omits the candidate who is 
 ranked 
  last by the
   most voters, right? Can't you apply that recursively to 
 build 
  the tree?
  
  
  But wouldn't you prefer to find the biggest faction of a size 
  around N/2? I
  must admit, I'm also confused. It's easy with toy examples, 
 but 
  I can't
  understand what Forest means for a broad set of candidates.
  
 
 Once we define precisely what we mean by coalition, the 
 coalition tree practically builds itself, and the traversal 
 order is found in O(n) steps.
 
 Let's say a faction is a (multi)set of identical ballots, so the 
 atoms of coalitions are weighted factions, where the weight of a 
 faction is the number of ballots in the faction. [These atoms 
 with their weights will be the leaves of the weighted coalition tree.]
 
 Suppose that two or more factions share some initial segment of 
 candidates in any order. Then all of the factions that rank no 
 candidate outside that set above any candidate in that set form 
 a coalition.
 
 In other words, the coalition C(S) based on a subset S of 
 candidates is the set of all factions that do not rank any 
 candidate outside of S ahead of any candidate inside S. The 
 weight of the W(S) of C(S) is the sum of the weights of the 
 factions in C(S).
 
 The set of all candidate coalitions is partially ordered by 
 containment. If C(S) contains C(S'), then C(S') is a 
 subcoalition of C(S).
 
 The Hasse diagram for a partially ordered set is a tree. In our 
 case the coalitions are the nodes of the tree, and the weights 
 of the coalitions make it into a weighted tree. 


***
 The universal 
 coalition consisting of all of the candidates is the root node. 
 Its weight is the total number of ballots. The leaves of the 
 tree are the atoms of the coalitions, i.e. the factions themselves.

This paragraph should read ...

The universal coalition consisting of all of the factions is the root node.  
Its weight is the sum of all of the 
faction weights, i.e. the total number of ballots.  The leaves of the tree are 
the atoms of the coalitions, 
i.e. the factions themselves.

 
 To find the sequence of play for the ideal version of SODA, 
 starting at the root node recursively order the leaves of the 
 daughter nodes and concatenate them together in descending order 
 of weight of the daughter nodes.
 
 There's probably a name for this order of traversal of a 
 weighted tree.
 
 Does anybody know it? If so, you can look for an efficient cook 
 book algorithm for computing the order of the leaves.
 
 Does that help?
 

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA

2011-07-07 Thread Jameson Quinn
 The Hasse diagram for a partially ordered set is a tree.


No, it's not. Or at least, not if I understand your terms correctly. If
there are three candidates [ABC], and all vote types exist, then is [A] a
leaf on the [AB] branch or on the [AC] branch?

 JQ

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA clarification

2011-07-06 Thread Jameson Quinn
2011/7/6 Andy Jennings electi...@jenningsstory.com

 Jameson,

 I have become confused about one point of operation in SODA.  Take this
 scenario:

 35 ABC
 34 BCA
 31 CAB

 If A delegates to A,B then does B have 69 votes he can delegate to B,C or
 does he have only 34 he can play with?

 In other words, can votes delegated from one candidate to another be
 re-delegated to a third candidate?


B has 34. Delegable votes are only bullet votes. In fact, a real SODA
scenario would probably be more like:

25 A (B)
5 A,X
5 A,B
26 B (C)
4 B,X
4 B, C
29 C (A)
1 C,X
1 C,A
Initial totals: 36A, 39B, 35C
Delegable: 25A, 26B, 29C

Note that in this example, C has the most delegable votes and would decide
delegation first, even though B has the most total initial votes. In this
case - a Condorcet cycle - the result would be the same no matter who
delegates first, as long as all candidates use correct strategy. But there
are cases where it wouldn't be:

25: Left (X)
15: Left, Center
5: Left, Right
25: Center (Right)
30: Right (Center)

The candidate Left has not declared any delegable preferences, but the left
voters clearly tend to prefer Center over Right. Center is the Condorcet
winner, but Right would get the chance to delegate before Center, and thus
would be the strategic winner under SODA. If delegation order went in order
of total votes instead of delegable votes, Center would win.

