Re: EEOC says Catholic College Discriminated by Removing Contraceptive Coverage from Health Insurance

2009-08-17 Thread Vance R. Koven
I don't see what Belmont Abbey's status under one statute necessarily has to
do with its status under another, especially one as general as RFRA. What I
think you are obliquely saying is that Belmont Abbey is not a "person" under
RFRA, on the grounds that RFRA doesn't apply to institutional "persons"
unless some context--determinable with reference to some other law--suggests
that it might be. That's a fair enough argument, which I think others on
this list can address better than I can based on the RFRA case law, but in
any event it should be addressed on its own merits. I also take your point
about Belmont Abbey's other conduct being potentially inconsistent with its
position on its insurance benefit (though I don't think the notion that
paying its employees fungible money constitutes a concession to their
ability to obtain contraception carries much weight).
Vance

On Sun, Aug 16, 2009 at 6:08 PM, Michael R. Masinter wrote:

> Belmont Abbey might have a better chance with its RFRA argument if it were
> a religious institution entitled by section 702(a) of Title VII to practice
> religious discrimination, and if as such an employer, it conditioned
> employment on foregoing the use of birth control as an expression of
> religious faith or obedience.  But as I understand what I have read of the
> EEOC proceedings, Belmont Abbey does not limit employment to those whom it
> defines as the faithful, does not require of its employees that they refrain
> from using birth control, and may not even be entitled to claim the 702(a)
> exemption authorizing religious discrimination.  It already pays employees
> money with which they are free to purchase (or not purchase) birth control;
> it offers them prescription drug coverage as an additional employee benefit,
> which, like money, they are free to use to purchase (or not purchase) birth
> control.  If Belmont Abbey is forbidden from practicing religious
> discrimination, then it's hard to make the argument that under RFRA it is
> entitled to practice sex discrimination.  I would think its best argument is
> the question which has divided the few courts that have considered it, and
> that is the question of whether denying coverage for prescription birth
> control pills is sex discrimination.
>
> Michael R. Masinter  3305 College Avenue
> Professor of Law Fort Lauderdale, FL 33314
> Nova Southeastern University 954.262.6151 (voice)
> masin...@nova.edu954.262.3835 (fax)
>
>
> Quoting "Vance R. Koven" :
>
>  So for purposes of the law-n-religion analysis, the issue is whether
>> Belmont
>> Abbey can claim, either under the constitution or RFRA (this being a
>> Federal
>> matter), that it is entitled to a religious exception. Sticking with RFRA
>> to
>> avoid the complexities of post-Smith analysis, the government would have
>> to
>> contend that the prevention of sex discrimination is a compelling interest
>> (which for sake of discussion I'm willing to concede). Belmont Abbey would
>> then have to respond that since PDA requires coverage for contraception
>> *irrespective* of actual sex discrimination as normally understood, the
>> failure to provide such coverage on a nondiscriminatory basis (that is,
>> because men are equally prevented from obtaining reproductive-health
>> benefits--putting aside whether it could "offset" the women-only benefit
>> denial with a *different* men-only denial--that would conflict with
>> Catholic
>> doctrine) makes the PDA proscription merely malum prohibitum and not malum
>> in se, which parries the "compelling interest" alleged? If that's so, then
>> the government could go back and attempt a standard sex-discrimination
>> analysis of the matter without the benefit of the PDA presumption.
>> Vance
>>
>> On Sat, Aug 15, 2009 at 5:51 PM, Michael R. Masinter  > >wrote:
>>
>>  The PDA makes denial of health insurance benefits relating to pregnancy
>>> sex
>>> discrimination without regard to whether an employer denies men coverage
>>> for
>>> some other condition that affects only men.  Denying coverage for a
>>> prescription drug that prevents pregnancy, a risk to which only women are
>>> exposed, may therefore be sex discrimination under the PDA even if men
>>> are
>>> not denied coverage for vasectomies.  Whether the cost of prevention of
>>> pregnancy, as distinct from the health related cost of pregnancy, counts
>>> as
>>> one of the risks and burdens associated with pregnancy the PDA was
>>> intended
>>> to relieve women from bearing under employer provided health insurance
>>> and
>>> other employee benefit programs might better frame the question a court
>>> ultimately will have to answer.
>>>
>>> Michael R. Masinter  3305 College Avenue
>>> Professor of Law Fort Lauderdale, FL 33314
>>> Nova Southeastern University 954.262.6151 (voice)
>>> masin...@nova.edu954.262.3835 

Re: EEOC says Catholic College Discriminated by Removing Contraceptive

2009-08-17 Thread Perry Dane
This point might have been made by someone else already, but 
I'll venture ahead anyway:


I'm not sure we need to accept the premise that Belmont 
Abbey is guilty of sex discrimination here.  The EEOC determination 
found that "By denying prescription contraception drugs, Respondent 
(the college) is discriminating based on gender because only females 
take oral prescription contraceptives"  "By denying coverage, men are 
not affected, only women."   The obvious analogy implicit here is to 
the sort of pregnancy discrimination at issue in Gilbert, which 
Congress has (rightly) determined to be a form of sex discrimination.


