Re: The seven step series (december 2009)

2009-12-11 Thread Bruno Marchal
Marty,

On 10 Dec 2009, at 16:40, m.a. wrote:

 Bruno,
This English version of the 7-Step Series is greatly  
 appreciated and I am more than willing to accept its conclusions on  
 faith. Unfortunately, it seems that the only proof of these  
 concepts, at present, requires the traversing of long chains of  
 logical formulae which I am unable to do. I assume that more easily  
 demonstrable proofs will appear when predictions based on your ideas  
 attain experimental reality e.g. teleportation, digital brain  
 recording and so on. Till then I remain, without religious  
 implications, a believer.m.a.



You are welcome.

It is not so much a question of a long chain of reasoning, it is much  
a question of developing a familiarity with each step of the  
reasoning. Take all your time, the fun is in staying interested in the  
subject. Have you read the book Mind's I edited by Hofstadter and  
Dennett, it introduced the mechanical mind-body problem.

Sometimes (in my theses for example) I begin by the movie graph  
argument. But this is the hardest part for the physicists and for the  
logicians. It  was a shortcut to explain what is the mind body  
problem. All the rest is harder for the philosopher of mind. It is the  
dificulty of working in interdisciplinary domain.

You know, what I do is really asking question here, just making them  
precise by the discovery of the universal machine. A discovery in  
mathematics.

Apparently I am explaining UDA in the Salvia Forum here, Marty, and  
some of you may follow, and intervenes. I guess.

http://www.entheogen.com/forum/showthread.php?t=25685page=4

As exercise I let you guess what is my username on that forum. I don't  
dare to put my username on this list ;-)


Bruno




 - Original Message -
 From: Bruno Marchal
 To: everything-list@googlegroups.com
 Sent: Wednesday, December 09, 2009 2:25 PM
 Subject: Re: The seven step series (december 2009)


 On 09 Dec 2009, at 01:42, m.a. wrote:

 Bruno,
This is a stupid question but I'm hoping it contains the  
 kernel of an idea. Since logic is based on a few common  
 definitions, do you really need all these complicated steps and  
 permutations to prove a theory? Why can't you show us what you mean  
 in a handful of clear, simple, logical  
 statements?marty a.




  Have you an understanding of the six first steps, which does not  
 use much of technics. Do you have the UDA slides in front of you?

 Then at the seven step, all you need it to accept the idea that  
 there is a (finite) program which generates all programs together  
 with all their executions. This follows from Church thesis, as I  
 have explained, but you can skip those explanations.

 Yet for other, notably those who objected to the end of MGA (the  
 Movie Graph Argument) that a movie made from a filmed brain could  
 lived a conscious experience qua computatio, I have to prepare  
 them better to the (necessarily technical) computational  
 supervenience (how consciousness is associated to infinities of  
 computations).

 Have you understand that my hypothesis is that the brain, or the  
 body, or whatever you are willing to suppose responsible for your  
 consciousness , is a machine (a digital machine, that is a machine  
 such that we can frozen its state and copy it ?). Later we will  
 relinquish a lot that assumption, note.

 Is the step 0, the definition of computationalism clear for you?  
 It is equivalent as accepting classical teleportation as a mean for  
 locomotion. The reasoning does not depend on the feasibility of  
 this, but on its logical possibility.

 Or do you prefer I state only the result, in english. I think, that  
 if you accept that a universal program like above exists (which it  
 did with Church thesis), then I think you can understand in which  
 sense physics arise in the mind of the machines, it is enough to get  
 some familiarity with the first sixth steps. The result is that  
 physics is derivable from computer science, assuming comp. And we  
 get as expected gift an explanation for the physical sensations, as  
 emerging from the difference between computers science (the truth,  
 in the sense of Tarski 1944) and computer's computer science (the  
 beliefs in the sense of Gödel 1931).

 As for AUDA there is a need to understand some mathematical theorems  
 (Gödel, Löb, Solovay). A journalistic version would be that we can  
 already make the UDA test to a universal machine, instead of you,  
 and use the math to see the shadows of the emergence of the physical  
 laws.

 This is what Lucas and Penrose missed, by the rather precise way  
 they pretend to tefute mechanism, the machine can already refute  
 their argument. This is known and completely uncontroversial in the  
 community of logicians, and many physicists agrees. But for some  
 reason that reflexion from the part of the machine is ignored.  
 Historically this has

Re: The seven step series (december 2009)

2009-12-10 Thread m.a.
Bruno,
   This English version of the 7-Step Series is greatly appreciated and 
I am more than willing to accept its conclusions on faith. Unfortunately, it 
seems that the only proof of these concepts, at present, requires the 
traversing of long chains of logical formulae which I am unable to do. I assume 
that more easily demonstrable proofs will appear when predictions based on your 
ideas attain experimental reality e.g. teleportation, digital brain recording 
and so on. Till then I remain, without religious implications, a believer.  
  m.a.



  - Original Message - 
  From: Bruno Marchal 
  To: everything-list@googlegroups.com 
  Sent: Wednesday, December 09, 2009 2:25 PM
  Subject: Re: The seven step series (december 2009)




  On 09 Dec 2009, at 01:42, m.a. wrote:


Bruno,
   This is a stupid question but I'm hoping it contains the kernel 
of an idea. Since logic is based on a few common definitions, do you really 
need all these complicated steps and permutations to prove a theory? Why can't 
you show us what you mean in a handful of clear, simple, logical statements?
marty a.






   Have you an understanding of the six first steps, which does not use much of 
technics. Do you have the UDA slides in front of you?


  Then at the seven step, all you need it to accept the idea that there is a 
(finite) program which generates all programs together with all their 
executions. This follows from Church thesis, as I have explained, but you can 
skip those explanations. 


  Yet for other, notably those who objected to the end of MGA (the Movie Graph 
Argument) that a movie made from a filmed brain could lived a conscious 
experience qua computatio, I have to prepare them better to the (necessarily 
technical) computational supervenience (how consciousness is associated to 
infinities of computations).


  Have you understand that my hypothesis is that the brain, or the body, or 
whatever you are willing to suppose responsible for your consciousness , is a 
machine (a digital machine, that is a machine such that we can frozen its state 
and copy it ?). Later we will relinquish a lot that assumption, note.


  Is the step 0, the definition of computationalism clear for you? It is 
equivalent as accepting classical teleportation as a mean for locomotion. The 
reasoning does not depend on the feasibility of this, but on its logical 
possibility.


  Or do you prefer I state only the result, in english. I think, that if you 
accept that a universal program like above exists (which it did with Church 
thesis), then I think you can understand in which sense physics arise in the 
mind of the machines, it is enough to get some familiarity with the first sixth 
steps. The result is that physics is derivable from computer science, assuming 
comp. And we get as expected gift an explanation for the physical sensations, 
as emerging from the difference between computers science (the truth, in the 
sense of Tarski 1944) and computer's computer science (the beliefs in the sense 
of Gödel 1931).


  As for AUDA there is a need to understand some mathematical theorems (Gödel, 
Löb, Solovay). A journalistic version would be that we can already make the 
UDA test to a universal machine, instead of you, and use the math to see the 
shadows of the emergence of the physical laws.


  This is what Lucas and Penrose missed, by the rather precise way they pretend 
to tefute mechanism, the machine can already refute their argument. This is 
known and completely uncontroversial in the community of logicians, and many 
physicists agrees. But for some reason that reflexion from the part of the 
machine is ignored. Historically this has been seen already by Godel in 1931, 
precisely proved by Hilbert and Bernays, clarified and exploited by Löb up to 
the discovery of G and G¨ by Solovay. 


  Take it easy. Ask for specific questions and I may be able to be more 
specific too. I think.


  Bruno









  --

  You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
  To post to this group, send email to everything-l...@googlegroups.com.
  To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com.
  For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en.

--

You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-l...@googlegroups.com.
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com.
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en.




Re: The seven step series (december 2009)

2009-12-09 Thread Bruno Marchal

On 09 Dec 2009, at 01:42, m.a. wrote:

 Bruno,
This is a stupid question but I'm hoping it contains the  
 kernel of an idea. Since logic is based on a few common definitions,  
 do you really need all these complicated steps and permutations to  
 prove a theory? Why can't you show us what you mean in a handful of  
 clear, simple, logical statements?marty a.




  Have you an understanding of the six first steps, which does not use  
much of technics. Do you have the UDA slides in front of you?

Then at the seven step, all you need it to accept the idea that there  
is a (finite) program which generates all programs together with all  
their executions. This follows from Church thesis, as I have  
explained, but you can skip those explanations.

Yet for other, notably those who objected to the end of MGA (the Movie  
Graph Argument) that a movie made from a filmed brain could lived a  
conscious experience qua computatio, I have to prepare them better  
to the (necessarily technical) computational supervenience (how  
consciousness is associated to infinities of computations).

Have you understand that my hypothesis is that the brain, or the  
body, or whatever you are willing to suppose responsible for your  
consciousness , is a machine (a digital machine, that is a machine  
such that we can frozen its state and copy it ?). Later we will  
relinquish a lot that assumption, note.

Is the step 0, the definition of computationalism clear for you? It  
is equivalent as accepting classical teleportation as a mean for  
locomotion. The reasoning does not depend on the feasibility of this,  
but on its logical possibility.

Or do you prefer I state only the result, in english. I think, that if  
you accept that a universal program like above exists (which it did  
with Church thesis), then I think you can understand in which sense  
physics arise in the mind of the machines, it is enough to get some  
familiarity with the first sixth steps. The result is that physics is  
derivable from computer science, assuming comp. And we get as expected  
gift an explanation for the physical sensations, as emerging from the  
difference between computers science (the truth, in the sense of  
Tarski 1944) and computer's computer science (the beliefs in the sense  
of Gödel 1931).

As for AUDA there is a need to understand some mathematical theorems  
(Gödel, Löb, Solovay). A journalistic version would be that we can  
already make the UDA test to a universal machine, instead of you,  
and use the math to see the shadows of the emergence of the physical  
laws.

This is what Lucas and Penrose missed, by the rather precise way they  
pretend to tefute mechanism, the machine can already refute their  
argument. This is known and completely uncontroversial in the  
community of logicians, and many physicists agrees. But for some  
reason that reflexion from the part of the machine is ignored.  
Historically this has been seen already by Godel in 1931, precisely  
proved by Hilbert and Bernays, clarified and exploited by Löb up to  
the discovery of G and G¨ by Solovay.

Take it easy. Ask for specific questions and I may be able to be more  
specific too. I think.

Bruno




--

You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-l...@googlegroups.com.
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com.
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en.




Re: The seven step series (december 2009)

2009-12-08 Thread m.a.
Bruno,
   This is a stupid question but I'm hoping it contains the kernel of 
an idea. Since logic is based on a few common definitions, do you really need 
all these complicated steps and permutations to prove a theory? Why can't you 
show us what you mean in a handful of clear, simple, logical statements?
marty a.






  - Original Message - 
  From: Bruno Marchal 
  To: everything-list List 
  Sent: Monday, December 07, 2009 1:12 PM
  Subject: Re: The seven step series (december 2009)


  Hi,


  We may be at a cross of the seventh step and Why I am I? thread.


  Chose your favorite universal system. 
  Like LISP, FORTRAN, the combinators, the diophantine equations, etc.


  Enumerate in lexicographical order the expressions corresponding to the 
algorithms of the partial computable function of one variable.
  (reread the math if necessary, or ask question).


  This enumerates, with repetition, all the partial (and thus the total) 
functions from N to N, usually described as the phi_i:
  phi_0, phi_1, phi_2, phi_3,  


  phi_7 is the name of the 7th partial function in that enumeration.


  So the official definition of a universal number I am using, is, having 
fixed such an enumeration, a number u such that


  phi_u(x, y) = phi_x(y). Where x,y represent some coding of the couple (x, 
y). u is usually called the computer (hard version) or the interpreter (soft 
version). (Later, or before, for some, soft and hard will be shown to be more 
absolute than most people thought, and this as a consequence of comp; but in 
the present context it could help to think them as relative notion).


  In the definition of the universal number u,  phi_u(x, y) = phi_x(y), u is 
called the computer, x is called the program, and y is called the data.
  phi_u itself is called the universal function, and u is just a program 
computing that universal function.




  From such a u, you can code easily a universal dovetailer. This is a program 
which generate all the programs i, and compute, by dovetailing of the phi_i 
executions, all those phi_i on all its different arguments, 0, 1, 2, ...


  I may come back to the seven step per se later. 


  Having said what is a universal number, I may say what is a Löbian number.  
Or if you prefer, having said what is a universal machine, I may say what is a 
Löbian machine. 


  A Löbian machine is a universal machine which knows, in a very weak and 
precise technical sense, that she is universal.


  I can prove that any of you are universal machine. And if you understand the 
proof, then I have a proof (for me!) that you are inhabited by a Löbian 
machine. It means also, that it is just a matter of some work, made by you, to 
convince yourself that a Löbian machine indeed inhabit your mind. Comp is the 
assumption that there is a level where you can hope your are such a Löbian 
machine.


  Now I tell you this. A formula like phi_u(x, y) = phi_x(y) (the 
definition of universal number) can be translated into an elementary formula of 
first order arithmetic (like Robinson Arithmetic, or Peano Aritmetic). 


  It ease the things considerably to chose elementary arithmetic as initial 
universal system. It happens that classical logic makes the very weak theory, 
where 0, s(0), s(s(0)) ... represent the number 0 and its successors.


  For all x:   x + 0 = x
  For all x and for all y: x + s(y) = s(x + y)


  For all x:   x * 0 = 0
  For all x and for all y: x * s(y) = (x * y) + x


  Those formula gives the usual recursive or inductive definition of addition 
and multiplication.


  Exercise: prove that 2 + 2 = 4. That is, prove that s(s(0)) + s(s(0)) = 
s(s(s(s(0.


  This theory is already universal, once we accept some coding of computations 
into proof in that theory (using classical logic).


  This is an amazing result, and actually is hard to prove. It is due mainly to 
Gödel, Hilbert  Bernays, Löb). It is easier to prove that the combinators 
equation Kxy = y, Sxyz = xz(yz) are Turing universal, than to show that 
addition and multiplication are Turing universal (and thus simply universal 
with Church thesis). If you know Matiyasevitch theorem, you can derive the 
universality of addition and multiplication). Well, if you know that Conway's 
game of life (2-dim cellular automata) is universal, you know universality is 
cheap (yet non trivial).


  But the theory, 


  For all x:   x + 0 = x
  For all x and for all y: x + s(y) = s(x + y)


  For all x:   x * 0 = 0
  For all x and for all y: x * s(y) = (x * y) + x


  although universal, is not Löbian.


  You get a Löbian machine by adding some axioms, like


  For all x and for all y:  NOT(x = y) - NOT(s(x) = s(y))(different 
numbers have different successors)
  For all x:  NOT(0 = s(x))   (0 is not a successor)


  And above all the following infinity of axioms, known as the induction 
axioms. That is, for any first order logical formula A, you take the following

Re: The seven step series (december 2009)

2009-12-07 Thread Bruno Marchal
Hi,

We may be at a cross of the seventh step and Why I am I? thread.

Chose your favorite universal system.
Like LISP, FORTRAN, the combinators, the diophantine equations, etc.

Enumerate in lexicographical order the expressions corresponding to  
the algorithms of the partial computable function of one variable.
(reread the math if necessary, or ask question).

This enumerates, with repetition, all the partial (and thus the total)  
functions from N to N, usually described as the phi_i:
phi_0, phi_1, phi_2, phi_3, 

phi_7 is the name of the 7th partial function in that enumeration.

So the official definition of a universal number I am using, is,  
having fixed such an enumeration, a number u such that

phi_u(x, y) = phi_x(y). Where x,y represent some coding of the  
couple (x, y). u is usually called the computer (hard version) or the  
interpreter (soft version). (Later, or before, for some, soft and hard  
will be shown to be more absolute than most people thought, and this  
as a consequence of comp; but in the present context it could help to  
think them as relative notion).

In the definition of the universal number u,  phi_u(x, y) =  
phi_x(y), u is called the computer, x is called the program, and y is  
called the data.
phi_u itself is called the universal function, and u is just a program  
computing that universal function.


 From such a u, you can code easily a universal dovetailer. This is a  
program which generate all the programs i, and compute, by dovetailing  
of the phi_i executions, all those phi_i on all its different  
arguments, 0, 1, 2, ...

I may come back to the seven step per se later.

Having said what is a universal number, I may say what is a Löbian  
number.  Or if you prefer, having said what is a universal machine, I  
may say what is a Löbian machine.

A Löbian machine is a universal machine which knows, in a very weak  
and precise technical sense, that she is universal.

I can prove that any of you are universal machine. And if you  
understand the proof, then I have a proof (for me!) that you are  
inhabited by a Löbian machine. It means also, that it is just a matter  
of some work, made by you, to convince yourself that a Löbian machine  
indeed inhabit your mind. Comp is the assumption that there is a level  
where you can hope your are such a Löbian machine.

Now I tell you this. A formula like phi_u(x, y) = phi_x(y) (the  
definition of universal number) can be translated into an elementary  
formula of first order arithmetic (like Robinson Arithmetic, or Peano  
Aritmetic).

It ease the things considerably to chose elementary arithmetic as  
initial universal system. It happens that classical logic makes the  
very weak theory, where 0, s(0), s(s(0)) ... represent the number 0  
and its successors.

For all x:   x + 0 = x
For all x and for all y: x + s(y) = s(x + y)

For all x:   x * 0 = 0
For all x and for all y: x * s(y) = (x * y) + x

Those formula gives the usual recursive or inductive definition of  
addition and multiplication.

Exercise: prove that 2 + 2 = 4. That is, prove that s(s(0)) + s(s(0))  
= s(s(s(s(0.

This theory is already universal, once we accept some coding of  
computations into proof in that theory (using classical logic).

This is an amazing result, and actually is hard to prove. It is due  
mainly to Gödel, Hilbert  Bernays, Löb). It is easier to prove that  
the combinators equation Kxy = y, Sxyz = xz(yz) are Turing universal,  
than to show that addition and multiplication are Turing universal  
(and thus simply universal with Church thesis). If you know  
Matiyasevitch theorem, you can derive the universality of addition and  
multiplication). Well, if you know that Conway's game of life (2-dim  
cellular automata) is universal, you know universality is cheap (yet  
non trivial).

But the theory,

For all x:   x + 0 = x
For all x and for all y: x + s(y) = s(x + y)

For all x:   x * 0 = 0
For all x and for all y: x * s(y) = (x * y) + x

although universal, is not Löbian.

You get a Löbian machine by adding some axioms, like

For all x and for all y:  NOT(x = y) - NOT(s(x) = s(y))(different  
numbers have different successors)
For all x:  NOT(0 = s(x))   (0 is not a successor)

And above all the following infinity of axioms, known as the  
induction axioms. That is, for any first order logical formula A,  
you take the following formula as axiom:

(A(0)  For all x: A(x) - A(s(x))) - For all x: A(x).

This is enough to get a Löbian machine, (Peano Arithmetic) which, as  
AUDA will illustrate has already a stable and very complex theology,  
including its physical quanta and qualia.

But before going to AUDA, I have to finish the seventh step properly,  
and probably come back to the Movie graph problems we have  
encountered. Why a movie of a computation is not a computation?  What  
is the difference between a computation and a description of a  
computation? etc. I guess we could finish properly the seventh and the  

Re: The seven step series (november 2009)

2009-11-17 Thread Bruno Marchal

On 16 Nov 2009, at 17:45, Brent Meeker wrote:

 Bruno Marchal wrote:

 On 11 Nov 2009, at 19:52, Brent Meeker wrote:


 But how is the first person point of view defined?  Can this  
 theory
 tell me how many persons exist at a given time?


 I come back on this. The question how many persons? is a question
 which remains very hard in the mechanist theory.

 To answer it, let me ask you a question. Suppose that old fashioned  
 time
 travel is possible, and that Brent Meeker of the future decides to
 travel in the past, and to say hello to the younger Brent Meeker.  
 They
 met in a kitchen and drink coffee. Nobody else is present in the
 kitchen. How many person are there in the kitchen? What would you  
 say?

 I think this: if you answer one, then I will tend to say that there  
 is
 only one person in the multiverse, but it manifests itself in  
 different
 overlapping contexts. If you answer two, then I will tend to say  
 that
 there are an infinity of persons in the multiverse.

 What do you think?

 I think closed time-like loops are probably impossible.  But your  
 answer
 just points to possible equivocation on person.  The time traveling
 Brent is a different person from the untraveled Brent because he has
 different memories just as the 70yr old Brent is a different person  
 than
 the 10yr old Brent.  But in another sense - causal continuity - they  
 are
  the same person.  It isn't necessary to introduce time travel to
 create this confusion of terms.


 But the first part of my question was about how a first person  
 view is
 defined in this mathematical abstraction?  What computations must my
 computer perform so that it has a first person view?

UDA has been constructed so that we don't have to answer this question  
to understand that the physical laws emerge from numbers (assuming  
comp).
It is just enough that we accept that there is a level of  
substitution. Then we can prove that we cannot know-for-sure which  
computations support consciousness, yet that we have to take into  
account an infinity of those computations (below the substitution  
level) to get the first person experiences measure.

But AUDA provides a hint of a more precise answer. Consciousness is  
associated to the universal machine having the cognitive ability of a  
Lobian machine(*). So PA and ZF are already conscious. Their  
provability predicate obey Bp - BBp. And their knowledge pseudo- 
predicate defined by Kp = Bp  p, obeys it too: Kp - KKp.

But remember that, by the movie graph (UDA step 8) consciousness is  
not associated to the performance of a computer (= one computation/one  
universal machine), but to the existence of the computations  
(=infinity of computations and universal machines as defined in the  
standard model of arithmetic). Consciousness is associated to the  
logical relations between numbers which defined the alternate  
consistent extensions of the subject. You are, in that sense, the  
same person as PA, and probably ZF, like you are the same person as  
the young baby Brent.

And probably: rich qualia (like our owns) need long and deep stories  
(very long computations capable of stabilizing on the interference of  
the infinity of computations which exists below our level of  
substitution).

Bruno

(*) Formally: it means they provability predicate obeys B(Bp - p) -  
Bp (Löb Formula).
Bp - BBp can be derived from this. It is actually done in Smullyan's  
Forever Undecided.

http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/



--

You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-l...@googlegroups.com.
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com.
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=.




Re: The seven step series (november 2009)

2009-11-16 Thread Bruno Marchal

On 11 Nov 2009, at 19:52, Brent Meeker wrote:


 But how is the first person point of view defined?  Can this theory
 tell me how many persons exist at a given time?


I come back on this. The question how many persons? is a question  
which remains very hard in the mechanist theory.

To answer it, let me ask you a question. Suppose that old fashioned  
time travel is possible, and that Brent Meeker of the future decides  
to travel in the past, and to say hello to the younger Brent Meeker.  
They met in a kitchen and drink coffee. Nobody else is present in the  
kitchen. How many person are there in the kitchen? What would you say?

I think this: if you answer one, then I will tend to say that there is  
only one person in the multiverse, but it manifests itself in  
different overlapping contexts. If you answer two, then I will tend  
to say that there are an infinity of persons in the multiverse.

What do you think?

Note that in UDA, I use a definition of first person which identify a  
person with its personal memory, and so where many different persons  
can exist.
But in AUDA, I use a more mathematical definition which eventually  
identify all persons. Then they can differentiate through a mixture of  
amnesia (they forget that they are the universal person), and  
personal memories (which they will use as self-identification means).

Bruno



http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/



--

You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-l...@googlegroups.com.
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com.
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=.




Re: The seven step series (november 2009)

2009-11-16 Thread Brent Meeker
Bruno Marchal wrote:
 
 On 11 Nov 2009, at 19:52, Brent Meeker wrote:
 

 But how is the first person point of view defined?  Can this theory
 tell me how many persons exist at a given time?
 
 
 I come back on this. The question how many persons? is a question 
 which remains very hard in the mechanist theory.
 
 To answer it, let me ask you a question. Suppose that old fashioned time 
 travel is possible, and that Brent Meeker of the future decides to 
 travel in the past, and to say hello to the younger Brent Meeker. They 
 met in a kitchen and drink coffee. Nobody else is present in the 
 kitchen. How many person are there in the kitchen? What would you say?
 
 I think this: if you answer one, then I will tend to say that there is 
 only one person in the multiverse, but it manifests itself in different 
 overlapping contexts. If you answer two, then I will tend to say that 
 there are an infinity of persons in the multiverse.
 
 What do you think?

I think closed time-like loops are probably impossible.  But your answer 
just points to possible equivocation on person.  The time traveling 
Brent is a different person from the untraveled Brent because he has 
different memories just as the 70yr old Brent is a different person than 
the 10yr old Brent.  But in another sense - causal continuity - they are 
  the same person.  It isn't necessary to introduce time travel to 
create this confusion of terms.


But the first part of my question was about how a first person view is 
defined in this mathematical abstraction?  What computations must my 
computer perform so that it has a first person view?

Brent
The person I was when I was 3 years old is dead. He died because
too much new information was added to his brain.
  -- Saibal Mitra

 
 Note that in UDA, I use a definition of first person which identify a 
 person with its personal memory, and so where many different persons can 
 exist.
 But in AUDA, I use a more mathematical definition which eventually 
 identify all persons. Then they can differentiate through a mixture of 
 amnesia (they forget that they are the universal person), and personal 
 memories (which they will use as self-identification means).
 
 Bruno
 
 
 
 http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/
 
 
 
 --
 
 You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google 
 Groups Everything List group.
 To post to this group, send email to everything-l...@googlegroups.com.
 To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
 everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com.
 For more options, visit this group at 
 http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=.

--

You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-l...@googlegroups.com.
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com.
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=.




Re: The seven step series (november 2009)

2009-11-11 Thread Bruno Marchal

On 10 Nov 2009, at 19:29, Brent Meeker wrote:



 But this seems like creating a problem where none existed.  The
 factorial is a certain function, the brain performs a certain  
 function.
 Now you say we will formalize the concept of function in order to  
 study
 what the brain does and perhaps understand what is consciousness.  But
 there is nothing that requires that you start over with all possible
 computations.  That is like explaining the factorial function by
 considering all possible computations that produce it (like the  
 above).
 It's not wrong, but it doesn't follow from saying that the factorial  
 is
 a function.  That's why I say I take it as an ansatz - Let's consider
 all possible computations and see if we can pick out physics and the
 brain and consciousness from them.


Hmm... The seventh step comes after six other steps. I think you  
confuse UDA and Tegmark or Egan speculation on the mathematical nature  
of physics. But when we assume comp, the physical appearance cannot be  
describe by *any* computation a priori: it *has* to be retrieve from  
all computation. Roughly speaking, if we are universal machine, we do  
belong to an infinity of computation, and matter, or anything below  
our substitution level, has to be described by all computations. It  
is an open problem if that sum converge toward something we could  
describe by one computation. It is the whole point of the reasoning.  
It is theorem in the comp theory that matter emerges from all  
computations. From this you can prove that comp implies the non- 
cloning of any piece of matter, like it proves the existence of a  
strong form of indeterminacy, etc.



 Could you remind me what the phi_i are?  The enumerated partial
 functions?


 The enumerated so called partial /computable/ functions.

 To get them, take your favorite universal system (fortran, lisp, c++,
 java, whatever), write down the grammatically correct description of
 function (of one argument, say, that is, from N to N). Put those  
 codes
 in lexicographical order, and you get the corresponding phi_i: phi_1,
 phi_2, ..., and their domain W_1, W_2, W_3, ...

 With Church thesis, all the computable functions (having the domain  
 N)
 will belong to that list, but there will be no algorithm capable of
 telling in advance for any phi_i if it compute partial computable
 function or a computable functions.

 Given that this is a key point for everything which will follow, I
 have to be sure that most people understand exactly why this has to  
 be so.

 Ok, I think I understand.  It's probably not relevant here, but
 physicist usually think of functions which can be computed  
 approximately
 by a uniformly convergent algorithm as computable (e.g. compute pi)  
 but
 I think in the above you mean computable in the Turing sense that the
 computation stops with the answer (e.g. compute pi to 100 decimal
 places).  Right?


Right. There is a vocabulary problem about what is a function, and  
unfortunately english speaker and french speaker have different  
conventions, and sometimes I slip from one to other, and this does not  
help. Usually a function from N to N is supposed to be defined on all  
element of N. And thus a computable function will have an algorithm  
which does stop on all of its input.
But the Kleene diagonalization shows that there is no computable list  
of all computable functions, so if a language is universal, it means  
that the computable functions can only belong to a list of something  
else. That something else are called partial computable function: they  
are allowed to be not necessarily define on some natural number. So to  
get ALL functions, in some computable way, we have to take something  
larger: all partial functions, and to get all execution of all  
algorithm, we will have to dovetail, and from the first person point  
of view, there is an emerging continuum of computations, and it plays  
the role of the background roots of the physical laws, below our  
substitution level.

The physical world is not just a mathematical space among mathematical  
spaces, it is really a sort of summary of the whole border of the  
whole set of mathematical spaces as seen by mean universal machines.  
That the laws of physics seems computable is a mystery now.

I am just showing that the comp theory reduces the mind-body problem  
to a pure arithmetical (or combinatorial, ...) body problem.

Bruno


http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series (november 2009)

2009-11-11 Thread Brent Meeker

Rex Allen wrote:
 On Tue, Nov 10, 2009 at 1:29 PM, Brent Meeker meeke...@dslextreme.com wrote:
   
 That's why I say I take it as an ansatz - Let's consider
 all possible computations and see if we can pick out physics and the
 brain and consciousness from them.
 

 I would think that it's pretty much a given that out of all possible
 computations, we surely will be able to find some way of representing
 physics, the brain, and the contents of conscious experience.
   

But it's the picking out that's problem.  That's the generic problem 
with the everything-theories.  Sure the UD generates all possible 
strings and physics must be in there somewhere - so what.  Tegmark 
hypothesizes all possible mathematical structures exist - so yeah 
physics must be in there too.

 If we can't find some way to symbolically/logically represent these
 things...what would that mean?  Wouldn't it mean that we ourselves
 aren't capable of grasping them?

 So, I don't think I see the significance of success in this
 project...I would think that success in finding some
 logico-mathematical representation of physics 
IF you can *find* it among all the detritus.

 and the rest is the
 expected outcome, and that conclusive failure would be big news.

 So with computationalism, you can't see beneath the substitution level
 to the underlying processor substrate of what really exists.  The
 conscious experience that results from the computation doesn't have to
 reveal anything about the nature of the computer...below the
 substitution level could be neurons, transistors, falling dominoes,
 dust clouds (a la Egan), numbers, platonic objects, alien matter
 existing in some alternate universe, Wang's Carpet (Egan again),
 ROCKS...basically anything capable of supporting computation...who
 knows?  It would all look the same to us above the substitution level,
 right?

 If we were to go with Bruno's proposal, wouldn't it be because a
 substrate of platonically existing numbers seemed like a more
 plausible substrate than a contingently existing physical universe of
 matter and energy and laws which sprang from...nothing?  Has existed
 eternally?  What?
Platonic existence seems like a very thin concept to me and it's not 
very plausible (to me) that it can provide the ontology of the 
universe.  I see numbers part of the description.  That the universe 
sprang from nothing is a going theory in cosmogony supported by the 
observation that whatever conserved quantities are evaluated, energy, 
momentum, charge, entropy,..., the total for the universe comes out 
zero.  The philosophical difference that seems to divide people is that 
some are happy to accept that some things are contingent and others feel 
it better to hypothesize infinities in order to secure determinism.

Brent

--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series (november 2009)

2009-11-11 Thread Brent Meeker

Bruno Marchal wrote:

 On 10 Nov 2009, at 19:29, Brent Meeker wrote:



 But this seems like creating a problem where none existed.  The
 factorial is a certain function, the brain performs a certain function.  
 Now you say we will formalize the concept of function in order to study
 what the brain does and perhaps understand what is consciousness.  But
 there is nothing that requires that you start over with all possible
 computations.  That is like explaining the factorial function by
 considering all possible computations that produce it (like the above).  
 It's not wrong, but it doesn't follow from saying that the factorial is
 a function.  That's why I say I take it as an ansatz - Let's consider
 all possible computations and see if we can pick out physics and the
 brain and consciousness from them.


 Hmm... The seventh step comes after six other steps. I think you 
 confuse UDA and Tegmark or Egan speculation on the mathematical nature 
 of physics. But when we assume comp,

But it seems there is a shift the meaning of assume comp here.  We 
start with comp = Consciousness is something a brain does.  A brain 
does a lot of things (metabolizes, takes up space,...) but the thing it 
does that produces consciousness is a kind of computation, i.e. 
information processing.   Almost all scientists and philosophers think 
that is good hypothesis and one they would assume.  But then it seems 
you use comp2 = We - our stream of consciousness - IS a computation 
that exists in the Platonic sense.  This seems slightly different.

 the physical appearance cannot be describe by *any* computation a priori:
But the main evidence for the comp hypothesis is that physics is so 
successfully described by computations.


 it *has* to be retrieve from all computation. Roughly speaking, if we 
 are universal machine,

But assuming we are a universal machine is assuming more than our 
brains do computations and that produces consciousness.

 we do belong to an infinity of computation, and matter, or anything 
 below our substitution level, has to be described by all 
 computations. It is an open problem if that sum converge toward 
 something we could describe by one computation.
If it is proven that it doesn't, would that refute comp2?  Would we be 
left with no explanation of the perceived unity of individual consciousness?


 It is the whole point of the reasoning. It is theorem in the comp 
 theory that matter emerges from all computations. From this you can 
 prove that comp implies the non-cloning of any piece of matter, like 
 it proves the existence of a strong form of indeterminacy, etc.

What's the non-cloning proof?




 Could you remind me what the phi_i are?  The enumerated partial
 functions?


 The enumerated so called partial /computable/ functions.

 To get them, take your favorite universal system (fortran, lisp, c++,
 java, whatever), write down the grammatically correct description of
 function (of one argument, say, that is, from N to N). Put those codes
 in lexicographical order, and you get the corresponding phi_i: phi_1,
 phi_2, ..., and their domain W_1, W_2, W_3, ...

 With Church thesis, all the computable functions (having the domain N)
 will belong to that list, but there will be no algorithm capable of
 telling in advance for any phi_i if it compute partial computable
 function or a computable functions.

 Given that this is a key point for everything which will follow, I
 have to be sure that most people understand exactly why this has to 
 be so.

 Ok, I think I understand.  It's probably not relevant here, but
 physicist usually think of functions which can be computed approximately
 by a uniformly convergent algorithm as computable (e.g. compute pi) but
 I think in the above you mean computable in the Turing sense that the
 computation stops with the answer (e.g. compute pi to 100 decimal
 places).  Right?


 Right. There is a vocabulary problem about what is a function, and 
 unfortunately english speaker and french speaker have different 
 conventions, and sometimes I slip from one to other, and this does not 
 help. Usually a function from N to N is supposed to be defined on all 
 element of N. And thus a computable function will have an algorithm 
 which does stop on all of its input.
 But the Kleene diagonalization shows that there is no computable list 
 of all computable functions, so if a language is universal, it means 
 that the computable functions can only belong to a list of something 
 else. That something else are called partial computable function: they 
 are allowed to be not necessarily define on some natural number. So to 
 get ALL functions, in some computable way, we have to take something 
 larger: all partial functions, and to get all execution of all 
 algorithm, we will have to dovetail,
Thanks, I did understand, but sometimes I need reassurance that I've 
grasped it.

 and from the first person point of view, there is an emerging 
 continuum of computations, 

Re: The seven step series (november 2009)

2009-11-11 Thread Bruno Marchal


On 11 Nov 2009, at 19:52, Brent Meeker wrote:


 Bruno Marchal wrote:

 On 10 Nov 2009, at 19:29, Brent Meeker wrote:



 But this seems like creating a problem where none existed.  The
 factorial is a certain function, the brain performs a certain  
 function.
 Now you say we will formalize the concept of function in order to  
 study
 what the brain does and perhaps understand what is consciousness.   
 But
 there is nothing that requires that you start over with all possible
 computations.  That is like explaining the factorial function by
 considering all possible computations that produce it (like the  
 above).
 It's not wrong, but it doesn't follow from saying that the  
 factorial is
 a function.  That's why I say I take it as an ansatz - Let's  
 consider
 all possible computations and see if we can pick out physics and the
 brain and consciousness from them.


