[PEN-L:4228] Re: Mexico

1995-02-19 Thread Allin Cottrell

I would second Barkley's note re. Sid Shniad postings.  So long
as they don't come too thick and fast, Sid is doing us a
valuable service. 

==
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==




[PEN-L:4153] Re: story

1995-02-15 Thread Allin Cottrell

On Tue, 14 Feb 1995, Doug Henwood wrote:

 When did economists start (over)using the word "story"? Anyone know the
 pedigree of turn of phrase?

I can't give a history, but I take Doug's point.  Seems to me the term
'story' is very much part of the 'model'/'story' pair.  That is,
neoclassical econ having become excessively enamoured of mathematical
models -- to the point where their manipulation becomes the sole truly
legitimate occupation of the professional economist -- any attempt to
motivate such models by reference to certain features of the real, or
to interpret the results obtained in terms of real processes, is set
off as 'story'-telling. 

======
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==




[PEN-L:3995] Veblen and the neoclassical agent

1995-01-31 Thread Allin Cottrell

There is a well known passage in which Thorstein Veblen ridicules the
neoclassical conception of the economic agent.  So far as I remember
he uses phrases like "a quivering globule of desire" and "lightning
calculator of pleasures and pains".  Can anyone help me out with the
precise citation for these remarks?

Thanks.
===
Allin Cottrell
Department of Economics
Wake Forest University
Winston-Salem, NC, USA
(910) 759-5762
===



Re: The Hayek critique

1994-10-26 Thread Allin Cottrell

It seems that everyone these days accepts the Hayek critique of planning. 
Are there any sharp new critiques of the critiques that the comrades 
could recommend?

As for sharpness, the reader will have to judge, but Paul Cockshott and I
have a piece that takes on the critique, primarily with reference to Mises
but also with some discussion of Hayek and Don Lavoie.  It's in the
Review of Political Economy, vol. 5 (1993), pp. 73-112, and it's titled
'Calculation, Complexity and Planning: The Socialist Calculation Debate
Once Again.'  Basically, it is an unabashed defense of a variant of
economy-wide planning.  Paul and I also have a working paper that
deals specifically with Hayek's 1945 article, 'The Use of Knowledge
in Society', which we hope to publish somewhere before long.  
===
Allin Cottrell
Department of Economics
Wake Forest University
Winston-Salem, NC 27109
(910) 759-5762
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
===



Re:discussion of coupon socialism

1994-09-28 Thread Allin Cottrell

Too busy to respond personally to the recent discussion of coupon
socialism versus a more full-blooded version; but the thoughts of
Paul Cockshott and myself on these matters can be found in a new
article, "Value, Markets and Socialism."  It's available in postscript
from the archive at colorado (ftp to csf.colorado.edu, then go to
the sub-dir /econ/authors/Cottrell.Allin.  The file is vms.ps.)

=======
Allin Cottrell
Department of Economics
Wake Forest University
Winston-Salem, NC 27109
(910) 759-5762
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
===



Re: Broken vows Coase

1994-09-12 Thread Allin Cottrell

Doug he asked:

 Do PEN-Lers have, or know of, any 
critiques of Coase's theorem of why firms exist? Relatedly, are there any 
Marxian theories of the firm?

One relevant item that comes to mind is an interesting piece by Axel
Leijonhufvud, which commends both Smith and Marx for having a lot
more to say about the existence of firms than do modern neoclassicals.
I can't remember the title offhand, but it's in a volume edited by
Langlois, entitled "Economics as a Process."
=======
Allin Cottrell
Department of Economics
Wake Forest University
Winston-Salem, NC 27109
(910) 759-5762
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
===



new socialism book

1994-07-15 Thread Allin Cottrell

In debate in pen-l a few months back I made reference to a recently-
published book, "Towards a New Socialism," by Paul Cockshott
and myself (Nottingham, England: Spokesman).  In case anyone is 
interested, it is now available in the US, from Coronet Books,
311 Bainbridge Street, Philadelphia, PA 19147.  Ph. (215) 925-2762;
fax (215) 925-1912. (Since Paul and I are getting no royalties,
advertising in this medium does not seem out of order.) 

You can see a description of the contents in the September 1994
issue of the JEL.  
=======
Allin Cottrell
Department of Economics
Wake Forest University
Winston-Salem, NC 27109
(910) 759-5762
===




Re: gopher pen-l

1994-06-09 Thread Allin Cottrell

could someone  give me the gopher path if one wants to consult the
pen-l archives?  or the pkt archives? thanks ahead of time.

csf.colorado.edu: Heterodox Economics/Archives: Pkt
===
Allin Cottrell
Department of Economics
Wake Forest University
Winston-Salem, NC 27109
(910) 759-5762
===



Re: rate of profit

1994-04-25 Thread Allin Cottrell

On Sat, 23 Apr 1994 [EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote inquiring
 
 1.  where to find reliable and current information on the [average] rate of
 profit in the US and elsewhere
 
 2.  what trends in the [average] rate of profit in the US have looked like
 in the 1945-1972 and 1972-1994 periods
 
 3.  how meaningful a statistic the rate of profit is.
 
 I have a similar question regarding the rate of exploitation.  Does anyone
 calculate that these days?

On the US economy, I recommend Fred Moseley, The Falling Rate of Profit
in the Postwar US Economy (London: Macmillan, 1991).  On Britain, try
Paul Dunne (ed.), Quantitative Marxism (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1991).
Paul Cockshott, Greg Michaelson and I have a paper, "Testing Marx: Some
New Results from UK Data" which may be forthcoming in Capital and Class.
I plan to post a copy to my directory at the pkt archive at csf.colorado.
edu, from where it will be available by ftp.

All of these sources have measures of both the rate of profit and the
rate of exploitation.

Figures on the total $ amount of corporate profits are readily avilable,
on a quarterly basis (for instance, among the BCI - Business Cycle
Indicator - files which are available in electronic form from the
University of Michigan library.  Rate of profit figures are harder to
come by.  The rate of profit is, of course, the amount of profit
divided by the stock of capital.  To be fair to the official statisticians,
it should be pointed out that the theoretical problems in measuring the
capital stock are more severe than those involved in measuring the
flow of profit income.

======
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==




Re: GE Appearances -- III (very long!

1994-04-19 Thread Allin Cottrell

A small point in response to one aspect of Jim D's latest
posting.  There is no contradiction in Marx's saying that
the price of commodities other than labor-power gravitate
towards their "prices of production" while the price of
labor-power gravitates towards its value (though there may 
be other problems with this formulation).  The point is
that labor-power, since it is not produced under
capitalistic conditions, via a process that participates
in the formation of a general rate of profit, *doesn't
have* a "price of production" in Marx's sense.  

======
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==




LTV: responses to critics

1994-03-29 Thread Allin Cottrell
stewardship properly override the 
labor-time calculus.  