But this case is different.  Belmont Abbey can credibly 
argue that its policy would be to refuse to pay for any 
contraceptive, regardless of whether the contraceptive is being taken 
by men or women.  That this policy affects men and women is not the 
product of biology, as it was in Gilbert, but of independent policy 
decisions made by other institutions to treat women's contraceptives, 
but not men's contraceptives, as prescription items.


To put it another way:  When General Electric argued in the 
Gilbert case that it was discriminating against pregnancy, not 
against women, that would rightly strike most observers as a 
laughable, or at least unduly formalistic, proposition.  But when 
Belmont Abbey argues that it is discriminating against contraception, 
not against women, that seems to me to be neither laughable nor formalistic.


Consider this analogy:  Imagine a pacifist landlord who 
refuses to rent to "combat soldiers."  Is that a form of 
discrimination against men merely because another institution (the 
U.S. Congress) has made an independent policy decision not to allow 
women to be combat soldiers?  (For purposes of the hypo, put aside 
the fact that many women do de facto serve in combat.)


Or imagine a landlord right next to a single-sex college who 
refuses to rent to "college students."  Is that a form of sex 
discrimination merely because the college has, of its own accord and 
as its right, chosen to be single-sex?


Now, these situations might, I guess, set up some sort of 
"disparate impact" claim, but that seems to me to require a more 
complicated analysis; in Bemont Abbey's case, it might leave more 
room for the operation of religious conscience or RFRA.


Perry



***
Perry Dane
Professor of Law

Rutgers University
School of Law  -- Camden
217 North Fifth Street
Camden, NJ 08102

d...@crab.rutgers.edu
Bio: www.camlaw.rutgers.edu/bio/925/
SSRN Author page: www.ssrn.com/author=48596
Academia.edu page: http://rutgers.academia.edu/PerryDane

Work:   (856) 225-6004
Fax:   (856) 969-7924
Home:   (610) 896-5702
***


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


Re: EEOC says Catholic College Discriminated by Removing Contraceptive

2009-08-17 Thread Michael R. Masinter
Contraceptives prevent pregnancy, and only women get pregnant.   
Denying contraceptive coverage to men does not expose men to  
pregnancy, but denying coverage to women does expose women to  
pregnancy.  Cpngress enacted the PDA because pregnancy uniquely  
burdens women in the workplace.  As I noted earlier, that still leaves  
the question of whether preventing the burden of pregnancy falls  
within the intended scope of the PDA, but answering that question does  
not hinge whether men can use contraceptives, prescription or otherwise.


Michael R. Masinter  3305 College Avenue
Professor of Law Fort Lauderdale, FL 33314
Nova Southeastern University 954.262.6151 (voice)
masin...@nova.edu954.262.3835 (fax)

Quoting Perry Dane :


This point might have been made by someone else already, but
I'll venture ahead anyway:

I'm not sure we need to accept the premise that Belmont Abbey
is guilty of sex discrimination here.  The EEOC determination found
that "By denying prescription contraception drugs, Respondent (the
college) is discriminating based on gender because only females take
oral prescription contraceptives"  "By denying coverage, men are not
affected, only women."   The obvious analogy implicit here is to the
sort of pregnancy discrimination at issue in Gilbert, which Congress
has (rightly) determined to be a form of sex discrimination.

But this case is different.  Belmont Abbey can credibly argue
that its policy would be to refuse to pay for any contraceptive,
regardless of whether the contraceptive is being taken by men or women.
 That this policy affects men and women is not the product of biology,
as it was in Gilbert, but of independent policy decisions made by other
institutions to treat women's contraceptives, but not men's
contraceptives, as prescription items.

To put it another way:  When General Electric argued in the
Gilbert case that it was discriminating against pregnancy, not against
women, that would rightly strike most observers as a laughable, or at
least unduly formalistic, proposition.  But when Belmont Abbey argues
that it is discriminating against contraception, not against women,
that seems to me to be neither laughable nor formalistic.