 Hmm... The seventh step comes after six other steps. I think you
 confuse UDA and Tegmark or Egan speculation on the mathematical  
 nature
 of physics. But when we assume comp,

 But it seems there is a shift the meaning of assume comp here.  We
 start with comp = Consciousness is something a brain does.  A brain
 does a lot of things (metabolizes, takes up space,...) but the thing  
 it
 does that produces consciousness is a kind of computation, i.e.
 information processing.   Almost all scientists and philosophers  
 think
 that is good hypothesis and one they would assume.  But then it seems
 you use comp2 = We - our stream of consciousness - IS a computation
 that exists in the Platonic sense.  This seems slightly different.


When some materialists, like some neuroscientists, assume the brain  
does computations at some high level, like with neuronal processing. I  
am not sure all are aware of the digitality assumption needed for  
making sense to the word computation.
But if we assume the brain obeys to the physical laws, then we assume  
comp already, given that the physical laws are, as far as we know,  
Turing emulable.

Comp is NOT the hypothesis that consciousness is something brain  
does. This is not even a precise definition of comp, given that  
strictly speaking we don't know what a brain is, nor what  
consciousness. But that's ok, because comp is very close to that,  
perhaps equivalent deending of what you mean by consciousness is  
something brain does.

Comp is two things: yes doctor, which means: there is a level such  
that I survive (or feel nothing) when may brain is substitute for  
digital part made at that level. This does not use any neither a  
definition of brain, except it is something which can be described by  
some machine (but not necessarily the one in the skull), nor any idea  
of consciousness, above what we can ask to a doctor (will I make it  
Doc?).

And then I believe you did understand the seventh step. In a concrete  
universe with a UD running in it (even materially), well, if my comp  
state is S, my future subjective experience is given by a sum on all  
computations going through S. So if the laws of physics still applies,  
they have to be recover from the mathematics of computations, which is  
a branch of math. In physics the notion does not admit definition  
which is different from the one by mathematicians. And quantum  
computation, actually a mathematical notion, is already close to the  
idea of sum on infinities of computations.

After the seven step, you can still invoke, to save both comp and  
materialist, that we live in a universe which is too little for a  
universal dovetailing to be executed integrally or on some large  
portion.

That is why there is an eight step, which shows that the universal  
machine (that we all provably are, even if comp is false) cannot, once  
comp is true, make the difference, for a short time on which bear the  
probabilities, distinguish between any implementations made below its  
substitution level, notably between physically implemented or  
arithmetically implemented. Step 8 shows that consciousness is not  
produced by the brain. Consciousness is produced by the arithmetical  
relation (or XYZ-ical relation with XXX being a first order  
specification of any universal system.
In that case the move to a little universe can not work, and reality,  
or more aptly the realities (corresponding to each points of view)  
have to emerge from the XYZ-relations.

I don't need any more platonic reality than I need to explain what  
is Church thesis, what is a universal machine or number, etc. No book  
of physics assume less.






 the physical appearance cannot be describe by *any* computation a  
 priori:
 But the main evidence for the comp hypothesis is that physics is so
 successfully described by computations.

Not necessarily. If you take Old QM (SWE + Collapse), the collapse of  
the wave, and its result,  IS NOT the output of a computation.
If you take the new QM, which assumes comp, the physical appearance  
is already described by 

Re: The seven step series (november 2009)

2009-11-10 Thread Brent Meeker

Bruno Marchal wrote:

 On 09 Nov 2009, at 20:43, Brent Meeker wrote:


 Bruno Marchal wrote:

 Hi,

 Let us come back on the seven step thread.

 Let me recall the initial motivation. The movie graph argument (cf the
 MGA thread) shows that it is senseless to attach consciousness to the
 physical activity of a brain or a computer.

 If we keep the computational thesis for the cognitive process, we have
 to associate consciousness to the computation, and not to its physical
 realization. Actually we have to explain what is a physical
 realization from the existence of computations.

 But then we have to understand better what we mean by computation, in
 the mathematical sense, given that we cannot use any physics, at this
 stage.

 Luckily, the notion of computation has been discovered last century by
 mathematicians. They were motivated by the foundation of mathematics
 after the crisis of set theory.

 So what is a computation? Let us try some definitions.

 Attempt 1: A computation is a sequence of computational states.

 If we agree with this, it remains to define what is a computational
 states. But the definition above misses something important. I suspect
 everything can be recoded as a sequence of computational states, and
 this could be the reason why some are willing to say that rock and
 thinks like that are conscious.

 A physicist could say that what is lacking is a genuine causality
 relation which links the states from the sequence of computational
 states. But:
 - in the context of the MGA argument, this should be seen as a red 
 herring
 - the notion of causality is extremely vague, even for a materialist.

 So:

 Attempt 2: A computation is a sequence of computational states
 obtained sequentially through the activity of some machine.

 This is actually a good definition, except that we have to define
 (without using physics) what we mean by activity, and machine. This
 may be problematic because we want to define activity by a sequence of
 state of some machine ... So:

 I don't think it's very good since it depends on the notion of
 computational states to define computation.  It is not clear that any
 sequence of states cannot be computational states.  It seems to me
 that we really take as primitive the concept of a function, something
 that is given some information and transforms it into some other
 information.  That's what we think brains do - and they do a lot of it
 which is not conscious.  When we have abstracted away what the
 information is about, we can regard it just as a string or number and
 apply the ideas of Turing, Church, et al to the transformation as a
 computation.  But we have left behind the idea that the information was
 about something or represented something.  In the context of a
 computation as a consciousness this representation is a relation between
 the information being transformed and the world of which one is
 conscious.  So it seems you have ignored physics rather than explained
 it.  However, I can accept it as an ansatz in hope that the explanation
 will emerge in the end.


 The problem which appears taking only the function is that a function 
 can be computed in many different way. For example here is a way to 
 compute the factorial function:

 BEGIN
 READ INPUT N
 SIMULATE BRENT MEEKER DRINKING COFFEE
 IF BRENT SAYS GOOD OUTPUT N*(N-1)* ... *1
 IF BRENT SAYS BAD OUTPUT N*(N-1)* ... *1
 IF BRENT SAYS NOTHING, AFTER AWHILE, OUTPUT N*(N-1)* ... *1
 END

 That program will go through the right computational state 
 corresponding to you drinking coffee, yet compute the same function 
 that any more reasonable way to compute the factorial.
 It will be impossible to dismiss those computational states if we 
 want a comp supervenience thesis.

But this seems like creating a problem where none existed.  The 
factorial is a certain function, the brain performs a certain function.  
Now you say we will formalize the concept of function in order to study 
what the brain does and perhaps understand what is consciousness.  But 
there is nothing that requires that you start over with all possible 
computations.  That is like explaining the factorial function by 
considering all possible computations that produce it (like the above).  
It's not wrong, but it doesn't follow from saying that the factorial is 
a function.  That's why I say I take it as an ansatz - Let's consider 
all possible computations and see if we can pick out physics and the 
brain and consciousness from them.






 Attempt 3: a computation is a sequence of states such that it exists a
 machine going through that sequence of states when computed by ...

 Well, we cannot refer to activity or to a physical implementation, so
 what?

 Attempt 4

 A computation is a sequence of states of some machine when executed by
 some Universal Machine.

 That is a progress, in case we succeed in defining executed by some
 universal machine, without using physics. But now we have the problem

 Does a 

Re: The seven step series (november 2009)

2009-11-10 Thread Rex Allen

On Tue, Nov 10, 2009 at 1:29 PM, Brent Meeker meeke...@dslextreme.com wrote:

 That's why I say I take it as an ansatz - Let's consider
 all possible computations and see if we can pick out physics and the
 brain and consciousness from them.

I would think that it's pretty much a given that out of all possible
computations, we surely will be able to find some way of representing
physics, the brain, and the contents of conscious experience.

If we can't find some way to symbolically/logically represent these
things...what would that mean?  Wouldn't it mean that we ourselves
aren't capable of grasping them?

So, I don't think I see the significance of success in this
project...I would think that success in finding some
logico-mathematical representation of physics and the rest is the
expected outcome, and that conclusive failure would be big news.

So with computationalism, you can't see beneath the substitution level
to the underlying processor substrate of what really exists.  The
conscious experience that results from the computation doesn't have to
reveal anything about the nature of the computer...below the
substitution level could be neurons, transistors, falling dominoes,
dust clouds (a la Egan), numbers, platonic objects, alien matter
existing in some alternate universe, Wang's Carpet (Egan again),
ROCKS...basically anything capable of supporting computation...who
knows?  It would all look the same to us above the substitution level,
right?

If we were to go with Bruno's proposal, wouldn't it be because a
substrate of platonically existing numbers seemed like a more
plausible substrate than a contingently existing physical universe of
matter and energy and laws which sprang from...nothing?  Has existed
eternally?  What?

--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series (november 2009)

2009-11-09 Thread Brent Meeker

Bruno Marchal wrote:

 Hi,

 Let us come back on the seven step thread.

 Let me recall the initial motivation. The movie graph argument (cf the 
 MGA thread) shows that it is senseless to attach consciousness to the 
 physical activity of a brain or a computer.

 If we keep the computational thesis for the cognitive process, we have 
 to associate consciousness to the computation, and not to its physical 
 realization. Actually we have to explain what is a physical 
 realization from the existence of computations.

 But then we have to understand better what we mean by computation, in 
 the mathematical sense, given that we cannot use any physics, at this 
 stage.

 Luckily, the notion of computation has been discovered last century by 
 mathematicians. They were motivated by the foundation of mathematics 
 after the crisis of set theory.

 So what is a computation? Let us try some definitions.

 Attempt 1: A computation is a sequence of computational states.

 If we agree with this, it remains to define what is a computational 
 states. But the definition above misses something important. I suspect 
 everything can be recoded as a sequence of computational states, and 
 this could be the reason why some are willing to say that rock and 
 thinks like that are conscious.

 A physicist could say that what is lacking is a genuine causality 
 relation which links the states from the sequence of computational 
 states. But:
 - in the context of the MGA argument, this should be seen as a red herring
 - the notion of causality is extremely vague, even for a materialist.

 So:

 Attempt 2: A computation is a sequence of computational states 
 obtained sequentially through the activity of some machine.

 This is actually a good definition, except that we have to define 
 (without using physics) what we mean by activity, and machine. This 
 may be problematic because we want to define activity by a sequence of 
 state of some machine ... So:

I don't think it's very good since it depends on the notion of 
computational states to define computation.  It is not clear that any 
sequence of states cannot be computational states.  It seems to me 
that we really take as primitive the concept of a function, something 
that is given some information and transforms it into some other 
information.  That's what we think brains do - and they do a lot of it 
which is not conscious.  When we have abstracted away what the 
information is about, we can regard it just as a string or number and 
apply the ideas of Turing, Church, et al to the transformation as a 
computation.  But we have left behind the idea that the information was 
about something or represented something.  In the context of a 
computation as a consciousness this representation is a relation between 
the information being transformed and the world of which one is 
conscious.  So it seems you have ignored physics rather than explained 
it.  However, I can accept it as an ansatz in hope that the explanation 
will emerge in the end.

 Attempt 3: a computation is a sequence of states such that it exists a 
 machine going through that sequence of states when computed by ...

 Well, we cannot refer to activity or to a physical implementation, so 
 what?

 Attempt 4

 A computation is a sequence of states of some machine when executed by 
 some Universal Machine.

 That is a progress, in case we succeed in defining executed by some 
 universal machine, without using physics. But now we have the problem

 Does a universal machine exist? And what is the mathematical meaning 
 of execution.

 But now, Church Thesis (Post, Church, Turing, Markov Thesis) is a 
 strengthening of the following weaker thesis: It exists a universal 
 machine. 

 And, all those machines, for Post, Turing, were mathematical 
 construction, right at the beginning.

 Church thesis is strictly speaking the statement that his formal 
 (mathematical) system, known as Lambda Calculus, is universal with 
 respect to computability. The basic entity there are the lambda 
 expressions  (those little cousins of the combinators, for those who 
 remembers old threads).

 Turing thesis is that the language describing Turing machines is 
 universal with respect of that same class, and soon it will be proved 
 that they are equivalent indeed, making Church thesis equivalent to 
 Turing thesis, (and equivalent to Post law).

 Then Turing proved the existence of the universal Turing Machine, 
 and indeed, since we know now that for each such universal system for 
 such system the understanding of the language can be encoded in the 
 language itself. So there is a universal lambda expression. There is a 
 universal Turing Machine. A universal Post production system, or a 
 Fortran interpreter (or compiled) in Fortran, or a Lisp intepreter in 
 Lisp.

 Some may ask which universal machine?. But the whole point of 
 classical computationalism (and UDA) consists in showing that below 
 your (our common) substitution 

Re: The seven step series

2009-10-11 Thread m.a.
And didn't Russell decide that this type of paradox should be outlawed from 
allowable statements within the practice of logic?  m.a.

  - Original Message - 
  From: m.a. 
  To: everything-list@googlegroups.com 
  Sent: Saturday, October 10, 2009 7:30 PM
  Subject: Re: The seven step series


  Or the barber is a special exception to the group designated as men and 
exists on a higher level of being. Therefore he can shave himself without 
transgressing the rule as stated in the premise. Isn't this one of Russell's 
paradoxes?   marty a.



- Original Message - 
From: John Mikes 
To: everything-list@googlegroups.com 
Sent: Saturday, October 10, 2009 3:47 PM
Subject: Re: The seven step series


Bruno, we had similar puzzles in middle school in the 30s. 
The barber could not shave himself because he shaved only those who did not 
shave themselves (and shaved all). So for  (Q #1) in the 1st vriant 
she(?) was a female, unless he(?) was a beardless male
(and the 'all' refers to only the bearded males requiring a shave).  
*
Q#2 is beyond me, I do not resort to a QM-pattern like Schrodinger's cat. 
(Sh/H)e is either-or, not both. 

John M


On Fri, Oct 9, 2009 at 12:00 PM, Bruno Marchal marc...@ulb.ac.be wrote:


  Hi,

  I am so buzy that I have not the time to give long explanations, so I
  give here a short exercise and a subject of reflexion instead.

  Exercise:

  There is Tyrannic country where by law it was forbidden for any man to
  have a beard.
  And there is village, in that country, and it is said that there is a
  barber in that village, who shaves all and only the men who don't
  shave themselves.

  Two questions:

  1) What is the gender of the barber?
  2) What the hell has all this to do with diagonalization, ...  and
  universal machine?

  Have a good day,

  Bruno

  http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/



  

--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-10-11 Thread Bruno Marchal
Hi John, hi Marty,
On 10 Oct 2009, at 21:47, John Mikes wrote:

 Bruno, we had similar puzzles in middle school in the 30s.
 The barber could not shave himself because he shaved only those who  
 did not shave themselves (and shaved all). So for  (Q #1) in the 1st  
 vriant
 she(?) was a female, unless he(?) was a beardless male


You are right. The barber gender is female. I don't see why you add  
that he could be a beardless male. It is part of the problem that we  
are in a tyrannic country where no man can have a beard.




 (and the 'all' refers to only the bearded males requiring a shave).
 *
 Q#2 is beyond me, I do not resort to a QM-pattern like Schrodinger's  
 cat.
 (Sh/H)e is either-or, not both.

I am not sure I understand, except that Q#2 remains unanswered, OK. I  
will first comment Marty's posts.


On 11 Oct 2009, at 01:30, m.a. wrote:

 Or the barber is a special exception to the group designated as  
 men and exists on a higher level of being. Therefore he can shave  
 himself without transgressing the rule as stated in the premise.  
 Isn't this one of Russell's paradoxes?   marty a.


Well, if the barber is not human, there is indeed no problem. But here  
the fact that it can be a woman, and that usually a barber is a human  
being, and that the question refer to a gender strongly suggest that  
the solution the barber is a woman is more reasonable that the  
barber is an extraterrestrial. I think.

 And didn't Russell decide that this type of paradox should be  
 outlawed from allowable statements within the practice of  
 logic?  m.a.

Nice you see the relation with Russel's paradox. This is a very deep  
paradox which shows we have to handle the notion of sets with some  
care. Torgny Tholerus already mentionned this, and he defended the  
idea this is an argument for ultrafinitism, which in my opinion is  
like throwing the baby (the infinite sets) with the water of the bath.

If we dare to consider that the collection of *all* sets is itself a  
set, we have a nice example of a set which contains itself as an  
element.
This is not problematical in itself, and in some axiomatic set  
theories, some sets can belong to themselves.

What becomes problematical is the idea of defining a set in intension  
by using *any* criteria.
Indeed, let us call *universe*, U,  the set of all sets. U belongs-to  
U. But {1, 2} does not belongs to {1, 2}, so some sets belong to  
themselves and some sets don't. So it looks like we could define a new  
set E of which contains all the sets which does not belongs to  
themselves. For example clearly the set {1, 2} is an element of E, and  
U is not an element of E.
But then we are in trouble. Does E belongs to E?
If E belongs to E, then he contradicts the definition of E, which  
contains only those set which does not belong to themselves. So E has  
to not belong to E. But then E does verify its own definition, so that  
he does belong to E. So E belongs to E and E does not belong to E.  
Damned.

Well, this proves that the intuitive idea of set is inconsistent. We  
do have to make the notion more precise to avoid such kind of  
reasoning. All the many very different attempts to make the notion of  
set precise have lead toward interesting mathematics, philosophy and  
even religion (i think). But this would lead us far away of the topic.  
We will have opportunity to come back on this. With the most usual  
axiomatic set theories, the set of all sets is not a set, and the  
criteria to defined set in intension is usually weakened. So much that  
some axioms have to be added to get a reasonably rich theory.


Question 2.

 2) What the hell has all this to do with diagonalization, ...  and
 universal machine?


Let us write (x y) to say that some relation between x and y exists.
In the problem, for example, (x y) means that x shaves y, and x and y  
are supposed to be humans.
In Russel's paradox (x y) means that x belongs to y, that is X  
contains y as an element, and x and y are supposed to be sets.

Argument by diagonalization always proceeds by using the diagonal  
twice. Which diagonal?

1) the first diagonal:

Well (x y) is a couple, and so belongs to the cartesian product of the  
set (of those x, y) with itself. Put in another way, if you look at  
all (x y) you get a matrix of pair of things (humans in the problem,  
sets in the paradox).

OK?

Well, the (x x) will constituted the diagonal of that matrix. x is  
supposed to vary in their respective domain (the humans in the  
village, the set, in the universe of all sets.

In the village, this gives something like (Sophie Sophie) (Claude  
Claude) (Arthur Arthur) etc. As long as there are inhabitants in the  
village. With the sets, the diagonal is any couple (x x) with x an  
arbitrary set.

The barber,  let us call it B, and the paradoxical set E from above  
are defined in a very similar way, said by diagonalization, because  
it involves the diagonal (x, x).

The barber is 

Re: The seven step series

2009-10-10 Thread John Mikes
Bruno, we had similar puzzles in middle school in the 30s.
The barber could not shave himself because he shaved only those who did not
shave themselves (and shaved all). So for  (Q #1) in the 1st vriant
*she(?)* was a female, unless *he(?)* was a beardless male
(and the 'all' refers to only the *bearded* males requiring a shave).
*
Q#2 is beyond me, I do not resort to a QM-pattern like Schrodinger's cat.
(Sh/H)e is either-or, not both.

John M

On Fri, Oct 9, 2009 at 12:00 PM, Bruno Marchal marc...@ulb.ac.be wrote:


 Hi,

 I am so buzy that I have not the time to give long explanations, so I
 give here a short exercise and a subject of reflexion instead.

 Exercise:

 There is Tyrannic country where by law it was forbidden for any man to
 have a beard.
 And there is village, in that country, and it is said that there is a
 barber in that village, who shaves all and only the men who don't
 shave themselves.

 Two questions:

 1) What is the gender of the barber?
 2) What the hell has all this to do with diagonalization, ...  and
 universal machine?

 Have a good day,

 Bruno

 http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




 


--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-10-10 Thread m.a.
Or the barber is a special exception to the group designated as men and 
exists on a higher level of being. Therefore he can shave himself without 
transgressing the rule as stated in the premise. Isn't this one of Russell's 
paradoxes?   marty a.



  - Original Message - 
  From: John Mikes 
  To: everything-list@googlegroups.com 
  Sent: Saturday, October 10, 2009 3:47 PM
  Subject: Re: The seven step series


  Bruno, we had similar puzzles in middle school in the 30s. 
  The barber could not shave himself because he shaved only those who did not 
shave themselves (and shaved all). So for  (Q #1) in the 1st vriant 
  she(?) was a female, unless he(?) was a beardless male
  (and the 'all' refers to only the bearded males requiring a shave).  
  *
  Q#2 is beyond me, I do not resort to a QM-pattern like Schrodinger's cat. 
  (Sh/H)e is either-or, not both. 

  John M


  On Fri, Oct 9, 2009 at 12:00 PM, Bruno Marchal marc...@ulb.ac.be wrote:


Hi,

I am so buzy that I have not the time to give long explanations, so I
give here a short exercise and a subject of reflexion instead.

Exercise:

There is Tyrannic country where by law it was forbidden for any man to
have a beard.
And there is village, in that country, and it is said that there is a
barber in that village, who shaves all and only the men who don't
shave themselves.

Two questions:

1) What is the gender of the barber?
2) What the hell has all this to do with diagonalization, ...  and
universal machine?

Have a good day,

Bruno

http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/





--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-10-09 Thread Bruno Marchal

Hi,

I am so buzy that I have not the time to give long explanations, so I  
give here a short exercise and a subject of reflexion instead.

Exercise:

There is Tyrannic country where by law it was forbidden for any man to  
have a beard.
And there is village, in that country, and it is said that there is a  
barber in that village, who shaves all and only the men who don't  
shave themselves.

Two questions:

1) What is the gender of the barber?
2) What the hell has all this to do with diagonalization, ...  and  
universal machine?

Have a good day,

Bruno

http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-09-24 Thread Bruno Marchal

Hi,

I sum up the definition and results seen so far.

N = {0, 1, 2, ...}, the set of natural numbers (also called positive  
integers).

N^N = {f such that f is a function from N to N} = the set of functions  
from N to N.

Universal language: a language in which we can describe formally how  
to compute any intuitively computable functions.

Weak Church thesis: there exists a universal language.

Church thesis: lambda-calculus is universal.
Turing thesis: the Turing machine specification language is universal
Markov thesis: the Markov formalism is universal
Post laws: production system is universal
Beniov-Deutsch: quantum turing machine is universal
etc.

All such thesis have been proved equivalent. Instead of lambda  
calculus, turing machines, Markov systems or Post production  
rules, ... you can use your favorite programming language (ADA,  
FORTRAN, LISP, Prolog, C++, etc.). Thanks to Church thesis, I will not  
need to actually use any of those formal systems, and what we prove  
will be true for any of them. Actually I am using only the weak Church  
thesis.

Computable = programmable in my favorite universal language (this  
definition use the (weak) Church thesis)

N^N-comp = {f such that f is a computable function from N to N}

N^N-comp+ = {f such that f is a computable function from a subset of N  
to N} = {f such that f is a partial computable function}


Note that N is a particular subset of N; so a computable function  
(defined on the whole N) is a particular case of a partial function,  
so N^N-comp is included in N^N-comp+

Training exercise: try to reprove for your own benefit that:

N^N is non enumerable

N^N-comp is enumerable

N^N-comp is non computably enumerable (the bijection exists but is not  
computable)

N^N-comp+ is enumerable

N^N-comp+ is computably enumerable (allowing repetition: different  
numbers can correspond to the same function).

Bruno




On 21 Sep 2009, at 19:47, Bruno Marchal wrote:



 On 18 Sep 2009, at 17:00, I wrote:


 On the set N^N of all functions from N to N, Cantor diagonal shows
 that N^N is non enumerable.
 On the set N-N-comp, the diagonal shows that N^N-comp, although
 enumerable is non computably enumerable.

 OK?  take the time to swallow this, and ask question if this seems
 not clear. We are at the crux of the subject.

 

 Next anticipative exercise.

 If N^N-comp is not  or non *computably* enumerable, so that we
 cannot enumerate mechanically, using some recipe, the f_n, is there
 still some hope to develop a *universal* machine, or a *universal*
 language, or a *universal* dovetailer? all capable of computing ALL
 computable function?  How to escape the diagonal contradiction?

 We would appreciate that a universal could be able, given the nth
 program (identified by the number n), and the datum m, to compute
 f_n(n). Indeed that is how we will *define* universal machine. But
 if the machine cannot find mechanically the f_n, what can we do or
 hope for? What is the price of universality?

 Gödel's theorem has forced us to abandon the notion of universal
 provability (in the realm of the relations and functions on
 numbers), and this results mainly from the use of a diagonal
 argument 5Godel 1931). So when Church told him that he decided to
 define computable by the formal language of Lambda-calculus, Kleene
 thought this was impossible, and that he could by diagonalization
 refute that universality pretension. But 'overnight', after failing
 to diagonalize against lambda-calculus, he realize that Church *may*
 be correct, and he invented the vocable of Church thesis.

 CHURCH's (original) thesis: a function from N to N is computable if
 we can explain in lamdda-calculus how to compute it.

 What could be so special about Church language that it could define
 ALL computable functions from N to N, and yet be immune to the
 diagonal argument?


 OK. I have defined a computable function (from N to N) as being a
 function which can computed from a finite description in some
 language, and this makes them intuitively enumerable. The admittedly
 vague idea here, is that any set of finite things is either finite or
 enumerable.

 But of course, this is not entirely convincing, we could use a non
 enumerable set to multiply non enumerably finite beings, and a case
 could be made that if we allow a non enumerable set of languages, or a
 non enumerable set of beings understanding those languages, we could
 find for *any* functions, a language defining that function or a being
 computing that function, making all function computable, by some
 being, and this would make the notion of computability relative if not
 trivial.

 Let me do something which illustrates this in a non trivial way,
 though, but which relies on what I have already said about the
 ordinals some times ago. I will repeat the definition.

 I will write as if I was criticizing myself.

 The notion of computable function does not make sense, by the argument
 above. To 

Re: The seven step series

2009-09-21 Thread Bruno Marchal


On 18 Sep 2009, at 17:00, I wrote:


 On the set N^N of all functions from N to N, Cantor diagonal shows  
 that N^N is non enumerable.
 On the set N-N-comp, the diagonal shows that N^N-comp, although  
 enumerable is non computably enumerable.

 OK?  take the time to swallow this, and ask question if this seems  
 not clear. We are at the crux of the subject.

 

 Next anticipative exercise.

 If N^N-comp is not  or non *computably* enumerable, so that we  
 cannot enumerate mechanically, using some recipe, the f_n, is there  
 still some hope to develop a *universal* machine, or a *universal*  
 language, or a *universal* dovetailer? all capable of computing ALL  
 computable function?  How to escape the diagonal contradiction?

 We would appreciate that a universal could be able, given the nth  
 program (identified by the number n), and the datum m, to compute  
 f_n(n). Indeed that is how we will *define* universal machine. But  
 if the machine cannot find mechanically the f_n, what can we do or  
 hope for? What is the price of universality?

 Gödel's theorem has forced us to abandon the notion of universal  
 provability (in the realm of the relations and functions on  
 numbers), and this results mainly from the use of a diagonal  
 argument 5Godel 1931). So when Church told him that he decided to  
 define computable by the formal language of Lambda-calculus, Kleene  
 thought this was impossible, and that he could by diagonalization  
 refute that universality pretension. But 'overnight', after failing  
 to diagonalize against lambda-calculus, he realize that Church *may*  
 be correct, and he invented the vocable of Church thesis.

 CHURCH's (original) thesis: a function from N to N is computable if  
 we can explain in lamdda-calculus how to compute it.

 What could be so special about Church language that it could define  
 ALL computable functions from N to N, and yet be immune to the  
 diagonal argument?


OK. I have defined a computable function (from N to N) as being a  
function which can computed from a finite description in some  
language, and this makes them intuitively enumerable. The admittedly  
vague idea here, is that any set of finite things is either finite or  
enumerable.

But of course, this is not entirely convincing, we could use a non  
enumerable set to multiply non enumerably finite beings, and a case  
could be made that if we allow a non enumerable set of languages, or a  
non enumerable set of beings understanding those languages, we could  
find for *any* functions, a language defining that function or a being  
computing that function, making all function computable, by some  
being, and this would make the notion of computability relative if not  
trivial.

Let me do something which illustrates this in a non trivial way,  
though, but which relies on what I have already said about the  
ordinals some times ago. I will repeat the definition.

I will write as if I was criticizing myself.

The notion of computable function does not make sense, by the argument  
above. To define a notion of computability, you have to define first a  
fixed language L, in which the correct grammatical expressions will be  
definition of functions, that is will correspond to the description of  
how to compute those functions, on each of their arguments. In that  
case, the f_n are clearly *computably* enumerable. The bijection n -  
f_n has to be computable, then. But in that case,  the g function,   
the one defined by g(n) = f_n(n) + 1,  is clearly computable, and the  
Cantor-like diagonal argument just showed that that g is NOT  
*definable* in the language L. L cannot be universal.

And given that the argument seems not to depend on which language L,  
it looks like we have proved that there is no universal language.

After all I could build a new language now, by adding a primitive  
computing g to the L language. Diagonalizing again would provide a new  
function g2, which we can add as new primitive again, and so one,  
getting

L, g, g2, g3, g4, ...

I could even build a more powerful language by adding a primitive  
which computes all gi automatically, giving a new primitive, that I  
can add to L, so that this process can be extended into the  
constructive tranfinite (if you remember the post on the growing  
functions, and the ordinals).

Could such a process converge toward a language computing all  
computable functions? That is, is there a universal language in which  
we can define all computable function?

It will not converge for any effective, or constructive of computable  
ordinal, because if it does, we would get a computable bijection from  
N to N^N-comp. This we already know cannot exist, the diagonal leads  
to 0 = 1.

Could it converge on non effective ordinals. Yes, and this can be used  
to make precise the idea that by liberalizing enough the notion of  
language we can define universal language. But using a non effective  
ordinal 

Re: The seven step series

2009-09-18 Thread Bruno Marchal


On 17 Sep 2009, at 18:17, John Mikes wrote:

 Dear Bruno,

 it is not very convincing when you dissect my sentences and  
 interject assuring remarks on statements to come later in the  
 sentence, negating such remarks  in advance, on a different basis.

 I argued that - upon what you (and the rest of the multimillion  
 mathematicians past and present) live with  - the applied  
 nomenclature is incomplete. It is not a counter-argument that it is  
 used by many or for so many purposes. Of course it is in use,  
 that was my point.
 I am not basing my position on opinions from within the argued  
 position.
 (May the -2 level point to a 'total senselessness' of my opinion?  
 I did not understand it, nor did I the (N + *) structure, which  
 therefore I find irrelevant in the question what I raised. (I, not  
 Rieman, Cantor, etc.).

 There is the idea of including 'quantities' in our worldview (excuse  
 my naive reference, but you illustrated earlier 2 as II and 3  
 as III etc. and THIS in my mind means sort of a quantity) and such  
 'system' would be qualitatively
 infinite if we try to include quantities from all directions (math  
 is the level of handling such quantities that 'came up' in the past  
 - gradually - and we may expect more to come, new discoveries,  
 extending the qualitative inventory)
 although in your words 'everything' can be expressed by (many many?)  
 of your natural numbers (except  square root 2?) - what is exactly  
 my point.

 I did not want to open a scientific argument - I am no match for  
 you, or any other 'mathematically educated' person. I scribbled a  
 'qualitative' idea of thinking in 'wider' terms than the defined  
 'natural numbers' in a worldview of a (qualitative) totality -  
 what I pursue, but do not understand in my sci.fic agnosticism.

 I am sorry if I bored you with my remark.

I apologize if I gave that impression, but I try sometimes to be not  
too much long in the mails, and being short can have given that  
impression. Sorry. My point was just that there is a sense where  
natural numbers are not enough in math, and that is why mathematicians  
have extended the set N. N, then Z, then Q, then R, then the complex  
numbers, then the quaternions, octonions, etc.
But, once we assume comp, N is ontologically enough, all other sort  
of numbers do necessarily appear as unavoidable epistemological  
constructions, if only to understand the (additive-multiplicative)  
behavior of the natural numbers, a bit like Riemann use complex  
numbers to provide information on the prime (natural) numbers.

Without digging a bit more on the technical issue, I can hardly say  
more than my usual: there is only natural number, together with the  
additive and multiplicative law. This, assuming comp, already defines  
a matrix of number's dreams, and those cannot avoid the internal  
phenomenological appearance of richer structures, like the other  
numbers, and indeed like the whole physical appearances.

Does this help you a little bit?

Best,

Bruno


http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-09-18 Thread John Mikes
Yes, Bruno, it helps - however: I did not want to put you into any apology!
The list is a free communication among free spirits and controversy is part
of it.
What I 'read' in your reply still sticks within 'math' and my principal
point is: the image represented is STILL what a human mind MAY think,
irrespective of 'machines' above it - as well humanly thought out.
Of course smart mathematicians came up with ideas similar to what I thought
and produced 'remedies' to cover the uncovered. Math extends as we go.

*...But, once we assume comp, N is ontologically enough, all other sort
of numbers do necessarily appear as unavoidable epistemological
constructions,...*
I am not for the *'ontological'* because that is based on whatever we KNOW
and I prefer the '*epistemological' (*in spe acquirable) totality.
Extending *yesterday's* ontology into *tomorrow's* by epistemic enrichment .


We cannot override the capabilities of our 'mind', restricted by the
brain- tissue - function and bordered by our 'existence'. And - I condone it
happily: the best we can do is math-ways (not mathematics) with all freedom
within.
WITHIN is the word.
I represent in my thinking the humbleness of being restricted. I call it my
scientific agnosticism - *allowing* things beyond our limitations.
This is why I don't use truth or even everything. And I use common
sense.
(Mine - that is G)

So far you always pronounced the (infinite?) series of NATURAL numbers and I
jumped on a number-wise defined item that was outside of them.
Sorry, when it comes to speculation, I am jumpy.
I did not know about those non-natural naturals.

Have a good day
 John

On Fri, Sep 18, 2009 at 3:23 AM, Bruno Marchal marc...@ulb.ac.be wrote:



 On 17 Sep 2009, at 18:17, John Mikes wrote:

  Dear Bruno,
 
  it is not very convincing when you dissect my sentences and
  interject assuring remarks on statements to come later in the
  sentence, negating such remarks  in advance, on a different basis.
 
  I argued that - upon what you (and the rest of the multimillion
  mathematicians past and present) live with  - the applied
  nomenclature is incomplete. It is not a counter-argument that it is
  used by many or for so many purposes. Of course it is in use,
  that was my point.
  I am not basing my position on opinions from within the argued
  position.
  (May the -2 level point to a 'total senselessness' of my opinion?
  I did not understand it, nor did I the (N + *) structure, which
  therefore I find irrelevant in the question what I raised. (I, not
  Rieman, Cantor, etc.).
 
  There is the idea of including 'quantities' in our worldview (excuse
  my naive reference, but you illustrated earlier 2 as II and 3
  as III etc. and THIS in my mind means sort of a quantity) and such
  'system' would be qualitatively
  infinite if we try to include quantities from all directions (math
  is the level of handling such quantities that 'came up' in the past
  - gradually - and we may expect more to come, new discoveries,
  extending the qualitative inventory)
  although in your words 'everything' can be expressed by (many many?)
  of your natural numbers (except  square root 2?) - what is exactly
  my point.
 
  I did not want to open a scientific argument - I am no match for
  you, or any other 'mathematically educated' person. I scribbled a
  'qualitative' idea of thinking in 'wider' terms than the defined
  'natural numbers' in a worldview of a (qualitative) totality -
  what I pursue, but do not understand in my sci.fic agnosticism.
 