9.  More generally, consider the moves towards environmental 
protection in advanced capitalist economies.  Are these an *effect* of 
the working of the price system?  Of course not.  The banning of 
CFCs, the mandating of lead-free gasoline, the limitation of sulfur 
dioxide emissions, and so on, are accomplished by governmental 
regulation, in response to pressures from the general population or the 
environmentalist lobby or the scientific community.  In a democratic 
socialist economy, the same pressures would operate.  Just as the 
imperatives of profit-maximization are (sometimes) overriden by 
environmental/conservationist concerns under capitalism, so may the 
application of a labor-time calculus, in a planned system, be 
constrained by the same concerns.  Paul and I have argued in our 
book that it is a mystification to suppose that environmental issues, 
involving non-reproducible resources, can be "factored into" a scalar 
representation of cost: they must, if people regard them as important, 
be imposed as external constraints on narrowly "economic" 
calculation.  


==
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==





Re: Allin C and LAWS OF CHAOS

1994-03-28 Thread Allin Cottrell

I think (of course!) that Ajit Sinha has grossly misrepresented
Farjoun and Mchover.  Two brief observations: (1) They think that
an adequate theory of price is important, but it is certainly not
the "sole purpose" of their argument.  Their theory of price is
harnessed to the usual concerns of Marxian economics (generating
and explaining the "laws of motion" etc.).  (2) Their argument
against the equalized rate of profit assumption is not that it
is an abstraction, but that it is a *bad* abstraction.  Their
own stochastic approach is also highly abstract, but the claim
is that it does not abstract from an *essential* feature of the
process of capitalist competition.  The F and M argument has its
weak points, and is certainly not beyond criticism; but I find
Ajit's dismissal patronizing and complacent.

======
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==




Re: Allin C and LAWS OF CHAOS

1994-03-28 Thread Allin Cottrell

I think (of course!) that Ajit Sinha has grossly misrepresented
Farjoun and Mchover.  Two brief observations: (1) They think that
an adequate theory of price is important, but it is certainly not
the "sole purpose" of their argument.  Their theory of price is
harnessed to the usual concerns of Marxian economics (generating
and explaining the "laws of motion" etc.).  (2) Their argument
against the equalized rate of profit assumption is not that it
is an abstraction, but that it is a *bad* abstraction.  Their
own stochastic approach is also highly abstract, but the claim
is that it does not abstract from an *essential* feature of the
process of capitalist competition.  The F and M argument has its
weak points, and is certainly not beyond criticism; but I find
Ajit's dismissal patronizing and complacent.

======
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==





LTV: Responses to critics

1994-03-26 Thread Allin Cottrell

I shall first attempt to answer Steve Keen's questions.

1. Steve asks whether I would accept that what I have defended
is really a Labor Measure of Value (LMV) rather than a Labor
Theory of Value (LTV).  No, I wouldn't.  An LMV, as I understand
it, is what you find in Smith's advocacy of labor *commanded*
as the proper measure of price, and in Keynes's use of the wage-
unit in The General Theory.  The LMV in itself says nothing
whatever about how prices are *determined*, only about how they
are most usefully expressed.  Smith, famously, argued that
that the labor-content theory of value (LTV) didn't apply
outside of the "early and rude state of society": for capitalism,
he advanced the theory that "natural price" is determined by
summing the natural recompense of the three factors of
production (natural wage, natural profit and natural rent) --
a doctrine that both Ricardo and Marx vehemently opposed.  But
even when he thus ditched the LTV, Smith continued to advocate
labor commanded as te best *measure* of the three components of
natural price.  Ricardo and Marx upheld the much more substantive
proposition that relative prices are *determined* by socially
necessary labor-content (or more confidently, that changes in
relative prices are determined by changes in labor-content).
I have defended a version of this thesis.  Steve talks about
using labor as a numeraire; but the choice of a numeraire is
basically just a matter of theoretical convenience, and my
claims on behalf of labor go far beyond that.  Barkley Rosser,
though he is a bit skeptical, has caught my meaning more clearly.

2.  Steve asks if I believe that "labor is the only source of (new) 
value, and therefore that machinery etc. do not add new value".  
I am inclined to refuse the terms of this catechism.  Talk of
labor "creating value" and machines "passing it on" is useful
heuristically and valid up to a point, but I wouldn't want to
push it too far, since it suggests a conception of "value" as
a sort of metaphysical substance exuded by human beings but not
machines.  Let me re-phrase and answer his question in two different
ways.  (1) Do I believe that in a rational calculus of social cost,
machines should be accounted as so much embodied labor time?
Basically, Yes.  (2) Do I believe that the (real) profit income
of capitalists (and the real interest-income of rentiers, and the
real rental income of landlords) is properly conceived as the
proceeds of the exploitation of (extraction of surplus labor from)
productive labor?  Yes, I do.  The arguments in the last several
"LTV Defense" postings were supposed to bear on these points.

==
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==





LTV defense, part 12 (and final)

1994-03-24 Thread Allin Cottrell
rvation of other 
*species* is arguably a different matter -- a moral imperative.)  

7.  Further, consider the issue of full employment.  Clearly, this is a 
priority under socialism.  The minimization of the labor time required 
to produce things is also a priority.  As a first approximation, the idea 
might be: "Use all the labor-power there is, but spread the resulting 
labor as thinly as possible over the things you are producing, so as to 
be able to produce as many things as possible."  

8.  Of course when we say we want full employment, that we want to 
use all the available labor power, this doesn't mean that we want to 
have everyone working as many hours as they possibly can.  We want 
to have everyone working as many hours as they would like to.  Let 
me cut through the intricacies of this point with the assumption that we 
have broad social agreement on a standard x-hour working day.  
Then full employment means that all fit and able labor-powers should 
be employed for x hours a day (naturally, with some flexibility for 
part-time work around the edges).  

9.  This requirement creates another special feature of labor.  Not only 
is labor *scarce* (leading to the need to economize it in any particular 
branch of production), but it should be *fully used* each period.  This 
feature does not carry over to other resources.  A non-reproducible 
natural resource such as oil may be scarce (in the sense that its 
ultimate supply is finite), yet there is no requirement that it be "fully 
used" each period.  Indeed, what would that mean in the case of oil?  
All we can say here is that there is no point in extracting more oil each 
period than one wants to use during the period (unless one has a 
specific reason for adding to stocks).  In that sense the current flow 
output of oil should be "fully used".  But of course this current flow 
output is endogenous: one produces just as much oil as one plans to 
use, and the planned usage in turn is determined by technology (in the 
form, let us say, of the oil-input to labor-input ratio in production), in 
conjunction with the amount of labor one plans to perform.  