Hmm... now that I look at this scenario in black and white, I'm starting to
think that delegation order should be in order of total, not delegable,
votes. Not that there isn't a case to be made for Right in this election; if
Center were really a better result, then they should get either Left's
delegation or more delegable votes from the nominally voters who chose
[Left, Center] here. This argument like FairVote's handwaving arguments
about strength of support - which is not necessarily invalid just because
it's imprecise and easy to reduce ad absurdem. But... I think that having
this scenario go to Right puts too much of a burden of strategic calculation
on the [Left, Center] voters.

So, yet another adjustment to SODA, I think. Delegation choice goes in
descending order of total votes; the person with the most total votes gets
the first move. If my grounded intuition is correct, this should not
matter when there's a 3-way cycle, only when there's a pairwise champion
(CW).

Hopefully this will be the last time I have to adjust SODA. Also note that
all the adjustments so far have been minor tweaks; any of the versions so
far would work well, though I believe they have been steadily improving.
Current rules, as always, are at
http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/Simple_Optionally-Delegated_Approval

JQ


 I looked at the wiki and still am unclear on this.  I still have the
 original SODA proposal in my head (where votes could not be delegated
 multiple times) and I can't remember if we've changed this detail at some
 point.

 Thanks,

 Andy



 On Tue, Jul 5, 2011 at 12:39 PM, Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.comwrote:

 Russ, you said that SODA was too complicated. In my prior message, I
 responded by saying that it was actually pretty simple. But thanks for your
 feedback; I realize that the SODA page was not conveying that simplicity
 well. I've changed the procedure there from 8 individual steps to 4 steps -
 simple one-sentence overviews - with the details in sub-steps. Of these 4
 steps, only step 1 is not in your proposal. And the whole of step 4 is just
 three words.

 The procedure is exactly the same, but I hope that this 
 versionhttp://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/Simple_Optionally-Delegated_Approval#Proceduredoes
  a better job of communicating the purpose and underlying simplicity of
 the system.

 Thanks,
 Jameson

 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list
 info




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA

2011-07-06 Thread fsimmons
Yes, you are right!

Now I would like to suggest a way to make this method clone proof:

The key is to use the solid coalition structure of the factions to determine 
the sequential order of play 
(i.e. delegation), from largest coalition to smallest.  I believe that 
completely solves the problem.

Here's an example where A got split into A1 and A2. 

16 A1A2B
12 A2A1B
24 BA1=A2
48 C

Even though the C faction is the biggest faction, and the A1 faction is the 
second smallest faction, 
candidate A1 is the first to delegate in this new order.  Here's why:

The largest coaltion (besides the entire set of factions) is the coalition made 
up of the set of factions 
{A1, A2, B} with 52 percent of the electorate (versus 48 percent for the 
coalition {C faction}).  Within the 
large coalition, the largest subcoalition is {A1, A2} with 26 percent of the 
entire electorate (versus 24 
percent for the coalition {B faction}).

Within this subcoalition the larger of the two subcoalitions is the A1 faction. 
 Since there are no further 
subcoalitions, candidate A1 plays first.

Then A2 goes next, because we finish the {A1, A2} subcoalition (which was 
larger than the B 
subcoalition) before letting B play. C goes last because at the root of the 
coalition tree C was the branch 
on the smaller side.

In sum the order of play is A1, A2, B, C.

The process of deciding the order of play can be summarized more succinctly 
with a recursive 
description:

Start at the root of the coalition tree, and recursively order the leaves (i.e. 
the individual factions) of the 
respective branches in descending order of the branch sizes.

I think that in selling the method, we can make the precise sequential order a 
technical detail easily 
glossed over by simply referring to it as the natural clone independent 
sequential order, or something 
like that.


- Original Message -
From: Jameson Quinn 
Date: Tuesday, July 5, 2011 7:25 pm
Subject: Re: [EM] SODA
To: fsimm...@pcc.edu
Cc: election-methods@lists.electorama.com

 2011/7/5, fsimm...@pcc.edu :
 
  I thought that A was required to make her approvals consistent 
 with her
  ordering, i.e. to approve
  everybody ranked above her cutoff. Doesn't that mean she is 
 required to
  approve herself?
 