  I am sorry if I bored you with my remark.

 I apologize if I gave that impression, but I try sometimes to be not
 too much long in the mails, and being short can have given that
 impression. Sorry. My point was just that there is a sense where
 natural numbers are not enough in math, and that is why mathematicians
 have extended the set N. N, then Z, then Q, then R, then the complex
 numbers, then the quaternions, octonions, etc.
 But, once we assume comp, N is ontologically enough, all other sort
 of numbers do necessarily appear as unavoidable epistemological
 constructions, if only to understand the (additive-multiplicative)
 behavior of the natural numbers, a bit like Riemann use complex
 numbers to provide information on the prime (natural) numbers.

 Without digging a bit more on the technical issue, I can hardly say
 more than my usual: there is only natural number, together with the
 additive and multiplicative law. This, assuming comp, already defines
 a matrix of number's dreams, and those cannot avoid the internal
 phenomenological appearance of richer structures, like the other
 numbers, and indeed like the whole physical appearances.

 Does this help you a little bit?

 Best,

 Bruno
 

 http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




 


--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to 

Re: The seven step series

2009-09-18 Thread Bruno Marchal
I give the answer.


On 17 Sep 2009, at 16:27, Bruno Marchal wrote:


 On 16 Sep 2009, at 18:12, Bruno Marchal wrote:




 If it is OK, in the next post we begin to address the computability  
 issue. I give you an anticipative exercise or subject reflection.  
 This is a deep exercise. Its solution leads to the notion of  
 universal function and universal number/machine. More exactly it  
 leads to an evaluation of the price we have to pay if we want to  
 believe in that notion.

 We have seen that the set N^N is non enumerable. This means it is a  
 *huge* infinite set, compared to N.
 We could argue that there are too much functions in that set. Most  
 usual functions that we encounter in real life, both in math and  
 physics, seem to share the property that they are computable. This  
 means that we can write some rules or recipe for computing them, or  
 that, may be, we can build some mechanical device capable of  
 computing them. The natural functions we met were the exponential  
 f(n) = 2^n, or the factorial(n), or similars. It seems that we can  
 explain to each other how to compute them, and you already known  
 that we can build machines computing them indeed. So, we could  
 decide, if only to avoid those big infinities, to restrict ourself  
 on the computable functions. Let us define N^N-comp to be the set  
 of computable functions from N to N.

 The question is: is there a bijection from N to N^N-comp ?


 This is a tricky question.

 I give you an argument that there is a bijection between N and N^N- 
 comp. Followed by an argument that there is no bijection between N  
 and N^N-comp.

 Which one is wrong?


 1) A proof that N^N-comp is enumerable.

 I said that a function from N to N, is computable (and thus in N^N- 
 comp), if there is a recipe explaining how to compute it.
 But this means that there has to be a language in which we can  
 describe or encode that explanation. A language is a set of finite  
 expressions build from some finite alphabet. But we have seen that  
 the set of finite expressions build on an alphabet (which is always  
 a finite set) is enumerable. Those expressions, corresponding to the  
 explanation describing the recipe for a computable function, will  
 constitute a subset of the set of all expressions, and is thus  
 enumerable. So N^N-comp is enumerable.


That is correct. N^N-comp is enumerable.




 2) A proof that N^N-comp is NOT enumerable.

 Suppose N^N-comp is enumerable, and let f_n be such an enumeration,  
 with n in {0, 1, 2, ...}. Consider the diagonal function g defined  
 by g(n) = f_n(n) + 1. All f_n are computable, and surely + 1 is  
 computable, so g is a computable function.

That is wrong. It is true that all the f_n are computable, and that +  
1 is computable. But to compute g on n I have to find f_n, and  
although all f_n are computable, the bijection itself which send n to  
f_n cannot be computable.


Why? Well if it is, given that by the reasoning above shows correctly  
that N^N-comp is enumerable, what follows would lead to 0 = 1.


 But then g has to belong to f_n, which enumerates the computable  
 functions. So there is a k such that g = f_k. But then g(k) = f_k(k)  
 = f_k(k) + 1. But f_k is a computable function from N to N, so  
 f_k(k) is a number, which I can subtract on both side, so 0 = 1. So  
 N^N^comp is not enumerable.

 Well, there is a problem, isn't it? N^N-comp cannot be both  
 enumerable and non enumerable. So one of those proofs has to be  
 wrong. Which one?

So it was the second proof which was wrong. We have implicitly  
assumed that the enumeration f_n was a computable enumeration. The  
reasoning above in 1) has show that there is a bijection between N  
and N^N-comp, and not that such an enumeration could be done by a  
*computable* bijection between N and N^N.

We say that the f_n are, although enumerable, not computably enumerable.
On the set N^N of all functions from N to N, Cantor diagonal shows  
that N^N is non enumerable.
On the set N-N-comp, the diagonal shows that N^N-comp, although  
enumerable is non computably enumerable.

OK?  take the time to swallow this, and ask question if this seems not  
clear. We are at the crux of the subject.



Next anticipative exercise.

If N^N-comp is not  or non *computably* enumerable, so that we cannot  
enumerate mechanically, using some recipe, the f_n, is there still  
some hope to develop a *universal* machine, or a *universal* language,  
or a *universal* dovetailer? all capable of computing ALL computable  
function?  How to escape the diagonal contradiction?

We would appreciate that a universal could be able, given the nth  
program (identified by the number n), and the datum m, to compute  
f_n(n). Indeed that is how we will *define* universal machine. But if  
the machine cannot find mechanically the f_n, what can we do or hope  
for? What is the price of universality?

Gödel's theorem has forced us to abandon the notion 

Re: The seven step series

2009-09-17 Thread John Mikes
Bruno,
 I loved your post on the square root of 2!
(I also laughed at it, to stay at the puns).

You went out of your way and did not save efforts to prove how inadequate
and wrong (y)our number system is. (ha ha).

Statement: *if square-rooting is right* (allegedly, and admittedly) *then
THERE IS such a 'quantity'* (call it number and by this definition it must
be natural) *we consider as the square root of '2'*.
You gave the plastic elemenary rule, how to get to it. Thankyou. Accepted.

I believe the '1' and the sophistication of Pythagoras. *(provided that *
* 1^2 = 1   which is also 'funny')  a n d :*
If it is not part of your series *of* - what you call: - *natural numbers*,
then *YOUR* series is wrong. We need another system (if we really need it).

Your math pupil
John, the 'commonsenser'.

On Wed, Sep 9, 2009 at 3:21 AM, Bruno Marchal marc...@ulb.ac.be wrote:

  This is the last post before we proof Cantor theorem. It is an antic
 interlude. We are about 2000 years back in time.

 *The square root of 2.*

 It is a number x such that x^2 = 2. It is obviously smaller than 2 and
 bigger than 1. OK? It cannot be a natural number. But could it be a
 fraction?

 The square root of two is the length of the diagonal of a square with side
 one unity.

 Do you see that? I can't draw, so you have to imagine a square. You may
 draw it. And then draw or imagine the square which sides the diagonal (of
 you square unity). Draw it with its diagonals and you will see, in your mind
 or on the paper that the second square is made of four times the half of
 your square unity: meaning that the square which sides the diagonal has an
 area twice the area of the square unity. But this means that if you call d
 the length of the diagonal of the square unity, you have, by the law of the
 area of square, d^2 = 2. OK?

 So the length of the diagonal d = square root of 2. It is a 'natural'
 length occurring in geometry (and quantum mechanics!).

 The function or operation taking the square root of two is the inverse
 operation of taking the square.
 (In term of the couples defining the function as set, it means that if (x,
 y) belongs-to taking the square root of two then (y, x) belongs-to taking
 the square of).

 Now, please continue to imagine the diagonal, and try to evaluate its
 length. Is is not clearly less than two unities, and clearly more than one?
 Is it 3/2 i.e. 1.5? Well, 1.5 should give two when squared, but (1.5)^2 =
 2,25. That's too much! Is 1,4?
 Oh, 1.4 gives 1.96, not too bad, it is slightly more, may be 1.41? 1.41^2
 gives 1,9881, we get closer and closer, but will such a search ends up with
 the best approximation? This would mean we can divide the side of the square
 unity in a finite number of smaller unities, and find a sufficiently little
 unity which could measure the diagonal exactly. It would mean d is equal to
 p * 1/q, where q is the number of divisions of the side of the square unity.
 If we find such a fraction the diagonal and the sided would be said
 commensurable.

 Is there such a fraction?

 It is not 3/2, we know already. Is it 17/12 (= 1,4166...)? (1712)^2
 = 2,006944). Close but wrong.
 Is it 99/70? (= 1,414285714...) (99/70)^2 = 2,000204082...). Very close,
 but still wrong!

 ...

 is it 12477253282759/8822750406821 ? My pocket computer says that the
 square of that fraction is 2. Ah, but this is due to its incompetence in
 handling too big numbers and too little numbers! It is still wrong!

 How could we know if that search will end, or not end?

 Sometimes, we can know thing in advance. Why, because things obeys laws,
 apparently.

 Which laws of numbers makes the problem decidable?

 Here is one:

 - a number is even if and only if the square of that number is even,
 similarly
 - a number is odd if and only if the square of that number is odd.

 Taking the square of an integer leaves invariant the parity (even/odd) of
 the number.

 Why? suppose n is odd. There will exist a k (belonging to {0, 1, 2, 3, ...}
 such that n = 2k+1. OK? So n^2 = (2k+1)^2 = 4k^2 + 4k + 1, OK? and this is
 odd. OK. And this is enough to show that if n^2 is even, then n is even. OK?

 And why does this answer the question.

 Let us reason 'by absurdo.

 Suppose that there are number p and q such (p/q)^2 = 2. And let us suppose
 we have already use the Euclid algorithm to reduce that fraction; so that p
 and q have no common factor.
  p^2 / q^2 = 2. OK? Then p^2 = 2q^2 (our 'Diophantine equation). OK?

 Then p^2 is even. OK? (because it is equal to 2 * an integer).
 Then p is even. OK? (by the law above).
 This means p is equal to some 2*k (definition of even number). OK?
 But p^2 = 2q^2 (see above), and substituting p by 2k, we get 4k^2 = 2q^2,
 and thus, dividing both sides by 2, we get that 2k^2 = q^2.
 So q^2 is even. OK?
 So q is even. (again by the law above). OK?
 So both p and q are even, but this means they have a common factor (indeed,
 2), and this is absurd, given that the 

Re: The seven step series

2009-09-17 Thread Bruno Marchal
Hi John,


On 17 Sep 2009, at 15:14, John Mikes wrote:


 You went out of your way and did not save efforts to prove how  
 inadequate and wrong (y)our number system is. (ha ha).

Wrong ?




 Statement: if square-rooting is right (allegedly, and admittedly)


Well, it is certainly right if we want that to measure by a number  
length of the diagonal of the square unity.




 then THERE IS such a 'quantity' (call it number and by this  
 definition it must be natural)


It cannot be natural number. It has to be strictly bigger than 1, and  
strictly bigger than 2. But there was some hope that it could be the  
ratio of two natural number, so that it can live in arithmetic with  
addition and multiplication.




 we consider as the square root of '2'.
 You gave the plastic elemenary rule, how to get to it. Thankyou.  
 Accepted.

 I believe the '1' and the sophistication of Pythagoras. (provided that
  1^2 = 1   which is also 'funny')  a n d :
 If it is not part of your series of - what you call: - natural  
 numbers, then YOUR series is wrong.


You could as well told something like My cave is at the level -2  
(minus two) of the building ...



 We need another system (if we really need it).

That is why N (the set of natiral numbers, alias positive integers)  
has been extended into Z, all the integers, itself included in Q (he  
ratio). The my point was that Q was still not enough to define the  
length of the diagonal, we need the real numbers, which are more  
difficult to define in the structure (N, +, *).

 From a logical point of view, N, Z, and Q are roughly equivalent. The  
real numbers are not, most are not definable in the structure N. yet,  
and we will see this (probably), most real numbers that we encounter  
in math and physics can still be defined in the structure (N,+,*). It  
is an open problem in math and physics if there is anything we cannot  
define in (N,+,*), and indeed it is an indirect consequence of COMP  
that we can. This probably why formal set theory is studied only by  
logicians.

Of course Riemann and number theorists, and knot theorists, are used  
to escape from the (N, +, *) structure all the time, and that is why  
we use analysis (based on the real numbers). But we have not yet find  
a theorem which *needs* to escape the structure (N, +, *), except  
those found by logicians to just provide examples. In the mechanical  
theory of mind, we have to escape the structure (N, +, *). Indeed the  
first person notion needs even more than Cantor paradise, from its  
point of view, and that is why and how the epistemology of comp is  
necessarily far bigger than its ontology. I may come back on this, but  
it asks for more model theory and logic to address the question  
technically.

Bruno


http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-09-17 Thread Bruno Marchal

On 16 Sep 2009, at 18:12, Bruno Marchal wrote:




 If it is OK, in the next post we begin to address the computability  
 issue. I give you an anticipative exercise or subject reflection.  
 This is a deep exercise. Its solution leads to the notion of  
 universal function and universal number/machine. More exactly it  
 leads to an evaluation of the price we have to pay if we want to  
 believe in that notion.

 We have seen that the set N^N is non enumerable. This means it is a  
 *huge* infinite set, compared to N.
 We could argue that there are too much functions in that set. Most  
 usual functions that we encounter in real life, both in math and  
 physics, seem to share the property that they are computable. This  
 means that we can write some rules or recipe for computing them, or  
 that, may be, we can build some mechanical device capable of  
 computing them. The natural functions we met were the exponential  
 f(n) = 2^n, or the factorial(n), or similars. It seems that we can  
 explain to each other how to compute them, and you already known  
 that we can build machines computing them indeed. So, we could  
 decide, if only to avoid those big infinities, to restrict ourself  
 on the computable functions. Let us define N^N-comp to be the set of  
 computable functions from N to N.

 The question is: is there a bijection from N to N^N-comp ?


This is a tricky question.

I give you an argument that there is a bijection between N and N^N- 
comp. Followed by an argument that there is no bijection between N and  
N^N-comp.

Which one is wrong?


1) A proof that N^N-comp is enumerable.

I said that a function from N to N, is computable (and thus in N^N- 
comp), if there is a recipe explaining how to compute it.
But this means that there has to be a language in which we can  
describe or encode that explanation. A language is a set of finite  
expressions build from some finite alphabet. But we have seen that the  
set of finite expressions build on an alphabet (which is always a  
finite set) is enumerable. Those expressions, corresponding to the  
explanation describing the recipe for a computable function, will  
constitute a subset of the set of all expressions, and is thus  
enumerable. So N^N-comp is enumerable.

2) A proof that N^N-comp is NOT enumerable.

Suppose N^N-comp is enumerable, and let f_n be such an enumeration,  
with n in {0, 1, 2, ...}. Consider the diagonal function g defined by  
g(n) = f_n(n) + 1. All f_n are computable, and surely + 1 is  
computable, so g is a computable function. But then g has to belong to  
f_n, which enumerates the computable functions. So there is a k such  
that g = f_k. But then g(k) = f_k(k) = f_k(k) + 1. But f_k is a  
computable function from N to N, so f_k(k) is a number, which I can  
subtract on both side, so 0 = 1. So N^N^comp is not enumerable.

Well, there is a problem, isn't it? N^N-comp cannot be both enumerable  
and non enumerable. So one of those proofs has to be wrong. Which one?

Bruno


http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-09-17 Thread John Mikes
Dear Bruno,

it is not very convincing when you dissect my sentences and interject
assuring remarks on statements to come later in the sentence, negating such
remarks  in advance, on a different basis.

I argued that - upon what you (and the rest of the multimillion
mathematicians past and present) live with  - *the applied nomenclature is
incomplete*. It is not a counter-argument that it is used by many or for
so many purposes. Of course it is in use, that was my point.
I am not basing my position on opinions from within the argued position.
(May the -2 level point to a 'total senselessness' of my opinion? I did
not understand it, nor did I the (N + *) structure, which therefore I find
irrelevant in the question what I raised. (I, not Rieman, Cantor, etc.).

There is the idea of including 'quantities' in our worldview (excuse my
naive reference, but you illustrated earlier 2 as II and 3 as III
etc. and THIS in my mind means sort of a quantity) and such 'system' would
be qualitatively
infinite if we try to include quantities from all directions (math is the
level of handling such quantities that 'came up' in the past - gradually -
and we may expect more to come, new discoveries, extending the qualitative
inventory)
although in your words 'everything' can be expressed by (many many?) of *
your* natural numbers (except  square root 2?) - what is exactly my point.

I did not want to open a scientific argument - I am no match for you, or any
other 'mathematically educated' person. I scribbled a 'qualitative' idea of
thinking in 'wider' terms than the *defined* 'natural numbers' in a
worldview of a (qualitative) totality - what I pursue, but do not
understand in my sci.fic agnosticism.

I am sorry if I bored you with my remark.

John M



On Thu, Sep 17, 2009 at 10:01 AM, Bruno Marchal marc...@ulb.ac.be wrote:

 Hi John,

  On 17 Sep 2009, at 15:14, John Mikes wrote:



 You went out of your way and did not save efforts to prove how inadequate
 and wrong (y)our number system is. (ha ha).


 Wrong ?




 Statement: *if square-rooting is right* (allegedly, and admittedly)



 Well, it is certainly right if we want that to measure by a number length
 of the diagonal of the square unity.




  *then THERE IS such a 'quantity'* (call it number and by this definition
 it must be natural)



 It cannot be natural number. It has to be strictly bigger than 1, and
 strictly bigger than 2. But there was some hope that it could be the ratio
 of two natural number, so that it can live in arithmetic with addition and
 multiplication.




  *we consider as the square root of '2'*.
 You gave the plastic elemenary rule, how to get to it. Thankyou. Accepted.

 I believe the '1' and the sophistication of Pythagoras. *(provided that *
 * 1^2 = 1   which is also 'funny')  a n d :*
 If it is not part of your series *of* - what you call: - *natural numbers*,
 then *YOUR* series is wrong.



 You could as well told something like My cave is at the level -2 (minus
 two) of the building ...



  We need another system (if we really need it).


 That is why N (the set of natiral numbers, alias positive integers) has
 been extended into Z, all the integers, itself included in Q (he ratio). The
 my point was that Q was still not enough to define the length of the
 diagonal, we need the real numbers, which are more difficult to define in
 the structure (N, +, *).

 From a logical point of view, N, Z, and Q are roughly equivalent. The real
 numbers are not, most are not definable in the structure N. yet, and we will
 see this (probably), most real numbers that we encounter in math and physics
 can still be defined in the structure (N,+,*). It is an open problem in math
 and physics if there is anything we cannot define in (N,+,*), and indeed it
 is an indirect consequence of COMP that we can. This probably why formal set
 theory is studied only by logicians.

 Of course Riemann and number theorists, and knot theorists, are used to
 escape from the (N, +, *) structure all the time, and that is why we use
 analysis (based on the real numbers). But we have not yet find a theorem
 which *needs* to escape the structure (N, +, *), except those found by
 logicians to just provide examples. In the mechanical theory of mind, we
 have to escape the structure (N, +, *). Indeed the first person notion needs
 even more than Cantor paradise, from its point of view, and that is why and
 how the epistemology of comp is necessarily far bigger than its ontology. I
 may come back on this, but it asks for more model theory and logic to
 address the question technically.

 Bruno


  http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




 


--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this 

Re: The seven step series

2009-09-16 Thread Bruno Marchal
I give the solution.

On 15 Sep 2009, at 16:30, Bruno Marchal wrote:

 OK? Take your time to compare with the last post, and to understand  
 what happens.

 Training exercise: prove, using that notation, that 2^N is non  
 enumerable. Hint: use a slightly different g.


2^N is non enumerable.

2^N is the set of functions from N to {0, 1}, and I will again note or  
identify a function from N to {0, 1} with an infinite sequence of 1  
and 0. For example, the function {(0, 0), (1, 1), (2, 0), (3, 1), (4,  
0), (5, 1), ...} is identified with the sequence 010101010...
OK?

I reason by absurdum,... again with the two notations.

Suppose that 2^N *is* enumerable, then there is a bijection from N to  
2^N, which is something like

0   000110100111011010011100 ...
1   110110010010...
2   0100...
3   101010101010101010101000...
4   11100010...
5   11001110100101001100...
6   ...
7   11100011100011100011...
8   11101101...
9   0001...
...

If the bijection exists, all the 1 and 0 are well defined in the  
infinite diagram, and the diagonal sequence is well defined too.
So the diagonal sequence,  made up from the diagonal sequence where  
all 0 are changed into 1 and vice versa, is well defined too. It is

1011001...(print it, and use a rule to verify!)

OK?

Suc a sequence cannot appears in the enumeration. Indeed, if it  
appears in the diagram, it appears at some line, let us say the kth  
line. But at the intersection of the diagonal and the kth line, there  
will be a problem. By the construction of the diagonal, the kth  
element of the kth sequence has to be simultaneously equal to 0 and 1.  
Contradiction.

OK?

So 2^N is non enumerable.

OK?

I do the proof with the usual notation:

Suppose f_n is an enumeration of the functions from N to {0, 1}. Let g  
be the function which send n on 1 - f_n(n).
g is a function from N to 2 (because both 1 - 1, and 1 - 0 gives 0 or  
1). We write g(n) = 1 - f_n(n).
g is a function from N to 2, yet cannot belong to the enumeration f_i.
Why?
Suppose g is in the enumeration f_n. It means there is a number k such  
that g = f_k. Thus for all n, g(n) = f_k(n).
In particular g(k) = f_k(k). But by definition, for all n g(n) = 1 -  
f_n(n). In particular g(k) = 1 - f_k(k). So we have that g(k) is equal  
to both f_k(k) and 1 - f_k(k). And f_k is a function from N to {0, 1},  
so we get either 0 = 1 (if f_k(k) = 0), and 1 = 0 if f_k(k) = 1.  
Contradiction.

We can say it is the same proof than the proof that N^N is non  
enumerable. The only change is in the diagonal function g.
Yesterday it was g(n) = f_n(n) + 1, and today it is g(n) = 1 - f_n(n).  
This comes from the fact that we want g to belong to N^N and 2^N  
respectively.

OK?

*

If it is OK, in the next post we begin to address the computability  
issue. I give you an anticipative exercise or subject reflection. This  
is a deep exercise. Its solution leads to the notion of universal  
function and universal number/machine. More exactly it leads to an  
evaluation of the price we have to pay if we want to believe in that  
notion.

We have seen that the set N^N is non enumerable. This means it is a  
*huge* infinite set, compared to N.
We could argue that there are too much functions in that set. Most  
usual functions that we encounter in real life, both in math and  
physics, seem to share the property that they are computable. This  
means that we can write some rules or recipe for computing them, or  
that, may be, we can build some mechanical device capable of computing  
them. The natural functions we met were the exponential f(n) = 2^n, or  
the factorial(n), or similars. It seems that we can explain to each  
other how to compute them, and you already known that we can build  
machines computing them indeed. So, we could decide, if only to avoid  
those big infinities, to restrict ourself on the computable functions.  
Let us define N^N-comp to be the set of computable functions from N to  
N.

The question is: is there a bijection from N to N^N-comp ?


Bruno


http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-09-15 Thread Bruno Marchal
Hi,

I will introduce notation for functions, and prove again Cantor  
theorem, without making any diagram.

I will lazily write the diagram



 0 = 34,  6,  678,  0,  6, 77,  8,  9, 39,  67009, ...
 1 =   0, 677, 901, 1, 67, 8, 768765, 56, 9, 9, ...
 2 =   1, 2, 4, 8, 16, 32, 64, 128, 256, 512, 1024, ...
 3 =   2, 2, 2, 2, 2, 2, 2, 2, 2, 2, 2, 2, ...
 4 =  1, 1, 2, 3, 6, 24, 120, 720, 5040, 40320, ...
 5 =  0, 0, 0, 0, 1, 0, 0, 0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1, 1, 1, 0, ...
 ...

in the following way

0 = f_0
1 = f_1
2 = f_2
3 = f_3
4 = f_4
5 = f_5


Here the label f_1 plays the role of a name for the function {(0,  
34), (1, 6), (2, 678), (3, 0), ...}. Indeed it plays the role of the  
name of the function which is the image by the bijection, which we  
were supposing the existence.

To say that f_1 send 0 to 34, or 1 to 6, ...  is usually written by  
either

f_0: 0 -- 34,  f_0 : 1 -- 6, ...

or by f_0(0) = 34, f_0(1) = 6, ...

More generally if f is a name for a function, to say that (x, y)  
belongs to f, we write very often f(x) = y, or y = f(x).
For example we say that factorial(5) = 120.

Now, because I am even more lazy, instead of writing

 0 = f_0
 1 = f_1
 2 = f_2
 3 = f_3
 4 = f_4
 5 = f_5
 


I will write:

i = f_i

which is much shorter. I could even write just f_i.  the index i is  
supposed to vary from 0 to infinity (excluded). I mean that i belongs  
to {0, 1, 2, ...}, or just that it is natural number.

So with that notation, I could begin the proof by saying this: Let us  
assume that there is a bijection B:  i == f_i between N and N^N. OK?  
This is the absurd hypothesis, that is the one we want to show  
leading to a contradiction. I call that bijection B to fix the idea.
Now the proof continues. Let us consider the function from N to N  
which is defined by g(n) = f_n(n) + 1.
Do you recognize g? if n varies from 0 to infinity, with the f_i given  
by the diagram above, f_n(n) describes the diagonal

34 677 4, 2, 6, 0, ...

And f_n(n) + 1, which is g(n), describes

35 678, 5, 3, 7, 1, ...

It is the function which is supposed not be in the range of the  
supposed bijection.

Not only this can satisfy my lazy mood, but more importantly, it is  
easier to show now more clearly the contradiction.

Indeed, suppose that g is in the range of the bijection. This means  
there is some number k which is send on g by the bijection. This means  
that there is some k such that g is equal to f_k. OK?
But if g = f_k, it follows that g(n) = f_k(n) for any n. Right? But  
then if g is applied to k, its own image under the bijection, we have  
that g(k) = f_k(k).
But by definition of g, g(n) = f_n(n) + 1. So g(k) = f_k(k) + 1.
  It follows that f_k(k) = f_(k) + 1. OK? This follows by the Leibniz  
rule (two quantities equal to a third one are equal with each other),  
applied on the two preceding line.
Now, each f_i is a function from N to N, so each f_i(n) are well  
defined number (if the bijection exists), so we can substract f_(k) on  
both side of the equality f_k(k) = f_(k) + 1, so we get 0 = 1.  
Contradiction. Such a bijection cannot exist.

Again, this makes N^N non enumerable. If you consider an enumeration  
(bijection from N to a set) f_i, it will means its corresponding  
diagonal g function.


OK? Take your time to compare with the last post, and to understand  
what happens.

Training exercise: prove, using that notation, that 2^N is non  
enumerable. Hint: use a slightly different g.

Bruno


-
On 14 Sep 2009, at 16:40, Bruno Marchal wrote:


 On 09 Sep 2009, at 09:21, Bruno Marchal wrote:

 Next post: Cantor theorem(s). There is NO bijection between N and  
 N^N. I will perhaps show that there is no bijection between N and  
 {0, 1}^N. The proof can easily be adapted to show that there is no  
 bijection between N and many sets.

 After Cantor theorem, we will be able to tackle Kleene theorem and  
 the 'mathematical discovery of the mathematical universal machine',  
 needed to grasp the mathematical notion of computation,  
 implementation, etc.




 CANTOR'S FIRST RESULT

 There is NO bijection between N and N^N  (N^N is the set of  
 functions from N to N. N = (0, 1, 2,  ...}

 Proof

 1) preliminaries

 Like for the irrationality of the square root of 2, we will proceed  
 by a reduction to an absurdity.

 First note that there are many obvious injection (= one-one  
 function) from N to N^N. For example the function which sends the  
 number n on the constant function from N to N which send all numbers  
 to n:

 0 ==  {(0, 0), (1, 0), (2, 0), (3, 0), (4, 0), (5, 0), (6,  
 0) }
 1 ==  {(0, 1), (1, 1), (2, 1), (3, 1), (4, 1), (5, 1), (6,  
 1) }
 2  == {(0, 2), (1, 2), (2, 2), (3, 2), (4, 2), (5, 2), (6,  
 2) }
 3 ...
 ...

 Such correspondence is one-one: two different numbers are send to  
 two different functions from N to N. OK?

 With Cantor, inspired by what 

Re: The seven step series

2009-09-14 Thread Bruno Marchal

On 09 Sep 2009, at 09:21, Bruno Marchal wrote:

 Next post: Cantor theorem(s). There is NO bijection between N and  
 N^N. I will perhaps show that there is no bijection between N and  
 {0, 1}^N. The proof can easily be adapted to show that there is no  
 bijection between N and many sets.

 After Cantor theorem, we will be able to tackle Kleene theorem and  
 the 'mathematical discovery of the mathematical universal machine',  
 needed to grasp the mathematical notion of computation,  
 implementation, etc.




CANTOR'S FIRST RESULT

There is NO bijection between N and N^N  (N^N is the set of functions  
from N to N. N = (0, 1, 2,  ...}

Proof

1) preliminaries

Like for the irrationality of the square root of 2, we will proceed by  
a reduction to an absurdity.

First note that there are many obvious injection (= one-one function)  
from N to N^N. For example the function which sends the number n on  
the constant function from N to N which send all numbers to n:

0 ==  {(0, 0), (1, 0), (2, 0), (3, 0), (4, 0), (5, 0), (6, 0) }
1 ==  {(0, 1), (1, 1), (2, 1), (3, 1), (4, 1), (5, 1), (6, 1) }
2  == {(0, 2), (1, 2), (2, 2), (3, 2), (4, 2), (5, 2), (6, 2) }
3 ...
...

Such correspondence is one-one: two different numbers are send to two  
different functions from N to N. OK?

With Cantor, inspired by what happens in the case of finite sets,  I  
will say that the cardinal of A is little or equal (≤) than the  
cardinal of B, when A and B are infinite sets, when there is a one-one  
function, also called injection, from A to B.

The injection described in the diagram above shows that the cardinal  
of N is little or equal than the cardinal of N^N.

  I will say that the cardinal of A is equal to the cardinal of B when  
there is a bijection between the two sets.

I will also use the canonical bijection between the set of functions  
from N to N  and the set of infinite sequences of numbers, to write  
any function from N to N, as a sequence of numbers. This will make the  
things more readable.

The diagram above becomes:

0 == 0, 0, 0, 0, 0, 0, 0, 0, 0, 0, 0, 0, ...
1 == 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, ...
2 == 2, 2, 2, 2, 2, 2, 2, 2, 2, 2, 2, 2, ...
etc.

OK?

We can do that because we have all in mind the canonical order of the  
natural numbers: 0, 1, 2, 3,  so that the sequence of numbers can  
be seen a short way to describe a function from N to N.

2) the proof

Let us do the Cantor's reduction to the absurd.

Suppose there is a bijection from N to N^N.  It will have some shape  
like:

0 = 34,  6,  678,  0,  6, 77,  8,  9, 39,  67009, ...
1 =   0, 677, 901, 1, 67, 8, 768765, 56, 9, 9, ...
2 =   1, 2, 4, 8, 16, 32, 64, 128, 256, 512, 1024, ...
3 =   2, 2, 2, 2, 2, 2, 2, 2, 2, 2, 2, 2, ...
4 =  1, 1, 2, 3, 6, 24, 120, 720, 5040, 40320, ...
5 =  0, 0, 0, 0, 1, 0, 0, 0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1, 1, 1, 0, ...
...

May be you recognize some functions in the correspondence. The first  
two functions seems arbitrary. The third one seems to be the power of  
two, the fourth one is the constant function sending all numbers on 2,  
the fifth one seems to be the factorial functions, the sixth one seems  
to be an arbitrary function from N to {0, 1}.  From such finite set of  
data we can never be sure, given that the ... could in this context  
mean practically anything.

BUT, if there is a bijection between N and N^N, the correspondence is  
well defined, at least in Platonia, or in the mind of God. This means  
that each line must be thought as representing *some*, perhaps  
unknown, precise function. In particular, all numbers, including the  
double infinity of numbers that we have not represented, are well  
defined, perhaps unknown by us, numbers.

But then, Cantor reasons, if the whole diagram above makes some sense,  
it is easy to conceive a NEW function, which can be shown not  
belonging to the diagram. That is there will be a function from N to N  
which is not represented at any line of the above diagram.
Indeed the following sequence will play that role:

35,  678, 5, 3, 7, 1, ...

Do you see where it comes from? It comes from the diagonal elements,  
from up-left to down-right, with one added to them:

34+1, 677+1, 4+1, 2+1, 6+1, 0+1, ...

Why does such sequence not belong to the diagram? Because it differs  
from the first sequence for the first output. Indeed the first output  
at the first line is 34, and the new function outputs 35. It differs  
from the second sequence at the second outputs. Indeed the second  
output of the second sequence is 677, and the second output of the new  
sequence is 678, etc. So, by construction, the new function differs  
from all the sequence in the list above. We proceed diagonally to be  
sure that by changing a function, we don't come back on some  
distinction already introduced.

All the function being well defined, in Platonia, or in God's eyes (or  
in the eye of some omniscient being), 

Re: The seven step series

2009-09-09 Thread Bruno Marchal
This is the last post before we proof Cantor theorem. It is an antic  
interlude. We are about 2000 years back in time.

The square root of 2.

It is a number x such that x^2 = 2. It is obviously smaller than 2 and  
bigger than 1. OK? It cannot be a natural number. But could it be a  
fraction?

The square root of two is the length of the diagonal of a square with  
side one unity.

Do you see that? I can't draw, so you have to imagine a square. You  
may draw it. And then draw or imagine the square which sides the  
diagonal (of you square unity). Draw it with its diagonals and you  
will see, in your mind or on the paper that the second square is made  
of four times the half of your square unity: meaning that the square  
which sides the diagonal has an area twice the area of the square  
unity. But this means that if you call d the length of the diagonal of  
the square unity, you have, by the law of the area of square, d^2 = 2.  
OK?

So the length of the diagonal d = square root of 2. It is a 'natural'  
length occurring in geometry (and quantum mechanics!).

The function or operation taking the square root of two is the  
inverse operation of taking the square.
(In term of the couples defining the function as set, it means that if  
(x, y) belongs-to taking the square root of two then (y, x) belongs- 
to taking the square of).

Now, please continue to imagine the diagonal, and try to evaluate its  
length. Is is not clearly less than two unities, and clearly more than  
one? Is it 3/2 i.e. 1.5? Well, 1.5 should give two when squared, but  
(1.5)^2 = 2,25. That's too much! Is 1,4?
Oh, 1.4 gives 1.96, not too bad, it is slightly more, may be 1.41?  
1.41^2 gives 1,9881, we get closer and closer, but will such a search  
ends up with the best approximation? This would mean we can divide the  
side of the square unity in a finite number of smaller unities, and  
find a sufficiently little unity which could measure the diagonal  
exactly. It would mean d is equal to p * 1/q, where q is the number of  
divisions of the side of the square unity. If we find such a fraction  
the diagonal and the sided would be said commensurable.

Is there such a fraction?

It is not 3/2, we know already. Is it 17/12 (= 1,4166...)?  
(1712)^2 = 2,006944). Close but wrong.
Is it 99/70? (= 1,414285714...) (99/70)^2 = 2,000204082...). Very  
close, but still wrong!

...

is it 12477253282759/8822750406821 ? My pocket computer says that the  
square of that fraction is 2. Ah, but this is due to its incompetence  
in handling too big numbers and too little numbers! It is still wrong!

How could we know if that search will end, or not end?

Sometimes, we can know thing in advance. Why, because things obeys  
laws, apparently.

Which laws of numbers makes the problem decidable?

Here is one:

- a number is even if and only if the square of that number is even,  
similarly
- a number is odd if and only if the square of that number is odd.

Taking the square of an integer leaves invariant the parity (even/odd)  
of the number.