10.  Thus, while it would in principle be possible to construct an oil 
theory of value in place of the LTV, there are several reasons why the 
LTV is of special significance to human societies.  One can imagine 
circumstances in which the calculation of embodied oil-values might be 
desirable in a planning context (scarcity of oil is the most pressing 
constraint on the economy, and there is no possibility of substituting 
some alternative, producible via the application of labor), but these do 
not in fact obtain.  Labor-content is clearly the best single, scalar 
measure of the cost to society of producing each sort of good.  To the 
extent that relative prices under capitalism reflect, albeit in a highly 
imperfect and distorted fashion, social cost of production, one would 
expect to see the LTV borne out empirically -- as indeed one does.  

11.  Well, that is enough from me.  I don't want to try people's 
patience too far; and besides, I need to get on with other things that 
I've been neglecting.  I hope that I have laid down sufficient of a trail 
so that those who think it might be headed in the right (or at least an 
interesting) direction, can extrapolate for themselves.  For anyone 
interested, some of the points made above, concerning the role of 
labor-values in a rational cost calculus for a planned system, are 
developed more fully in a paper with Paul Cockshott in Review of 
Political Economy, vol. 5, no. 1, 1993; an earlier paper, expanding on 
different aspects of the issue, may be found in Economy and Society, 
vol. 18, no. 1, 1989.  

Thanks to everyone who offered encouragement along the way, and I
hope these postings have been of some use-value.


==
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==





Re: It's not Marx

1994-03-23 Thread Allin Cottrell

Not wanting to get myself any deeper into hot water, I'll
respond to just one of Jim Devine's points.  I don't
really get the idea that (quote)

price/value deviations befuddle our consciousness and obscure the
class nature of the capitalist system to its participants. (unquote)

Elsewhere Jim makes the same point the other way round, i.e.
if only prices and values were strictly proportional, capitalist
exploitation would be "visible" to all.  

Where is this idea coming from?  I would have said that although
feudal exploitation may be "visible" (e.g. the corvee), cap.
exploitation is "concealed" by "fair exchange" -- and, in
a sense, the fairer the exchange the *better* the disguise.
Marx's task was to show -- contrary to a widespread view --
that *even* if commodities exchanged in proportion to their
labor-content, there would still be exploitation.  Thus I
feel that Jim has this point backwards.   

==
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==




Re: It's not Marx

1994-03-23 Thread Allin Cottrell

Not wanting to get myself any deeper into hot water, I'll
respond to just one of Jim Devine's points.  I don't
really get the idea that (quote)

price/value deviations befuddle our consciousness and obscure the
class nature of the capitalist system to its participants. (unquote)

Elsewhere Jim makes the same point the other way round, i.e.
if only prices and values were strictly proportional, capitalist
exploitation would be "visible" to all.  

Where is this idea coming from?  I would have said that although
feudal exploitation may be "visible" (e.g. the corvee), cap.
exploitation is "concealed" by "fair exchange" -- and, in
a sense, the fairer the exchange the *better* the disguise.
Marx's task was to show -- contrary to a widespread view --
that *even* if commodities exchanged in proportion to their
labor-content, there would still be exploitation.  Thus I
feel that Jim has this point backwards.   

==
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==





LTV defense, part 11

1994-03-23 Thread Allin Cottrell
 X-content theory of value (as opposed to a 
non X-content theory, such as the Sraffian or GE systems).  Since 
exchange ratios, the explananda of such a theory, are scalars, X-
content must itself be a scalar.  In other words, X must be 
homogeneous -- or at least it must be possible to treat X as 
homogeneous for theoretical purposes, without departing too radically 
from reality.  This requirement clearly rules out "land" (i.e. one can't 
even begin to think of the land-content of a commodity as a scalar 
quantity), though it would seem not to rule out oil.  (And neither, of 
course, does it rule out labor.  Yes, human labor-time is not truly 
homogeneous.  But nonetheless human labor-power is an all-purpose 
resource, in the sense that anyone of average intelligence and dexterity 
can be trained to perform almost any of the tasks required in the 
economy.)  

10.  Conclusions so far: An XTV is in principle possible for any X that 
(a) is 'basic' in the technical sense, (b) is only weakly producible and 
(c) may be conceived as homogeneous as a tolerable first 
approximation.  Coming up: Some final suggestions on why the LTV is 
properly privileged over any other XTV.  


==
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==





LTV defense, part 10

1994-03-22 Thread Allin Cottrell
ess peasants against a landlord class 
-- for the redistribution of land -- but it is not applicable to the struggle 
of wage-workers against a capitalist class.  

Next time I'll begin on my final topic, a fuller defense of the
'specialness' of labor as it relates to the LTV.


======
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==





LTV defense, part 10

1994-03-22 Thread Allin Cottrell
ess peasants against a landlord class 
-- for the redistribution of land -- but it is not applicable to the struggle 
of wage-workers against a capitalist class.  

Next time I'll begin on my final topic, a fuller defense of the
'specialness' of labor as it relates to the LTV.


======
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==






LTV defense, digression

1994-03-21 Thread Allin Cottrell

LTV defense: interim responses
== 

1.  There are still a few more instalments of my "LTV defense" to 
come, before the whole structure -- or at least a sketch of it -- is "on 
the table" for criticism.  Nonetheless, it would be churlish to plough 
(plow) ahead without regard to comments received, so in this note I 
break off to indicate briefly the sort of answers I would have to the 
points raised by Mike Lebowitz and Steve Keen.  

2.  Both Mike and Steve are concerned, though in different ways, that 
I am not making enough of a distinction between Marx's theory of 
value (MTV) as such and the LTV, considered as a theory that was 
(very broadly) shared by Smith, Ricardo and Marx.  Mike's focus is 
on abstract versus concrete labor; Steve's is on Marx's conception of 
use-value.  A few words on these points in turn.

3.  Yes, the distinction between abstract and concrete labor is 
essential to MTV; but it is strongly implicit in any LTV.  Ricardo 
proposes that "commodities derive their exchangeable value from . . . 
the quantity of labour required to obtain them."  To render this 
meaningful, we must be able, in principle if not in practice, to quantify 
the labor required to obtain any given commodity.  But one can't add 
up hours of baking labor, spinning labor, mining labor, etc. (i.e. 
specific concrete labors), unless one conceives of these as just various 
instances of human labor in general (i.e. abstract labor).  Marx was 
clearer and more explicit on this, to be sure, but I don't see the 
concrete labor/abstract labor distinction as something that Ricardo 
would have objected to; rather, he seems to have taken it for granted.  

4.  I think it is a serious mistake, however, to go on to say (as Mike 
does) that abstract, socially-necessary labor-time is something that is 
manifest or measurable *only in the market prices of commodities*.  
This is to render the LTV empirically vacuous.  If the LTV (or MTV) 
is to have any empirical content, one must suppose that although one 
cannot *identify* the actual clocked labor-content of any given 
commodity with its abstract, socially-necessary labor-content, 
nonetheless market competition ensures that these two magnitudes do 
not diverge to an arbitrary extent.  And if one is dealing with large 
collections of specific commodities (as when using an input-output 
matrix with around 100 sectors, as Paul Cockshott and I were in our 
empirical work), it is reasonable to take clocked labor-content as a 
measure of Marx's "substance of value."  