  Maybe I'm thinking of an older version of SODA.
 
  I hope you are right that there is nothing to fix.
 
 Let's do this slowly. Here's the scenario:
 
 34 ABC
 35 BCA
 31 CAB,
 
 B delegates first. B delegates to B,C. Totals are now C 66, B35, A34.
 A's turn. If A does not delegate, C will be winning when it 
 comes to
 C's turn, and so C will not delegate. So A delegates to A,B. Totals
 are now B69, C66, A34. C's turn. C is unhappy with B and so delegates
 to C,A - but it's not enough. Final totals are B69, C66, A65.
 
 I believe that the correct strategy for any combination of delegable
 and undelegable votes (including minor, non-Smith candidates) in a
 3-candidate Smith set is always for everyone to approve two 
 members of
 the Smith set if they care between the bottom two. This gives 
 the same
 result as minimax and most Condorcet methods. I haven't proven this,
 and I don't have a general understanding of strategy for larger Smith
 sets.
 
 It is possible, when there are 3 or more near-clones A1, A2, A3...
 running against a different candidate B with almost 50% - that 
 is, B
 can beat any combination of fewer than all the A's, and B has no
 preference among the A's - that the true Condorcet winner among the
 A's is subject to center squeeze, and the A's are forced to throw
 their support to whichever of them has the most delegable votes, in
 order to prevent B from winning. The upshot is that SODA, even
 assuming candidates are honest in their pre-vote rankings and
 strategic in their delegation, does not pass the Condorcet criterion,
 but does pass the majority Condorcet criterion (that is, a pairwise
 winner always wins if each of the pairwise wins constitutes a
 majority). But I can't find any nonmonotonic scenario pairs, so this
 Plurality within the faction is the worst result I can find. I think
 that it's both unlikely and, really, not so bad.
 
 JQ
 
 
 
  - Original Message -
  From: Jameson Quinn
  Date: Tuesday, July 5, 2011 1:07 pm
  Subject: Re: [EM] SODA
  To: fsimm...@pcc.edu
  Cc: election-methods@lists.electorama.com
 
  2011/7/5
 
   Jameson suggested that the SODA candidates make their approval
  decisions sequentially instead of
   simultaneously.
  
   The problem with this is that if a winning candidate moves to
  first place
   in the sequence by an increase
   in support, she may become a losing candidate:
  
   Assume sincere preferences are
  
   35 ABC
   34 BCA
   31 CAB
  
   If approval decisions are made in descending order of faction
  size A, B, C,
   then B wins.
  
   If B gains more support so that the totals become
  
   34 ABC
   35 BCA
   31 CAB,
  
   the sequential order becomes B, A, C, and the winner will 
 be C

Re: [EM] SODA

2011-07-06 Thread Jameson Quinn
2011/7/6 fsimm...@pcc.edu

 By the way, when the delegations are done sequentially, the optimum
 strategy for each player is
 (generically) deterministic.  No mixed strategies are needed to get optimum
 game theoretic results.


Yes, that's the point.



 Because of this, a DSV (Delegated Strategy Voting) version would give the
 same result as rational
 players.


Yes, but I don't recommend actually using the DSV version. Having candidates
actually decide is a safeguard against candidates using dishonest strategy
in the ranking - the only phase when dishonest strategy is possible.



 Therefore, we finally have a monotone, clone free, DSV that takes rankings
 as input, and puts out
 rationally determined approval ballots.


Well, you'd have to impute the most popular ranking among a candidate's
voters to the candidate, and either use some direct approval strategy or
make fake candidates for all other rankings among a candidate's voters...
and that breaks the nice symmetry of the method somewhat, but none of it
should break the monotonicity or the clone-freeness.



 This should be of interest to Rob LeGrand, who has done a lot of study on
 DSV methods that turn
 rankings into approval ballots.

 Furthermore, this gives us a way of generating Yee diagrams for SODA, i.e.
 to make Yee diagrams for
 Approval without just assuming that Approval will always find the Condorcet
 winner.