Why? suppose n is odd. There will exist a k (belonging to {0, 1, 2,  
3, ...} such that n = 2k+1. OK? So n^2 = (2k+1)^2 = 4k^2 + 4k + 1, OK?  
and this is odd. OK. And this is enough to show that if n^2 is even,  
then n is even. OK?

And why does this answer the question.

Let us reason 'by absurdo.

Suppose that there are number p and q such (p/q)^2 = 2. And let us  
suppose we have already use the Euclid algorithm to reduce that  
fraction; so that p and q have no common factor.
  p^2 / q^2 = 2. OK? Then p^2 = 2q^2 (our 'Diophantine equation). OK?

Then p^2 is even. OK? (because it is equal to 2 * an integer).
Then p is even. OK? (by the law above).
This means p is equal to some 2*k (definition of even number). OK?
But p^2 = 2q^2 (see above), and substituting p by 2k, we get 4k^2 =  
2q^2, and thus, dividing both sides by 2, we get that 2k^2 = q^2.
So q^2 is even. OK?
So q is even. (again by the law above). OK?
So both p and q are even, but this means they have a common factor  
(indeed, 2), and this is absurd, given that the fraction has been  
reduced before.

So p and q does not exist, and now we know that our search for a  
finite or periodic decimal, or for a fraction, will never end.

The diophantine equation x^2 = 2y^2 has no solution in the integers,  
and the number sqrt(2) = square root of two is not the ratio of two  
integers/ Such a number will be said irrational. If we want associate  
a number to each possible length of line segment, we have to expand  
the rational number (the reduced fraction, the periodic decimal) with  
the irrational number.

The numerical value of the sqrt(2) can only be given through some  
approximation, like

sqrt(2) =  1,414 213 562 373 095 048 801 688 724  
209 698 078 569 671 875 376 948 073 176 679 737  
990 732 478...

OK?

I have to go now.

Please ask any question.

Does the beginners see that (2k+1)^2 = 4k^2 + 4k + 1? This comes  
from the 

Re: The seven step series

2009-09-09 Thread Bruno Marchal
Hi,

I want to add something.

I said recently to John that the excluded middle principle should be  
seen as a tolerance-of-ignorance principle. Actually this will play an  
important role later, and it justifies the arithmetical realism:  
what it is, and why it is important.

Let me illustrate this on the following problem. You have to prove the  
existence of two irrational numbers x and y such that x^y is rational.  
We don't ask that x is different from y..

This is not obvious. If x is not a fraction, and y is not a fraction,  
how could we hope that x^y gives a fraction?

Yet a very simple proof shows that there exists such a couple of  
irrational numbers.

Do you agree that a number x is either rational, or is not rational?

If you answer yes, you are arithmetical realist. You believe that  
either there exist integers p and q such that x is equal to p/q, or  
that such integers don't exist.

We already know that sqrt(2) is irrational. That was the peurpose of  
the preceding post. OK?

Now, let us consider S = sqrt(2) ^ sqrt(2).

By arithmetical realism, either S is rational or it is not rational. OK?

But if S is rational, then our problem is solved.  x = y = sqrt(2) are  
not rational, and x^y is rational.
But if S is not rational, then our problem is solved too. Indeed is S  
is not rational then S^sqrt(2) is a solution. Indeed S^sqrt(2) =  
[sqrt(2) ^ sqrt(2)]^sqrt(2) = sqrt(2) ^[sqrt(2) * sqrt(2)] = sqrt(2) ^  
2 = 2; which is rational(*).

So by admitting that either sqrt(2) ^ sqrt(2) is rational or is not  
rational, we know that either sqrt(2) ^ sqrt(2) is our solution of
[sqrt(2) ^ sqrt(2)]^sqrt(2 is our solution.

So we know that a solution exists(**).

We may feel uneasy here, because although we know there is a solution,  
we remain unable to provide one. But we were not asked to provide a  
solution. We are asked if a solution exist. And we know that either S  
or S^sqrt(2) is a solution. We know that the solution belongs to the  
set {S, S^sqrt(2)}, although we don't know which one among S and  
S^sqrt(2) is the solution.

It is like a crime inquest which concludes that the murderer is either  
Arthur or Penelope, but is incapable to know which one.

Such a proof is called non constructive. It proves that something  
exists, yet does not provide the existing object. All what the proof  
provides is a set, and a proof that what we are searching for is in  
the set. It is in that sense that such a proof provides incomplete  
information. The non constructive reasoning tolerates some amount of  
ignorance.

Non constructive reasoning is usually accepted by most mathematicians,  
and even by enginers, but not by intuitionists who ask always for  
constructive existence proof.

Actually in theoretical artificial intelligence, and in mathematical  
theology not only such non constructive proofs abound, but in many  
case it can be proved that there are no better existence proof. That  
is we can prove that the proof is necessarily not constructive. It is  
that phenomenon which makes eventually comp a vaccine against  
reductionism. We can prove the existence of very 'clever' machine, but  
then we can prove that nobody can recognize as such, such a machine.
This is not the case for the present problem. It can be shown that S   
(sqrt(2)^sqrt(2)) is irrational, and this provides a constructive  
solution. The proof that S is irrational is not elementary at all.

Such a phenomenon will already appears in the post on Kleene's theorem.

Bruno


(*) We have used the laws of exponentiation: (a^b)^c = a^(b*c).
(**) That proof is sometimes attributed to Jarden.


On 09 Sep 2009, at 09:21, Bruno Marchal wrote:

 This is the last post before we proof Cantor theorem. It is an  
 antic interlude. We are about 2000 years back in time.

 The square root of 2.

 It is a number x such that x^2 = 2. It is obviously smaller than 2  
 and bigger than 1. OK? It cannot be a natural number. But could it  
 be a fraction?

 The square root of two is the length of the diagonal of a square  
 with side one unity.

 Do you see that? I can't draw, so you have to imagine a square. You  
 may draw it. And then draw or imagine the square which sides the  
 diagonal (of you square unity). Draw it with its diagonals and you  
 will see, in your mind or on the paper that the second square is  
 made of four times the half of your square unity: meaning that the  
 square which sides the diagonal has an area twice the area of the  
 square unity. But this means that if you call d the length of the  
 diagonal of the square unity, you have, by the law of the area of  
 square, d^2 = 2. OK?

 So the length of the diagonal d = square root of 2. It is a  
 'natural' length occurring in geometry (and quantum mechanics!).

 The function or operation taking the square root of two is the  
 inverse operation of taking the square.
 (In term of the couples defining the function as set, it means that  
 if (x, y) belongs-to taking 

Re: The seven step series

2009-09-08 Thread Bruno Marchal


On 31 Aug 2009, at 19:31, Bruno Marchal wrote:

 Next: I will do some antic mathematic, and prove the irrationality  
 of the square root of two, for many reasons, including some thought  
 about what is a proof. And then I will prove Cantor theorem. Then I  
 will define what is a computable function. I will explain why Cantor  
 reasoning seems to prove, in that context, the impossibility of  
 the existence of universal machine, and why actually Cantor  
 reasoning will just make them paying the big price for their  
 existence.

 Any question, any comment?  I guess that I am too quick for some,  
 too slow for others.

 Don't forget the exercise: show that there is always a bijection  
 between A+ and N.
 (A+ = set of finite strings on the alphabet A). This is important  
 and will be used later.

I illustrate the solution on a simple alphabet.

An alphabet is just any finite set. Let us take A = {a, b, c}.
A+ is the set of words made with the letters taken in A. A word is  
any finite sequence of letters.

To build the bijection from N to A+, the idea consists in enumerating  
the words having 0 letters (the empty word), then 1 letter, then 2  
letters, then 3 letters, and so on. For each n there is a finite  
numbers of words of length n, and those can be ordered alphabetically,  
by using some order on the alphabet. In our case we will decide that a  
  b, and b c (a  b should be read a is before b).

So we can send 0 on the empty word. Let us note the empty word as *.

0 -- *

then we treat the words having length 1:

1 --  a
2 --  b
3 --  c

then the words having length 2:

4 --- aa
5 --  ab
6 --  ac

7 --  ba
8 --  bb
9 --  bc

10 -- ca
11 -- cb
12 -- cc

Then the words having lenght 3. There will be a finite number of such  
words, which can be ranged alphabetically,

etc.

Do you see that this gives a bijection from N = {0, 1, 2, 3 ...} to A+  
= {*, a, b, c, aa, ab, ac, ba, bb, bc, ...}

It is one-one: no two identical words will appears in the enumeration.
It is onto: all words will appear soon or later in the enumeration.

I will call such an enumeration, or order, on A+, the lexicographic  
order.

Its mathematical representation is of course the set of couples:

{(0, *), (1, a), (2, b), (3, c), (4, aa), ...}

OK? No question?

Next, I suggest we do some antic mathematics. It will, I think, be  
helpful to study a simple  impossibility theorem, before studying  
Cantor theorems, and then the many impossibilities generated by the  
existence of universal machines. It is also good to solidify our  
notion of 'real numbers', which does play some role in the  
computability general issue.


Here are some preparation. I let you think about relationship between  
the following propositions. I recall that: the square root of X  is  Y  
means that Y^2 = X. (It is the 'inverse function of the power 2  
function). The square root of 9 is 3, for example, because 3^2 = 3*3 =  
9. OK?

- There exists incommensurable length  (finite length segment of line  
with no common integral unity)
- the Diophantine equation x^2 = 2(y^2) has no solution  (Diophantine  
means that x and y are supposed to be integers).
- the square root of 2 is irrational (= is not the ratio of integers)
- The square root of 2 has an infinite and never periodic decimal.
- If we want to measure by numbers any arbitrary segment of line, we  
need irrational numbers

Take it easy, explanation will follow. This antic math interlude will  
not presuppose the 'modern math' we have seen so far.

Bruno







http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-09-08 Thread m.a.

Bruno,
   Just to let you know that while I can't do the exercises, I am 
following as best I can. I think I understand that powersets of sets lead to 
ladders of larger and larger infinities and hope your exposition of how this 
results in the existence of universal machines will be equally clear. Best 
wishes,
 
marty a.


- Original Message - 
From: Bruno Marchal marc...@ulb.ac.be
To: everything-list@googlegroups.com
Sent: Tuesday, September 08, 2009 4:43 AM
Subject: Re: The seven step series




 On 31 Aug 2009, at 19:31, Bruno Marchal wrote:


 Any question, any comment?  I guess that I am too quick for some,
 too slow for others.

 http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




  


--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-09-08 Thread Bruno Marchal

Thanks for telling me Marty,
I wish you the best,

Bruno


On 08 Sep 2009, at 14:17, m.a. wrote:


 Bruno,
   Just to let you know that while I can't do the exercises,  
 I am
 following as best I can. I think I understand that powersets of sets  
 lead to
 ladders of larger and larger infinities and hope your exposition of  
 how this
 results in the existence of universal machines will be equally  
 clear. Best
 wishes,

marty a.


 - Original Message -
 From: Bruno Marchal marc...@ulb.ac.be
 To: everything-list@googlegroups.com
 Sent: Tuesday, September 08, 2009 4:43 AM
 Subject: Re: The seven step series




 On 31 Aug 2009, at 19:31, Bruno Marchal wrote:


 Any question, any comment?  I guess that I am too quick for some,
 too slow for others.

 http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/







 

http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-09-02 Thread Mirek Dobsicek

Bruno Marchal wrote:
 Ouh la la ... Mirek,
 
 You may be right, but I am not sure. You may verify if this was not in  
 a intuitionist context. Without the excluded middle principle, you may  
 have to use countable choice in some situation where classical logic  
 does not, but I am not sure.

Please see
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Countable_set
the sketch of proof that the union of countably many countable sets is
countable is in the second half of the article. I don't think it has
anything to do with the law of excluded middle.

Similar reasoning is described here
http://at.yorku.ca/cgi-bin/bbqa?forum=ask_a_topologist_2008;task=show_msg;msg=1545.0001


 My opinion on choice axioms is that there are obviously true, and this  
 despite I am not a set realist.

OK, thanks.

 I am glad, nevertheless that ZF and ZFC have exactly the same  
 arithmetical provability power, so all proof in ZFC of an arithmetical  
 theorem can be done without C, in ZF. This can be seen through the use  
 of Gödel's constructible models.

I am sorry, but I have no idea what might an arithmetical provability
power refer to. Just give me a hint ...

 I use set theory informally at the metalevel, and I will not address  
 such questions. As I said, I use Cantor theorem for minimal purpose,  
 and as a simple example of diagonalization.

OK. Fair enough.

 I am far more puzzled by indeterminacy axioms, and even a bit  
 frightened by infinite game theory  I have no intuitive clues in  
 such fields.

Do you have some links please? Just to check it and write down few new
key words.

Cheers,
 Mirek


 On 01 Sep 2009, at 14:30, Mirek Dobsicek wrote:
 
 The reason why I am puzzled is that I was recently told that in  
 order to
 prove that

 * the union of countably many countable sets is countable

 one needs to use at least the Axiom of Countable Choice (+ ZF, of
 course). The same is true in order to show that

 * a set A is infinite if and only if there is a bijection between A  
 and
 a proper subset of A

 (or in another words,

 * if the set A is infinite, then there exists an injection from the
 natural numbers N to A)

 Reading the proofs, I find it rather subtle that some (weaker)  
 axioms of
 choices are needed. The subtlety comes from the fact that many  
 textbook
 do not mention it.

 In order to understand a little bit more to the axiom of choice, I am
 thinkig if it has already been used in the material you covered or
 whether it was not really needed at all. Not being able to answer  
 it, I
 had to ask :-)

 Please note that I don't have any strong opinion about the Axiom of
 Choice. Just trying to understand it. May I ask about your opinion?

 Mirek





 Bruno Marchal wrote:
 Hi Mirek,


 On 01 Sep 2009, at 12:25, Mirek Dobsicek wrote:


 I am puzzled by one thing. Is the Axiom of dependent choice (DC)
 assumed
 implicitly somewhere here or is it obvious that there is no need for
 it
 (so far)?
 I don't see where I would have use it, and I don't think I will use
 it. Cantor's theorem can be done in ZF without any form of choice
 axioms.  I think.

 Well, I may use the (full) axiom of choice by assuming that all
 cardinals are comparable, but I don't think I will use this above  
 some
 illustrations.

 If you suspect I am using it, don't hesitate to tell me. But so far I
 don't think I have use it.

 Bruno


--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-09-02 Thread Bruno Marchal


On 02 Sep 2009, at 17:16, Mirek Dobsicek wrote:


 Bruno Marchal wrote:
 Ouh la la ... Mirek,

 You may be right, but I am not sure. You may verify if this was not  
 in
 a intuitionist context. Without the excluded middle principle, you  
 may
 have to use countable choice in some situation where classical logic
 does not, but I am not sure.

 Please see
 http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Countable_set
 the sketch of proof that the union of countably many countable sets is
 countable is in the second half of the article. I don't think it has
 anything to do with the law of excluded middle.

I was thinking about the equivalence of the definitions of infinite  
set (self-injection, versus injection of omega), which, I think are  
inequivalent without excluded middle, but perhaps non equivalent with  
absence of choice, I don't know)



 Similar reasoning is described here
 http://at.yorku.ca/cgi-bin/bbqa?forum=ask_a_topologist_2008;task=show_msg;msg=1545.0001

I am not sure ... I may think about this later ...



 My opinion on choice axioms is that there are obviously true, and  
 this
 despite I am not a set realist.

 OK, thanks.

 I am glad, nevertheless that ZF and ZFC have exactly the same
 arithmetical provability power, so all proof in ZFC of an  
 arithmetical
 theorem can be done without C, in ZF. This can be seen through the  
 use
 of Gödel's constructible models.

 I am sorry, but I have no idea what might an arithmetical provability
 power refer to. Just give me a hint ...

By arithmetical provability power, I mean the set of first order  
arithmetical sentences provable in the theory, or by a machine.
I will say, for example,  that the power of Robinson Arithmetic is  
smaller than the power of Peano Aritmetic, *because* the set of  
arithmetical theorems of Robinson Ar. is included in the set of  
theorems of Peano Ar. Let us write this by RA  PA. OK?
Typically, RA  PA  ZF = ZFC  ZF + k  (k = there exists a  
inaccessible cardinal).
The amazing thing is ZF = ZFC (in this sense!). Any proof of a theorem  
of arithmetic using the axiom of choice, can be done without it.


 I use set theory informally at the metalevel, and I will not address
 such questions. As I said, I use Cantor theorem for minimal purpose,
 and as a simple example of diagonalization.

 OK. Fair enough.

 I am far more puzzled by indeterminacy axioms, and even a bit
 frightened by infinite game theory  I have no intuitive clues in
 such fields.

 Do you have some links please? Just to check it and write down few new
 key words.


This is not too bad, imo, (I should have use determinacy, it is a  
better key word):

http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Determinacy

Bruno
http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-09-01 Thread Mirek Dobsicek

Hi Bruno,

I am puzzled by one thing. Is the Axiom of dependent choice (DC) assumed
implicitly somewhere here or is it obvious that there is no need for it
(so far)?

Thanks!
 mirek



--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-09-01 Thread Bruno Marchal

Hi Mirek,


On 01 Sep 2009, at 12:25, Mirek Dobsicek wrote:


 I am puzzled by one thing. Is the Axiom of dependent choice (DC)  
 assumed
 implicitly somewhere here or is it obvious that there is no need for  
 it
 (so far)?

I don't see where I would have use it, and I don't think I will use  
it. Cantor's theorem can be done in ZF without any form of choice  
axioms.  I think.

Well, I may use the (full) axiom of choice by assuming that all  
cardinals are comparable, but I don't think I will use this above some  
illustrations.

If you suspect I am using it, don't hesitate to tell me. But so far I  
don't think I have use it.

Bruno



http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-09-01 Thread Mirek Dobsicek

The reason why I am puzzled is that I was recently told that in order to
prove that

* the union of countably many countable sets is countable

one needs to use at least the Axiom of Countable Choice (+ ZF, of
course). The same is true in order to show that

* a set A is infinite if and only if there is a bijection between A and
a proper subset of A

(or in another words,

* if the set A is infinite, then there exists an injection from the
natural numbers N to A)

Reading the proofs, I find it rather subtle that some (weaker) axioms of
choices are needed. The subtlety comes from the fact that many textbook
do not mention it.

In order to understand a little bit more to the axiom of choice, I am
thinkig if it has already been used in the material you covered or
whether it was not really needed at all. Not being able to answer it, I
had to ask :-)

Please note that I don't have any strong opinion about the Axiom of
Choice. Just trying to understand it. May I ask about your opinion?

Mirek





Bruno Marchal wrote:
 Hi Mirek,
 
 
 On 01 Sep 2009, at 12:25, Mirek Dobsicek wrote:
 
 
 I am puzzled by one thing. Is the Axiom of dependent choice (DC)  
 assumed
 implicitly somewhere here or is it obvious that there is no need for  
 it
 (so far)?
 
 I don't see where I would have use it, and I don't think I will use  
 it. Cantor's theorem can be done in ZF without any form of choice  
 axioms.  I think.
 
 Well, I may use the (full) axiom of choice by assuming that all  
 cardinals are comparable, but I don't think I will use this above some  
 illustrations.
 
 If you suspect I am using it, don't hesitate to tell me. But so far I  
 don't think I have use it.
 
 Bruno
 


--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-09-01 Thread Bruno Marchal

Ouh la la ... Mirek,

You may be right, but I am not sure. You may verify if this was not in  
a intuitionist context. Without the excluded middle principle, you may  
have to use countable choice in some situation where classical logic  
does not, but I am not sure.
I know that in intuitionist math, the definition of infinite set by  
there is an injection on a subset is NOT equivalent with the  
traditional definition.

My opinion on choice axioms is that there are obviously true, and this  
despite I am not a set realist.

I am glad, nevertheless that ZF and ZFC have exactly the same  
arithmetical provability power, so all proof in ZFC of an arithmetical  
theorem can be done without C, in ZF. This can be seen through the use  
of Gödel's constructible models.

I use set theory informally at the metalevel, and I will not address  
such questions. As I said, I use Cantor theorem for minimal purpose,  
and as a simple example of diagonalization.

I am far more puzzled by indeterminacy axioms, and even a bit  
frightened by infinite game theory  I have no intuitive clues in  
such fields. And yet, the few I understand makes me doubt even of the  
consistency of ZFC. But this is 99% due, I think, to my own  
incompetence in the subject.

Bruno


On 01 Sep 2009, at 14:30, Mirek Dobsicek wrote:


 The reason why I am puzzled is that I was recently told that in  
 order to
 prove that

 * the union of countably many countable sets is countable

 one needs to use at least the Axiom of Countable Choice (+ ZF, of
 course). The same is true in order to show that

 * a set A is infinite if and only if there is a bijection between A  
 and
 a proper subset of A

 (or in another words,

 * if the set A is infinite, then there exists an injection from the
 natural numbers N to A)

 Reading the proofs, I find it rather subtle that some (weaker)  
 axioms of
 choices are needed. The subtlety comes from the fact that many  
 textbook
 do not mention it.

 In order to understand a little bit more to the axiom of choice, I am
 thinkig if it has already been used in the material you covered or
 whether it was not really needed at all. Not being able to answer  
 it, I
 had to ask :-)

 Please note that I don't have any strong opinion about the Axiom of
 Choice. Just trying to understand it. May I ask about your opinion?

 Mirek





 Bruno Marchal wrote:
 Hi Mirek,


 On 01 Sep 2009, at 12:25, Mirek Dobsicek wrote:


 I am puzzled by one thing. Is the Axiom of dependent choice (DC)
 assumed
 implicitly somewhere here or is it obvious that there is no need for
 it
 (so far)?

 I don't see where I would have use it, and I don't think I will use
 it. Cantor's theorem can be done in ZF without any form of choice
 axioms.  I think.

 Well, I may use the (full) axiom of choice by assuming that all
 cardinals are comparable, but I don't think I will use this above  
 some
 illustrations.

 If you suspect I am using it, don't hesitate to tell me. But so far I
 don't think I have use it.

 Bruno



 

http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-08-31 Thread Bruno Marchal
I give the solution to the last exercises.


On 26 Aug 2009, at 19:06, Bruno Marchal wrote:


 Hi,

 I sum up, a little bit, and then I go quickly, just to provide some  
 motivation for the sequel.

 We have seen the notion of set. We have seen examples of finite sets  
 and infinite sets.

 For example the sets

 A = {0, 1, 2},

 B = {2, 3}

 are finite.

 The set N = {0, 1, 2, 3, ...} is infinite.

 We can make the union of sets, and their intersection:

 A union B = {x such-that x is in A OR x is in B} = {0, 1, 2, 3}

 A intersection B = {x such-that x is in A AND x (the same x) is in  
 B} = {2}. 2 is the only x being both in A and B.

 OK?

 We have seen the notion of subset. X is a subset of Y, if each time  
 that x is in X, x is also in Y.

 And we have seen the notion of powerset of a set. The powerset is  
 the set of all subset of a set.

 Example: the powerset of {2, 3} is the set {{ }, {2}, {3}, {2, 3}}.

 OK?

 In particular we have seen that the number of element of the  
 powerset of a set with n elements is 2^n.

 Example: {2, 3} has two elements, and the powerset of {2, 3}, i.e.   
 {{ }, {2}, {3}, {2, 3}} has 2^2 = 4 elements. OK?

 We have seen the notion of function from a set A to a set B.

 It is just a set of couples (x, y) with x in A and y in B. x is  
 supposed to be any elements of A, and y some element of B.

 To be a function, a set of couples has to verify the *functional  
 condition* that no x is send to two or more different y. This is  
 because we want y be depending on x. Think about the function which  
 describes how the temperature  evolves with respect to time: an  
 instant t cannot be send on two different temperature.

 Let A = {1, 2} and B = {a, b, c}

 F1 = {(1, a), (2, a)}

 F2 = {(1, c}, (2, a)}

 F1 and F2 are functions.

 But the following are not:

 G1 = {(1, a), (2, b}, (2, c)}  because 2 is send on two different  
 elements

 G2 = {(1, a), (2, b), (1, b)} because 1 is send on two different  
 elements.

 OK?

 We have then consider the set of all functions from A to B, written  
 B^A, and seen that this number is equal to
 card(B) ^card(A)  where card(A) is the number of elements of A.A  
 is supposed to be a finite set, and later we will see how Cantor  
 will generalize the notion of cardinal for infinite sets.




 We have then studied the notion of bijection.


 A function from A to B is a bijection from A to B when it is both

 - ONE-ONE  two different elements of A are send to two different  
 elements of B

 - ONTO, this means that all elements of B are in the range of the  
 function, i.e. for any y in B there is some couple (x, y) in the  
 function.

 Example: F from {a, b} to {1, 2} with F = {(a, 1}, (b, 2)} is a  
 bijection, but G = {(a, 1), (b, 1)} is not because G is not ONTO,  
 nor ONE-ONE.

 OK?

 We have seen that if A and B are two finite sets, then we have

 A and B have the same number of element if and only if there exists  
 a bijection from A to B.

 OK?

 Now I can give you the very ingenious idea from Cantor. Cantor will  
 say that two INFINITE sets have the same cardinality if and only if  
 there exists a bijection between them.



 This leads to some surprises.

 Let N = {0, 1, 2, 3, ...} be the usual set of all natural numbers.  
 This is obviously an infinite set, all right?
 Let 2N = {0, 2, 4, 6, } be the set of even numbers. This is  
 obviously a subset of N OK?, and actually an infinite subset of N.


 Now consider the function from N to 2N which send each n on 2*n.  
 This function is one-one. Indeed if n is different from m, 2*n is  
 different from 2*m. OK?
 And that function, from N to 2N is onto. Indeed any element of 2N,  
 has the shape 2*n for some n, and (n, 2*n) belongs to the function.

 In extension the bijection is {(0, 0), (1, 2), (2, 4), (3, 6), (4,  
 8), (5, 10), (6, 12), ...}

 So here we have the peculiar fact that a bijection can exist between  
 a set and some of its proper subset. (A subset of A is a proper  
 subset of A if it is different of A).


 The first who discovered this is GALILEE. But, alas, he missed  
 Cantor discovery. Like Gauss later, such behavior was for them an  
 argument to abandon the study of infinite sets. They behave too much  
 weirdly for them.

 OK?

 At first sight we could think that all infinite sets have the same  
 cardinality. After all those sets are infinite, how could an  
 infinite  set have a bigger cardinality than another infinite set?  
 This is the second surprise, and the main discovery of Cantor: the  
 fact that there are some infinite sets B such that there is no  
 bijection between N and B.

 Cantor will indeed show that there is no bijection between N and  
 N^N, nor between N and 2^N. We will study this.

 Cantor will prove a general theorem, know as Cantor theorem, which  
 asserts that for ANY set A, there are no bijection between A and the  
 powerset of A.
 The powerset operation leads to a ladder of bigger infinities.  I  
 will 

Re: The seven step series

2009-08-26 Thread Bruno Marchal

Hi,

I sum up, a little bit, and then I go quickly, just to provide some  
motivation for the sequel.

We have seen the notion of set. We have seen examples of finite sets  
and infinite sets.

For example the sets

A = {0, 1, 2},

B = {2, 3}

are finite.

The set N = {0, 1, 2, 3, ...} is infinite.

We can make the union of sets, and their intersection:

A union B = {x such-that x is in A OR x is in B} = {0, 1, 2, 3}

A intersection B = {x such-that x is in A AND x (the same x) is in B}  
= {2}. 2 is the only x being both in A and B.

OK?

We have seen the notion of subset. X is a subset of Y, if each time  
that x is in X, x is also in Y.

And we have seen the notion of powerset of a set. The powerset is the  
set of all subset of a set.

Example: the powerset of {2, 3} is the set {{ }, {2}, {3}, {2, 3}}.

OK?

In particular we have seen that the number of element of the powerset  
of a set with n elements is 2^n.

Example: {2, 3} has two elements, and the powerset of {2, 3}, i.e.   
{{ }, {2}, {3}, {2, 3}} has 2^2 = 4 elements. OK?

We have seen the notion of function from a set A to a set B.

It is just a set of couples (x, y) with x in A and y in B. x is  
supposed to be any elements of A, and y some element of B.

To be a function, a set of couples has to verify the *functional  
condition* that no x is send to two or more different y. This is  
because we want y be depending on x. Think about the function which  
describes how the temperature  evolves with respect to time: an  
instant t cannot be send on two different temperature.

Let A = {1, 2} and B = {a, b, c}

F1 = {(1, a), (2, a)}

F2 = {(1, c}, (2, a)}

F1 and F2 are functions.

But the following are not:

G1 = {(1, a), (2, b}, (2, c)}  because 2 is send on two different  
elements

G2 = {(1, a), (2, b), (1, b)} because 1 is send on two different  
elements.

OK?

We have then consider the set of all functions from A to B, written  
B^A, and seen that this number is equal to
card(B) ^card(A)  where card(A) is the number of elements of A.A  
is supposed to be a finite set, and later we will see how Cantor will  
generalize the notion of cardinal for infinite sets.




We have then studied the notion of bijection.


A function from A to B is a bijection from A to B when it is both

- ONE-ONE  two different elements of A are send to two different  
elements of B

- ONTO, this means that all elements of B are in the range of the  
function, i.e. for any y in B there is some couple (x, y) in the  
function.

Example: F from {a, b} to {1, 2} with F = {(a, 1}, (b, 2)} is a  
bijection, but G = {(a, 1), (b, 1)} is not because G is not ONTO, nor  
ONE-ONE.

OK?

We have seen that if A and B are two finite sets, then we have

A and B have the same number of element if and only if there exists a  
bijection from A to B.

OK?

Now I can give you the very ingenious idea from Cantor. Cantor will  
say that two INFINITE sets have the same cardinality if and only if  
there exists a bijection between them.



This leads to some surprises.

Let N = {0, 1, 2, 3, ...} be the usual set of all natural numbers.  
This is obviously an infinite set, all right?
Let 2N = {0, 2, 4, 6, } be the set of even numbers. This is  
obviously a subset of N OK?, and actually an infinite subset of N.


Now consider the function from N to 2N which send each n on 2*n. This  
function is one-one. Indeed if n is different from m, 2*n is different  
from 2*m. OK?
And that function, from N to 2N is onto. Indeed any element of 2N, has  
the shape 2*n for some n, and (n, 2*n) belongs to the function.

In extension the bijection is {(0, 0), (1, 2), (2, 4), (3, 6), (4, 8),  
(5, 10), (6, 12), ...}

So here we have the peculiar fact that a bijection can exist between a  
set and some of its proper subset. (A subset of A is a proper subset  
of A if it is different of A).


The first who discovered this is GALILEE. But, alas, he missed Cantor  
discovery. Like Gauss later, such behavior was for them an argument to  
abandon the study of infinite sets. They behave too much weirdly for  
them.

OK?

At first sight we could think that all infinite sets have the same  
cardinality. After all those sets are infinite, how could an infinite   
set have a bigger cardinality than another infinite set? This is the  
second surprise, and the main discovery of Cantor: the fact that there  
are some infinite sets B such that there is no bijection between N and  
B.

Cantor will indeed show that there is no bijection between N and N^N,  
nor between N and 2^N. We will study this.

Cantor will prove a general theorem, know as Cantor theorem, which  
asserts that for ANY set A, there are no bijection between A and the  
powerset of A.
The powerset operation leads to a ladder of bigger infinities.  I  
will come back with some detail later.

Some surprises were BAD surprises. Conceptual problems which Cantor  
will hide in its desk, to treat them later. The so-called paradoxes  
of naïve set 

Re: The seven step series

2009-08-22 Thread Mirek Dobsicek

m.a. wrote:
 a towel into the ring.
 I simply don't have the sort of mind that takes to juggling letters,
 numbers and symbols in increasingly fine-grained, complex arrangements.

[...]

Marty,

If I can ask, I'd be really interested what do you think of this
socratic experiment
http://www.garlikov.com/Soc_Meth.html

Cheers,
 mirek





--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-08-22 Thread m.a.

Mirek,
 I think it must be a very effective method of teaching binary 
numbers. Perhaps I'll try it on my grandchildren. My four-year-old grandson 
calls VCR tapes rectangular DVD's. So he's probably ready for abstract 
thinking. Thanks for the lesson.
 marty a.




- Original Message - 
From: Mirek Dobsicek m.dobsi...@gmail.com
To: everything-list@googlegroups.com
Sent: Saturday, August 22, 2009 11:05 AM
Subject: Re: The seven step series



 Marty,

 If I can ask, I'd be really interested what do you think of this
 socratic experiment
 http://www.garlikov.com/Soc_Meth.html

 Cheers,
 mirek





  


--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-08-21 Thread Bruno Marchal


On 21 Aug 2009, at 01:24, meekerdb @dslextreme.com wrote:


 On Thu, Aug 20, 2009 at 12:32 PM, Bruno Marchalmarc...@ulb.ac.be  
 wrote:


 Hi,

 I give the solution of the first of the last exercises.
 ...
 This motivates the definition of the following function from N to N,
 called factorial.
 factorial(0) = 1, and factorial(n) = n*(n-1)*(n-2)*(n-3) * ... *1, if
 is n is different from 0.

 Note this: if n is different from 0, for each n we have that  
 fact(n) =
 n*fact(n).

 Of course you meant fact(n)=n*fact(n-1).


Yes, indeed.

Note that later we will see stronger form of recursion, but here it is  
just a typo mistake.

Bruno


http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-08-21 Thread m.a.
Bruno,
   I'm terribly sorry to disappoint you and ashamed to admit that I'm 
throwing in the towel. This is an idiom used in professional boxing; when a 
coach decides that his fighter can't take anymore punishment, he ends the fight 
by throwing a towel into the ring. I simply don't have the sort of mind that 
takes to juggling letters, numbers and symbols in increasingly fine-grained, 
complex arrangements. I think that in any endeavor, when we struggle towards a 
goal, there should be some satisfaction...some sense of accomplishment...in 
each step along the way. But in this quest, I find each step to be difficult 
and unrewarding in and of itself. Sometimes the goal is so compelling that we 
force ourselves to overcome huge impediments to reach it; but in this case, I 
already know what the goal is, and I am only motivated by the desire to 
understand how it is proven. Well, I must be content to leave verification of 
the proof to people who are far better able than I to follow its intricacies. I 
trust they have checked it accurately and will point out inconsistencies in 
this open forum if such exist. Meanwhile, I'm happy to take it on faith. I 
shall certainly continue to lurk here gleaning what I can from the 
philosophical debates whose endless probing of the foundations of existence is 
a source of constant fascination. Best,


  marty a.








   
- Original Message - 
From: Bruno Marchal marc...@ulb.ac.be
To: everything-list@googlegroups.com
Sent: Friday, August 21, 2009 3:47 AM
Subject: Re: The seven step series


 
 
 On 21 Aug 2009, at 01:24, meekerdb @dslextreme.com wrote:
 

 On Thu, Aug 20, 2009 at 12:32 PM, Bruno Marchalmarc...@ulb.ac.be  
 wrote:


 Hi,

 I give the solution of the first of the last exercises.
 ...
 This motivates the definition of the following function from N to N,
 called factorial.
 factorial(0) = 1, and factorial(n) = n*(n-1)*(n-2)*(n-3) * ... *1, if
 is n is different from 0.

 Note this: if n is different from 0, for each n we have that  
 fact(n) =
 n*fact(n).

 Of course you meant fact(n)=n*fact(n-1).
 
 
 Yes, indeed.
 
 Note that later we will see stronger form of recursion, but here it is  
 just a typo mistake.
 
 Bruno
 
 
 http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/
 
 
 
 
 
--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-08-21 Thread Bruno Marchal
Thanks for telling Marty.

It is a pity you stop just before Cantor Theorem, but it could ask for  
some work if your math disposition have been dormant for a too long  
time.

I am sure you could come by, because what will follow will be a  
recurrent use of the same idea.

The difficulty, for many, is to understand what is a mathematical  
computation, but to explain this we have to explain what are the  
mathematical objects which will computed and be computed.

Sets of numbers and functions from numbers to numbers are those things  
which will be either computable or not computable.