5.  Steve Keen seems to reckon that I'm underplaying the importance 
of use-value in MTV.  His main point, made by reference to Marx's 
notes on Adolf Wagner and to Rosdolsky, relates to the special use-
value of *labor-power*, namely its ability to contribute more labor 
time to the production process than is embodied in its payment.  Well, 
this is obviously of great importance to Marx's theory of exploitation -
- which I'm just about to get to in my sequence of postings -- but I 
don't see it as inconsistent with anything I have said to date.  

6.  More generally, what distinguishes MTV from LTV?  I would say 
that MTV is LTV set in a particular theoretical and political context; it 
is LTV developed into a theory of exploitation and a critique of 
capitalism, something foreign to both Smith and Ricardo.  To achieve 
this development, Marx had to distinguish very clearly between labor 
the activity and labor-power the commodity: I reckon that is the key 
conceptual advance over Ricardo.  MTV is also in a sense LTV 
generalized -- a hint of this can be found in the Marx quotation at the 
end of my last posting (LTV defense, part 8).  That is, the exchange of 
commodities at prices roughly proportional to socially-necessary labor 
content is conceived by Marx as the specific manifestation, under 
capitalism, of the "necessity of the distribution of social labour in 
specific proportions" in order to satisfy the conditions of reproduction 
of any economic formation.  

==
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==




LTV defense, part 9

1994-03-21 Thread Allin Cottrell
(unquote)

8.  First response:  The 'exploitability' of oil is a consequence of 
technology (i.e. it is a technological datum that a barrel of oil can be 
extracted at a total oil-cost of less than one barrel).  This is not so for 
labor: the 'exploitability' of labor depends in part on the consumption 
bundle, which is socially determined.  Here is a real economic 
difference, which gives a special role to the exploitability of labor in 
explaining the existence of profits.  By raising the price of labor-power 
sufficiently, workers could, in principle, render themselves 
'unexploitable' -- which observation points us towards the socio-
economic factors that *prevent* the workers from doing so: these 
factors explain the possibility of profit.  

9.  Second, consider the whole list of commodities which capitalists 
*might* choose to produce.  Some of the items on this list may turn 
out, given current technology, to be inherently 'unexploitable' (e.g. 
currently it takes a larger energy input to produce a given energy 
ouput from a nuclear fusion reactor).  This is not a problem: capitalists 
simply don't try to produce them (there are no commercial fusion 
reactors for electricity generation).  From this perspective, the 
'exploitability' of all of the commodities actually produced in capitalist 
economies is not an *explanation* of profits.  Rather, the need for 
profitability explains why only 'exploitable commodities' get produced.  
Labor's special role -- in this context -- consists in the fact that its use 
is *not* optional (short of a science-fiction world of complete 
automation).  Labor is not employed because it 'happens to be 
exploitable', but rather it is the exploitability of (non-optional) labor 
that explains the possibility of profit.  

======
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==




LTV defense, digression

1994-03-21 Thread Allin Cottrell

LTV defense: interim responses
== 

1.  There are still a few more instalments of my "LTV defense" to 
come, before the whole structure -- or at least a sketch of it -- is "on 
the table" for criticism.  Nonetheless, it would be churlish to plough 
(plow) ahead without regard to comments received, so in this note I 
break off to indicate briefly the sort of answers I would have to the 
points raised by Mike Lebowitz and Steve Keen.  

2.  Both Mike and Steve are concerned, though in different ways, that 
I am not making enough of a distinction between Marx's theory of 
value (MTV) as such and the LTV, considered as a theory that was 
(very broadly) shared by Smith, Ricardo and Marx.  Mike's focus is 
on abstract versus concrete labor; Steve's is on Marx's conception of 
use-value.  A few words on these points in turn.

3.  Yes, the distinction between abstract and concrete labor is 
essential to MTV; but it is strongly implicit in any LTV.  Ricardo 
proposes that "commodities derive their exchangeable value from . . . 
the quantity of labour required to obtain them."  To render this 
meaningful, we must be able, in principle if not in practice, to quantify 
the labor required to obtain any given commodity.  But one can't add 
up hours of baking labor, spinning labor, mining labor, etc. (i.e. 
specific concrete labors), unless one conceives of these as just various 
instances of human labor in general (i.e. abstract labor).  Marx was 
clearer and more explicit on this, to be sure, but I don't see the 
concrete labor/abstract labor distinction as something that Ricardo 
would have objected to; rather, he seems to have taken it for granted.  

4.  I think it is a serious mistake, however, to go on to say (as Mike 
does) that abstract, socially-necessary labor-time is something that is 
manifest or measurable *only in the market prices of commodities*.  
This is to render the LTV empirically vacuous.  If the LTV (or MTV) 
is to have any empirical content, one must suppose that although one 
cannot *identify* the actual clocked labor-content of any given 
commodity with its abstract, socially-necessary labor-content, 
nonetheless market competition ensures that these two magnitudes do 
not diverge to an arbitrary extent.  And if one is dealing with large 
collections of specific commodities (as when using an input-output 
matrix with around 100 sectors, as Paul Cockshott and I were in our 
empirical work), it is reasonable to take clocked labor-content as a 
measure of Marx's "substance of value."  

5.  Steve Keen seems to reckon that I'm underplaying the importance 
of use-value in MTV.  His main point, made by reference to Marx's 
notes on Adolf Wagner and to Rosdolsky, relates to the special use-
value of *labor-power*, namely its ability to contribute more labor 
time to the production process than is embodied in its payment.  Well, 
this is obviously of great importance to Marx's theory of exploitation -
- which I'm just about to get to in my sequence of postings -- but I 
don't see it as inconsistent with anything I have said to date.  

6.  More generally, what distinguishes MTV from LTV?  I would say 
that MTV is LTV set in a particular theoretical and political context; it 
is LTV developed into a theory of exploitation and a critique of 
capitalism, something foreign to both Smith and Ricardo.  To achieve 
this development, Marx had to distinguish very clearly between labor 
the activity and labor-power the commodity: I reckon that is the key 
conceptual advance over Ricardo.  MTV is also in a sense LTV 
generalized -- a hint of this can be found in the Marx quotation at the 
end of my last posting (LTV defense, part 8).  That is, the exchange of 
commodities at prices roughly proportional to socially-necessary labor 
content is conceived by Marx as the specific manifestation, under 
capitalism, of the "necessity of the distribution of social labour in 
specific proportions" in order to satisfy the conditions of reproduction 
of any economic formation.  

==
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==





LTV defense, part 9

1994-03-21 Thread Allin Cottrell
(unquote)

8.  First response:  The 'exploitability' of oil is a consequence of 
technology (i.e. it is a technological datum that a barrel of oil can be 
extracted at a total oil-cost of less than one barrel).  This is not so for 
labor: the 'exploitability' of labor depends in part on the consumption 
bundle, which is socially determined.  Here is a real economic 
difference, which gives a special role to the exploitability of labor in 
explaining the existence of profits.  By raising the price of labor-power 
sufficiently, workers could, in principle, render themselves 
'unexploitable' -- which observation points us towards the socio-
economic factors that *prevent* the workers from doing so: these 
factors explain the possibility of profit.  