Yes, that is true, with the caveats above.

JQ

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA

2011-07-06 Thread fsimmons
   Therefore, we finally have a monotone, clone free, DSV that 
 takes rankings
  as input, and puts out
  rationally determined approval ballots.
 
 
 Well, you'd have to impute the most popular ranking among a 
 candidate'svoters to the candidate, and either use some direct 
 approval strategy or
 make fake candidates for all other rankings among a candidate's 
 voters...and that breaks the nice symmetry of the method 
 somewhat, but none of it
 should break the monotonicity or the clone-freeness.

Actually, the same coalition tree technique would work for as many factions as 
desired, outputing a 
(potentially) different approval ballot for each faction, even when several 
different factions have the same 
favorite.

Of course, with too many factions, the optimal strategy computation would be 
intractable.

Let's see how it would work on the simple example

45 BCA.
15 CBA
30 ACB
10 CAB

The coalition tree is  (45BCA /\15CBA)/root\(30ACB /\ 10CAB).

I have ordered the factions so that traversing the tree in its preorder gives 
the correct sequence.

At the root node the left branch accounts for 60 percent of the ballots, while 
the right branch accounts 
for 40 percent, so the left branch is rightfully traversed first (as in a 
preorder traversal), etc.

Since there are two approval cutoff possibilities for each faction, there are 
sixteen possible cutoff 
configurations.

I'm not going to list them all, but (if I am not grossly mistaken) the 
(essentially) unique optimal solution is

45B, 15C, 30 AC, 10 C, 

which gives approval totals for A, B, and C as
30, 45, and 55, respectively.

I say essentially because it makes no difference whether the BCA faction 
approves C or not.

In the long run any of Rob LeGrand's DSV (Designated Strategy Voting) methods 
(whether batch or 
sequential, whether strategy A or not) would yield approvals in the same 
proportion for this particular 
example..

Our coalition tree based method uses the same solid coalition structure as 
Woodall's Descending Solid 
Coalition (DSC) method, but soon parts company with DSC, although in this 
particular example it yields 
the same result, namely that C wins.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] SODA

2011-07-05 Thread fsimmons
Jameson suggested that the SODA candidates make their approval decisions 
sequentially instead of 
simultaneously.

The problem with this is that if a winning candidate moves to first place in 
the sequence by an increase 
in support, she may become a losing candidate:

Assume sincere preferences are

35 ABC
34 BCA
31 CAB

If approval decisions are made in descending order of faction size A, B, C, 
then B wins.

If B gains more support so that the totals become

34 ABC
35 BCA
31 CAB,

the sequential order becomes B, A, C, and the winner will be C.

Going from smallest to largest has its problems, too.  I don't think it fixes 
the monotonicity problem, and 
it introduces other problems like changing what would be the game of chicken in 
the simultaneous case 
into a clear cut win for the smaller faction:

49 C
27 AB
24 BA

In the simultaneous case there is a game of chicken between A and B.

In the sequential case whichever member of the set {A,B} goes first wins.

How can we fix this?

How about allowing the largest faction (in this example 49 C) to go second, and 
making the second 
largest faction (in this example 27 AB) go first?

That would also work in the example above.  How bad would it be in a worst case 
example?

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA

2011-07-05 Thread Jameson Quinn
2011/7/5 fsimm...@pcc.edu

 Jameson suggested that the SODA candidates make their approval decisions
 sequentially instead of
 simultaneously.

 The problem with this is that if a winning candidate moves to first place
 in the sequence by an increase
 in support, she may become a losing candidate:

 Assume sincere preferences are

 35 ABC
 34 BCA
 31 CAB

 If approval decisions are made in descending order of faction size A, B, C,
 then B wins.

 If B gains more support so that the totals become

 34 ABC
 35 BCA
 31 CAB,

 the sequential order becomes B, A, C, and the winner will be C.


No. B still wins. If A feels that C is winning, then A can delegate to B,
and then B cannot lose. So C cannot be the winner. And therefore B will
delegate to C, to force A's hand. Whether or not C delegates then is
irrelevant.