Consider this analogy:  Imagine a pacifist landlord who refuses
to rent to "combat soldiers."  Is that a form of discrimination against
men merely because another institution (the U.S. Congress) has made an
independent policy decision not to allow women to be combat soldiers?
(For purposes of the hypo, put aside the fact that many women do de
facto serve in combat.)

Or imagine a landlord right next to a single-sex college who
refuses to rent to "college students."  Is that a form of sex
discrimination merely because the college has, of its own accord and as
its right, chosen to be single-sex?

Now, these situations might, I guess, set up some sort of
"disparate impact" claim, but that seems to me to require a more
complicated analysis; in Bemont Abbey's case, it might leave more room
for the operation of religious conscience or RFRA.

Perry



***
Perry Dane
Professor of Law

Rutgers University
School of Law  -- Camden
217 North Fifth Street
Camden, NJ 08102

d...@crab.rutgers.edu
Bio: www.camlaw.rutgers.edu/bio/925/
SSRN Author page: www.ssrn.com/author=48596
Academia.edu page: http://rutgers.academia.edu/PerryDane

Work:   (856) 225-6004
Fax:   (856) 969-7924
Home:   (610) 896-5702
***


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.







___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: EEOC says Catholic College Discriminated by Removing Contraceptive

2009-08-17 Thread Stuart Buck

How is declining to subsidize the *prevention* of pregnancy a sign of 
discrimination *against* pregnancy?  



> Date: Mon, 17 Aug 2009 16:31:29 -0400
> From: masin...@nova.edu
> To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
> Subject: Re: EEOC says Catholic College Discriminated by Removing 
> Contraceptive
> 
> Contraceptives prevent pregnancy, and only women get pregnant.   
> Denying contraceptive coverage to men does not expose men to  
> pregnancy, but denying coverage to women does expose women to  
> pregnancy.  Cpngress enacted the PDA because pregnancy uniquely  
> burdens women in the workplace.  As I noted earlier, that still leaves  
> the question of whether preventing the burden of pregnancy falls  
> within the intended scope of the PDA, but answering that question does  
> not hinge whether men can use contraceptives, prescription or otherwise.
> 
> Michael R. Masinter  3305 College Avenue
> Professor of Law Fort Lauderdale, FL 33314
> Nova Southeastern University 954.262.6151 (voice)
> masin...@nova.edu954.262.3835 (fax)
> 
> Quoting Perry Dane :
> 
> > This point might have been made by someone else already, but
> > I'll venture ahead anyway:
> >
> > I'm not sure we need to accept the premise that Belmont Abbey
> > is guilty of sex discrimination here.  The EEOC determination found
> > that "By denying prescription contraception drugs, Respondent (the
> > college) is discriminating based on gender because only females take
> > oral prescription contraceptives"  "By denying coverage, men are not
> > affected, only women."   The obvious analogy implicit here is to the
> > sort of pregnancy discrimination at issue in Gilbert, which Congress
> > has (rightly) determined to be a form of sex discrimination.
> >
> > But this case is different.  Belmont Abbey can credibly argue
> > that its policy would be to refuse to pay for any contraceptive,
> > regardless of whether the contraceptive is being taken by men or women.
> >  That this policy affects men and women is not the product of biology,
> > as it was in Gilbert, but of independent policy decisions made by other
> > institutions to treat women's contraceptives, but not men's
> > contraceptives, as prescription items.
> >
> > To put it another way:  When General Electric argued in the
> > Gilbert case that it was discriminating against pregnancy, not against
> > women, that would rightly strike most observers as a laughable, or at
> > least unduly formalistic, proposition.  But when Belmont Abbey argues
> > that it is discriminating against contraception, not against women,
> > that seems to me to be neither laughable nor formalistic.
> >
> > Consider this analogy:  Imagine a pacifist landlord who refuses
> > to rent to "combat soldiers."  Is that a form of discrimination against
> > men merely because another institution (the U.S. Congress) has made an
> > independent policy decision not to allow women to be combat soldiers?
> > (For purposes of the hypo, put aside the fact that many women do de
> > facto serve in combat.)
> >
> > Or imagine a landlord right next to a single-sex college who
> > refuses to rent to "college students."  Is that a form of sex
> > discrimination merely because the college has, of its own accord and as
> > its right, chosen to be single-sex?
> >
> > Now, these situations might, I guess, set up some sort of
> > "disparate impact" claim, but that seems to me to require a more
> > complicated analysis; in Bemont Abbey's case, it might leave more room
> > for the operation of religious conscience or RFRA.
> >
> > Perry
> >
> >
> >
> > ***
> > Perry Dane
> > Professor of Law
> >
> > Rutgers University
> > School of Law  -- Camden
> > 217 North Fifth Street
> > Camden, NJ 08102
> >
> > d...@crab.rutgers.edu
> > Bio: www.camlaw.rutgers.edu/bio/925/
> > SSRN Author page: www.ssrn.com/author=48596
> > Academia.edu page: http://rutgers.academia.edu/PerryDane
> >
> > Work:   (856) 225-6004
> > Fax:   (856) 969-7924
> > Home:   (610) 896-5702
> > ***
> >
> >
> > ___
> > To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
> > To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
> > http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
> >
> > Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
> > private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
> > posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
> > or wrongly) forward the messages to others.
> 
> 
> 
> 
> 
> 
> ___
> To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
> To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, se