9.  Second, consider the whole list of commodities which capitalists 
*might* choose to produce.  Some of the items on this list may turn 
out, given current technology, to be inherently 'unexploitable' (e.g. 
currently it takes a larger energy input to produce a given energy 
ouput from a nuclear fusion reactor).  This is not a problem: capitalists 
simply don't try to produce them (there are no commercial fusion 
reactors for electricity generation).  From this perspective, the 
'exploitability' of all of the commodities actually produced in capitalist 
economies is not an *explanation* of profits.  Rather, the need for 
profitability explains why only 'exploitable commodities' get produced.  
Labor's special role -- in this context -- consists in the fact that its use 
is *not* optional (short of a science-fiction world of complete 
automation).  Labor is not employed because it 'happens to be 
exploitable', but rather it is the exploitability of (non-optional) labor 
that explains the possibility of profit.  

======
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==





LTV defense, part 8

1994-03-18 Thread Allin Cottrell
 differing and quantitatively 
determined amounts of society's aggregate labour.  It is self-evident 
that this necessity of the distribution of social labour in specific 
proportions is certainly not abolished by the specific form of social 
production; it can only change its form of manifestation.  


==
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==




LTV defense, part 8

1994-03-18 Thread Allin Cottrell
 differing and quantitatively 
determined amounts of society's aggregate labour.  It is self-evident 
that this necessity of the distribution of social labour in specific 
proportions is certainly not abolished by the specific form of social 
production; it can only change its form of manifestation.  


==
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==





pen and pine

1994-03-18 Thread Allin Cottrell

Depending on the software you use for dealing with e-mail, you
may or may not have any idea of the problem some of us have
been having with mail from PEN-L lately.

The point is this.  E-mail messages carry a header which contains
copious information, much of it redundant from a human point of
view.  Among the 'fields' in the header are: Received from, Return-
path, Originator, Sender, Reply to, and From.

Now PEN-L messages identify PEN as the source in several of these
fields, but not in "From" or "Reply to".  Sensible e-mail software,
such as PINE, displays by default only the content of those
fields that are likely to be relevant to the user: Date, From, To,
Subject, cc., and Reply to (if different from "From").

Since with its current settings, PEN-L has the person who actually
wrote the message in both the From and Reply to fields, PINE only
displays the former, with no indication that the message is from the
list.

Solutions for PINE users: (1) If the folks at Chico can change
things so that PEN appears in the Reply to field, that would be
great.  (2) There may be a way of configuring PINE so that it
displays the contents of the Sender field.  That would identify
the source OK, but still means that we wouldn't have the option
of using the Reply command to dash off a response to the list,
without having to type in the PEN address.  


======
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==





LTV defense, part 6

1994-03-17 Thread Allin Cottrell


Does the LTV have a mechanism?
==

1.  I want to get on to Roemer, Elster and exploitation, but first I think 
I need to address a concern that I suspect may be building in some 
quarters.  I have stressed the empirical validity of the LTV, but I 
suspect that will not cut much ice in itself.  

2.  David Hume famously argued that we can never discover any 
*necessity* in causal connections between matters of fact.  Necessity 
resides solely in the realm of mathematics and logic; among matters of 
fact there can at best be "constant conjunctions", brute empirical 
associations.  Hume's argument is notoriously difficult to refute, yet 
surely most scientists feel that there *must* be something wrong with 
it.  We expect of a "good" theory that it does more than produce 
predictions that happen to come out right most of the time.  We 
expect the theory to specify some underlying *mechanism* 
responsible for the production of the effect in question.  So: Empirical 
success apart, what is the mechanism of the LTV supposed to be?  

3.  Of the classical proponents of the LTV -- Smith, Ricardo and 
Marx -- only Adam Smith (whose version of the LTV was of course 
considered confused by the latter two) actually specified a mechanism.  
In Smith, the pressure towards the exchange of commodity bundles 
containing equal quantitites of labor time resided in the *subjective 
reckoning* of the parties to the exchange.  The beaver-hunter, 
*seeing* that his "output" took twice as much labor to produce as that 
of the deer-hunter, refuses to part with the beaver for less than two 
deer.  But unfortunately this mechanism would seem to operate, at 
best, only in the "early and rude state of society which precedes both 
the accumulation of stock and the appropriation of land".  Capitalists 
don't calculate the labor-content of their products, or of the 
commodities they purchase.  (Plus, even if they wanted to, it's much 
more difficult to calculate the labor-content of a commodity produced 
via a complex division of labor.)

4.  Neither Ricardo nor Marx specified an alternative mechanism.  
Ricardo was perfectly confident that the LTV was right, but if you 
look for a definite mechanism in the Principles you will be 
disappointed.  What purports to be an argument for the LTV appears 
on p. 25 of the Sraffa edition, but it is actually no more than an 
account of what will happen under certain circumstances *on the 
maintained hypothesis of the LTV*.  

5.  Marx, though he doesn't give a *mechanism* as such, does offer 
an argument, in chapter 1 of Capital, I.  It goes roughly like this.  (a) 
Commodity exchange should be conceived as an equation.  To make 
sense of the "exchange of equivalents" we must suppose that there is 
*something* present in equal quantities on both sides of the exchange.  
(b) Labor time is the only acceptable candidate for this "something" 
(since the use-values of commodities are incommensurable).  

6.  This argument has not persuaded many people.  At least on the 
face of it, it seems to be full of holes.  For instance:  (1) Why do we 
*have* to conceive of exchange as an equation (other than, trivially, of 
equal monetary magnitudes)?  There doesn't seem to be anything 
compelling about this "picture".  (2) Even if we do think of exchange in 
that way, and if we accept Marx's point about the incommensurability 
of disparate use-values, is labor time really the only candidate for the 
thing that is equated?  What about, say, energy-content?  (3) Besides, 
when we get to volume III of Capital, Marx admits that embodied 
labor time is *not* actually equated in commodity exchange under 
capitalism, even in "long-run equilibrium," so to speak.  

7.  There would seem to be two possibilities here.  (1) The confidence 
of Ricardo and Marx concerning the LTV was just misplaced.  Their 
failure to come up with a convincing mechanism is fatal.  (2) The 
*intuition* of Ricardo and Marx was sound, but outran their capacity 
to articulate a proper justification of the LTV: the job can, however, 
be done.  I think the second interpretation is the right one.  More later.  


==
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==





LTV defense, part 7

1994-03-17 Thread Allin Cottrell
tion is analogous -- this is still Farjoun and 
Machover -- to statistical mechanics.  The ideal gas laws, for instance, 
are "statistically emergent" from the interaction of millions of individual 
molecules.  