Of course, if A actually prefers C to B, and has managed to keep B ignorant
of this fact, then C will win. But then, in such a case, A could have gotten
the same result by being honest from the start.



 How can we fix this?


I don't think there's anything that needs fixing, though you may find
another example to show I'm wrong.


 How about allowing the largest faction (in this example 49 C) to go second,
 and making the second
 largest faction (in this example 27 AB) go first?

 That would also work in the example above.  How bad would it be in a worst
 case example?
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA

2011-07-05 Thread fsimmons

I thought that A was required to make her approvals consistent with her 
ordering, i.e. to approve 
everybody ranked above her cutoff.  Doesn't that mean she is required to 
approve herself?

Maybe I'm thinking of an older version of SODA.

I hope you are right that there is nothing to fix.


- Original Message -
From: Jameson Quinn 
Date: Tuesday, July 5, 2011 1:07 pm
Subject: Re: [EM] SODA
To: fsimm...@pcc.edu
Cc: election-methods@lists.electorama.com

 2011/7/5 
 
  Jameson suggested that the SODA candidates make their approval 
 decisions sequentially instead of
  simultaneously.
 
  The problem with this is that if a winning candidate moves to 
 first place
  in the sequence by an increase
  in support, she may become a losing candidate:
 
  Assume sincere preferences are
 
  35 ABC
  34 BCA
  31 CAB
 
  If approval decisions are made in descending order of faction 
 size A, B, C,
  then B wins.
 
  If B gains more support so that the totals become
 
  34 ABC
  35 BCA
  31 CAB,
 
  the sequential order becomes B, A, C, and the winner will be C.
 
 
 No. B still wins. If A feels that C is winning, then A can 
 delegate to B,
 and then B cannot lose. So C cannot be the winner. And therefore 
 B will
 delegate to C, to force A's hand. Whether or not C delegates 
 then is
 irrelevant.
 
 Of course, if A actually prefers C to B, and has managed to keep 
 B ignorant
 of this fact, then C will win. But then, in such a case, A could 
 have gotten
 the same result by being honest from the start.
 
 
 
  How can we fix this?
 
 
 I don't think there's anything that needs fixing, though you may find
 another example to show I'm wrong.
 
 
  How about allowing the largest faction (in this example 49 C) 
 to go second,
  and making the second
  largest faction (in this example 27 AB) go first?
 
  That would also work in the example above. How bad would it 
 be in a worst
  case example?
  
  Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em 
 for list info
 
 

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA

2011-07-05 Thread Jameson Quinn
2011/7/5, fsimm...@pcc.edu fsimm...@pcc.edu:

 I thought that A was required to make her approvals consistent with her
 ordering, i.e. to approve
 everybody ranked above her cutoff.  Doesn't that mean she is required to
 approve herself?

 Maybe I'm thinking of an older version of SODA.

 I hope you are right that there is nothing to fix.

Let's do this slowly. Here's the scenario:

 34 ABC
 35 BCA
 31 CAB,

B delegates first. B delegates to B,C. Totals are now C 66, B35, A34.
A's turn. If A does not delegate, C will be winning when it comes to
C's turn, and so C will not delegate. So A delegates to A,B. Totals
are now B69, C66, A34. C's turn. C is unhappy with B and so delegates
to C,A - but it's not enough. Final totals are B69, C66, A65.

I believe that the correct strategy for any combination of delegable
and undelegable votes (including minor, non-Smith candidates) in a
3-candidate Smith set is always for everyone to approve two members of
the Smith set if they care between the bottom two. This gives the same
result as minimax and most Condorcet methods. I haven't proven this,
and I don't have a general understanding of strategy for larger Smith
sets.