RE: EEOC says Catholic College Discriminated by Removing Contraceptive

2009-08-17 Thread Brownstein, Alan
I know it is shifting the focus of the discussion, but one way to think about 
the broader issue here is to ask if there is a way to protect the religious 
liberty of Catholic institutions that do not want to subsidize coverage for 
prescription contraceptives in the health plans they provide to their employees 
and also make sure that women employees receive equal prescription drug 
coverage.

Government might be able to play a more positive role here in addition to or as 
an alternative to a finding of gender discrimination.

Alan Brownstein

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Michael R. Masinter
Sent: Monday, August 17, 2009 1:31 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: EEOC says Catholic College Discriminated by Removing Contraceptive

Contraceptives prevent pregnancy, and only women get pregnant.   
Denying contraceptive coverage to men does not expose men to  
pregnancy, but denying coverage to women does expose women to  
pregnancy.  Cpngress enacted the PDA because pregnancy uniquely  
burdens women in the workplace.  As I noted earlier, that still leaves  
the question of whether preventing the burden of pregnancy falls  
within the intended scope of the PDA, but answering that question does  
not hinge whether men can use contraceptives, prescription or otherwise.

Michael R. Masinter  3305 College Avenue
Professor of Law Fort Lauderdale, FL 33314
Nova Southeastern University 954.262.6151 (voice)
masin...@nova.edu954.262.3835 (fax)

Quoting Perry Dane :

> This point might have been made by someone else already, but
> I'll venture ahead anyway:
>
> I'm not sure we need to accept the premise that Belmont Abbey
> is guilty of sex discrimination here.  The EEOC determination found
> that "By denying prescription contraception drugs, Respondent (the
> college) is discriminating based on gender because only females take
> oral prescription contraceptives"  "By denying coverage, men are not
> affected, only women."   The obvious analogy implicit here is to the
> sort of pregnancy discrimination at issue in Gilbert, which Congress
> has (rightly) determined to be a form of sex discrimination.
>
> But this case is different.  Belmont Abbey can credibly argue
> that its policy would be to refuse to pay for any contraceptive,
> regardless of whether the contraceptive is being taken by men or women.
>  That this policy affects men and women is not the product of biology,
> as it was in Gilbert, but of independent policy decisions made by other
> institutions to treat women's contraceptives, but not men's
> contraceptives, as prescription items.
>
> To put it another way:  When General Electric argued in the
> Gilbert case that it was discriminating against pregnancy, not against
> women, that would rightly strike most observers as a laughable, or at
> least unduly formalistic, proposition.  But when Belmont Abbey argues
> that it is discriminating against contraception, not against women,
> that seems to me to be neither laughable nor formalistic.
>
> Consider this analogy:  Imagine a pacifist landlord who refuses
> to rent to "combat soldiers."  Is that a form of discrimination against
> men merely because another institution (the U.S. Congress) has made an
> independent policy decision not to allow women to be combat soldiers?
> (For purposes of the hypo, put aside the fact that many women do de
> facto serve in combat.)
>
> Or imagine a landlord right next to a single-sex college who
> refuses to rent to "college students."  Is that a form of sex
> discrimination merely because the college has, of its own accord and as
> its right, chosen to be single-sex?
>
> Now, these situations might, I guess, set up some sort of
> "disparate impact" claim, but that seems to me to require a more
> complicated analysis; in Bemont Abbey's case, it might leave more room
> for the operation of religious conscience or RFRA.
>
> Perry
>
>
>
> ***
> Perry Dane
> Professor of Law
>
> Rutgers University
> School of Law  -- Camden
> 217 North Fifth Street
> Camden, NJ 08102
>
> d...@crab.rutgers.edu
> Bio: www.camlaw.rutgers.edu/bio/925/
> SSRN Author page: www.ssrn.com/author=48596
> Academia.edu page: http://rutgers.academia.edu/PerryDane
>
> Work:   (856) 225-6004
> Fax:   (856) 969-7924
> Home:   (610) 896-5702
> ***
>
>
> ___
> To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
> To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
> http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
>
> Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
> private.  Anyone ca