Up to now, I am only introducing vocabulary, so that we can avoid  
future misunderstanding. Numbers, sets, functions are common in exact  
science, but rarely well known ...

I will soon explain Cantor theorem. And soon after should the  
mathematical discovery of the (mathematical) universal machine appear.

I have to explain a minimal amount of theoretical computer science to  
give a precise sense to the comp supervenience thesis.

I like to summarize 20th century computer science by its two main  
'discoveries', really two creative bombs, the universal machine, and  
the other universal machine. The universal machine, and the quantum  
universal machine. I put 'discoveries' in quote because strictly  
speaking they are thesis or hypothesis.

Take a look on what follows because it happen that some beginners  
understand math the day they understand the first non trivial result,  
but take it easy any way. It is a pleasure to share interest wherever  
we come from, and I appreciate your open mind,

Bruno


On 21 Aug 2009, at 16:22, m.a. wrote:

 Bruno,
I'm terribly sorry to disappoint you and ashamed to admit  
 that I'm throwing in the towel. This is an idiom used in  
 professional boxing; when a coach decides that his fighter can't  
 take anymore punishment, he ends the fight by throwing a towel into  
 the ring. I simply don't have the sort of mind that takes to  
 juggling letters, numbers and symbols in increasingly fine-grained,  
 complex arrangements. I think that in any endeavor, when we struggle  
 towards a goal, there should be some satisfaction...some sense of  
 accomplishment...in each step along the way. But in this quest, I  
 find each step to be difficult and unrewarding in and of itself.  
 Sometimes the goal is so compelling that we force ourselves to  
 overcome huge impediments to reach it; but in this case, I already  
 know what the goal is, and I am only motivated by the desire to  
 understand how it is proven. Well, I must be content to leave  
 verification of the proof to people who are far better able than I  
 to follow its intricacies. I trust they have checked it accurately  
 and will point out inconsistencies in this open forum if such exist.  
 Meanwhile, I'm happy to take it on faith. I shall certainly continue  
 to lurk here gleaning what I can from the philosophical debates  
 whose endless probing of the foundations of existence is a source of  
 constant fascination. Best,
   
   
   marty 
  a.









 - Original Message -
 From: Bruno Marchal marc...@ulb.ac.be
 To: everything-list@googlegroups.com
 Sent: Friday, August 21, 2009 3:47 AM
 Subject: Re: The seven step series

 
 
  On 21 Aug 2009, at 01:24, meekerdb @dslextreme.com wrote:
 
 
  On Thu, Aug 20, 2009 at 12:32 PM, Bruno Marchalmarc...@ulb.ac.be
  wrote:
 
 
  Hi,
 
  I give the solution of the first of the last exercises.
  ...
  This motivates the definition of the following function from N  
 to N,
  called factorial.
  factorial(0) = 1, and factorial(n) = n*(n-1)*(n-2)*(n-3) * ...  
 *1, if
  is n is different from 0.
 
  Note this: if n is different from 0, for each n we have that
  fact(n) =
  n*fact(n).
 
  Of course you meant fact(n)=n*fact(n-1).
 
 
  Yes, indeed.
 
  Note that later we will see stronger form of recursion, but here  
 it is
  just a typo mistake.
 
  Bruno
 
 
  http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/
 
 
 
 
 
 

http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-08-20 Thread Bruno Marchal


Hi,

I give the solution of the first of the last exercises.


I reason aloud. I go slowly for those who did not get some math  
courses, or just forget them.  I cannot stress the importance of the  
notion of bijection in the mathematical discovery of the universal  
machine (the quote means that a nuance will be added here).

Counting is not so important. Th exercise motivation is in to develop  
familiarity with the notion of function and bijection. Then counting  
things provides example of functions from N to N.


 1) count the number of bijections from a set A to itself.  (= card{x
 such that x is bijection from A to A})


This does not seem very obvious, so let us begin with the simplest  
set, for example the one which admits the shorter description when  
written in extension, that is the empty set { }.

The question in this case is: count the number of bijection between  
{ } and { }.

Hmm... This smells the subtle trap and it may be a good advise to  
avoid the simplest set or number. Zero and the empty set may be  
simplest in term of description but may be harder conceptually.

A simple case, in this and many cases, would be a set with not much  
elements. Let us count the number of bijections from {a, b} to itself.  
i.e. the bijections from {a, b} to {a, b}.

Here some beginners could have a trouble: I don't remember what is a  
bijection. Well, the exercise is obviously with notes. I am not yet  
asking to buy a webcam so that I can look if you are not cheating, all  
right?

Two things can happen. Either you find the passage in your diary where  
I explain bijection with the legendary story of the humans who cannot  
count, and compare the bigness of sets by using ropes.

You may remember how the farmer compare their *set* of animals,  
without being able to count. They compare two sets of animals by  
attaching a rope to ONE animal belonging to the set of your animals,  
say, and you bring that to ONE animal of your neighbor.
Three things can happen:
1) All your animals get attached to a rope, and got attached to some  
neighbor's animals, but some other animal of the neighbor are still  
freely going here and there. In this situation we say damned, the set  
of animals of my neighbor is bigger than mine.
2) All your animals get they rope, and got attached  to the neighbor's  
animals. And all neighbor's animals are attached. In this situation we  
say OK, my set of animals has the same cardinality than the set of my  
neighbor animals. Cardinality is the measure of set, when we compare  
it in this way. Now, this is the situation where a bijection exists.
3) All the neighbor's animal are attached to the rope, yet some of  
your own animals remain free. You can attach the rope to those free  
animals, but you will be unable to attach them to some neighbor  
animal, they are already all attached. In this situation you say  
nothing, because you are polite, you just let the neighbor saying  
damned, the set of animals of my neighbor is bigger than mine.

   Or you don't remember that story, so you consult the austere  
notes with the definition. A, B ... represent sets.

A bijection between A and B is a function from A to B which is ONE-ONE  
and ONTO.

And what is a function? A set of couples (x, y), x in A, y in B,  
verifying the condition that no x in A is sent on different y in B. In  
a very large sense, the element of B depend on the element of A, and  
that dependence is represented by a couple (x, y).

With the farmer, the couples where made with one animal x attached by  
a rope to one animal y:  (x, y).

Well let us go back to the bijections from {a, b} to {a, b}. Oh, I see  
some anxiousness can rise due to the fact that we have the same set of  
both side. Why would ever a farmer compare the bigness of its set of  
animals with the bigness of its set of animals? Is that not a pure  
mathematical absurdity?

To ease the pain, in math, consists always in simplifying, so, just to  
keep the intuition provided by the farmer, let us distinguish the  
animal's neighbor, those which makes the arrival set, by different  
letters. And let us first search the bijections from {a, b} to {c, d}.  
{a, b} is the set of my animals. {c, d} is the set of animals of my  
neighbor. OK?

Well I have to build a bijection, which is a set, so I have to begin  
by {, indicating I am building a set. Of course, this is implicit in  
the farmer's mind, because his goal consists in just comparing the two  
sets. But our goal is to find all bijections. So we have to be clear  
about them as mathematically represented objects, and bijections, like  
functions, have been defined or represented as sets.

Now I have to choose one of my animals; let us choose a. and attach  
the rope. The description of the bijection looks like:

{(a,

I have to choose an animal belonging to the set of my neighbor's  
animals. Well, I have two choices: c or d. Let us choose c. The  
description of the bijection looks 

Re: The seven step series

2009-08-20 Thread meekerdb @dslextreme.com

On Thu, Aug 20, 2009 at 12:32 PM, Bruno Marchalmarc...@ulb.ac.be wrote:


 Hi,

 I give the solution of the first of the last exercises.
...
 This motivates the definition of the following function from N to N,
 called factorial.
 factorial(0) = 1, and factorial(n) = n*(n-1)*(n-2)*(n-3) * ... *1, if
 is n is different from 0.

 Note this: if n is different from 0, for each n we have that fact(n) =
 n*fact(n).

Of course you meant fact(n)=n*fact(n-1).

Brent

--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-08-19 Thread Bruno Marchal

Hi,

Just a reminder, for me, and perhaps some training for you. In  
preparation to the mathematical discovery of the universal machine.

exercises:

1) count the number of bijections from a set A to itself.  (= card{x  
such that x is bijection from A to A})

2) describe some canonical bijection between 2^A and the powerset of A.

3) I say that a set S is a proper subset of A if it is a subset of A,  
and different from A.
 We have seen that there is a bijection between N and 2N = {0, 2,  
4, 6, ...}. (see below *)
 2N is a proper subset of N.
 So we see that an infinite set can have a bijection with a proper  
subset.
 The question is, could that be possible for a finite set?

The bijection between N and 2N is the set {(0,0), (1,2), (2, 4), (3,  
6), (4, 8), ...}.  More schematically, if you remember the ropes:

N  2N

0 --- 0
1 2
2 4
3 6


4) Be sure that you have been convinced by Brent  that there is a  
bijection between N and NxN, and between N and NxNxN, and etc. That is  
be sure there is a bijection between N and N^m for each N.

5) Key exercise for the sequel. First a definition. An alphabet A is a  
non empty finite set. I call its elements letter.
Exemple. A = {a, b, c},, B = {0, 1}.. By A+ I mean the set of finite  
words on the alphabet A. A word is a finite sequence of letters, from  
some alphabet, like, on the alphabet A, aaabab, acbababcccacab, etc.
IA+ is obviously infinite, it contains *notably* a, aa, aaa, ,  
a, aa, aaa, ...

The word word has a larger meaning in math than in natural language.  
On the usual alphabet {A, B, ... Z}, an expression like  
HHYUJLIFSEFGXWKKODENN is a fully respectable word.

Show that for any alphabet A, there is a bijection between N and A+


Soon (asap, though) the proof of many theorems found by Cantor.  
Notably that there is NO bijection from N to N^N.
Then Cantor proof will be done again and again, and again, ... in  
deeper and deeper and deeper contexts.

Please ask any questions. It is not too late before we go in the  
*very* interesting matter, and very illuminating with respect to the  
question of the existence of universal machines, languages and numbers.

Bruno


http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-08-19 Thread Bruno Marchal


On 19 Aug 2009, at 23:03, meekerdb @dslextreme.com wrote:


 On Wed, Aug 19, 2009 at 12:12 PM, Bruno Marchalmarc...@ulb.ac.be  
 wrote:

 Hi,

 Just a reminder, for me, and perhaps some training for you. In
 preparation to the mathematical discovery of the universal machine.

 exercises:
 ...
 

 4) Be sure that you have been convinced by Brent  that there is a
 bijection between N and NxN, and between N and NxNxN, and etc. That  
 is
 be sure there is a bijection between N and N^m for each N.

 Don't you mean for each m?

Yes. Sorry. I type too much quickly. I made other mistakes of that  
type. Hope you can see them and make the correction.
In case of doubt ask, like Brent.

Some people seems afraid asking questions, please, do. Nobody judge  
you. We have different baggages.

Bruno


http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-08-14 Thread Bruno Marchal

Brent,

I said: this is food for Friday and the week-end, and you provide  
already the solutions!

It is OK, and you are correct. Thanks for playing.
I add short comments. I have not much time till monday, and I intend  
to come back on some issues. I will comment the important recent post  
by David though.


On 13 Aug 2009, at 22:49, Brent Meeker wrote:

 Bruno Marchal wrote:

 ...
 4) Key questions for the sequel, on which you can meditate:

 - is there a bijection between N and NxN?  (NxN = the cartesian
 product of N with N)
 - is there a bijection between N and N^N?


 You're making me think, Bruno. :-)

 A bijection between N and NxN can be constructed by enumerating all  
 the N pairs summing to 0, followed by those summing to 1, followed  
 by those summing to 2 as follows (per Cantor):

 N - NxN
 1   0,0
 2  1,0
 3  0,1
 4  2,0
 5  1,1
 6  0,2
 7  3,0
 8  2,1
 9  1,2
 10 0,3
 ...

OK.  I hope everyone see that your bijection is indeed one-one and  
onto. Each number is sned on one couple, and each couple is touched by  
the bijection. I take it as a function from N to NxN.







 New exercises for the adventurous:

 In the context of sets, 2 will represent the set {0, 1}. OK?  And 3
 will represent {0, 1, 2}, etc.

 Find a bijection between NxN and N^2

this means find a bijection between NXN and the set of functions
 from 2(= {0,1})  to N.

 Since there are two elements in the domain {0,1}, if we write down  
 all pairs of numbers (n,m) and map 0 to the first and 1 to the  
 second we will have constructed all functions from 2 to N.  But  
 above we've already enumerated all pairs of numbers, NxN.  So we  
 just map 0 to the number in first one and 1 to the second and we  
 have an enumerated list of the functions from 2 to N.


 N - NxN  -  N^2
 1   0,0   {(0,0) (1,0)}
 2  1,0   {(0,1) (1,0)}
 3  0,1   {(0,0) (1,1)}
 4  2,0   {(0,2) (1,0)}
 5  1,1   {(0,1) (1,1)}
 6  0,2   {(0,0) (1,2)}
 7  3,0   ...
 8  2,1
 9  1,2
 10 0,3
 ...


 Define NxNxN by Nx(NxN), with (x,y,z) represented (bijectively) by  
 (x,
 (y,z)) OK?

 Find a bijection between NxNxN and N^3

 Show that there is a bijection between NxNxNxNxNx ... xN (m times)  
 and
 N^m, in the sense of above. That is
 NxNxNxNxNx ... xN is defined by Nx(Nx(Nx ... ), and N^m is the  
 set
 of functions from m to N, and m = {0, 1, ... m-1}.

 First note that we can use the mapping NxN - N to reduce NxNx...xN  
 (m times) to NxNx...xN (m-1 times) by substituting for a pair in NxN  
 the number from N determined by the above bijection.  So we can  
 construct a bijection NxNx...xN - N.


OK.





 Second, N^m is the set of mappings from m to all m-tuples of numbers  
 to N.  So if we write down the m-tuples, i.e. the elements of  
 NxNx...xN (m times) as we did the pairs above and then for each m- 
 tuple map 0 to the first element, 1 to the second, and so forth up  
 to the mth element we will have constructed all the functions N^m  
 and we will have enumerated them, i.e. shown a bijection between N^m  
 and N.  Since bijection is transitive, this also shows there is a  
 bijection between NxNx...xN (n times) and N^m (n and m not  
 necessarily equal).

 For the very adventurous:

 Find a bijection between NxNxNx   and N^N?

 Hmmm?  I could say I've already proven it above or that it follows  
 from the above by induction, but the scheme would require writing  
 down infinitely many infinite lists so I'm not sure the above proof  
 generalizes to N^N.


I will come back on this next week. A simple way to see that there is  
indeed a bijection between NxNx and N^N, consists in observing  
that an element of NxNx... is really an infinite-uple. A couple is a 2- 
uple, a triple is a 3-uple, and an element of NxNxNx... is really an  
infinity-uple (a, b, c, ). This is just a sequence of number. The  
canonical bijection is given by

(a, b, c, ...)     {(0, a), (1, b), (2, c), }

A function from N to N is really just an infinite sequence of numbers.  
This generalize your correspondence above between NxN and N^2  (with 2  
= {0, 1}).

So now we know that there is a bijection between NxNxNx ...xN  (m  
times) and N^m. And you have shown all those sets can be put in  
bijection with N.
And we know that the infinite cartesian product NxNx... is in  
bijection with N^N.

But the question which remains is: does there exist a bijection  
between NxNx and N?





 Despite perhaps the appearances, all those new exercises are rather
 easy. The above in 4) key questions are more difficult.

 Oh! I forget to ask you the simplest exercise :

 Find a bijection between N and N^1,  with 1 = {0}.

 N^1 is of course the set of functions from 1 to N, i.e. from {0} to  
 N.

You did not solve this one? Too much easy perhaps :)

An element of N^1 is a function from {0} 

Re: The seven step series

2009-08-13 Thread Bruno Marchal


On 12 Aug 2009, at 19:55, Bruno Marchal wrote:



 1) Convince yourself that if A and B are finite sets, then there  
 exists a bijection between A and B if and only if card(A) = card(B).

Only you can convince yourself. I try to help by going very slowly,  
but people should really mind it y themselves, without hesitating to  
reread the definitions in case of doubt, or to attack me on the typo  
errors, I mean it is not very difficult, but revise well the  
definitions if problems.

I provide a detailed solution of the first problem, hints for the  
other problems, and new problems for the adventurous.



 2) If A has n elements (card(A) = n), how many bijections exists  
 from A to B?

  Again start with simple examples, and try to generalize.

  For example, how many bijections from {a, b, c} to {1, 2}. How  
 many bijections from (a, b, c} to {a, b, c}?


How many bijections are there from {a, b, c} to {1, 2}?

Let us try to build one. A bijection is a function which has to be one- 
one and onto. So I start from {a, b, c}, and I build my bijective  
function, so I open the accolades { , I open the parenthesis ( of  
the first couple of my function, and I choose a in {a, b, c},  
which is the set of input/argument of my function. This very beginning  
looks like

{(a,

And I have to decide where in the set {1, 2} a will be sent.  
Remembering all the times that I am building a function, so that once  
a is sent, I can no more send it again, and that my goal here is to  
build a bijection, so that I cannot send two different elements of my  
starting set on the same element in the arrival set. Nor should I miss  
an element of the arrival set.

Well, cool, I *can* continue, I have actually two choices, I can send  
a on 1, or I can send a on 2. I decide to send it on 1,

This means (a, 1) will belong to my bijection, well, the one I try to  
build.
My future bijection looks like

{(a, 1),

And I have to decide where b is send, now:   {(a, 1), (b,

Could I send b to 1? No. I can't. The function would not be one- 
one! I do have a solution yet, I can send b on 2.
Note that our freedom has decreased, here. Now my bijection looks like

{(a, 1), (b, 2),

And I have to decide where I will send c.  {(a, 1), (b, 2), (c,

Could I send it on 1? No. I can't. The function would not be one-one!
Could I send it on 2? No. I can't. The function would not be one-one!
Is there anywhere else? Well, the function is from {a, b, c} to {1,  
2}. If you want a function which i just ONTO, it is OK, send c on  
1 or 2 as you wish, but none of such function can be one-one.

Or attempt has failed.

OK. Perhaps it is like in the Sudoku, and our first choice was bad. My  
be we should have send a, not on 1, but on 2, After all we get  
two choices at the beginning. Surely we have made the bad choice. So  
let us try again:

{(a, 2),

and then

{(a, 2), (b, 1),    we realize with some anxiousness that the  
number of choices has gone again from 2 to 1, and now we have to send  
c on something which has to be different from 1 and 2, and yet  
in the arrival set {1, 2}. Zero possibility, we are trapped. Perhaps,  
we should have begin by sending b. This would not change anything.

We have to conclude that there is no bijection from {a, b, c} to {1, 2}.

Is there a bijection from {1, 2} to {a, b, c}. No. In this case  
convince yourself that you can build a function which is one-one, but  
that there is no onto functions.

Convince yourself that if there is a bijection from A to B, then there  
is a bijection from B to A. That is why we talk also of bijection  
between A and B. Hint: show that to each bijection from A to B, you  
can associate canonically a bijection from B to A.

How many bijections from (a, b, c} to {a, b, c}? I let you search.  
Hint: look what happen to our choices above, compare to the choices in  
our previews counting.



 3) can you find, or define a bijection between the infinite set N,  
 and the infinite set E = {0, 2, 4, 6, 8, ...} (E for even).


This means, by definition of bijection, can you find a function from N  
to E which is both one-one and onto.

Example:

The identity function which send n on n, that is I = {(0,0), (1,1),  
(2,2), (3, 3) ...} is a function from N to N which is onto and one- 
one. It is a bijection between N and itself. But it is not a function  
from N to E.

The function which send n on 8*n, that is, f8 = {(0,0) (1,8) (2,16),  
(3, 24), ...} is a function from N to E. And it is one-one. But it is  
not onto. The number 4 in E remains untouched by it, like 6, or 66, or  
82, and many other numbers in E.

To find a bijection between N and E, just search for a function which  
is one and onto, from N to E.





 4) Key questions for the sequel, on which you can meditate:

 - is there a bijection between N and NxN?  (NxN = the cartesian  
 product of N with N)
 - is there a bijection between N and N^N?


New exercises for the adventurous:

In the context of sets, 2 

Re: The seven step series

2009-08-13 Thread Brent Meeker





Bruno Marchal wrote:
...
  
4) Key questions for the sequel, on which you can meditate:

- is there a bijection between N and NxN?  (NxN = the cartesian  
product of N with N)
- is there a bijection between N and N^N?

  
  
  

You're making me think, Bruno. :-)

A bijection between N and NxN can be constructed by enumerating all the
N pairs summing to 0, followed by those summing to 1, followed by those
summing to 2 as follows (per Cantor):

N - NxN
1   0,0
2  1,0
3  0,1
4  2,0
5  1,1
6  0,2
7  3,0
8  2,1
9  1,2
10  0,3
...



  
New exercises for the adventurous:

In the context of sets, 2 will represent the set {0, 1}. OK?  And 3  
will represent {0, 1, 2}, etc.

Find a bijection between NxN and N^2

   this means find a bijection between NXN and the set of functions  
from 2(= {0,1})  to N.
  

Since there are two elements in the domain {0,1}, if we write down all
pairs of numbers (n,m) and map 0 to the first and 1 to the second we
will have constructed all functions from 2 to N. But above we've
already enumerated all pairs of numbers, NxN. So we just map 0 to the
number in first one and 1 to the second and we have an enumerated list
of the functions from 2 to N.


N - NxN - N^2
1   0,0 {(0,0) (1,0)}
2  1,0 {(0,1) (1,0)}
3  0,1 {(0,0) (1,1)}
4  2,0 {(0,2) (1,0)}
5  1,1 {(0,1) (1,1)}
6  0,2 {(0,0) (1,2)}
7  3,0 ...
8  2,1
9  1,2
10  0,3
...



  
Define NxNxN by Nx(NxN), with (x,y,z) represented (bijectively) by (x, 
(y,z)) OK?

Find a bijection between NxNxN and N^3

Show that there is a bijection between NxNxNxNxNx ... xN (m times) and  
N^m, in the sense of above. That is
NxNxNxNxNx ... xN is defined by Nx(Nx(Nx ... ), and N^m is the set  
of functions from m to N, and m = {0, 1, ... m-1}.
  

First note that we can use the mapping NxN - N to reduce NxNx...xN
(m times) to NxNx...xN (m-1 times) by substituting for a pair in NxN
the number from N determined by the above bijection. So we can
construct a bijection NxNx...xN - N.

Second, N^m is the set of mappings from m to all m-tuples of numbers to
N. So if we write down the m-tuples, i.e. the elements of NxNx...xN (m
times) as we did the pairs above and then for each m-tuple map 0 to the
first element, 1 to the second, and so forth up to the mth element we
will have constructed all the functions N^m and we will have enumerated
them, i.e. shown a bijection between N^m and N. Since bijection is
transitive, this also shows there is a bijection between NxNx...xN (n
times) and N^m (n and m not necessarily equal).


  
For the very adventurous:

Find a bijection between NxNxNx   and N^N?
  

Hmmm? I could say I've already proven it above or that it follows from
the above by induction, but the scheme would require writing down
infinitely many infinite lists so I'm not sure the above proof
generalizes to N^N.

Brent


  
Despite perhaps the appearances, all those new exercises are rather  
easy. The above in "4)" key questions are more difficult.

Oh! I forget to ask you the simplest exercise :

Find a bijection between N and N^1,  with 1 = {0}.

N^1 is of course the set of functions from 1 to N, i.e. from {0} to N.

Don't worry, if this last exercise didn't give the clue (for the new  
exercises), I will explain why this new exercises are really simple,  
and why it is simpler than the key questions.

OK, this is food for friday and the week-end,
Ask any questions, or do any remarks. We approach surely to the first  
big theorem (Cantor).

Bruno



http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/



--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups Everything List group.  To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com  To unsubscribe from this group, send email to everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com  For more options, visit this group at http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---





Re: The seven step series

2009-08-13 Thread Brian Tenneson

There is an explicit formula that maps N onto Q.. I found it some years 
back. 

Brent Meeker wrote:
 Bruno Marchal wrote:
 ...
 4) Key questions for the sequel, on which you can meditate:

 - is there a bijection between N and NxN?  (NxN = the cartesian  
 product of N with N)
 - is there a bijection between N and N^N?
 

   
 You're making me think, Bruno. :-)

 A bijection between N and NxN can be constructed by enumerating all 
 the N pairs summing to 0, followed by those summing to 1, followed by 
 those summing to 2 as follows (per Cantor):

 N - NxN
 1   0,0
 2  1,0
 3  0,1
 4  2,0
 5  1,1
 6  0,2
 7  3,0
 8  2,1
 9  1,2
 10 0,3
 ...


 New exercises for the adventurous:

 In the context of sets, 2 will represent the set {0, 1}. OK?  And 3  
 will represent {0, 1, 2}, etc.

 Find a bijection between NxN and N^2

this means find a bijection between NXN and the set of functions  
 from 2(= {0,1})  to N.
   
 Since there are two elements in the domain {0,1}, if we write down all 
 pairs of numbers (n,m) and map 0 to the first and 1 to the second we 
 will have constructed all functions from 2 to N.  But above we've 
 already enumerated all pairs of numbers, NxN.  So we just map 0 to the 
 number in first one and 1 to the second and we have an enumerated list 
 of the functions from 2 to N.


 N - NxN  -  N^2
 1   0,0   {(0,0) (1,0)}
 2  1,0   {(0,1) (1,0)}
 3  0,1   {(0,0) (1,1)}
 4  2,0   {(0,2) (1,0)}
 5  1,1   {(0,1) (1,1)}
 6  0,2   {(0,0) (1,2)}
 7  3,0   ...
 8  2,1
 9  1,2
 10 0,3
 ...


 Define NxNxN by Nx(NxN), with (x,y,z) represented (bijectively) by (x, 
 (y,z)) OK?

 Find a bijection between NxNxN and N^3

 Show that there is a bijection between NxNxNxNxNx ... xN (m times) and  
 N^m, in the sense of above. That is
 NxNxNxNxNx ... xN is defined by Nx(Nx(Nx ... ), and N^m is the set  
 of functions from m to N, and m = {0, 1, ... m-1}.
   
 First note that we can use the mapping NxN - N to reduce NxNx...xN (m 
 times) to NxNx...xN (m-1 times) by substituting for a pair in NxN the 
 number from N determined by the above bijection.  So we can construct 
 a bijection NxNx...xN - N.

 Second, N^m is the set of mappings from m to all m-tuples of numbers 
 to N.  So if we write down the m-tuples, i.e. the elements of 
 NxNx...xN (m times) as we did the pairs above and then for each 
 m-tuple map 0 to the first element, 1 to the second, and so forth up 
 to the mth element we will have constructed all the functions N^m and 
 we will have enumerated them, i.e. shown a bijection between N^m and 
 N.  Since bijection is transitive, this also shows there is a 
 bijection between NxNx...xN (n times) and N^m (n and m not necessarily 
 equal).

 For the very adventurous:

 Find a bijection between NxNxNx   and N^N?
   
 Hmmm?  I could say I've already proven it above or that it follows 
 from the above by induction, but the scheme would require writing down 
 infinitely many infinite lists so I'm not sure the above proof 
 generalizes to N^N.

 Brent

 Despite perhaps the appearances, all those new exercises are rather  
 easy. The above in 4) key questions are more difficult.

 Oh! I forget to ask you the simplest exercise :

 Find a bijection between N and N^1,  with 1 = {0}.

 N^1 is of course the set of functions from 1 to N, i.e. from {0} to N.

 Don't worry, if this last exercise didn't give the clue (for the new  
 exercises), I will explain why this new exercises are really simple,  
 and why it is simpler than the key questions.

 OK, this is food for friday and the week-end,
 Ask any questions, or do any remarks. We approach surely to the first  
 big theorem (Cantor).

 Bruno



 http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/


 


--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-08-12 Thread Bruno Marchal

On 11 Aug 2009, at 22:24, Mirek Dobsicek wrote:



 Well, A^B is the set of functions from B to A. By definition of set
 exponentiation.

 I'd just like to point out that Bruno in his previous post in the  
 seven
 step serii made a small typo

 A^B - the set of all functions from A to B.

 It should have been from B to A. The latest post is correct in this  
 respect.


And now Simplicius is coming back and asks:  but why do you define  
the exponentiation of sets, A^B, by the set of functions from B to A?.

The answer of the sadistic teacher: this is a DEFINITION, and is part  
of the program. If you have complains about the program, write a  
letter to the minister of education.

Hmm...

A better answer is given by the solution of the preceding exercise:


 If card(A) = n, and card(B) = m. What is
 card(A^B)?



It happens that if A^B is defined as the set of functions from B to A,  
then card(A^B) is given by card(A)^card(B)

How many functions exist from a set with m elements in a set with n  
elements? n^m.

Hope you see that n^m is NOT equal to m^n (when n and m are  
different). 3^4 = 3x3x3x3 = 81, and 4^3 = 4x4x4 = 64.
2^7 = 128, 7^2 = 49.

In that way, A^B generalizes for set what n^m is for numbers.

And why card(A^B) = card(A)^card(B) ?

You can see this in the following way: let card(A) = m, and card(B) =  
n. We must understand why card(A^B) = n^m.

For example a function from {a, b, c, d, e, f, g} in {0, 1, 2, 3, 4}.  
To fix the idea. So m = 7, and n = 5. OK?

Let us build an arbitrary function F. Well,we begin with F =  
{(a, ..., and we have to say where a is sent. We have five (n)  
choices, and then we have to choose where b is sent, and we have again  
n choices, and for each first choice any second choice is acceptable  
so we have 5 (n) choices multiplied by 5 (n) choices, itself  
multiplied by 5 (n) choices, as many times there are elements in the  
starting set, that is 7 (m). This gives 5 x 5 x 5 x 5 x 5 x 5 x 5,  
that is 5^7. or more generally n x n x n x n x ... x n, m times.

OK?

We will be interested in N^N. That is, the set of functions from N to N.
The set of computable functions will be an important subset of that set.

Let me give a precise definition of bijection, as I promise.


I need two rather useful definitions.

  - I will say that a function from A to B is ONTO, if all elements of  
B appears in the couples of the function. Note that card(B) has to be  
less or equal to card(A) to make that possible, by the functional  
condition.

  - I will say a function is ONE-ONE, if two different elements of A  
are sent to two different elements of B. Note that card(A) has to be  
less or equal to card(B) to make that possible.
The condition one-one is the reverse of the functional condition. The  
functional conditions says that an element cannot be sent on two  
different elements (a time cannot give two temperature!), and the one- 
one condition says that two different elements cannot be sent on one  
element.

Exercises: build many examples with little finite sets. You may search  
examples for infinite sets.


OK. The definition of bijection. I will say that a function is a  
bijection between A and B if it is both a function ONTO from A to B,  
and a function ONE-ONE from A to B. we say more quicky that f is a  
bijection if f is both onto and one-one.

Exercises:   for 2)  below, the real needed exercise is:  do you  
understand the question? Unless you like to count things, but such  
skills are not needed for the sequel.

1) Convince yourself that if A and B are finite sets, then there  
exists a bijection between A and B if and only if card(A) = card(B).

2) If A has n elements (card(A) = n), how many bijections exists from  
A to B?

  Again start with simple examples, and try to generalize.

  For example, how many bijections from {a, b, c} to {1, 2}. How  
many bijections from (a, b, c} to {a, b, c}?

3) can you find, or define a bijection between the infinite set N, and  
the infinite set E = {0, 2, 4, 6, 8, ...} (E for even).

4) Key questions for the sequel, on which you can meditate:

- is there a bijection between N and NxN?  (NxN = the cartesian  
product of N with N)
- is there a bijection between N and N^N?


Bruno

http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-08-11 Thread Mirek Dobsicek


 3) compute { } ^ { } and card({ } ^ { })

 If card(A) = n, and card(B) = m. What is
 card(A^B)? 

I find it neat to write | {} ^ {} | = | { {} } | = 1 :-)
It's almost like ASCII art. Just wanted to signal that I'm following.

mirek

--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-08-11 Thread Bruno Marchal


On 11 Aug 2009, at 15:32, Mirek Dobsicek wrote:



 3) compute { } ^ { } and card({ } ^ { })

 If card(A) = n, and card(B) = m. What is
 card(A^B)?

 I find it neat to write | {} ^ {} | = | { {} } | = 1 :-)

You will make panic those who are not familiar with symbols!



 It's almost like ASCII art. Just wanted to signal that I'm following.

Thank for telling me.


OK, people, good time to solve the problems. Please don't read this  
post, unless you find it is the good time for you to do some math. If  
not, postpone until a good time. Technical posts have to be studied,  
not read. Take the time needed. Tell me if I am too quick.

The solution of 3) has been given.

Let us look at:


 If card(A) = n, and card(B) = m. What is
 card(A^B)?


card(A) = n
This means A is a finite set with n elements.

card(B) = m
This means B is a finite set with m elements.

Let us simplify by supposing that m = 3, and n = 2. Hoping that the  
reasoning done for finding the solution on the particular case will  
inspire the reasoning for finding the solution in the general case.

Let us imagine that A is the set {a, b, c}, with its three elements,  
and that B is the set {1, 2}, with its two elements.

And let us try now to remember what is the question.

The question is: what is card(A^B)?

Well, card(A^B) is the number of elements of A^B.   By definition of  
the cardinal.

What is A^B?

Well, A^B is the set of functions from B to A. By definition of set  
exponentiation.

Well, if the question was just what is card(A^B)?, this would  
provide the best solution, or the best note if you want. But the  
teacher provided the information that A has n elements, and that B has  
m elements, and intuitively we can bet that the number of functions  
from a set to another can depend on the number of elements of each  
sets involved, so that what is card( A^B)? meant probably how to  
compute card(A^B) in function of card(A) and card(B).

Ok, we decided to look on the particular case with A = {a, b, c}, and  
B = {1, 2}.

A^B = the set of all functions from B to A.

That is the set of functions from {1, 2} to {a, b, c}.

Well, let us try to find, or to build, one function from B to A.

But , here a moment of panic can occur, (empirical observation). For  
the unnameable sake, what *is* a function? What is a function from B  
to A.
Well, if it is an open manual home work, such panic can be eased by  
looking in the math notes. You may remember the motivation or the  
informal sense of what a function represents, which is a relation of  
dependency, and this is in the most general sense, so that all  
possible dependency are tolerated. For a function from B to A, it  
means the element of A depends in function of the elements of B. Such  
a dependency is well described by a couple (x, y) with x in B and y in  
A.

we have (x,y) belongs-to F representing the meaning that y depends in  
the function F of x.

Think about x as time and y as temperature.

So, a function from B to A is just a set of couples (x, y) with x in B  
and y in A, with the functional restriction that x is not send to two  
different values y. At each time x, you can have only one temperature y.

That is, here: a set of couples (x, y) with x in {1, 2} and y in {a,  
b, c}, and such that if (1, x) belongs-to F, no other (1, y) belongs  
to F.

Let us build one function from {1, 2} to {a, b, c}.

OK, 1, from B,  can determine what in A ? Well, we have three  
possibilities a, b and c. OK, i will use my free will to decide that  
for this function I want now, 1 will determine a. So I put the couple  
(1, a) in the function.

At this stage, the function looks like {(1, a)}.

Finished?

No, a function from a set to another one gives a values, outcomes,  
outputs for all elements of its domain. I have to say what is  
determine by 2, in B. OK, I will use my free will again, and decide to  
add the couples (2, a).

At this stage, the function looks like {(1, a) (2, a)}.

Finished?

Yes.

We do have a function from B to A. The set {(1, a) (2, a)} describes  
completely a function from B to A, a so-called constant function.  
think of 1 and 2 as moment of times, and think of a, b, c, as possible  
temperature. The function  {(1, a) (2, a)} describe a case here the  
temperature is constant and equal to a.

Finished? No, we have to find all functions from B to A. All functions  
from {1, 2} to {a, b, c}.