9.  But here is a further concern for future treatment.  Suppose you 
grant the above, at least for the sake of argument.  You may still 
wonder:  But after all, what is really special about labor?  Couldn't you 
do the same sort of statistical number using oil-content, timber-content 
or what-have-you?  Why is the LTV of any more intrinsic significance 
than the OTV or the TTV?  

End of seventh message.  

==
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==





LTV defense, part 4

1994-03-15 Thread Allin Cottrell


Back to Steedman


[Note: I hope I'm not wearing out my welcome too rapidly.  I think it 
will take about 10 messages in all, of roughly this length, to get the 
position I'm peddling "out into the open" -- perhaps Michael P can tell 
me to shut up if necessary.]

1.  What does one need to know in order to calculate labor-values?  
The input-output structure of the economy, including intersectoral 
technical coefficients and direct labor coefficients.  With this knowledge, 
one can invert the "Leontief matrix" (or perform an iterative 
approximation of same) and derive the full set of labor-values.  (With 
the same information, and by means of the same computations, one can 
determine the vector of gross outputs required to support any given 
vector of final demand -- a basic planning problem.)

2.  What does one need to know to calculate Sraffian prices?  Basically 
the same: the full set of input-output coefficients, plus a distributional 
variable -- either the (uniform) wage or the (uniform) rate of profit.  

3.  Is it in any way necessary to calculate labor-values as a step on the 
way to calculating Sraffian prices?  No.  This is one of Steedman's key 
points, and of course he is right.  In this sense there is no 
"transformation problem".  *If* one's object is to derive the set of 
Sraffian prices or "prices of production," one does not have to go via 
labor-values.  That would be an awkward detour.  And the question 
"What is the correct mathematical relationship between labor-values 
and prices of production?" would seem to be of interest only if one has 
some prior commitment to labor-values.  Why should one have any 
such commitment?  Labor-values seem to be analytically redundant.

4. But this argument loses its force if, as I have claimed, it turns out that 
labor-values and prices of production are about equally good as 
predictors of actual prices in capitalist economies.  Labor-values are a 
"detour" only if one's theoretical terminus is prices of production/Sraffian 
prices -- but why should *that* be one's theoretical terminus if one's 
ultimate object is to analyze real economies and their laws of motion?  

End of posting the fourth.

==
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==




LTV defense, part 4

1994-03-15 Thread Allin Cottrell


Back to Steedman


[Note: I hope I'm not wearing out my welcome too rapidly.  I think it 
will take about 10 messages in all, of roughly this length, to get the 
position I'm peddling "out into the open" -- perhaps Michael P can tell 
me to shut up if necessary.]

1.  What does one need to know in order to calculate labor-values?  
The input-output structure of the economy, including intersectoral 
technical coefficients and direct labor coefficients.  With this knowledge, 
one can invert the "Leontief matrix" (or perform an iterative 
approximation of same) and derive the full set of labor-values.  (With 
the same information, and by means of the same computations, one can 
determine the vector of gross outputs required to support any given 
vector of final demand -- a basic planning problem.)

2.  What does one need to know to calculate Sraffian prices?  Basically 
the same: the full set of input-output coefficients, plus a distributional 
variable -- either the (uniform) wage or the (uniform) rate of profit.  

3.  Is it in any way necessary to calculate labor-values as a step on the 
way to calculating Sraffian prices?  No.  This is one of Steedman's key 
points, and of course he is right.  In this sense there is no 
"transformation problem".  *If* one's object is to derive the set of 
Sraffian prices or "prices of production," one does not have to go via 
labor-values.  That would be an awkward detour.  And the question 
"What is the correct mathematical relationship between labor-values 
and prices of production?" would seem to be of interest only if one has 
some prior commitment to labor-values.  Why should one have any 
such commitment?  Labor-values seem to be analytically redundant.

4. But this argument loses its force if, as I have claimed, it turns out that 
labor-values and prices of production are about equally good as 
predictors of actual prices in capitalist economies.  Labor-values are a 
"detour" only if one's theoretical terminus is prices of production/Sraffian 
prices -- but why should *that* be one's theoretical terminus if one's 
ultimate object is to analyze real economies and their laws of motion?  

End of posting the fourth.

==
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==





LTV defense, part 2

1994-03-14 Thread Allin Cottrell


First substantive remarks:  On Sraffa-Steedman
==

1.  There is no doubt a nice Latin name for the fallacy of seeking to 
defend one's own position by attacking one's opponent's.  
Nonetheless I will open by doing exactly that.  Why?  Because there 
is considerable truth in the dictum "It takes a theory to beat a 
theory"; and I think that skepticism among progressive economists 
concerning the LTV has as one of its bases this sort of thought:  Why 
conjure with the primitive Ricardo-Marx LTV -- at best only a first 
approximation -- when for the same price (i.e. at the same sort of 
level of abstraction) one can have the *correct* (i.e. Sraffa-
Steedman) theory?  I wish, therefore, to undermine this thought.  (Of 
course, if the only thing that could be said in favor of the LTV is that 
the Sraffa-Steedman theory is faulty, this would not cut much ice.  
But please remember what I said about the provisional suspension of 
disbelief: there *are* positive arguments to be made too.)  

2.  Although theorists may sometimes be inclined to forget, the 
equalized rate of profit is NOT a fact.  It is, however, an assumption 
that is absolutely crucial to all theories of Sraffian derivation.  
Farjoun ("Production of commodities by means of what?" in Mandel 
(ed.) Ricardo, Marx, Sraffa) is able to show, for instance, that many 
Steedman-type examples, of the sort used to demonstrate the frailty 
of the LTV, fall apart and become economically meaningless given 
the slightest deviation from this assumption.  (Yes, Marx assumed an 
equalized rate of profit too, when producing the concept of prices of 
production, but the point is that this assumption is *not* crucial to 
the LTV as such -- more on this later.)

3.  What IS a fact, is that the distribution of the rate of profit in 
capitalist economies is quite wide, and broadly stable over time.  
Yes, there are forces working in the direction of equalization, but 
there are complementary forces working in the direction of dis-
equalization; and the joint outcome of these forces seems to be an 
"equilibrium" degree of dispersion of profit rates (with different 
capitals occupying different places in the distribution at different 
times).  (Farjoun and Machover, Laws of Chaos, Verso, 1983)  

4.  It is therefore not at all obvious that a theory based centrally on 
the assumption of an equalized rate of profit has any claim to 
*correctness*, to the status of a benchmark against which the 
deficiencies of the LTV may be assessed.  