It is possible, when there are 3 or more near-clones A1, A2, A3...
running against a different candidate B with almost 50% - that is, B
can beat any combination of fewer than all the A's, and B has no
preference among the A's - that the true Condorcet winner among the
A's is subject to center squeeze, and the A's are forced to throw
their support to whichever of them has the most delegable votes, in
order to prevent B from winning. The upshot is that SODA, even
assuming candidates are honest in their pre-vote rankings and
strategic in their delegation, does not pass the Condorcet criterion,
but does pass the majority Condorcet criterion (that is, a pairwise
winner always wins if each of the pairwise wins constitutes a
majority). But I can't find any nonmonotonic scenario pairs, so this
Plurality within the faction is the worst result I can find. I think
that it's both unlikely and, really, not so bad.

JQ



 - Original Message -
 From: Jameson Quinn
 Date: Tuesday, July 5, 2011 1:07 pm
 Subject: Re: [EM] SODA
 To: fsimm...@pcc.edu
 Cc: election-methods@lists.electorama.com

 2011/7/5

  Jameson suggested that the SODA candidates make their approval
 decisions sequentially instead of
  simultaneously.
 
  The problem with this is that if a winning candidate moves to
 first place
  in the sequence by an increase
  in support, she may become a losing candidate:
 
  Assume sincere preferences are
 
  35 ABC
  34 BCA
  31 CAB
 
  If approval decisions are made in descending order of faction
 size A, B, C,
  then B wins.
 
  If B gains more support so that the totals become
 
  34 ABC
  35 BCA
  31 CAB,
 
  the sequential order becomes B, A, C, and the winner will be C.
 

 No. B still wins. If A feels that C is winning, then A can
 delegate to B,
 and then B cannot lose. So C cannot be the winner. And therefore
 B will
 delegate to C, to force A's hand. Whether or not C delegates
 then is
 irrelevant.

 Of course, if A actually prefers C to B, and has managed to keep
 B ignorant
 of this fact, then C will win. But then, in such a case, A could
 have gotten
 the same result by being honest from the start.

 
 
  How can we fix this?
 
 
 I don't think there's anything that needs fixing, though you may find
 another example to show I'm wrong.


  How about allowing the largest faction (in this example 49 C)
 to go second,
  and making the second
  largest faction (in this example 27 AB) go first?
 
  That would also work in the example above. How bad would it
 be in a worst
  case example?
  
  Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em
 for list info
 



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] SODA in a de-facto two-party system

2011-06-29 Thread fsimmons

 Having considered these issues, there are two refinements I'd
 make to SODA:

 - If, after voting, one candidate has an absolute majority OR
 is the only
 possible winner, they win immediately.

 Sure, I can think an argument for why SODA should elect someone
 who's not
 the initial majority winner. But I don't relish the thought of
 having to
 make that argument, either with a politician or with a regular
 voter. And in
 reality, a majority winner is the correct winner in more than
 95% of the
 cases, so let's just save the time and admit that immediately.


 - If, after voting, one candidate has fewer than 5% of the
 votes, their
 votes are automatically delegated to the first candidate on
 their preference
 list who has more than 5% (if any). The receiving candidate
 may delegate
 them in turn, only if the result thereby obtained or
 encouraged is
 consistent with the preference order of the original
 candidate. (That means
 that if minor A's order is B,C,D,E,F, and D is the first one
 of those with
 more than 5%, and D's order is C,F,X, E,..., then D may
 delegate these votes
 to C, or to C and F if F is already leading E by a greater
 margin than the
 number of votes in question, or to C, F, and E if D is
 delegating their own
 votes to X as well.)

 This appears to be a bigger compromise of principle than the
 above. But
 consider the kingmaker case: in a basically 50/50 split, some
 tiny party
 has the balance of votes, and manages to extract concessions far
 bigger than
 their base of support justifies, just in order to [not] delegate those
 votes. I think that's unjust, and this rule would prevent it.

 I think that 5% is a good cutoff here; that's tens of millions
 of voters,
 and enough to deserve a voice. It shouldn't be too high, because
 this rule
 is effectively taking power away from voters; that's only
 justified if the
 faction is so small that the power is not legitimate, and so
 it's better to
 err a bit on the small side if anything. But under 5% - that is,
 under 10%
 of the winning coalition - doesn't deserve kingmaker power.

 JQ

I like it! Don't be impatient; some of us don't have time to read these things
every day.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info