Well actually, we need to find only the number of such functions. For  
1 I have three choices, then for 2, I have still three choices, and  
the choices are independent, so that for each choice the remaining  
three choice will lead to distinct functions, this make 3 X 3  
functions = 9 functions:

{(1, a) (2, a)}
{(1, a) (2, b)}
{(1, a) (2, c)}

{(1, b) (2, a)}
{(1, b) (2, b)}
{(1, b) (2, c)}

{(1, c) (2, a)}
{(1, c) (2, b)}
{(1, c) (2, c)}

so A^B = {{(1, a) (2, a)}, {(1, a) (2, b)}, {(1, a) (2, c)}, ... ,  
{(1, c) (2, c)}}, and card(A^B) = 9. In this case. This give 

Re: The seven step series

2009-08-11 Thread Bruno Marchal


On 11 Aug 2009, at 22:24, Mirek Dobsicek wrote:



 Well, A^B is the set of functions from B to A. By definition of set
 exponentiation.

 I'd just like to point out that Bruno in his previous post in the  
 seven
 step serii made a small typo

 A^B - the set of all functions from A to B.


I wrote that? I was wrong. Thanks for saying.




 It should have been from B to A.


Yes!




 The latest post is correct in this respect.

Thank God!

Apologies for typos, mispelling, and believe me, I can do even bigger  
mistakes. I will. Be vigilant.

Bruno



http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-08-05 Thread Bruno Marchal

Hi Mirek,


On 05 Aug 2009, at 00:52, Mirek Dobsicek wrote:

 I've ordered the dialogue from a second-hand book shop :-) The  
 Stanford
 encyclopedia says
 Arguably, it is his (Plato) greatest work on anything.
 So I'll give it a try :-)


I love that book, and it is also my favorite piece of Plato.
To be sure, I don't think it is needed to understand neither UDA nor  
AUDA, but it can help.


 This is probably the key problem for me. I know next to nothing about
 provability, the logic of provability, PA/ZF provers.

 I know that quite often you reference Boolos 1993 - The Logic of
 Provability. I took a look at it at Google Books preview but ... there
 is something missing in my education. From the beginning I am puzzled
 with Why?, what?. What a headache :-)

You miss an introductory course on mathematical logic.
Have you herad about Gödel's incompletness theorem. Boolos book  
explains the sequel.

I thought that, after Hofstadter best selling book on Gödel's theorem  
(Gödel, Escher, Bach), it would be possible to talk on mathematical  
logic to the layman, like we can talk on physics to the layman. But I  
was wrong. Gödel's theorem is not yet part of the common knowledge,  
and when it is used by non mathematician, in general it is abused.



 x divides y if and only if it exists a number z such that y = x*z.

 I don't dare to correct your english but there is/exists a  
 number ...
 is what I would write.

Thanks.




 Ad 3) If natural numbers and their relations are the only entities  
 which
 do exist then me, you, everything is a recipe of a Turing-computable
 number.

 No. Not at all. Sorry. Gosh, you will be very surprised if you follow
 the UDA-7. On the contrary. Arithmetical truth VASTLY extends the
 computable domain. Most relations between numbers are not Turing  
 emulable.

 Aha! Then I really have a wrong mental picture of your work. I
 understood to arithmetical realism along the lines of this quotation
 from the Stanford article on realism:

 According to a platonist about arithmetic, the truth of the  
 sentence '7
 is prime' entails the existence of an abstract object, the number 7.
 This object is abstract because it has no spatial or temporal  
 location,
 and is causally inert. A platonic realist about arithmetic will say  
 that
 the number 7 exists and instantiates the property of being prime
 independently of anyone's beliefs, linguistic practices, conceptual
 schemes, and so on.

That is quite correct. All mathematicians are realist about  
arithmetic, and most are realist about sets. But set realism is a much  
more stronger belief than arithmetical realism.
Comp necessitates arithmetical realism if only to be able to state  
Church thesis. Theoretical computer scientist are realist, because  
they belief that all machine either stop or not stop.




 So I thought that you essentially take
 a) Numbers and their properties and relations exists.

Yes, but some people put to much sense in exists. It is the  
mathematical usual sense, like when you derive there exists a prime  
number from the statement 17 is a prime number. No need to invoke  
Plato Heaven, in the assumption.




 b) Now, since you don't assume existence of anything else = your  
 body,
 your bike and coffee must emerge as patterns in the world of numbers.

I am agnostic. I assume neither that something else exists nor that it  
does not exist, and then I prove from the assumption that we are  
turing emulable, that physics is no more the fundamental science. I  
prove that if we are machine then matter has to be an emerging  
epistemological concept, and physics is a branch of machine biology/ 
psychology/theology, or mathematical computer science.
b) is obviously non valid. The fact that bike an coffee must emerge  
from numbers is really the conclusion of the whole UD reasoning. It is  
not because I don't assume them, it is because their independent  
existence is shown contradictory.
I show that mechanism makes physicalism epistemologically  
inconsistent. Even if matter really exists, it cannot be used to  
justify our belief in matter. A slight application of Occam razor  
eliminates matter, at that stage.


 c) Taking the Church-Turing thesis, these patterns are Turing- 
 computable.

Not at all. The world of number is provably not Turing-computable.  
Only a very tiny part of the world of number is computable. There is a  
whole branch of mathematical logic devoted to the study of the degree  
of non computability of the relations existing among the numbers.
Church thesis asserts only that the *computable* patterns are Turing  
computable. It is just the assertion that Turing computability can be  
used to define computability.


 d) Definitely, the vast majority of all patterns is not Turing- 
 computable.

I don't understand.




 This is how I have thought about your working framework. Notice,  
 that I
 don't talk about what you try to show, argue for, want to end up  
 with etc.

My framework, 

Re: The seven step series

2009-08-05 Thread John Mikes
Bruno, just to take off some mal-deserved feathers:
I think Theaetetus has two different 'e' sounds one after the other (anybody
can pronounce him better?) and in Hungarian we have them (' e ' like in
'have' and e' like in 'take') with a 3rd variation where the accent is not
applied: a closed and an open ' e ' sound (instrumental in dialects). So I
have no problem to pronounce the discussing gentleman as The'-etetus. Maybe
he called himself (?) Te-aythetos? Ask Plato you are close to him.

(And I always proudly thought that Hungarian - vs. English - has a simple
vowel-code in an unchanging uniform pronunciation...).
German proverb: Fremdworter sind glucksache (= foreign words are a matter
of luck). A friend added: you can NEVER know what they mean.

John
On Tue, Aug 4, 2009 at 11:06 AM, Bruno Marchal marc...@ulb.ac.be wrote:

  John,

 Thanks for those informations. I thought that the æ was just a french,
 if not an old french, usage.
 Note that when I wrote Theatetus, it is just a mispelling. I tend to
 forget that second e, but your remark will help me to remind it. Note that
 Miles Burnyeat, in his book  The Theaetetus of Plato, and Levett in his
 traduction wrote simply Theaetetus. But in french too, more and more
 people forget to attach the o and e in words like oeuvre, or soeur
 (sister).

 Bruno

  On 04 Aug 2009, at 15:05, John Mikes wrote:

  Bruno and Mirek,
  concerning Theateticus vs. Theaeteticus:
  in my strange linguistic background I make a difference betwee ai and ae -
 the spelling in Greek and Latin of the name. As far as I know, nobody knows
 for sure how did the 'ancient' Greeks pronounce their ai - maybe as the flat
 'e' like in German lehr while the 'e' pronounciation might have been
 clsoer to (between) 'make' and 'peck' - the reason why the Romans
 transcribed it by their *ONE letter* *ae,* (lehr) and not as English
 would read: *'a'+'ee'*. The spelling you gave points to this latter. The
 Latin 'ae' is not TWO separate letters (a+e), it is a twin, as marked in the
 Wiki article
 ...*Theætetus... **and not Theaetetus *
 which looked strange to me from the beginning  .
 *(I wonder if the e-mail reproduces the (ae) one sign? look up in Wiki's
 Theaetetus Dialogue (in the title with the wrong spelling) the 1st line
 brings the merged-together double 'æ'.) *
 ***
 *English spelling always does a job on classical words, the Greek 'oi' has
 been transcribed into Latin sometimes as 'oe' and pronounced as in girl
 (oeuvre) while many think it was a sound like what the pigs say: as oy.
 then comes America, with it's Phoenix (pron: feenix) *
 I don't think the Romans were much better off, centuries after and a world
 apart from the ancient (classical for them) Greeks.
 And who knows today if the great orator was Tzitzero or Kikero to turn
 later into Tchitchero?
 ***
 *The Old Man did quite a job on us at the tower of Babel. *
 ***
 *[[ - I am enjoying your 'other' post where you spelled out my own
 vocabulary as indeed thinking functions as relations, lately not as a static
 description, but also the interchanging factor - ]]*
 **
 *John*


  http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




 


--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-08-04 Thread John Mikes
Bruno and Mirek,
 concerning Theateticus vs. Theaeteticus:
 in my strange linguistic background I make a difference betwee ai and ae -
the spelling in Greek and Latin of the name. As far as I know, nobody knows
for sure how did the 'ancient' Greeks pronounce their ai - maybe as the flat
'e' like in German lehr while the 'e' pronounciation might have been
clsoer to (between) 'make' and 'peck' - the reason why the Romans
transcribed it by their *ONE letter* *ae,* (lehr) and not as English would
read: *'a'+'ee'*. The spelling you gave points to this latter. The Latin
'ae' is not TWO separate letters (a+e), it is a twin, as marked in the Wiki
article
...*Theætetus... **and not Theaetetus *
which looked strange to me from the beginning  .
*(I wonder if the e-mail reproduces the (ae) one sign? look up in Wiki's
Theaetetus Dialogue (in the title with the wrong spelling) the 1st line
brings the merged-together double 'æ'.) *
***
*English spelling always does a job on classical words, the Greek 'oi' has
been transcribed into Latin sometimes as 'oe' and pronounced as in girl
(oeuvre) while many think it was a sound like what the pigs say: as oy.
then comes America, with it's Phoenix (pron: feenix) *
I don't think the Romans were much better off, centuries after and a world
apart from the ancient (classical for them) Greeks.
And who knows today if the great orator was Tzitzero or Kikero to turn later
into Tchitchero?
***
*The Old Man did quite a job on us at the tower of Babel. *
***
*[[ - I am enjoying your 'other' post where you spelled out my own
vocabulary as indeed thinking functions as relations, lately not as a static
description, but also the interchanging factor - ]]*
**
*John*




On Mon, Aug 3, 2009 at 4:55 AM, Bruno Marchal marc...@ulb.ac.be wrote:


  On 02 Aug 2009, at 23:20, Mirek Dobsicek wrote:



  I am in a good mood and a bit picky :-) Do you know how many entries

  google gave me upon entering

  Theaetetical -marchal -bruno



 Well 144?


 Good way to find my papers on that. The pages refer quickly to this

 list or the FOR list.


 I am sorry for the delay, I've just got back from my vacation.

 Hmm. The above written search should not return any references to your
 papers/letters as the minus sign in front of your name asks for an
 exclusion.

 Given that it works as supposed google then gives only 1 hit in my
 location (Sweden). That hit is a translation of the word Theaetetical
 into some eastern characters. Thus, I end up with zero meaningful hits
 and a feeling that you might be the only one using this word.

 That makes me insists a little bit more (in a very polite way) that,
 occasionally, your work is
 difficult to read unless one is willing to undertake long
  discussions, clarifications and position adjustments.

 I am writing this in a reference to your complains that sometimes you
 have troubles to get enough relevant feedback to your work.




 Come on Mirek: Theaetetical is an adjective I have forged from
 Theatetus.
 Theatetus gives 195.000 results on Google.
 Theatetus wiki 4310.

 By theatetical notion of knowledge, I mean the well known attempts to
 define knowledge by Theaetetus in Plato's Theaetetus. The most known
 definition is truye justified belief, that Bill taylor just mentionned on
 the FOR list recently as:
 This old crock should have been given a decent burial long ago.
 I guess I will have to make a comment ...


 My work is, without doubt, very difficult to read because it crosses three
 or four fields: mathematical logic, philosophy of mind and computer
 science;  + quantum mechanics to evaluate the plausibility of the derived
 computationalist physics. This does not help in an epoch of
 hyper-specialization.
 I am also using a deductive approach in the philosophy of mind. I am
 apparently the first to *postulate* mechanism.  Most philosophers of mind
 accept mechanism as the only rational theory, or reject it with some
 passion. Few, if any, use it as an hypothesis, in a deductive strategy. Then
 mathematical logic is virtually unknown, except by mathematical logicians,
 who, for historical reasons, do not want to come back to the earlier
 philosophical motivations: they want to be accepted as pure mathematicians.
 Except the philosophical logicians, who in majority criticized classical
 logic, and see philosphy as a mean to criticize classical philosophy.
 Mathematicians are so used to classical philosophy, that they consider it as
 science, and hate to be remind that this is still a philosophical.

 I have no feedback for purely contingent reason related to facts which have
 nothing to do with the startling feature of the conclusion of the reasoning.
 Up to now, I heard continuously about critics on an imaginary work I have
 never done. The price of the best PhD thesis that I got in France has
 eventually only spread those rumor from Brussels to elsewhere.
 All real scientist who have studied my work and have accepted to meet me,
 or to write a real 

Re: The seven step series

2009-08-04 Thread Mirek Dobsicek


 Come on Mirek: Theaetetical is an adjective I have forged from
 Theatetus.
 Theatetus gives 195.000 results on Google.
 Theatetus wiki 4310.

Of course, after all you reference the dialogue Theaetetus in your
papers thus one can easily match the word Theaetetical agains it.
Let me quickly summarize the experience I had with theatetical notion
of knowledge while reading one of your papers for the first time.

Maybe I am an ignorant, then shame on me, but I have not read the
Theaetetus. So I took a look at the Wikipedia and read

 In this dialogue, Socrates and Theaetetus discuss three definitions of
knowledge: knowledge as nothing but perception, knowledge as true
judgment, and, finally, knowledge as a true judgment with an account.
Each of these definitions are shown to be unsatisfactory.

Hmm that really helps .., I told to myself and continued with reading.
With an uneasy feeling of stepping into the water I eventually settled
down to conclusion that you likely mean something as true justified
belief.
I really wished you wrote it more straightforwardly without turning your
readers quite unnecessarily down to the Theaetetus and inventing new
words such as Theaetetical.

Anyway, I'd like to stop discussing this issue :-) since my only point
was to give you a hint why I said that it is not easy to read your
papers/letters.

 Feel free to ask for any clarification, position
 adjustments, question, at any level ...Do you understand what is the
 comp hypothesis? 

Let us see if I get it right. Your comp hypothesis is
1) I'm a machine,
2) Each possible computation is Turing-computable,
3) Natural numbers and their relations do exist.

This should not be confused with other quite common comp hypothesis that
the universe is a big computer. This hypothesis entails the existence of
a physical computer.


Ad 1) I take the position that I is only a convenient temporary
pointer to a part of universe. The pointer Socrates' thoughts is of
the same quality.

Ad 2) Breath taking. While 1) and 3) are assumptions of the kind OK,
let's think for a while that ..., 2) has the status of a thesis. I
don't have any firm position on what could an objective reality be (and
without a justification I tend to think it is inaccessible to us), but
if there is any objective reality, 2) could be a statement about it.

Ad 3) If natural numbers and their relations are the only entities which
do exist then me, you, everything is a recipe of a Turing-computable number.

OK, that is it. This is how I understand to your starting assumptions.

Mirek





--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-08-04 Thread Bruno Marchal
John,

Thanks for those informations. I thought that the æ was just a  
french, if not an old french, usage.
Note that when I wrote Theatetus, it is just a mispelling. I tend to  
forget that second e, but your remark will help me to remind it.  
Note that Miles Burnyeat, in his book  The Theaetetus of Plato, and  
Levett in his traduction wrote simply Theaetetus. But in french too,  
more and more people forget to attach the o and e in words like  
oeuvre, or soeur (sister).

Bruno

On 04 Aug 2009, at 15:05, John Mikes wrote:

 Bruno and Mirek,
  concerning Theateticus vs. Theaeteticus:
  in my strange linguistic background I make a difference betwee ai  
 and ae - the spelling in Greek and Latin of the name. As far as I  
 know, nobody knows for sure how did the 'ancient' Greeks pronounce  
 their ai - maybe as the flat 'e' like in German lehr while the 'e'  
 pronounciation might have been clsoer to (between) 'make' and 'peck'  
 - the reason why the Romans transcribed it by their ONE letter ae,  
 (lehr) and not as English would read: 'a'+'ee'. The spelling you  
 gave points to this latter. The Latin 'ae' is not TWO separate  
 letters (a+e), it is a twin, as marked in the Wiki article
 ...Theætetus... and not Theaetetus
 which looked strange to me from the beginning  .
 (I wonder if the e-mail reproduces the (ae) one sign? look up in  
 Wiki's Theaetetus Dialogue (in the title with the wrong spelling)  
 the 1st line brings the merged-together double 'æ'.)
 *
 English spelling always does a job on classical words, the Greek  
 'oi' has been transcribed into Latin sometimes as 'oe' and  
 pronounced as in girl (oeuvre) while many think it was a sound  
 like what the pigs say: as oy. then comes America, with it's  
 Phoenix (pron: feenix)
 I don't think the Romans were much better off, centuries after and a  
 world apart from the ancient (classical for them) Greeks.
 And who knows today if the great orator was Tzitzero or Kikero to  
 turn later into Tchitchero?
 *
 The Old Man did quite a job on us at the tower of Babel.
 *
 [[ - I am enjoying your 'other' post where you spelled out my own  
 vocabulary as indeed thinking functions as relations, lately not as  
 a static description, but also the interchanging factor - ]]

 John


http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-08-04 Thread Bruno Marchal
Hi Mirek,

Long and perhaps key post.

On 04 Aug 2009, at 15:32, Mirek Dobsicek wrote:



 Come on Mirek: Theaetetical is an adjective I have forged from
 Theatetus.
 Theatetus gives 195.000 results on Google.
 Theatetus wiki 4310.

 Of course, after all you reference the dialogue Theaetetus in your
 papers thus one can easily match the word Theaetetical agains it.
 Let me quickly summarize the experience I had with theatetical notion
 of knowledge while reading one of your papers for the first time.

 Maybe I am an ignorant, then shame on me, but I have not read the
 Theaetetus.

There is no shame in being ignorant. Only in staying ignorant :)
I feel a bit sorry with my last post. I hate to look like patronizing,  
but it is a professional deformation. Apology.

Note that all the Theaetetus' stuff is really needed just to motivate  
the arithmetical definition of the knower, alias the first person,  
alias the universal soul, and this concerns AUDA (the arithmetical  
UDA), which should be done normally after getting straight the UDA's  
point, ... unless you are mathematical logician, who are the only one  
who can find AUDA more easy than UDA.


 So I took a look at the Wikipedia and read

 In this dialogue, Socrates and Theaetetus discuss three definitions  
 of
 knowledge: knowledge as nothing but perception, knowledge as true
 judgment, and, finally, knowledge as a true judgment with an account.
 Each of these definitions are shown to be unsatisfactory.

Socrates asks Theaetetus to define knowledge. That is a very  
difficult question.
Then Socrates shows that all attempts made by Theaetetus lead to  
difficulties. He literally concludes that the problem is open, and  
this is debated in the philosophical literature since then.

The remarkable thing is that if you accept to modelize account by  
sound machine provability, which can be done for the not too complex  
machine, like Peano Arithmetic provers, or Zermelo Fraenkel Set Theory  
prover, the definitions of Theaetetus make sense, and can be use to  
show, at least, that many philosopher are deductively invalid in   
their critics. Actually, even the critics by Socrates have to be  
weakened.

All the arithmetical hypostases (in the Plotinus paper) are variant of  
Theaetetus definition.

The main one (corresponding to Plotinus primary hypostases) are the  
following one:

p (the truth of p)
Bp (the provability of p, the account of p)
Bp  p (the provability of p when p is true)

The amazing thing is that the incompleteness theorem can be used to  
show that, about sound machine, we have

Bp - Bp  p.

But this equivalence is true but not provable by the machine, making  
the ideal knower already obeying a different logic than the ideal  
prover. This introduces a non trivial notion of first person for the  
machines.
If you remember G and G*, the equivalence between proof and knowledge  
belongs to G* minus G. The corona of the true but unprovable (by the  
machine) statements. Yet they prove (know) the same arithmetical p,  
yet, from those points of view, it appears very different.



 Hmm that really helps .., I told to myself and continued with reading.
 With an uneasy feeling of stepping into the water I eventually settled
 down to conclusion that you likely mean something as true justified
 belief.

I have found dozen of different translations, in french and in  
english, of the greek expressions.



 I really wished you wrote it more straightforwardly without turning  
 your
 readers quite unnecessarily down to the Theaetetus and inventing new
 words such as Theaetetical.

In french students are burned alive if they dare to create new  
adjective, and I thought that in English we have more freedom, but I  
may be wrong. Sorry.




 Anyway, I'd like to stop discussing this issue :-) since my only point
 was to give you a hint why I said that it is not easy to read your
 papers/letters.

There are other reasons, if only the difficulty of the subject.




 Feel free to ask for any clarification, position
 adjustments, question, at any level ...Do you understand what is the
 comp hypothesis?

 Let us see if I get it right. Your comp hypothesis is
 1) I'm a machine,

OK. This of course could be interpreted in many ways, and that is why  
I have introduce the quasi-operational yes doctor. It makes clear  
hat the I is the conscious first person I, not the third person body.



 2) Each possible computation is Turing-computable,

OK. That is Church thesis. Very few people doubt it, but it is a  
refutable statement. If a human find a well defined function with an  
account of how human can compute it, but no machine can, then CT will  
be refuted. Only Kalmar did pretend to have such a function, but  
eventually his function was not well defined.



 3) Natural numbers and their relations do exist.

This is arithmetical realism. Just a way to prevent infinite  
discussion about intutionism and ultrafinitism.  It is no more than  
the belief of 

Re: The seven step series

2009-08-04 Thread Mirek Dobsicek

Hi Bruno,

Bruno Marchal wrote:
 Hi Mirek,
 
 Long and perhaps key post.

Thank you a lot for a prompt and long reply. I am digesting it :-)

Just some quick comments.

 There is no shame in being ignorant. Only in staying ignorant :)

I've ordered the dialogue from a second-hand book shop :-) The Stanford
encyclopedia says
 Arguably, it is his (Plato) greatest work on anything.
So I'll give it a try :-)


 judgment, and, finally, knowledge as a true judgment with an account.

 The remarkable thing is that if you accept to modelize account by
 sound machine provability, 

This is probably the key problem for me. I know next to nothing about
provability, the logic of provability, PA/ZF provers.

I know that quite often you reference Boolos 1993 - The Logic of
Provability. I took a look at it at Google Books preview but ... there
is something missing in my education. From the beginning I am puzzled
with Why?, what?. What a headache :-)

 In french students are burned alive if they dare to create new
 adjective, and I thought that in English we have more freedom, but I may
 be wrong. Sorry.

I'd grant this freedom to rational native speakers only :-)


 x divides y if and only if it exists a number z such that y = x*z.

I don't dare to correct your english but there is/exists a number ...
is what I would write.

 Ad 3) If natural numbers and their relations are the only entities which
 do exist then me, you, everything is a recipe of a Turing-computable
 number.
 
 No. Not at all. Sorry. Gosh, you will be very surprised if you follow
 the UDA-7. On the contrary. Arithmetical truth VASTLY extends the
 computable domain. Most relations between numbers are not Turing emulable.

Aha! Then I really have a wrong mental picture of your work. I
understood to arithmetical realism along the lines of this quotation
from the Stanford article on realism:

According to a platonist about arithmetic, the truth of the sentence '7
is prime' entails the existence of an abstract object, the number 7.
This object is abstract because it has no spatial or temporal location,
and is causally inert. A platonic realist about arithmetic will say that
the number 7 exists and instantiates the property of being prime
independently of anyone's beliefs, linguistic practices, conceptual
schemes, and so on.

So I thought that you essentially take
 a) Numbers and their properties and relations exists.
 b) Now, since you don't assume existence of anything else = your body,
your bike and coffee must emerge as patterns in the world of numbers.
 c) Taking the Church-Turing thesis, these patterns are Turing-computable.
 d) Definitely, the vast majority of all patterns is not Turing-computable.

This is how I have thought about your working framework. Notice, that I
don't talk about what you try to show, argue for, want to end up with etc.

Cheers,
 Mirek

--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-08-03 Thread Bruno Marchal

On 02 Aug 2009, at 23:20, Mirek Dobsicek wrote:



 I am in a good mood and a bit picky :-) Do you know how many entries
 google gave me upon entering
 Theaetetical -marchal -bruno


 Well 144?

 Good way to find my papers on that. The pages refer quickly to this
 list or the FOR list.

 I am sorry for the delay, I've just got back from my vacation.

 Hmm. The above written search should not return any references to your
 papers/letters as the minus sign in front of your name asks for an
 exclusion.

 Given that it works as supposed google then gives only 1 hit in my
 location (Sweden). That hit is a translation of the word  
 Theaetetical
 into some eastern characters. Thus, I end up with zero meaningful hits
 and a feeling that you might be the only one using this word.

 That makes me insists a little bit more (in a very polite way) that,
 occasionally, your work is
 difficult to read unless one is willing to undertake long
  discussions, clarifications and position adjustments.

 I am writing this in a reference to your complains that sometimes you
 have troubles to get enough relevant feedback to your work.



Come on Mirek: Theaetetical is an adjective I have forged from  
Theatetus.
Theatetus gives 195.000 results on Google.
Theatetus wiki 4310.

By theatetical notion of knowledge, I mean the well known attempts  
to define knowledge by Theaetetus in Plato's Theaetetus. The most  
known definition is truye justified belief, that Bill taylor just  
mentionned on the FOR list recently as:
This old crock should have been given a decent burial long ago.
I guess I will have to make a comment ...


My work is, without doubt, very difficult to read because it crosses  
three or four fields: mathematical logic, philosophy of mind and  
computer science;  + quantum mechanics to evaluate the plausibility  
of the derived computationalist physics. This does not help in an  
epoch of hyper-specialization.
I am also using a deductive approach in the philosophy of mind. I am  
apparently the first to *postulate* mechanism.  Most philosophers of  
mind accept mechanism as the only rational theory, or reject it with  
some passion. Few, if any, use it as an hypothesis, in a deductive  
strategy. Then mathematical logic is virtually unknown, except by  
mathematical logicians, who, for historical reasons, do not want to  
come back to the earlier philosophical motivations: they want to be  
accepted as pure mathematicians. Except the philosophical logicians,  
who in majority criticized classical logic, and see philosphy as a  
mean to criticize classical philosophy. Mathematicians are so used to  
classical philosophy, that they consider it as science, and hate to be  
remind that this is still a philosophical.

I have no feedback for purely contingent reason related to facts which  
have nothing to do with the startling feature of the conclusion of the  
reasoning. Up to now, I heard continuously about critics on an  
imaginary work I have never done. The price of the best PhD thesis  
that I got in France has eventually only spread those rumor from  
Brussels to elsewhere.
All real scientist who have studied my work and have accepted to meet  
me, or to write a real report on it, have understood it. True, some  
took a rather long time to understand, but that is normal: the subject  
matter is very complex, and still taboo, especially for the atheists,  
and other religious-based thinkers. But when they study it, they  
quickly discover that I use the scientific method, that is I am just  
asking a question, what is wrong with the following reasoning? ... The  
reasoning is decomposed in easy steps, so people accepting (for  
personal belief or for the sake of the argument) the hypotheses and  
wanting to reject the conclusion have a way to put their fingers on  
some problems.

UDA has been judged to obvious and simple in Brussels, and that is why  
I have augmented the thesis with the AUDA, which unfortunately is  
considered as ... too much simple for logicians, and too much  
difficult for non logicians. But AUDA is not needed at all to  
understand the simple and clear result: if we are digitalisable  
machine, the laws of physics emerge from a statistics on computations,  
in a verifiable way (quantitatively and qualitatively). The result is  
very simple and clear: the reasoning which leads to that result is  
much more subtle and difficult.

I am not at all pretending that reasoning is correct. Science progress  
when people do errors, but we have to find them, and sometimes, if we  
don't find them, we have to accept momentarily the conclusion, perhaps  
with the hope an error will be find later. But the attitude of a (tiny  
but influencing) part of the community consists in hiding the  
reasoning, or deforming it completely. This can't help.

Some people, even here recently (see 1Z's post) and recently on the  
FOR list, attributes me a curious theory, where they confuse the  
conclusion with the 

Re: The seven step series

2009-08-02 Thread Mirek Dobsicek


 I am in a good mood and a bit picky :-) Do you know how many entries
 google gave me upon entering
 Theaetetical -marchal -bruno
 
 
 Well 144?
 
 Good way to find my papers on that. The pages refer quickly to this  
 list or the FOR list.

I am sorry for the delay, I've just got back from my vacation.

Hmm. The above written search should not return any references to your
papers/letters as the minus sign in front of your name asks for an
exclusion.

Given that it works as supposed google then gives only 1 hit in my
location (Sweden). That hit is a translation of the word Theaetetical
into some eastern characters. Thus, I end up with zero meaningful hits
and a feeling that you might be the only one using this word.

That makes me insists a little bit more (in a very polite way) that,
occasionally, your work is
 difficult to read unless one is willing to undertake long
  discussions, clarifications and position adjustments.

I am writing this in a reference to your complains that sometimes you
have troubles to get enough relevant feedback to your work.


 I let those interested to meditate on two questions (N is {0, 1, 2, 3,  
 4, ...}):
 
 1) What is common between the set of all subsets of a set with n  
 elements, and the set of all finite sequences of 0 and 1 of length  
 n.
 2) What is common between the set of all subsets of N, and the set of  
 all infinite sequences of 0 and 1.
 
 Just some (finite and infinite) bread for surviving the day :)

I am going to catch up with the thread ...

Cheers,
 mirek

--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-07-30 Thread John Mikes
Hi, Bruno,
let me skip the technical part and jump on the following text.
*F u n c t i o n*  as I believe is - for you - the y = f(x) *form*. For me:
the *activity -* shown when plotting on a coordinate system the f(x) values
of the Y-s to the values on the x-axle resulting in a relation (curve). And
here is my problem: who does the plotting? (Do not say: YOU are, or Iam,
that would add to the function concept the homunculus to make it from a
written format into a F U N C T I O N ).

John M



On Wed, Jul 29, 2009 at 11:59 AM, Bruno Marchal marc...@ulb.ac.be wrote:

  SOLUTIONS


 OK. I give the solution of the exercises of the last session, on the
 cartesian product of sets.

 I recall the definition of the product A X B.

 A X B=   {(x,y) such that x belongs to A and y belongs to B}

  I gave A = {0, 1}, and B = {a, b}.


 In this case, A X B = {(0,a), (0, b), (1, a), (1, b)}

 The  cartesian drawing is, for AXB :


 a (0, a)   (1, a)

 b (0, b)  (1, b)

 0  1


 Exercise: do the cartesian drawing for BXA.

 Solution:

 1 (a, 1)   (b, 1)

 0 (a, 0)  (b, 0)

 a  b

 You see that B X A = {(a,0), (a,1), (b,0), (b, 1)}

 You should see that, not only A X B is different from B X A, but AXB and
 BXA have an empty intersection. They have no elements in common at all. But
 they do have the same cardinal 2x2 = 4.

 1)
 Compute
 {a, b, c} X {d, e} =
 I show you a method (to minimize inattention errors):

 I wrote first {(a, _),  (b, _), (c, _), (a, _),  (b, _), (c, _)}  two times
 because I have seen that {d, e} has two elements.
 Then I add the second elements of the couples, which comes from {d, e}:

 {(a, d),  (b, d), (c, d), (a, e),  (b, e), (c, e)}

 OK?


 {d, e} X {a, b, c} = {(d, a), (d, b), (d, c), (e, a), (e, b), (e, c)}

 {a, b} X {a, b} = {(a, a), (a, b), (b, a), (b, b)}

 {a, b} X { } = { }.

 OK?

 2)
 Convince yourself that the cardinal of AXB is the product of the
 cardinal of A and the cardinal of B.
 A and B are finite sets here. Hint: meditate on their cartesian drawing.

 Question? This should be obvious. No?


 3) Draw a piece of NXN.(with, as usual, N = {0, 1, 2, 3, ...}):

 ..  . . .  . .   .
 ..  . . .  . ..
 ..  . . .  . . .
 5(0,5)  (1,5)  (2,5)  (3,5)  (4,5)  (5,5)  ...
 4(0,4)  (1,4)  (2,4)  (3,4)  (4,4)  (5,4)  ...
 3(0,3)  (1,3)  (2,3)  (3,3)  (4,3)  (5,3)  ...
 2(0,2)  (1,2)  (2,2)  (3,2)  (4,2)  (5,2)  ...
 1(0,1)  (1,1)  (2,1)  (3,1)  (4,1)  (5,1)  ...
 0(0,0)  (1,0)  (2,0)  (3,0)  (4,0)  (5,0)  ...

   0   1 2   3 4   5  ...


 OK?


 N is infinite, so N X N is infinite too.


  Look at the diagonal: (0,0) (1,1) (2,2) (3,3) (4,4) (5,5) ...

 definition: *the diagonal of AXA,* a product of a set with itself,  is the
 set of couples (x,y) with x = y.

 All right? No question? Such diagonal will have a quite important role in
 the sequel.

 Next: I will say one or two words on the notion of relation, and then we
 will define the most important notion ever discovered by the humans: the
 notion of function. Then, the definition of the exponentiation of sets, A^B,
 is very simple: it is the set of functions from B to A.
 What is important will be to grasp the notion of function. Indeed, we will
 soon be interested in the notion of computable functions, which are mainly
 what computers, that is universal machine, compute. But even in physics, the
 notion of function is present everywhere. That notion capture the notion of
 dependency between (measurable) quantities. To say that the temperature of a
 body depends on the pressure on that body, is very well described by saying
 that the temperature of a body is a function of the pressure.
 Most phenomena are described by relation, through equations, and most
 solution of those equation are functions. Functions are everywhere, somehow.

 I have some hesitation, though. Functions can be described as particular
 case of relations, and relations can be described as special case of
 functions. This happens many times in math, and can lead to bad pedagogical
 decisions, so I have to make a few thinking, before leading you to
 unnecessary complications.

 Please ask questions if *any*thing is unclear. I suggest the beginners in
 math take some time to invent exercises, and to solve them. Invent simple
 little sets, and compute their union, intersection, cartesian product,
 powerset.
 You can compose exercises: for example: compute the cartesian product of
 the powerset of {0, 1} with the set {a}. It is not particularly funny, but
 it is like music. If you want to be able to play some music instrument,
 sometimes you have to faire ses gammes,we say in french; you know, playing
 repetitively annoying musical patterns, if only to teach your lips or
 fingers to do the right 

Re: The seven step series

2009-07-30 Thread Bruno Marchal
Hi John, and the other.

John motivates me to explain what is a function, for a mathematician.

On 30 Jul 2009, at 17:53, John Mikes wrote:

 Hi, Bruno,
 let me skip the technical part


OK. But I remind you this current thread *is* technical.



 and jump on the following text.
 F u n c t i o n  as I believe is - for you - the y = f(x) form. For  
 me: the activity - shown when plotting on a coordinate system the  
 f(x) values of the Y-s to the values on the x-axle resulting in a  
 relation (curve). And here is my problem: who does the plotting? (Do  
 not say: YOU are, or Iam, that would add to the function concept the  
 homunculus to make it from a written format into a F U N C T I O N ).


But I have not yet say what is a function. I just mentioned that they  
are everywhere to open the appetite of the audience.


 F u n c t i o n  as I believe is - for you - the y = f(x) form.


You take a risk believing things - for me -.

Actually the y = f(x)  form will come later, with the goal of  
distinguishing clearly the key difference between a function and the  
many possible forms of a function.


Ah! but you force me to define what is a function right on (for a  
mathematician of course). Take it easy. You can skip to the sum-up  
line below.


OK, ready? I mean the others among those who pursue this mathematical  
shortcut toward the seventh step (the UD step, actually).