5.  The greater the equilibrium dispersion of profit rates, the worse 
are Sraffian prices as approximations to actual prices -- or even to 
their "centers of gravity," discounting the effects of short-run supply-
demand disequilibria.  On the other hand, on the maintained 
hypothesis of an equalized rate of profit, the greater the dispersion of 
the value composition of capital, the worse are labor-values as 
approximations to actual prices.  Since both of these distributions are 
non-degenerate, the question of whether Sraffian prices or labor-
values offer the better systematic approximation to actual prices is an 
empirical one.  The evidence to date shows, with remarkable 
consistency across data-sets drawn from different capitalist 
economies and different time periods, that the two approximations 
are *roughly equally good*.  It is not the case that labor-values are a 
crude first approximation, and Sraffian prices a clearly superior 
second approximation.  

I have made this point before, but I wanted to set it out 
systematically before developing its implications.  

End of second posting.



==
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==





LTV defense, part 3

1994-03-14 Thread Allin Cottrell


1.  At this point I shall digress briefly to cover a flank, i.e. to address a 
concern that I suspect many students of Marxism may have.  

2.  I appear to be treating the LTV and the Sraffian system as 
alternative theories of (the "systematic component" of) relative prices.  
But isn't this to miss the point?  Wasn't Marx's Capital subtitled a 
Critique of Political Economy, not a Continuation of same?  How can I 
bracket Ricardo and Marx as proponents of the LTV when Marx was 
concerned to explode Ricardo, not merely to second him?  (I think Jim 
Devine has something like this in mind, and perhaps others too.)

3.  There is some force in this objection, but I think it is overdone.  
True, Marx's primary object was not to develop a theory of relative 
prices.  He wanted to lay bare the basis of profit in the capitalist 
exploitation of labor, to discern the "laws of motion" of capitalism, and 
to demonstrate that capitalism is a historically transient mode of 
production, whose internal contradictions necessarily propel it in the 
direction of its supercession by socialism.  From this standpoint, the 
LTV was but a stepping stone towards a theory of *surplus value* -- 
something quite foreign to Ricardo.  And, it may be said, whatever is 
valid or salvageable from among the latter ambitions may be 
reconstructed without appeal to the LTV.  

4.  This last claim I will tackle shortly.  For the moment I want to point 
out that although a theory of relative prices was not Marx's central 
concern, as such, it does nonetheless play a key role in his work -- if 
not in Roemerian reconstructions of it.  And it is a valid scientific 
question in its own right.  (And I might add that Ricardo, too, placed the 
LTV in the service of an analysis of the "laws of motion" of capitalism as 
he saw them -- e.g. the progress towards the famous "stationary state" 
via a falling rate of profit.)  

5.  Marx's analysis of exploitation assumes that the prices of 
commodities in terms of money are in proportion to their labor-values.  
There is weak and a strong reading of this assumption.  On the weak 
reading, it is just an expositional tactic for representing at the level of the 
individual factory and the individual worker, social relations that obtain 
between the class of workers and the class of capitalists.  It projects 
onto the *individual* working day a division into surplus and necessary 
labour time that is in reality a relationship between parts of the *total 
social working day*.  This is divided between time spent in industries 
producing workers' consumer goods and time spend producing goods 
used by the capitalists.  The weak position would say that these 
conditions of projection need not hold empirically for the thesis about 
the social totality to be valid.  

6.  The strong position would state that the conditions of projection are 
more or less empirically valid, in the sense that there is such a strong 
correlation between the prices of commodities and their values that 
what is true at the social level is also true at the micro level.  

7.  Hence, although the principal concern of Marx in his famous chapter 
on the commodity may have been the analysis of the *social form* of 
value, this does not indicate that he was unconcerned with the empirical 
relationship between price and value.  Generally he held that movements 
in price reflected movements in value.  This indeed was the specific 
form of representation of the category value (abstract social labour) in 
capitalist society.  The essence of this form of representation was that 
there was a homomorphism between the structure of prices and the 
structure of values.  Marx of course allows for disturbing elements -- 
temporary imbalances of supply and demand, differing organic 
compositions of capital between branches, etc. -- but the existence of 
these distorting factors no more invalidates the underlying hypothesis 
than the reality of air resistance invalidated Galileo's theory of falling 
bodies.  The claim is that the underlying tendency will produce clear 
measurable effects, which can be distinguished from the effects of the 
disturbing factors.  

[Paras 5-7 above are based on notes made by Paul Cockshott.]

End of third posting.



==
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==






LTV defense

1994-03-13 Thread Allin Cottrell

 Emboldened by positive remarks from some pen-lers I hereby 
embark on a defense of the classical labor theory of value (LTV), 
or something closely resembling it.  

Preface
===

1.  I realize that I have an uphill struggle ahead, given the volume 
and authority of the critiques that are out there.  These critiques -- 
I'm thinking mainly of those produced by people who are broadly 
sympathetic to a revised marxism as they conceive it, e.g. 
Steedman, Roemer, Elster -- are clearly smart work, and although 
I strongly believe that they are ultimately wrong, insofar as they 
lead to a rejection of the LTV, they make many undeniably 
correct points along the way.  Further, I think it's true that many 
(though certainly not all) of the defenses of the LTV that have 
been made to date partake in some degree or other of the sort of 
obscurantism, dogmatism, or general woolly thinking that are 
anathema to a razor-sharp logician such as Steedman.  My 
strategy here will be to offer a sampling of arguments that serve to 
sever the valid points made by the critics from their general anti-
LTV conclusion, as well as a sampling of positive grounds for 
considering the LTV scientifically useful.  Some willingness on the 
part of readers *provisionally* to "suspend disbelief" is 
presupposed.  (That is, if I am called on every point at the outset, 
I will not get very far.)

2.  I also realize that this electronic forum is not suitable for the 
posting of long, detailed arguments.  If my own practice is 
anything to go by, long messages from the lists get saved at first 
("for future reading"), then deleted a month or so later when one 
is in danger of exceeding one's disk quotas.  I will therefore try to 
serve up this argument in reasonably small and digestible chunks.  
For anyone who would like a synoptic view of where the 
argument is headed -- well, I'm afraid I can't yet point you to a 
finished paper on the subject.  The ideas I will present are the 
outcome of several years' discussion with my friend Paul 
Cockshott (and have been influenced in some respects by the 
work of Farjoun and Machover).  We have a number of 
publications dealing with the use of a labor-time calculus for 
planning purposes, including a recent book, Towards a New 
Socialism (e-mail me for details if you wish), and our general 
thoughts on the LTV are quite closely related to the ideas in these 
works; but we have not yet written up our stuff on the LTV itself.  
We do have two lengthy documents on the subject, which we are 
willing to share under the right circumstances, but they are more 
at the level of notes than even working papers.  

3.  While I understand Gil Skillman's suggestion that I start out
from vol. 1, chap. 1 of Capital, I shall not do so.  I think there
are several good reasons for accepting the LTV in some form, but
the argument given by Marx at the beginning of Capital *is not
one of them* (IMO).  I will have some comments to make about that
argument, but not at first.  

End of preface.
End of first posting.