We have already seen functions. If you remember the bijection between  
A = {a,b,c,d,e,f,g} and B = {1,  2,  3,  4,  5,  6,  7}.

a  --  7
b  --  2
c  --  3
d  --  4
e  --  5
f  --  6
g  --  1


I said that the following set of couples

{(a,1), (b,2) (c,3) (d,4), (e,5), (f,6), (g,7)}

was a nice set theoretical representation of the bijection, and that  
the bijection is an example of function. We can give it a name, F, for  
example.

F = {(a,1), (b,2) (c,3) (d,4), (e,5), (f,6), (g,7)}.

A function is a mathematical object, actually a set, which embodies an  
association between the elements of two sets. Here the two sets  
involved are A and B.
A is said to be the domain of F. B is said to be the range of F. And  
the function itself, F,  get a nice set theoretical  form of a set.  
The set of all the couples which determine or define the association.  
Here it is the set {(a,1), (b,2) (c,3) (d,4), (e,5), (f,6), (g,7)}.

Arbitrary set of couples will appear as very good way to describe  
relation, in general.


But for function a key condition, the functional condition, has to be  
applied:

   - If (a, b) belongs to F then if (a, c) belongs to F we have  
that b = c.   (the functional condition).


This means, that if F is a function from the set A to the set B, you  
cannot associate to one object of A, many objects of B.

For example the temperature in a place can be a function of time,  
because at each moment of time you will not associate two temperatures.
It is the key point for seeing that a function from A to B, describe a  
very general notion of dependency.

We will be interested in functions from N to N. (With N = {0, 1,  
2, ...}. Where examples abound.

Take the function which associates to each natural number its successor.

The function is (or is represented fully) by the infinite set of  
couples

{(0, 1), (1,2), (2,3), (3,4), (4,5), (5, 6), (6, 7), ...}

We will be interested in function having two arguments. Those will be  
the function from NXN to N. Example: take addition. This is a  
function, because when you add any numbers, 3 and 6, for example, 3+6,  
you don't expect two results. So the functional condition is  
respected. OK? So the function addition can be defined or represented  
by the set

{((0, 0), 0), ((0, 1) 1) ...  ((4, 8) 12) ... }

With the numbers, all the operations are functions. The same with the  
sets.


To sum up: a function is a set of couples, most of the time infinite,  
respecting the functional condition.

A good training consists in searching all functions between little sets:


Exercise:


1) how many functions and what are they, from the set {0, 1} to  
himself. What are the functions from {0, 1) to {0, 1}?

Solution:

{(0,0), (1,0)}   the constant function which associates zero to any  
value of its argument.
{(0,1), (1,1)}   the constant function which associates one to any  
value of its argument.
{(0,0), (1,1)}  the identity function, which output its argument as  
value.
{(0,1), (1,0)}, the NOT function, which associate 0 to 1, and 1 to 0.

There is four functions from {0, 1} to {0, 1}.


2) how many functions, and what are they, from the set cartesian  
product {0, 1} X {0, 1} to {0, 1}

Among them many are celebrities, you know. The AND, the OR, and many  
(how many?) others.

For a beginner in math, this is not at all an easy exercise. The real  
useful exercise is to try to understand the enunciation of the  
question. We will take the time needed.


3) A bit tricky perhaps: how many functions exist from { } 

Re: The seven step series

2009-07-29 Thread Bruno Marchal

Ronald,

On 28 Jul 2009, at 12:51, ronaldheld wrote:


 Bruno:
 I meant the mathematical formalism you are teaching us. When we
 eventually get to the UDA steps, I wil be better able to do that
 assessment.


OK.
Note that the first 6 steps have already be done recently, with Kim,  
and even before. But there is no problem to come back on this, later.  
The key point there consists in explaining the first person  
indeterminacy, and its invariance for set of transformations (adding  
delays in the computation, going from real to virtual, etc.).
You may prepare yourself by reading the relevant portion of the sane04  
paper.  Eventually the seventh step itself somehow recapitulates the 6  
preceding steps, so it is OK.

Best,

Bruno


http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-07-29 Thread Bruno Marchal
SOLUTIONS


OK. I give the solution of the exercises of the last session, on the  
cartesian product of sets.

I recall the definition of the product A X B.

A X B=   {(x,y) such that x belongs to A and y belongs to B}

  I gave A = {0, 1}, and B = {a, b}.


In this case, A X B = {(0,a), (0, b), (1, a), (1, b)}

The  cartesian drawing is, for AXB :


a (0, a)   (1, a)

b (0, b)  (1, b)

 0  1


Exercise: do the cartesian drawing for BXA.

Solution:

1 (a, 1)   (b, 1)

0 (a, 0)  (b, 0)

 a  b

You see that B X A = {(a,0), (a,1), (b,0), (b, 1)}

You should see that, not only A X B is different from B X A, but AXB  
and BXA have an empty intersection. They have no elements in common at  
all. But they do have the same cardinal 2x2 = 4.

1)
Compute
{a, b, c} X {d, e} =
I show you a method (to minimize inattention errors):

I wrote first {(a, _),  (b, _), (c, _), (a, _),  (b, _), (c, _)}  two  
times because I have seen that {d, e} has two elements.
Then I add the second elements of the couples, which comes from {d, e}:

{(a, d),  (b, d), (c, d), (a, e),  (b, e), (c, e)}

OK?


{d, e} X {a, b, c} = {(d, a), (d, b), (d, c), (e, a), (e, b), (e, c)}

{a, b} X {a, b} = {(a, a), (a, b), (b, a), (b, b)}

{a, b} X { } = { }.

OK?

2)
Convince yourself that the cardinal of AXB is the product of the
cardinal of A and the cardinal of B.
A and B are finite sets here. Hint: meditate on their cartesian drawing.

Question? This should be obvious. No?


3) Draw a piece of NXN.(with, as usual, N = {0, 1, 2, 3, ...}):

..  . . .  . .   .
..  . . .  . ..
..  . . .  . . .
5(0,5)  (1,5)  (2,5)  (3,5)  (4,5)  (5,5)  ...
4(0,4)  (1,4)  (2,4)  (3,4)  (4,4)  (5,4)  ...
3(0,3)  (1,3)  (2,3)  (3,3)  (4,3)  (5,3)  ...
2(0,2)  (1,2)  (2,2)  (3,2)  (4,2)  (5,2)  ...
1(0,1)  (1,1)  (2,1)  (3,1)  (4,1)  (5,1)  ...
0(0,0)  (1,0)  (2,0)  (3,0)  (4,0)  (5,0)  ...

   0   1 2   3 4   5  ...


OK?


N is infinite, so N X N is infinite too.


  Look at the diagonal: (0,0) (1,1) (2,2) (3,3) (4,4) (5,5) ...

definition: the diagonal of AXA, a product of a set with itself,  is  
the set of couples (x,y) with x = y.

All right? No question? Such diagonal will have a quite important role  
in the sequel.

Next: I will say one or two words on the notion of relation, and then  
we will define the most important notion ever discovered by the  
humans: the notion of function. Then, the definition of the  
exponentiation of sets, A^B, is very simple: it is the set of  
functions from B to A.
What is important will be to grasp the notion of function. Indeed, we  
will soon be interested in the notion of computable functions, which  
are mainly what computers, that is universal machine, compute. But  
even in physics, the notion of function is present everywhere. That  
notion capture the notion of dependency between (measurable)  
quantities. To say that the temperature of a body depends on the  
pressure on that body, is very well described by saying that the  
temperature of a body is a function of the pressure.
Most phenomena are described by relation, through equations, and most  
solution of those equation are functions. Functions are everywhere,  
somehow.

I have some hesitation, though. Functions can be described as  
particular case of relations, and relations can be described as  
special case of functions. This happens many times in math, and can  
lead to bad pedagogical decisions, so I have to make a few thinking,  
before leading you to unnecessary complications.

Please ask questions if *any*thing is unclear. I suggest the  
beginners in math take some time to invent exercises, and to solve  
them. Invent simple little sets, and compute their union,  
intersection, cartesian product, powerset.
You can compose exercises: for example: compute the cartesian product  
of the powerset of {0, 1} with the set {a}. It is not particularly  
funny, but it is like music. If you want to be able to play some music  
instrument, sometimes you have to faire ses gammes,we say in french;  
you know, playing repetitively annoying musical patterns, if only to  
teach your lips or fingers to do the right movement without thinking.  
Math needs also such a kind of practice, especially in the beginning.
Of course, as Kim said, passive understanding of music (listening)  
does not need such exercises. Passive understanding of math needs,  
alas, many simple exercises. Active understanding of math, needs  
difficult exercises up to open problems, but this is not the goal here.

Bruno



http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this 

Re: The seven step series

2009-07-28 Thread ronaldheld

Bruno:
 I meant the mathematical formalism you are teaching us. When we
eventually get to the UDA steps, I wil be better able to do that
assessment.
  Ronald

On Jul 27, 1:27 pm, Bruno Marchal marc...@ulb.ac.be wrote:
 On 27 Jul 2009, at 16:07, ronaldheld wrote:



    I am following, but have not commented, because there is nothing
  controversal.

 Cool. Even the sixth first steps of UDA?



    When you are done, can your posts be consolidated into a paper or a
  document that can be read staright through?

 I should do that.

 Bruno





  On Jul 23, 9:28 am, Bruno Marchal marc...@ulb.ac.be wrote:
  On 23 Jul 2009, at 15:09, m.a. wrote:

  Bruno,
              Yes, yours and Brent's explanations seem very clear. I
  hate to ask you to spell things out step by step all the way, but I
  can tell you that when I'm confronted by a dense hedge or clump of
  math symbols, my mind refuses to even try to disentangle them and
  reels back in terror. So I beg you to always advance in baby steps
  with lots of space between statements. I want to assure you that I'm
  printing out all of your 7-step lessons and using them for study and
  reference. Thanks for your patience,   m.a.

  Don't worry, I understand that very well. And this illustrates also
  that your despair is more psychological than anything else. I have
  also abandoned the study of a mathematical book until I realize that
  the difficulty was more my bad eyesight than any conceptual
  difficulties. With good spectacles I realize the subject was not too
  difficult, but agglomeration of little symbols can give a bad
  impression, even for a mathematician.

  I will make some effort, tell me if my last post, on the relation

        (a^n) * (a^m) = a^(n + m)

  did help you.

  You are lucky to have an infinitely patient teacher. You can ask any
  question, like Bruno,

  is (a^n) * (a^m) the same as a^n times a^m?
    Answer: yes, I use often *, x, as shorthand for times, and I
  use ( and ) as delimiters in case I fear some ambiguity.

  Bruno

  -- Original Message -
  From: Bruno Marchal
  To: everything-list@googlegroups.com
  Sent: Wednesday, July 22, 2009 12:20 PM
  Subject: Re: The seven step series

  Marty,

  Brent wrote:

  On 21 Jul 2009, at 23:24, Brent Meeker wrote:

  Take all strings of length 2
  00             01                   10               11
  Make two copies of each
  00      00      01      01      10      10      11      11
  Add a 0 to the first and a 1 to the second
  000    001      010   011      100   101   110      111
  and you have all strings of length 3.

  Then you wrote

  I can see where adding 0 to the first and 1 to the second gives 000
  and 001 and I think I see how you get 010 but the rest of the
  permutations don't seem obvious to me. P-l-e-a-s-e  explain,  Best,

                                                                           
                                                                           
                                                                           
       m
  . (mathematically hopeless)  a.

  Let me rewrite Brent's explanation, with a tiny tiny tiny  
  improvement:

  Take all strings of length 2
  00
  01
  10
  11
  Make two copies of each

  first copy:
  00
  01
  10
  11

  second copy
  00
  01
  10
  11

  add a 0 to the end of the strings in the first copy, and then add a
  1  to the end of the strings in the second copy:

  first copy:
  000
  010
  100
  110

  second copy
  001
  011
  101
  111

  You get all 8 elements of B_3.

  You can do the same reasoning with the subsets. Adding an element to
  a set multiplies by 2 the number of elements of the powerset:

  Exemple. take a set with two elements {a, b}. Its powerset is {{ }
  {a} {b} {a, b}}. How to get all the subset of {a, b, c} that is the
  set coming from adding c to {a, b}.

  Write two copies of the powerset of {a, b}

  { }
  {a}
  {b}
  {a, b}

  { }
  {a}
  {b}
  {a, b}

  Don't add c to the set in the first copy, and add c to the sets in
  the second copies. This gives

  { }
  {a}
  {b}
  {a, b}

  {c}
  {a, c}
  {b, c}
  {a, b, c}

  and that gives all subsets of {a, b, c}.

  This is coherent with interpreting a subset {a, b} of a set {a, b,
  c}, by a string like 110, which can be conceived as a shortand for

  Is a in the subset?   YES, thus 1
  Is b in the subset?   YES thus  1
  Is c in the subset?    NO thus   0.

  OK?

  You say also:

  The example of Mister X only confuses me more.

  Once you understand well the present post, I suggest you reread the
  Mister X examples, because it is a key in the UDA reasoning. If you
  still have problem with it, I suggest you quote it, line by line,
  and ask question. I will answer (or perhaps someone else).

  Don't be afraid to ask any question. You are not mathematically
  hopeless. You are just not familiarized with reasoning in math. It
  is normal to go slowly. As far

Re: The seven step series

2009-07-28 Thread m.a.
Bruno,
 I have searched my notes for an exposition of BIJECTION and found 
only one mention in an early email which promises to define it in a later 
lesson. Do you have a reference to that lesson or perhaps an instant 
explanation of it? Thanks,
  
Chief Ignoramus



  
- Original Message - 
From: Bruno Marchal marc...@ulb.ac.be
To: everything-list@googlegroups.com
Sent: Monday, July 27, 2009 4:54 PM
Subject: Re: The seven step series


 
 We have discovered SBIJECTION between powersets of a set with cardinal  
 n, and the set of binary strings of length n.
 And we have presented reasons for the existence of a bijection between  
 the powerset of N = {0, 1, 2, ...} and the set of infinite binary   
 strings.
 
 OK?










 
 
 
--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-07-28 Thread Bruno Marchal

On 28 Jul 2009, at 17:36, m.a. wrote:

 Bruno,
  I have searched my notes for an exposition of BIJECTION  
 and found only one mention in an early email which promises to  
 define it in a later lesson. Do you have a reference to that lesson  
 or perhaps an instant explanation of it? Thanks,
   
 Chief 
  Ignoramus


I hope you are not stuck by that, given that the cartesian product  
does not rely on the understanding of bijection.

An instant explanation of bijection is this:

Suppose you have two sets A and B, and you would like to know if they  
have the same number of elements. For example:

A = {a,b,c,d,e,f,g}

and

B = {1,  2,  3,  4,  5,  6,  7}

Suppose that you cannot count. You forget the lessons for counting!

But you have ficelles, I mean ropes, cords, or strings.

So you can line up the two sets, and try to attach to each elements of  
A a piece of rope, and joint them to one element of the set B.
IF you succeed doing that, and respecting the one-one or 1-1link, and  
getting all the elements of B (the onto condition), THEN you have  
shown the existence of a bijection between the two sets.

Let us see if that work on the example.  The -- represent  
the pieces of rope. OK?

a  --  1
b  --  2
c  --  3
d  --  4
e  --  5
f  --  6
g  --  7

So there is a bijection between A and B.

The bijection *is* that association, as we will defined much later(*).

Other bijections can exist between A and B, like

a  --  7
b  --  2
c  --  3
d  --  4
e  --  5
f  --  6
g  --  1

It is enough that one exist, to conclude the sets have the same  
number of elements, or same cardinal.

Convince you that if two sets have different number of elements, there  
is no bijection in between. It has to be 1-1, and onto (no missing  
element).

Exercise (but no hurry):
Verify if you can see some bijections existing between the powerset of  
a set with 2 elements, and B_2. The same for the powerset of a set  
with 3 elements, and B_3.

Bruno

!*) Oh! I can give you the particular mathematical bijection, existing  
between A and B, given that I have already define the notion of couple.
It is the set of couples representing naturally those rope association:

{(a,1), (b,2) (c,3) (d,4), (e,5), (f,6), (g,7)}.Take it easy, and  
be sure you have read what I say about the couples before.




http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-07-27 Thread Bruno Marchal


On 27 Jul 2009, at 16:07, ronaldheld wrote:

   I am following, but have not commented, because there is nothing
 controversal.

Cool. Even the sixth first steps of UDA?



   When you are done, can your posts be consolidated into a paper or a
 document that can be read staright through?

I should do that.

Bruno




 On Jul 23, 9:28 am, Bruno Marchal marc...@ulb.ac.be wrote:
 On 23 Jul 2009, at 15:09, m.a. wrote:

 Bruno,
 Yes, yours and Brent's explanations seem very clear. I
 hate to ask you to spell things out step by step all the way, but I
 can tell you that when I'm confronted by a dense hedge or clump of
 math symbols, my mind refuses to even try to disentangle them and
 reels back in terror. So I beg you to always advance in baby steps
 with lots of space between statements. I want to assure you that I'm
 printing out all of your 7-step lessons and using them for study and
 reference. Thanks for your patience,   m.a.

 Don't worry, I understand that very well. And this illustrates also
 that your despair is more psychological than anything else. I have
 also abandoned the study of a mathematical book until I realize that
 the difficulty was more my bad eyesight than any conceptual
 difficulties. With good spectacles I realize the subject was not too
 difficult, but agglomeration of little symbols can give a bad
 impression, even for a mathematician.

 I will make some effort, tell me if my last post, on the relation

   (a^n) * (a^m) = a^(n + m)

 did help you.

 You are lucky to have an infinitely patient teacher. You can ask any
 question, like Bruno,

 is (a^n) * (a^m) the same as a^n times a^m?
   Answer: yes, I use often *, x, as shorthand for times, and I
 use ( and ) as delimiters in case I fear some ambiguity.

 Bruno







 -- Original Message -
 From: Bruno Marchal
 To: everything-list@googlegroups.com
 Sent: Wednesday, July 22, 2009 12:20 PM
 Subject: Re: The seven step series

 Marty,

 Brent wrote:

 On 21 Jul 2009, at 23:24, Brent Meeker wrote:

 Take all strings of length 2
 00 01   10   11
 Make two copies of each
 00  00  01  01  10  10  11  11
 Add a 0 to the first and a 1 to the second
 000001  010   011  100   101   110  111
 and you have all strings of length 3.

 Then you wrote

 I can see where adding 0 to the first and 1 to the second gives 000
 and 001 and I think I see how you get 010 but the rest of the
 permutations don't seem obvious to me. P-l-e-a-s-e  explain,  Best,



   m
 . (mathematically hopeless)  a.

 Let me rewrite Brent's explanation, with a tiny tiny tiny  
 improvement:

 Take all strings of length 2
 00
 01
 10
 11
 Make two copies of each

 first copy:
 00
 01
 10
 11

 second copy
 00
 01
 10
 11

 add a 0 to the end of the strings in the first copy, and then add a
 1  to the end of the strings in the second copy:

 first copy:
 000
 010
 100
 110

 second copy
 001
 011
 101
 111

 You get all 8 elements of B_3.

 You can do the same reasoning with the subsets. Adding an element to
 a set multiplies by 2 the number of elements of the powerset:

 Exemple. take a set with two elements {a, b}. Its powerset is {{ }
 {a} {b} {a, b}}. How to get all the subset of {a, b, c} that is the
 set coming from adding c to {a, b}.

 Write two copies of the powerset of {a, b}

 { }
 {a}
 {b}
 {a, b}

 { }
 {a}
 {b}
 {a, b}

 Don't add c to the set in the first copy, and add c to the sets in
 the second copies. This gives

 { }
 {a}
 {b}
 {a, b}

 {c}
 {a, c}
 {b, c}
 {a, b, c}

 and that gives all subsets of {a, b, c}.

 This is coherent with interpreting a subset {a, b} of a set {a, b,
 c}, by a string like 110, which can be conceived as a shortand for

 Is a in the subset?   YES, thus 1
 Is b in the subset?   YES thus  1
 Is c in the subset?NO thus   0.

 OK?

 You say also:

 The example of Mister X only confuses me more.

 Once you understand well the present post, I suggest you reread the
 Mister X examples, because it is a key in the UDA reasoning. If you
 still have problem with it, I suggest you quote it, line by line,
 and ask question. I will answer (or perhaps someone else).

 Don't be afraid to ask any question. You are not mathematically
 hopeless. You are just not familiarized with reasoning in math. It
 is normal to go slowly. As far as you can say I don't understand,
 there is hope you will understand.

 Indeed, concerning the UDA I suspect many in the list cannot say I
 don't understand, they believe it is philosophy, so they feel like
 they could object on philosophical ground, when the whole point is
 to present a deductive argument in a theory. So it is false, or you
 have to accept the theorem in the theory

Re: The seven step series

2009-07-27 Thread Bruno Marchal


Hi,

OK, I will come back on the square root of 2 later.

We have talked on sets.

Sets have elements, and elements of a set define completely the set,  
and a set is completely defined by its elements.

Example: here is a set of numbers {1, 2, 3}
and a set of sets of numbers {{1, 2}, {3}, { }}.

We can do some operations, like their union, or their intersection.
Examples:
{1,2,3} union {3,4,5} = {1,2,3,4,5},
{1,2,3} intersection {3,4,5} = { }.

We can verify if some relation hold for them, like equality, or  
inclusion.
{1, 2} = {2, 1, 1}   (yes!)
{1, 2} included-in {3, 2, 1}
{1, 2} not-included-in {1, 3}

We can compute their powerset.
Powerset {1, 2} = {{ }, {1}, {2}, {1, 2}}

We have discovered SBIJECTION between powersets of a set with cardinal  
n, and the set of binary strings of length n.
And we have presented reasons for the existence of a bijection between  
the powerset of N = {0, 1, 2, ...} and the set of infinite binary   
strings.

OK?

Today, I suggest we look at two new operations on sets. The product of  
sets, and the exponentiation of sets. Well, I will probably do only  
the product today.

First I have to introduce a new, well actually *very* well known,  and  
absolutely important, notion: the couple.

A couple is when there is two things, but with some order. It looks  
like a pair, but the order counts.

Usually a couple of things a , b is designated, in math, like this:

(a, b).

It looks like a pair {a, b}, but it is not. Indeed, {a, b} = {b, a},  
but the couple (a, b) is NOT equal to the couple (b, a).

When are two couples (a, b) and (c, d) equal? Only when a = c and b = d.

Examples. the couple of number (2, 3) is not equal to the couple (3,  
2), but the couple (0, 666) is equal to the couple (0, 666).

OK?

APARTE: Are couples sets? No. Nor are numbers. But yes, you can easily  
represent them by sets, so we could work only with sets, but we will  
not do that. Much later we will work only with numbers, in fact. The  
very notion of representation will be important, though.

Now we are ready to define the so called cartesian product of sets.  
It is indeed a cousin of Descartes' discovery that you can represent a  
point of the plane by a couple of (real) numbers. I read somewhere  
that Descartes discovered this by trying to describe a spider walking  
on a window with squared little piece of glass. But such a  
localization works also for cities like Los Angeles where you address  
is something like 15th avenue 61th street. The whole field of  
analytical geometry is founded on this idea.

That cartesian idea generalises on sets A and B. It is written A X B,  
and it is defined by
the set of couples (x, y) such that x belongs to A, and y belongs to B.

AXB = {(x, y) such-that x belongs-to A, and y belongs to B}.
(compare with the preceding definitions).

Example:  what is the product {0, 1} X {a, b}?  Well it is the set of  
all the couples made from elements of A in company of elements of  B,  
and in that order, with A = {0, 1}, and B = {a, b}.
So (0, a) is in there, and there are others. The product of {0, 1)  
with {a, b} is equal to

{(0,a), (0, b), (1, a), (1, b)}

The convenient usual cartesian drawing is, for AXB, with A = {0, 1},  
and B = {a, b} :


a (0, a)   (1, a)

b (0, b)  (1, b)

 0  1

A product of numbers a and b,  ab, can be conceived as the area of a  
rectangle of sides a and b. Here you can see that the product of sets  
AXB can fit in a rectangle when you dispose horizontally the elements  
of A, and vertically the elements of B. By convention, usually A is  
put horizontally, and B vertically.
But note that if the number ab is equal to the number ba, it is not  
the case that the set AXB is equal to the set BXA. (0, a) does not  
belong to BXA, for example.

Exercise: to the cartesian drawing for BXA.

1)
Compute
{a, b, c} X {d, e} =
{d, e} X {a, b, c} =
{a, b} X {a, b} =
{a, b} X { } =

2)
Convince yourself that the cardinal of AXB is the product of the  
cardinal of A and the cardinal of B.
A and B are finite sets here. Hint: meditate on their cartesian drawing.

3) Draw a piece of NXN.

Solution and sequel tomorrow.

Any question?

Bruno

http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-07-23 Thread m.a.
Hi Bruno,
I asked Brent Meeker a question which he referred back to you. 
Will you be covering it? (see para in bold below)

- Original Message - 
From: Brent Meeker meeke...@dslextreme.com
To: everything-list@googlegroups.com
Sent: Wednesday, July 22, 2009 11:49 PM
Subject: Re: The seven step series


 *   000100100011 0100010101100111
 1000 1001 1010   1011 1100 1101   
 1110  *
 ** 
 *and this is the binary sequence of length 4.*
 
 Right, it's all the binary strings of length 4
 
 ** 
 *How do these translate into ordinary numerals? 1,2,3,4...*
 
 Bruno's using them to represent sets and subsets.  So if we have a set {a b 
 c} 
 we can represent the subset {a c} by 101 and {a b} by 110, etc.  That's quite 
 different from using a binary string to represent a number in positional 
 notation.  I'll leave it to Bruno whether he wants to go into that.







 
 Brent
 
 
--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-07-23 Thread m.a.
Bruno,
Yes, yours and Brent's explanations seem very clear. I hate to ask 
you to spell things out step by step all the way, but I can tell you that when 
I'm confronted by a dense hedge or clump of math symbols, my mind refuses to 
even try to disentangle them and reels back in terror. So I beg you to always 
advance in baby steps with lots of space between statements. I want to assure 
you that I'm printing out all of your 7-step lessons and using them for study 
and reference. Thanks for your patience,   m.a.




-- Original Message - 
  From: Bruno Marchal 
  To: everything-list@googlegroups.com 
  Sent: Wednesday, July 22, 2009 12:20 PM
  Subject: Re: The seven step series


  Marty,


  Brent wrote:


  On 21 Jul 2009, at 23:24, Brent Meeker wrote:



Take all strings of length 2
00 01   10   11
Make two copies of each
00  00  01  01  10  10  11  11
Add a 0 to the first and a 1 to the second
000001  010   011  100   101   110  111
and you have all strings of length 3.




  Then you wrote


I can see where adding 0 to the first and 1 to the second gives 000 and 001 
and I think I see how you get 010 but the rest of the permutations don't seem 
obvious to me. P-l-e-a-s-e  explain,  Best,



m. 
(mathematically hopeless)  a.






  Let me rewrite Brent's explanation, with a tiny tiny tiny improvement:




  Take all strings of length 2
  00 
  01
  10
  11
  Make two copies of each

  first copy:
  00 
  01
  10
  11


  second copy
  00 
  01
  10
  11


  add a 0 to the end of the strings in the first copy, and then add a 1  to the 
end of the strings in the second copy:


  first copy:
  000
  010
  100
  110


  second copy
  001
  011
  101
  111


  You get all 8 elements of B_3.


  You can do the same reasoning with the subsets. Adding an element to a set 
multiplies by 2 the number of elements of the powerset:


  Exemple. take a set with two elements {a, b}. Its powerset is {{ } {a} {b} 
{a, b}}. How to get all the subset of {a, b, c} that is the set coming from 
adding c to {a, b}.


  Write two copies of the powerset of {a, b}


  { }
  {a}
  {b}
  {a, b}


  { }
  {a}
  {b}
  {a, b}


  Don't add c to the set in the first copy, and add c to the sets in the second 
copies. This gives


  { }
  {a}
  {b}
  {a, b}


  {c}
  {a, c}
  {b, c}
  {a, b, c}


  and that gives all subsets of {a, b, c}.


  This is coherent with interpreting a subset {a, b} of a set {a, b, c}, by a 
string like 110, which can be conceived as a shortand for


  Is a in the subset?   YES, thus 1
  Is b in the subset?   YES thus  1
  Is c in the subset?NO thus   0.


  OK?


  You say also:


The example of Mister X only confuses me more.


  Once you understand well the present post, I suggest you reread the Mister X 
examples, because it is a key in the UDA reasoning. If you still have problem 
with it, I suggest you quote it, line by line, and ask question. I will answer 
(or perhaps someone else).


  Don't be afraid to ask any question. You are not mathematically hopeless. You 
are just not familiarized with reasoning in math. It is normal to go slowly. As 
far as you can say I don't understand, there is hope you will understand.


  Indeed, concerning the UDA I suspect many in the list cannot say I don't 
understand, they believe it is philosophy, so they feel like they could object 
on philosophical ground, when the whole point is to present a deductive 
argument in a theory. So it is false, or you have to accept the theorem in the 
theory. It is a bit complex, because it is an applied theory. The mystery are 
in the axioms of the theory, as always.


  So please ask *any* question. I ask this to everyone. I am intrigued by the 
difficulty some people can have with such reasoning (I mean the whole UDA 
here). (I can understand the shock when you get the point, but that is always 
the case with new results: I completely share Tegmark's idea that our brain 
have not been prepared to have any intuition when our mind try to figure out 
what is behind our local neighborhood).


  Bruno






  http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/







  

--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-07-23 Thread Bruno Marchal
Hi Marty,

I can if you really want it, but it is out of topic and could  
introduced some confusion.  I suggest we could come back on this later  
perhaps. But if you insist, I can do it. have you get my last post?
Note that I have also already explained how binary strings can  
represent number in some older post. Honestly we will not need this,  
so it is better not to accumulate too many new materials, especially  
when I can fear some confusion. It is good to be familiar with the  
object binary strings seen as an object by itself.

Bruno


On 23 Jul 2009, at 14:02, m.a. wrote:

 Hi Bruno,
 I asked Brent Meeker a question which he referred  
 back to you. Will you be covering it? (see para in bold below)

 - Original Message -
 From: Brent Meeker meeke...@dslextreme.com
 To: everything-list@googlegroups.com
 Sent: Wednesday, July 22, 2009 11:49 PM
 Subject: Re: The seven step series

  *   000100100011 0100010101100111
  1000 1001 1010   1011 1100 1101
  1110  *
  **
  *and this is the binary sequence of length 4.*
 
  Right, it's all the binary strings of length 4
 
  **
  *How do these translate into ordinary numerals? 1,2,3,4...*
 
  Bruno's using them to represent sets and subsets.  So if we have a  
 set {a b c}
  we can represent the subset {a c} by 101 and {a b} by 110, etc.   
 That's quite
  different from using a binary string to represent a number in  
 positional
  notation.  I'll leave it to Bruno whether he wants to go into that.







 
  Brent
 
 
 

http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-07-23 Thread Bruno Marchal

On 23 Jul 2009, at 15:09, m.a. wrote:

 Bruno,
 Yes, yours and Brent's explanations seem very clear. I  
 hate to ask you to spell things out step by step all the way, but I  
 can tell you that when I'm confronted by a dense hedge or clump of  
 math symbols, my mind refuses to even try to disentangle them and  
 reels back in terror. So I beg you to always advance in baby steps  
 with lots of space between statements. I want to assure you that I'm  
 printing out all of your 7-step lessons and using them for study and  
 reference. Thanks for your patience,   m.a.


Don't worry, I understand that very well. And this illustrates also  
that your despair is more psychological than anything else. I have  
also abandoned the study of a mathematical book until I realize that  
the difficulty was more my bad eyesight than any conceptual  
difficulties. With good spectacles I realize the subject was not too  
difficult, but agglomeration of little symbols can give a bad  
impression, even for a mathematician.

I will make some effort, tell me if my last post, on the relation

  (a^n) * (a^m) = a^(n + m)

did help you.

You are lucky to have an infinitely patient teacher. You can ask any  
question, like Bruno,

is (a^n) * (a^m) the same as a^n times a^m?
  Answer: yes, I use often *, x, as shorthand for times, and I  
use ( and ) as delimiters in case I fear some ambiguity.

Bruno







 -- Original Message -
 From: Bruno Marchal
 To: everything-list@googlegroups.com
 Sent: Wednesday, July 22, 2009 12:20 PM
 Subject: Re: The seven step series

 Marty,

 Brent wrote:

 On 21 Jul 2009, at 23:24, Brent Meeker wrote:


 Take all strings of length 2
 00 01   10   11
 Make two copies of each
 00  00  01  01  10  10  11  11
 Add a 0 to the first and a 1 to the second
 000001  010   011  100   101   110  111
 and you have all strings of length 3.


 Then you wrote

 I can see where adding 0 to the first and 1 to the second gives 000  
 and 001 and I think I see how you get 010 but the rest of the  
 permutations don't seem obvious to me. P-l-e-a-s-e  explain,  Best,

  
  
   m 
 . (mathematically hopeless)  a.




 Let me rewrite Brent's explanation, with a tiny tiny tiny improvement:


 Take all strings of length 2
 00
 01
 10
 11
 Make two copies of each

 first copy:
 00
 01
 10
 11

 second copy
 00
 01
 10
 11

 add a 0 to the end of the strings in the first copy, and then add a  
 1  to the end of the strings in the second copy:

 first copy:
 000
 010
 100
 110

 second copy
 001
 011
 101
 111

 You get all 8 elements of B_3.

 You can do the same reasoning with the subsets. Adding an element to  
 a set multiplies by 2 the number of elements of the powerset:

 Exemple. take a set with two elements {a, b}. Its powerset is {{ }  
 {a} {b} {a, b}}. How to get all the subset of {a, b, c} that is the  
 set coming from adding c to {a, b}.

 Write two copies of the powerset of {a, b}

 { }
 {a}
 {b}
 {a, b}

 { }
 {a}
 {b}
 {a, b}

 Don't add c to the set in the first copy, and add c to the sets in  
 the second copies. This gives

 { }
 {a}
 {b}
 {a, b}

 {c}
 {a, c}
 {b, c}
 {a, b, c}

 and that gives all subsets of {a, b, c}.

 This is coherent with interpreting a subset {a, b} of a set {a, b,  
 c}, by a string like 110, which can be conceived as a shortand for

 Is a in the subset?   YES, thus 1
 Is b in the subset?   YES thus  1
 Is c in the subset?NO thus   0.

 OK?

 You say also:

 The example of Mister X only confuses me more.

 Once you understand well the present post, I suggest you reread the  
 Mister X examples, because it is a key in the UDA reasoning. If you  
 still have problem with it, I suggest you quote it, line by line,  
 and ask question. I will answer (or perhaps someone else).

 Don't be afraid to ask any question. You are not mathematically  
 hopeless. You are just not familiarized with reasoning in math. It  
 is normal to go slowly. As far as you can say I don't understand,  
 there is hope you will understand.

 Indeed, concerning the UDA I suspect many in the list cannot say I  
 don't understand, they believe it is philosophy, so they feel like  
 they could object on philosophical ground, when the whole point is  
 to present a deductive argument in a theory. So it is false, or you  
 have to accept the theorem in the theory. It is a bit complex,  
 because it is an applied theory. The mystery are in the axioms of  
 the theory, as always.

 So please ask *any* question. I ask this to everyone. I am intrigued  
 by the difficulty some people can have with such reasoning (I mean  
 the whole UDA here). (I can understand the shock when you get the  
 point

Re: The seven step series

2009-07-22 Thread m.a.
Hi Brent,
I really appreciate the help and I hate to impose on your 
patience but...(see below)

- Original Message - 
From: Brent Meeker meeke...@dslextreme.com
To: everything-list@googlegroups.com
Sent: Tuesday, July 21, 2009 5:24 PM
Subject: Re: The seven step series


 
 Take all strings of length 2
 00 01   10   11
 Make two copies of each
 00  00  01  01  10  10  11  11


 Add a 0 to the first and a 1 to the second
 000001  010   011  100   101   110  111
 and you have all strings of length 3.

I can see where adding 0 to the first and 1 to the second gives 000 and 001 and 
I think I see how you get 010 but the rest of the permutations don't seem 
obvious to me. P-l-e-a-s-e  explain,  Best,



m. 
(mathematically hopeless)  a.






 
 Brent
 
 m.a. wrote:
 *Thanks Brent,*
 *   Could you supply some illustrative examples?*
 * 
 marty a.*
 ** 
  
 - Original Message -
 From: Brent Meeker meeke...@dslextreme.com 
 mailto:meeke...@dslextreme.com
 To: everything-list@googlegroups.com 
 mailto:everything-list@googlegroups.com
 Sent: Tuesday, July 21, 2009 3:57 PM
 Subject: Re: The seven step series

 
  Each binary string of length n has two possible continuations of  
 length
  n+1, one of them by appending a 0 and one of them by appending a 1.  So
  to get all binary strings of length n+1 take each string of length n,
  make two copies, to one copy append a 0 and to the other copy append 
 a 1.
 
  Brent
 
  m.a. wrote:
  Hi Bruno,
 I'm not clear on the sentence in bold below,
  especially the word correspondingly. The example of Mister X only
  confuses me more. Could you please give some simple examples? Thanks,
 
 
 
 
  marty a.
  
  
 
   
  
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-07-22 Thread Bruno Marchal
Marty,

Brent wrote:

On 21 Jul 2009, at 23:24, Brent Meeker wrote:


 Take all strings of length 2
 00 01   10   11
 Make two copies of each
 00  00  01  01  10  10  11  11
 Add a 0 to the first and a 1 to the second
 000001  010   011  100   101   110  111
 and you have all strings of length 3.


Then you wrote

 I can see where adding 0 to the first and 1 to the second gives 000  
 and 001 and I think I see how you get 010 but the rest of the  
 permutations don't seem obvious to me. P-l-e-a-s-e  explain,  Best,

   
   
 m 
 . (mathematically hopeless)  a.




Let me rewrite Brent's explanation, with a tiny tiny tiny improvement:


Take all strings of length 2
00
01
10
11
Make two copies of each

first copy:
00
01
10
11

second copy
00
01
10
11

add a 0 to the end of the strings in the first copy, and then add a 1   
to the end of the strings in the second copy:

first copy:
000
010
100
110

second copy
001
011
101
111

You get all 8 elements of B_3.

You can do the same reasoning with the subsets. Adding an element to a  
set multiplies by 2 the number of elements of the powerset:

Exemple. take a set with two elements {a, b}. Its powerset is {{ } {a}  
{b} {a, b}}. How to get all the subset of {a, b, c} that is the set  
coming from adding c to {a, b}.

Write two copies of the powerset of {a, b}

{ }
{a}
{b}
{a, b}

{ }
{a}
{b}
{a, b}

Don't add c to the set in the first copy, and add c to the sets in the  
second copies. This gives

{ }
{a}
{b}
{a, b}

{c}
{a, c}
{b, c}
{a, b, c}

and that gives all subsets of {a, b, c}.

This is coherent with interpreting a subset {a, b} of a set {a, b, c},  
by a string like 110, which can be conceived as a shortand for

Is a in the subset?   YES, thus 1
Is b in the subset?   YES thus  1
Is c in the subset?NO thus   0.

OK?

You say also:

 The example of Mister X only confuses me more.

Once you understand well the present post, I suggest you reread the  
Mister X examples, because it is a key in the UDA reasoning. If you  
still have problem with it, I suggest you quote it, line by line, and  
ask question. I will answer (or perhaps someone else).

Don't be afraid to ask any question. You are not mathematically  
hopeless. You are just not familiarized with reasoning in math. It is  
normal to go slowly. As far as you can say I don't understand, there  
is hope you will understand.

Indeed, concerning the UDA I suspect many in the list cannot say I  
don't understand, they believe it is philosophy, so they feel like  
they could object on philosophical ground, when the whole point is to  
present a deductive argument in a theory. So it is false, or you have  
to accept the theorem in the theory. It is a bit complex, because it  
is an applied theory. The mystery are in the axioms of the theory,  
as always.

So please ask *any* question. I ask this to everyone. I am intrigued  
by the difficulty some people can have with such reasoning (I mean the  
whole UDA here). (I can understand the shock when you get the point,  
but that is always the case with new results: I completely share  
Tegmark's idea that our brain have not been prepared to have any  
intuition when our mind try to figure out what is behind our local  
neighborhood).

Bruno



http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-07-22 Thread Brent Meeker

m.a. wrote:
 Hi Brent,
 I really appreciate the help and I hate to impose on 
 your patience but...(see below)
  
 - Original Message -
 From: Brent Meeker meeke...@dslextreme.com 
 mailto:meeke...@dslextreme.com
 To: everything-list@googlegroups.com 
 mailto:everything-list@googlegroups.com
 Sent: Tuesday, July 21, 2009 5:24 PM
 Subject: Re: The seven step series
 
  
   Take all strings of length 2
   00 01   10   11
   Make two copies of each
   00  00  01  01  10  10  11  11
  
   Add a 0 to the first and a 1 to the second
   000001  010   011  100   101   110  111
   and you have all strings of length 3.
 *I can see where adding 0 to the first and 1 to the second gives 000 and 
 001 and I think I see how you get 010 but the rest of the permutations 
 don't seem obvious to me. P-l-e-a-s-e  explain,  Best,*
 ** 
 
 
 
* m. (mathematically hopeless)  a.*

They aren't permutations.  They're just sticking a 0 or 1 on the end.  One copy 
of 01 becomes 010 and the other become 011.

Brent

--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-07-22 Thread m.a.
Going a step further... (see below)

- Original Message - 
From: Brent Meeker meeke...@dslextreme.com
To: everything-list@googlegroups.com
Sent: Wednesday, July 22, 2009 12:57 PM
Subject: Re: The seven step series


 
 m.a. wrote:
 Hi Brent,
 I really appreciate the help and I hate to impose on 
 your patience but...(see below)
  
 - Original Message -
 From: Brent Meeker meeke...@dslextreme.com 
 mailto:meeke...@dslextreme.com
 To: everything-list@googlegroups.com 
 mailto:everything-list@googlegroups.com
 Sent: Tuesday, July 21, 2009 5:24 PM
 Subject: Re: The seven step series
 
  
   Take all strings of length 2
   00 01   10   11
   Make two copies of each
   00  00  01  01  10  10  11  11
  
   Add a 0 to the first and a 1 to the second
   000001  010   011  100   101   110  111
   and you have all strings of length 3.
 *I can see where adding 0 to the first and 1 to the second gives 000 and 
 001 and I think I see how you get 010 but the rest of the permutations 
 don't seem obvious to me. P-l-e-a-s-e  explain,  Best,*
 ** 
 
 
 They aren't permutations.  They're just sticking a 0 or 1 on the end.  One 
copy 
 of 01 becomes 010 and the other become 011.

Then I assume the next step would be making two copies of each of those:

000000   001 001  010  010   011 011 100  
100   101 101 110   110 111  111

...and sticking a 0 or 1 at the end:

   000100100011 01000101011001111000 1001   
  1010   1011 1100 1101   1110  

and this is the binary sequence of length 4.

How do these translate into ordinary numerals? 1,2,3,4...

 
 Brent
 
 
--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-07-22 Thread Brent Meeker

m.a. wrote:
 *Going a step further... (see below)*
 ** 
 - Original Message -
 From: Brent Meeker meeke...@dslextreme.com 
 mailto:meeke...@dslextreme.com
 To: everything-list@googlegroups.com 
 mailto:everything-list@googlegroups.com
 Sent: Wednesday, July 22, 2009 12:57 PM
 Subject: Re: The seven step series
 
  
   m.a. wrote:
   Hi Brent,
   I really appreciate the help and I hate to impose on
   your patience but...(see below)
   
   - Original Message -
   From: Brent Meeker meeke...@dslextreme.com 
 mailto:meeke...@dslextreme.com
   mailto:meeke...@dslextreme.com
   To: everything-list@googlegroups.com 
 mailto:everything-list@googlegroups.com
   mailto:everything-list@googlegroups.com
   Sent: Tuesday, July 21, 2009 5:24 PM
   Subject: Re: The seven step series
  

 Take all strings of length 2
 00 01   10   11
 Make two copies of each
 00  00  01  01  10  10  11  11
   
 Add a 0 to the first and a 1 to the second
 000001  010   011  100   101   110  111
 and you have all strings of length 3.
   *I can see where adding 0 to the first and 1 to the second gives 000 
 and
   001 and I think I see how you get 010 but the rest of the permutations
   don't seem obvious to me. P-l-e-a-s-e  explain,  Best,*
   **
  
   
 They aren't permutations.  They're just sticking a 0 or 1 on the end.  
 One copy
   of 01 becomes 010 and the other become 011.
  
 *Then I assume the next step would be making two copies of each of those:*
 ** 
 *000**000   001 001  010  010   011 011 
 100  100   101 101 110   110 
 111  111*
 ** 
 *...and sticking a 0 or 1 at the end:*
 ** 
 *   000100100011 0100010101100111
 1000 1001 1010   1011 1100 1101   
 1110  *
 ** 
 *and this is the binary sequence of length 4.*

Right, it's all the binary strings of length 4

 ** 
 *How do these translate into ordinary numerals? 1,2,3,4...*

Bruno's using them to represent sets and subsets.  So if we have a set {a b c} 
we can represent the subset {a c} by 101 and {a b} by 110, etc.  That's quite 
different from using a binary string to represent a number in positional 
notation.  I'll leave it to Bruno whether he wants to go into that.

Brent

--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-07-21 Thread m.a.
Hi Bruno,
   I'm not clear on the sentence in bold below, especially the 
word correspondingly. The example of Mister X only confuses me more. Could 
you please give some simple examples? Thanks,



marty a.


  - Original Message - 
  From: Bruno Marchal 
  To: everything-list@googlegroups.com 
  Sent: Monday, July 20, 2009 3:17 PM
  Subject: Re: The seven step series




  On 20 Jul 2009, at 15:34, m.a. wrote:


And then we have seen that such cardinal was given by 2^n. 
  You can see this directly by seeing that adding an element in a set, double 
the number of subset, due to the dichotomic choice in creating a subset 
placing or not placing the new element in the subset.

  Likewise with the strings. If you have already all strings of length n, you 
get all the strings of length n+1, by doubling them and adding zero or one 
correspondingly.

  This is also illustrated by the iterated self-duplication W, M. Mister X is 
cut and paste in two rooms containing each a box, in which there is a paper 
with zero on it, in room W, and 1 on it in room M. After the experience, the 
'Mister X' coming out from room W wrote 0 in his diary, and the 'Mister X' 
coming out from room M wrote 1 in his diary. And then they redo each, the 
experiment. The Mister-X with-0-in-his-diary redoes it, and gives a Mister-X 
with-0-in-his-diary coming out from room W, and adding 0 in its diary and a  
Mister-X with-0-in-his-diary coming out from room M, adding 1 in its diary: 
they have the stories 



  Bruno






  http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/






  

--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-07-21 Thread Brent Meeker

Each binary string of length n has two possible continuations of  length 
n+1, one of them by appending a 0 and one of them by appending a 1.  So 
to get all binary strings of length n+1 take each string of length n, 
make two copies, to one copy append a 0 and to the other copy append a 1.

Brent

m.a. wrote:
 Hi Bruno,
I'm not clear on the sentence in bold below, 
 especially the word correspondingly. The example of Mister X only 
 confuses me more. Could you please give some simple examples? Thanks,
 
 
 
 
 marty a.
  
  

 - Original Message -
 *From:* Bruno Marchal mailto:marc...@ulb.ac.be
 *To:* everything-list@googlegroups.com
 mailto:everything-list@googlegroups.com
 *Sent:* Monday, July 20, 2009 3:17 PM
 *Subject:* Re: The seven step series


 On 20 Jul 2009, at 15:34, m.a. wrote:

 And then we have seen that such cardinal was given by 2^n. 
 You can see this directly by seeing that adding an element in a
 set, double the number of subset, due to the dichotomic choice in
 creating a subset placing or not placing the new element in the
 subset.
  
 *Likewise with the strings. If you have already all strings of
 length n, you get all the strings of length n+1, by doubling them
 and adding zero or one correspondingly.*
  
 This is also illustrated by the iterated self-duplication W, M.
 Mister X is cut and paste in two rooms containing each a box, in
 which there is a paper with zero on it, in room W, and 1 on it in
 room M. After the experience, the 'Mister X' coming out from room
 W wrote 0 in his diary, and the 'Mister X' coming out from room M
 wrote 1 in his diary. And then they redo each, the experiment. The
 Mister-X with-0-in-his-diary redoes it, and gives a Mister-X
 with-0-in-his-diary coming out from room W, and adding 0 in its
 diary and a  Mister-X with-0-in-his-diary coming out from room M,
 adding 1 in its diary: they have the stories 

  
 Bruno



 http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/
 http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/%7Emarchal/





 


--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-07-21 Thread m.a.
Thanks Brent,
   Could you supply some illustrative examples?

 marty a.


- Original Message - 
From: Brent Meeker meeke...@dslextreme.com
To: everything-list@googlegroups.com
Sent: Tuesday, July 21, 2009 3:57 PM
Subject: Re: The seven step series


 
 Each binary string of length n has two possible continuations of  length 
 n+1, one of them by appending a 0 and one of them by appending a 1.  So 
 to get all binary strings of length n+1 take each string of length n, 
 make two copies, to one copy append a 0 and to the other copy append a 1.
 
 Brent
 
 m.a. wrote:
 Hi Bruno,
I'm not clear on the sentence in bold below, 
 especially the word correspondingly. The example of Mister X only 
 confuses me more. Could you please give some simple examples? Thanks,
 
 
 
 
 marty a.
  
  

  
 
 
 
 
--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-07-21 Thread Brent Meeker

Take all strings of length 2
 00 01   10   11
Make two copies of each
 00  00  01  01  10  10  11  11
Add a 0 to the first and a 1 to the second
000001  010   011  100   101   110  111
and you have all strings of length 3.

Brent

m.a. wrote:
 *Thanks Brent,*
 *   Could you supply some illustrative examples?*
 * 
 marty a.*
 ** 
  
 - Original Message -
 From: Brent Meeker meeke...@dslextreme.com 
 mailto:meeke...@dslextreme.com
 To: everything-list@googlegroups.com 
 mailto:everything-list@googlegroups.com
 Sent: Tuesday, July 21, 2009 3:57 PM
 Subject: Re: The seven step series

 
  Each binary string of length n has two possible continuations of  
 length
  n+1, one of them by appending a 0 and one of them by appending a 1.  So
  to get all binary strings of length n+1 take each string of length n,
  make two copies, to one copy append a 0 and to the other copy append 
 a 1.
 
  Brent
 
  m.a. wrote:
  Hi Bruno,
 I'm not clear on the sentence in bold below,
  especially the word correspondingly. The example of Mister X only
  confuses me more. Could you please give some simple examples? Thanks,
 
 
 
 
  marty a.
  
  
 
   
  
 
 
 
 


--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-07-20 Thread Bruno Marchal

On 20 Jul 2009, at 15:34, m.a. wrote:

 Bruno,
  I don't know about Kim, but I'm ready to push on. I'm  
 waiting for the answer to problem 2) see below. And could you please  
 retstate that problem as I'm not sure which one it is? Thanks,
 marty a.



Let us see:


 
  1) What is common between the set of all subsets of a set with n
  elements, and the set of all finite sequences of 0 and 1 of  
 length
  n.
  2) What is common between the set of all subsets of N, and the  
 set of
  all infinite sequences of 0 and 1.
 




Let me restate by introducing a definition (made precise later). The  
cardinal of a set S is the number of elements in the set S.

The cardinal of { } = 0. All singletons have cardinal one. All pairs,  
or doubletons, have cardinal two.

Problem 1 has been solved. They have the same cardinal, or if you  
prefer, they have the same number of elements. The set of all subsets  
of a set with n elements has the same number of elements than the set  
of all strings of length n.

Let us write  B_n for the sets of binary strings of length n. So,

B_0 = { }
B_1 = {0, 1}
B_2 = {00, 01, 10, 11}
B_3 = {000, 010, 100, 110, 001, 011, 101, 111}

We have seen, without counting, that the cardinal of the powerset of a  
set with cardinal n is the same as the cardinal of B_n.

And then we have seen that such cardinal was given by 2^n.
You can see this directly by seeing that adding an element in a set,  
double the number of subset, due to the dichotomic choice in creating  
a subset placing or not placing the new element in the subset.
Likewise with the strings. If you have already all strings of length  
n, you get all the strings of length n+1, by doubling them and adding  
zero or one correspondingly.
This is also illustrated by the iterated self-duplication W, M. Mister  
X is cut and paste in two rooms containing each a box, in which there  
is a paper with zero on it, in room W, and 1 on it in room M. After  
the experience, the 'Mister X' coming out from room W wrote 0 in his  
diary, and the 'Mister X' coming out from room M wrote 1 in his diary.  
And then they redo each, the experiment. The Mister-X with-0-in-his- 
diary redoes it, and gives a Mister-X with-0-in-his-diary coming out  
from room W, and adding 0 in its diary and a  Mister-X with-0-in-his- 
diary coming out from room M, adding 1 in its diary: they have the  
stories

00

01,

and then the Mister-X-coming-from room W, and with 1 written in the  
diary, similarly redoes the experiment, and this gives two more  
Misters X, having written in their diaries

10

11.

Obviously the iteration of the self-duplication, gives as result  
2x2x2x2x...x2 number of Mister X. If those four Mister X duplicate  
again, there will be 8 of them, with each of those guys having an  
element of B_3 written in his diary. OK.

And we have seen that a powerset of a set with n elements can but put  
in a nice correspondence with B_n.

For example: The powerset of {a, b}, that is {{ }, {a}, {b}, {a, b}},  
has the following nice correspondence

00 .. { }
01 .. {a}
10 ...{b}
11 ...{a, b}

Each 0 and 1 corresponding to the answer to the yes/no questions 'is a  
in the subset?', is 'b in the subset?'.

Such a nice correspondence between two sets is called a BIJECTION, and  
will be defined later. What we have seen, thus, is that there is a  
bijection between the powerset of set with n elements, and the set of  
binary strings B_n.

And the second question?

What is common between the subsets of N, and the set of infinite  
binary sequences. An infinite binary sequence is a infinite sequences  
of 0 and 1.
For example: 000..., with only zero is such a sequence. It  
could be the first person story of 'the mister X who comes always from  
room W. Or, if the zero and one represents the result of the fair coin  
throw experiment, it could be the result of the infinitely unlucky  
guy: he always get the head.
Another one quite similar is ..., the  
infinitely lucky guy.
A more 'typical' would be 11001001110110101010001000...  
(except that this very one *is* typical, it is PI written in binary;  
PI = 11. 00100...).

The link with the subsets of N? It is really the same as above, except  
that we extend the idea on the infinite.

A subset of N, that is, a set included in N,  is entirely determined  
by the answer to the following questions:

Is 0 in the subset?
Is 1 in the subset?
Is 2 in the subset?
Is 3 in the subset?
etc.

You will tell me that nobody can answer an infinity of questions. I  
will answer that in many situation we can.

Let us take a simple subset of N, the set {3, 4, 7}. It seems to me we  
can answer to the infinite set of corresponding question:

Is 0 in the subset?NO
Is 1 in the subset?NO
Is 2 in the subset?  NO
Is 3 in the subset?   YES
Is 4 in the subset?YES
Is 5 in the subset?NO
Is 6 in the subset?   NO
Is 7 in 

Re: The seven step series

2009-07-16 Thread Bruno Marchal

On 15 Jul 2009, at 04:15, m.a. wrote:


 - Original Message -
 From: Bruno Marchal
 To: everything-list@googlegroups.com
 Sent: Tuesday, July 14, 2009 4:40 AM
 Subject: Re: The seven step series

 Hi Kim, Marty, Johnathan, John, Mirek, and all...


 Bruno: May I advise you about an instance of English usage? The word  
 supposed in the next sentence is often used as sarcasm to imply  
 serious doubt about the statement. In this context it can be  
 interpreted as a slight. I think you meant to say assumed which  
 implies an evident fact. Please don't apologize, we are most  
 grateful for your efforts in using English and are happy to make  
 allowances for minor slips.
 B = {Kim, Marty, Russell, Bruno, George, Jurgen} is  a set with 5  
 elements which are supposed to be humans.

Thanks for letting me know. In french I assume is the same as I  
suppose. I'm afraid it will take time for me not doing that error  
again. But don't hesitate to remind me of the false friend behavior.  
Sorry for the unintended sarcasm.
To be sure it is not really an assumption, and a supposition means  
more like an obvious implicit fact we should take into account  
without mentioning, as opposed to an assumption which is more akin  
to a key hypothesis. Here I was referring to conventions only, but  
then, as yopu point out, an non intended sarcasm could be see.  
Difficult. That is why I prefer to stick on less ambiguous, purely  
mathematical examples of sets.



 I also have a question: see below:

 We have seen INTERSECTION, and UNION.

 The intersection of the two sets S1 = {1, 2, 3} and S2 = {2, 3, 7,  
 8} will be written (S1 \inter S2), and is equal to the set of  
 elements which belongs to both S1 and S2. We have

 (S1 \inter S2) = {2, 3}

 We can define (S1 \inter S2) = {x such-that ((x belongs-to S1) and  
 (x belongs-to S2))}

 2 belongs to (S1 \inter S2) because ((2 belongs-to S1) and (2  
 belongs-to S2))
 8 does not belongs to (S1 \inter S2) because it is false that ((2  
 belongs-to S1) and (2 belongs-to S2)). Indeed 8 does not belong to S1.

 Doesn't the statement in bold (above) contradict the statement  
 immediately preceding (also in bold)?



You are completely right. I just did a copy and past, and forget to  
substitute the 2 by the 8.

So the statements are:

2 belongs to (S1 \inter S2) because ((2 belongs-to S1) and (2 belongs- 
to S2))
8 does not belongs to (S1 \inter S2) because it is false that ((8  
belongs-to S1) and (8 belongs-to S2)).

Bruno


http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-07-16 Thread Bruno Marchal

On 15 Jul 2009, at 09:09, Kim Jones wrote:



 On 14/07/2009, at 6:40 PM, Bruno Marchal wrote:

 The intersection of the two sets S1 = {1, 2, 3} and S2 = {2, 3, 7,
 8} will be written (S1 \inter S2), and is equal to the set of
 elements which belongs to both S1 and S2. We have

 (S1 \inter S2) = {2, 3}

 We can define (S1 \inter S2) = {x such-that ((x belongs-to S1) and
 (x belongs-to S2))}

 2 belongs to (S1 \inter S2) because ((2 belongs-to S1) and (2
 belongs-to S2))
 8 does not belongs to (S1 \inter S2) because it is false that ((2
 belongs-to S1) and (2 belongs-to S2)). Indeed 8 does not belong to  
 S1.




 Quick (silly) questions:

 1.

 why do you have to write \inter  ? Why not just write inter  ?

 Typing \ causes me to make use of a key on my keyboard I have never
 used before which is scary ;-)

For the intersection of two sets S1 and S1,  I have used

1)  S1 ∩ S2

But the math symbol ∩  did not go through all emailing system, so,  
I have used

2) S1 INTERSECTION S2

But then I recall that in mails, capital letters seems aggressive,  
loudly ..., so I have used

3) S1 intersection S2

But then the difference between what is supposed to be represent a  
mathematical symbols, and a word in english, disappears, so I have used

4) S1 \intersection S2

But this, on the last post, seems to me to be a little too long, and  
so I am using now

5) S1 \inter S2

Only God knows what I will use tomorrow. You should learn that there  
is no standard of mathematical notations, and no two mathematicians  
use the same symbols, and not one mathematician use the same symbols  
in two different texts. What is nice, is that, usually, mathematicians  
quickly redefine what they mean by any symbols at the beginning of  
their books and papers.
Of course doing math on mails aggravates apparently this search for  
the symbols which could satisfy everyone.

Sorry to scare you,


 2.

 such-that is surely such that but the hyphen might just mean
 something
 (this is mathematics; there are dots and dashes and slashes all over
 the place so you have to know what they all mean)

 likewise

 belongs-to would still mean the same thing if we wrote belongs to
 would it not?

Same remark. I should have use \such-that, and \belongs-to.

Note that at this stage it is really not important to be aware of the  
difference between a symbol and what the symbols refer too, but in  
logic such differences acquire some importance at some point, and I  
just try to prepare you for such nuances, having the sequel of this  
introduction in my mind.

You question are not silly and makes sense, as you see,

Bruno


http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-07-16 Thread John Mikes
*Please read between your lines included in bold* letters
*John
*
On Thu, Jul 16, 2009 at 4:13 AM, Bruno Marchal marc...@ulb.ac.be wrote:


  On 15 Jul 2009, at 00:50, John Mikes wrote:

  Bruno,
 I appreciate your grade-school teaching. We (I for one) can use it.
 I still find that whatever you explain is an 'extract' of what can be
 thought of a 'set' (a one representing a many).
 Your 'powerset' is my example.
 All those elements you put into { }s are the same as were the physical
 objects to Aristotle in his 'total' - the SUM of which was always MORE than
 the additives of those objects.
 Relations!
 The set is not an inordinate heap (correct me please, if I am off) of the
 elements, the elements are in SOME relation to each other and the set-idea
 of their ensemble, to *form* a SET.
 You stop short at the naked elements *together*, as I see.


 You get the idea.
 We can add structure to sets, by explicitly endowing them with operations
 and relations.


 *Furhter below you also expose the contrary (to simplify) - **I am afraid
 your operations and relations are restricted to the numbers-based (math?)
 domain, which is not what I mean by 'totality'. *

  **

  *They wear cloths and hold hands. Mortar is among them.*
 Maybe your math-idea can tolerate any sequence and hiatus concerning to the
 'set', and it still stays the same, as far as the *math-idea you need*goes,


 Yes, it is the methodology.



  but if I go further (and you indicated that ANYTHING can form a set)


 More precisily, we can form a set of multiple thing we can conceive or
 defined.



   *I would not restrict 'a set' to what WE can conceive, or define now.
 (Not even within the 'math'-related domain).*

  the relations of the set-partners comes into play. Not only those which
 WE choose for 'interesting' to such set, but ALL OF THEM influencing the
 character of that *ONE.*
 *Just musing.*


 It is OK. The idea consists in simplifying the things as much as possible,
 and then to realize that despite such simplification we are quickly driven
 to the unprovable, unnameable, un-reductible, far sooner than we could have
 imagine.


*I may suggest (or: assume?) that instead of despite it would make more
sense to write: AS A CONSEQUENCE *
*- think about it.*
**


 Bruno
   *John*

  On Tue, Jul 14, 2009 at 4:40 AM, Bruno Marchal marc...@ulb.ac.be wrote:

 Hi Kim, Marty, Johnathan, John, Mirek, and all...

 We were studying a bit of elementary set theory to prepare ourself to
 Cantor's theorem, and then Kleene's theorem, which are keys to a good
 understanding of the universal numbers, and to Church thesis, which are the
 keys of the seven steps.
 I intend to bring you to the comp enlightenment :)

 But first some revision. Read the following with attention!

 A set is a collection of things, which in general can themselves be
 anything. Its use consists in making a many into a one.
 If something, say x,  belongs to a set S, it is usually called element
 of S. We abbreviate this by (x \belongs-to S).

 Example:

 A = {1, 2, 56}. A is a set with three elements which are the numbers 1, 2
 and 56.

 We write:

 (1 \belongs-to {1, 2, 56}), or (1 \belongs-to A), or simply 1 \belongs-to
 A, when no confusions exist. The parentheses ( and ) are just delimiters
 for easing the reading. I write \belongs-to the relation belongs to to
 remind it is a mathematical symbol.

 B = {Kim, Marty, Russell, Bruno, George, Jurgen} is  a set with 5 elements
 which are supposed to be humans.

 C = {34, 54, Paul, {3, 4}}

 For this one, you may be in need of spectacles. In case of doubt, you can
 expand it a little bit:

 C = {34, 54,Paul,   {3, 4} }

 You see that C is a sort of hybrid set which has 4 elements:

- the number 34
- the number 54
- the human person Paul
- the set {3, 4}

 Two key remarks:
 1) the number 3 is NOT an element of C. Nor is the number 4 an element of
 C. 3 and 4 are elements of {3, 4}, which is an element of C. But, generally,
 elements of elements are not elements! It could happen that element of
 element are element, like in D = {3, 4, {3, 4}}, the number 3 is both an
 element of D and element of an element of D ({3, 4}), but this is a special
 circumstance due to the way D is defined.
 2) How do I know that Paul is a human, and not a dog. How do I know that
 Paul does not refer just to the string paul. Obvioulsy the expression
 paul is ambiguous, and will usually be understood only in some context.
 This will not been a problem because the context will be clear. Actually we
 will consider only set of numbers, or set of mathematical objects which have
 already been defined. Here I have use the person Paul just to remind that
 typically set can have as elements any object you can conceive.

 What is the set of even prime number strictly bigger than 2. Well, to
 solve this just recall that ALL prime numbers are odd, except 2. So this set
 is empty. The empty set { } is the set which has no elements. It 

Re: The seven step series

2009-07-16 Thread Bruno Marchal


On 14 Jul 2009, at 10:40, Bruno Marchal wrote:

snip

 So the subsets of {a, b} are { }, {a}, {b}, {a, b}.

 But set have been invented to make a ONE from a MANY, and it is  
 natural to consider THE set of all subsets of a set. It is called  
 the powerset of that set.

 So the powerset of {a, b} is THE set {{ }, {a}, {b}, {a, b}}. OK?

 Train yourself on the following exercises:

 What is the powerset of { }
 What is the powerset of {a}
 What is the powerset of {a, b, c}


I give the answer, and I continue slowly.

1) What is the powerset of {a, b, c}?

By definition, the powerset of {a, b, c} is the set of all subsets of  
{a, b, c}.
I go slowly.

Is the set {d, e, f} a subset of {a, b, d}? No. None of the elements  
of {d, e, f} are elements of {a, b, c}. The question was ridiculous.

Is the set {a, b, d} a subset of {a, b, c}? No. One element of {a, b,  
d}, indeed, d, does not belong to {a, b, c}, so {a, b, d} cannot be a  
subset of {a, b, c}. The question was ridiculous again, but less  
obviously so.

Is the set {a, b, c} a subset of {a, b, c}. Yes. All elements of {a,  
b, c} are elements of {a, b, c}. {a, b, c} is included in {a, b, c}.

Can we conclude from this that the powerset of {a, b, c} is {{a, b,  
c}}. No. We can conclude only that {{a, b, c}} is included in the  
powerset. It is very plausible that there are other subsets!

Indeed,

Is {a, b} included in {a, b, c}? Yes, all elements of {a, b} are  
elements of {a, b, c}. This take two verifications: we have to verify  
that a belongs to {a, b, c}. And that b belongs to {a, b, c}.

Can we conclude from this that the powerset of {a, b, c} is {{a, b, c}  
{a, b}}. No, we could still miss other subsets.

I accelerate a little bit.
Is {a, c} a subset of {a, b, c}? Yes, by again two easy verification.

Is there another doubleton (set with two elements) having elements in  
{a, b, c}? Yes. {c, b}. It is easy to miss them, so you have to be  
careful. All two elements of {c, b} are elements of {a, b, c}, as can  
be verified by two easy verification.

  Is {b, c} a subset of {a, b, c}. Yes, but we have already consider  
it. Indeed the set {b, c} is the same set as {c, b}.

Is there another doubleton? No. Why? I search and don't find it.

is there yet some subset to find?

Yes, the set with one element, notably. They are called singleton.

Here it is easy to guess that there will be as many singletons  
included in (a, b, c} that there is elements in {a, b, c}. So the  
singletons are {a}, {b}, and {c}. This can be verified by one  
verification for each.

Are there still subset? Yes. We have seen that the empty set { } is  
included in any set. This can be (re)verify by 0 verifications, given  
that there is 0 element in { }..

Conclusion:
There are 8 subsets in {a, b, c}, which are { }, {a}, {b}, {c}.{a, b},  
{a, c}, {c, b} and {a, b, c}. And thus,

The powerset of {a, b, c}  is the set { { }, {a}, {b}, {c}.{a, b}, {a,  
c}, {c, b} {a, b, c}}.


2) What is the powerset of {a}?

Answer {{ } {a}}. It has two elements.

3) What is the powerset of { }
We could think at first sight that there are no subsets, given that  
{ } is empty. But we have seen that { } is included in any set. So { }  
is included in { }. Again you can verify this by zero verification!  
But then the powerset of { }, which is the set of sets included in { }  
is not empty:  It has one element, the empty set. It is {{ }}. Think  
that {{ }} is a box containing that empty box.


Attempt toward a more general conclusion.

The powerset of a set with 0 element has been shown having 1 elements,  
and no more.
The powerset of a set with 1 element has been shown having 2 elements,  
and no more.
The powerset of a set with 2 elements has been shown having 4  
elements, and no more. (preceding post)
The powerset of a set with 3 elements has been shown having 8  
elements, and no more.
The powerset of a set with 4 elements has been shown having 16  
elements, and no more. (older post)

In math we like to abstract things. Let us look at the preceding line  
with all the words dropped! This gives

--- 0  1 ---
--- 1  2 ---
--- 2  4 ---
--- 3  8 ---
--- 4  16 ---

On the left, we see, vertically disposed, the natural numbers,  
appearing with their usual order.
On the right, we see, vertically disposed, some natural numbers, which  
seems to depend in some way from what numbers appears on the left. It  
looks like there is a functional relation, that is a function.

The notion of function is the most important and pervading notion in  
math, physics, science in general, and we will have to come back on  
that very notion soon enough.

The idea that there is a function lurking there, is the idea that we  
can guess a general law, capable of providing the answer to the  
general line:

   The powerset of a set with n element has been shown having ?  
elements, and no more.

Can we determine ? from n. Surely it depends on n.

In this case, a simple guess can be 

Re: The seven step series

2009-07-16 Thread m.a.
Bruno,
I have no idea how to even begin to answer these questions. Have 
you given us the definitions we need to do so?  


 marty a.


- Original Message - 
From: Bruno Marchal marc...@ulb.ac.be


 
 I let those interested to meditate on two questions (N is {0, 1, 2, 3,  
 4, ...}):
 
 1) What is common between the set of all subsets of a set with n  
 elements, and the set of all finite sequences of 0 and 1 of length  
 n.
 2) What is common between the set of all subsets of N, and the set of  
 all infinite sequences of 0 and 1.
 
 
 http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/
 
 
 
 
 
--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



Re: The seven step series

2009-07-16 Thread Bruno Marchal

On 16 Jul 2009, at 15:17, John Mikes wrote:


 I would not restrict 'a set' to what WE can conceive, or define now.  
 (Not even within the 'math'-related domain).


Nor do I.
I never say so. On the contrary we will see how different are sets  
when seen by machines and gods, but to explain this it is necessary we  
agree on elementary properties and definitions on sets, so that we can  
proceed.
Here by we you are free to take the  we by any entities (machines,  
humans, gods, or whatever).





 the relations of the set-partners comes into play. Not only those  
 which WE choose for 'interesting' to such set, but ALL OF THEM  
 influencing the character of that ONE.
 Just musing.

 It is OK. The idea consists in simplifying the things as much as  
 possible, and then to realize that despite such simplification we  
 are quickly driven to the unprovable, unnameable, un-reductible, far  
 sooner than we could have imagine.

 I may suggest (or: assume?) that instead of despite it would make  
 more sense to write: AS A CONSEQUENCE
 - think about it.

It could make sense. This would lead to finitism and or mechanism,  
which I am trying to share with you. But again, this is an  
anticipation, and can hardly been made precise if we don't train  
ourselves to think about those simple things before.

Bruno

http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/




--~--~-~--~~~---~--~~
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
Everything List group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en
-~--~~~~--~~--~--~---



  1   2   >