======
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==





Re: the aggregate demand curve

1994-03-11 Thread Allin Cottrell

On Fri, 11 Mar 1994 [EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:

 The price level is taken as exogenous in defining the LM, and by 
 extension, in deriving the AD curve, so the question translates as 
 follows:  is there any way to explain a shift in the price level
 that does not presuppose a change in the money supply?
 
 The answer is yes, from an upward shift in (the non-vertical section 
 of) the aggregate supply curve, due say to some "supply shock" like 
 the OPEC price increases of the early '70s. 

Or from a shift of the AD curve for reasons other than monetary
expansion as such: fiscal policy or swings in private-sector
investment demand.  In AD/AS models, this will cause a temporary
departure from potential gnp, which will in turn cause a change in
inflation relative to money growth.  Integrated over time, this
amounts to a change in the price level.

======
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==




Re: the aggregate demand curve

1994-03-11 Thread Allin Cottrell

On Fri, 11 Mar 1994 [EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:

 The price level is taken as exogenous in defining the LM, and by 
 extension, in deriving the AD curve, so the question translates as 
 follows:  is there any way to explain a shift in the price level
 that does not presuppose a change in the money supply?
 
 The answer is yes, from an upward shift in (the non-vertical section 
 of) the aggregate supply curve, due say to some "supply shock" like 
 the OPEC price increases of the early '70s. 

Or from a shift of the AD curve for reasons other than monetary
expansion as such: fiscal policy or swings in private-sector
investment demand.  In AD/AS models, this will cause a temporary
departure from potential gnp, which will in turn cause a change in
inflation relative to money growth.  Integrated over time, this
amounts to a change in the price level.

======
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==





RE: marx on money

1994-03-10 Thread Allin Cottrell

I'm not sure I understand Jim's references to Marx's
"silliness" in assuming that prices are proportional
to (labor) values, or to the "so-called labor theory
of value".  Shaikh has showed, by reference to both 
US and Italian input-output tables, that values and
prices are indeed very close to proportional, with
R^2's on the order of 96-98 per cent.  (In "Ricardo,
Marx, Sraffa", E. Mandel, ed., 1984).  Petrovic and
Ochoa (CJE, 1987 and 1989 respectively), confirmed
this result on Yugoslav and further US data.  Paul
Cockshott and I have recently replicated Shaikh's
study using the 1984 UK input-output tables: our
findings were essentially the same.  Ricardo and Marx
were right: the labor theory of value stands up to
empirical scrutiny as well as just about any theory
in economics, and better than most!

======
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==





Re: Interest rates and politics

1994-02-23 Thread Allin Cottrell

I don't quite understand Trond's reasoning re. the money
market.  If I read him right, he's saying that widespread
insolvencies somehow tell the possessors of liquidity that
the rate they are charging for lending the stuff is
unreasonably high -- i.e., that insolvencies lead to a
reuction in the rate of interest via their effect on the
supply side in the money market.

To me, this seems perverse.  If (potential) lenders see
insolvencies, won't that make lending seem all the
riskier?  And won't that tend to raise rates further, via
an increased "risk premium"?  I'd have thought that if
a spate of insolvencies is associated with a reduction
in the rate of interest, this association would have to
come about via a reuction in the demand for loanable
funds (i.e., potential borrowers are forced to think
twice) rather than via an increase in supply.  On the
supply side, lenders should be willing to lend at
lower rates, the _safer_ that lending appears to be.

======
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==




Re: Interest rates and politics

1994-02-23 Thread Allin Cottrell

I don't quite understand Trond's reasoning re. the money
market.  If I read him right, he's saying that widespread
insolvencies somehow tell the possessors of liquidity that
the rate they are charging for lending the stuff is
unreasonably high -- i.e., that insolvencies lead to a
reuction in the rate of interest via their effect on the
supply side in the money market.

To me, this seems perverse.  If (potential) lenders see
insolvencies, won't that make lending seem all the
riskier?  And won't that tend to raise rates further, via
an increased "risk premium"?  I'd have thought that if
a spate of insolvencies is associated with a reduction
in the rate of interest, this association would have to
come about via a reuction in the demand for loanable
funds (i.e., potential borrowers are forced to think
twice) rather than via an increase in supply.  On the
supply side, lenders should be willing to lend at
lower rates, the _safer_ that lending appears to be.

======
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==





Slavery and capitalism

1994-02-16 Thread Allin Cottrell


The points made by Paul Cockshott and Jim Devine, regarding
the differences between slavery and capitalism, are well
taken.  Nontheless, I don't think it would be an oxymoron to
describe the system of the antebellum South as "slave
capitalism".  This is because (a) there existed a well-
developed market and trade in slaves, and (b) the output of
slave labor took the commodity-form to a large degree (on
the big plantations at any rate).  That is, the plantations
partook of the circuit M-C-M', with the "C" taking the form
of slaves and inanimate means of production rather than
labor-power and means of production.

Whether slave capitalism could have existed as a mode of
production in its own right, or whether it was inherently
parasitic on "regular" capitalism, is another matter.  Some
of Paul's points suggest the latter (i.e. the internal 
market within the slave system would have been too
restricted).


======
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==






Various debates

1994-02-04 Thread Allin Cottrell

Pen-l subscribers may be interested in the following, which was
originally posted on the Post-Keynesian Thought network. It
relates to an old debate over pen-l and  refers to a book which
may be of interest to many concerning how socialism should be
organized.
I dropped Allin Cottrell's third point, which didn't seem of
interest to pen-l.-- Jim Devine

 Allin Cottrell's Original message (abbreviated):

Some thoughts on a few things that have whizzed by
lately:

(1) Doug Henwood cites Nancy Folbre's characterization of
Albert and Hahnel's participatory economics as "one long
student council meeting," and wonders how supporters of
such schemes would reply.  I can't speak for A and H, and
am somewhat reluctant to criticize their work when they are
(apparently) not on PKT to make their case, but I will say
that Paul Cockshott and I ("Towards a New Socialism")
envisage democratic decision-making as having a broader,
parametric role in a planned economy, while many of the
details are worked out more or less algorithmically within
those parameters, avoiding participatory overload.

(2) Is there any prospect for linking up the sort of
paradigmatically PK concerns expressed by, eg, Paul
Davidson with the planning proposals that some of us have
been discussing?  Keynes thought that the shortcomings of
capitalism were severe enough to require "the more or less
comprehensive socialisation of investment".  How seriously
should we take this?  I'm not aware that Keynes ever
spelled out what he meant by this, or discussed the sort
of institutions that would be required to undertake this
"socialisation," but on the face of it, it sure sounds
like planning.  No, it's not on the US agenda for the near
future, but is it something PKs should discuss?

==
Allin Cottrell
Department of Economics
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==
end of copied message.

in pen-l solidarity,

Jim Devine   BITNET: jndf@lmuacad.   INTERNET: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Econ. Dept., Loyola Marymount Univ., Los Angeles, CA 90045-2699 USA
310/338-2948 (off); 310/202-6546 (hm); FAX: 310/338-1950