Re: EEOC says Catholic College Discriminated by Removing Contraceptive Coverage from Health Insurance

2009-08-17 Thread Michael R. Masinter
There are many hurdles to a successful RFRA defense to otherwise  
unlawful sex discrimination (making the contested assumption that  
denial of coverage is sex discrimination).  Congress has already  
provided both the 702(a) exemption and the bona fide occupational  
qualification defense for employers; the two generally provide greater  
protection for religious employers than does RFRA.  Though RFRA  
applies to all government action, including government action under  
Title VII, most Title VII claims are brought by a charging party after  
receipt of a right to sue letter, not by EEOC.  The Seventh Circuit  
has held that RFRA does not apply to Title VII claims brought by  
private litigants.  Tomic v. Catholic Diocese of Peoria, 442 F.3d 1036  
(7th Cir. 2006).  A panel of the Second Circuit held otherwise in  
Hankins v. Lyght, 441 F.3d 96 (2d Cir. 2006), but a later Second  
Circuit panel questioned the soundness of that decision.  Rweyemamu v.  
Cote, 520 F.3d 198 (2d Cir. 2008).  Unless EEOC sues Belmont Abbey,  
RFRA may not apply for lack of government action.


Assuming RFRA applies, Belmont Abbey may have difficulty demonstrating  
that the resolution of that claim in favor of plaintiffs substantially  
burdens the free exercise of religion for reasons I already noted.   
The individual female employee makes the choice to purchase birth  
control pills, and whether she does so with the proceeds of her  
employer paid salary or her employer paid prescription drug benefits,  
she is doing so with funds traceable to her employer, who does not  
condition employment on refusing to use birth control or on refusing  
to pay for birth control with funds that are proceeds of employment,  
and who therefore may have trouble convincing a judge that a finding  
of sex discrimination is substantially burdens the free exercise of  
religion, and that Title VII's does not further the government's  
compelling interest in the eradication of workplace sex discrimination  
as defined by the PDA in the least restrictive manner.


That's not to say RFRA the scope of RFRA's application to Title VII is  
clear; perhaps RFRA does apply to private claims of discrimination, a  
finding of sex discrimination would substantially burden the free  
exercise of religion, and the government's compelling interest in  
eradicating workplace sex discrimination as defined to include  
pregnancy could be carried out in a less restrictive manner.  If so,  
and if denying coverage is sex discrimination, then I agree RFRA will  
matter.


Mike

Michael R. Masinter  3305 College Avenue
Professor of Law Fort Lauderdale, FL 33314
Nova Southeastern University 954.262.6151 (voice)
masin...@nova.edu954.262.3835 (fax)


Quoting "Vance R. Koven" :


I don't see what Belmont Abbey's status under one statute necessarily has to
do with its status under another, especially one as general as RFRA. What I
think you are obliquely saying is that Belmont Abbey is not a "person" under
RFRA, on the grounds that RFRA doesn't apply to institutional "persons"
unless some context--determinable with reference to some other law--suggests
that it might be. That's a fair enough argument, which I think others on
this list can address better than I can based on the RFRA case law, but in
any event it should be addressed on its own merits. I also take your point
about Belmont Abbey's other conduct being potentially inconsistent with its
position on its insurance benefit (though I don't think the notion that
paying its employees fungible money constitutes a concession to their
ability to obtain contraception carries much weight).
Vance

On Sun, Aug 16, 2009 at 6:08 PM, Michael R. Masinter   
wrote:



Belmont Abbey might have a better chance with its RFRA argument if it were
a religious institution entitled by section 702(a) of Title VII to practice
religious discrimination, and if as such an employer, it conditioned
employment on foregoing the use of birth control as an expression of
religious faith or obedience.  But as I understand what I have read of the
EEOC proceedings, Belmont Abbey does not limit employment to those whom it
defines as the faithful, does not require of its employees that they refrain
from using birth control, and may not even be entitled to claim the 702(a)
exemption authorizing religious discrimination.  It already pays employees
money with which they are free to purchase (or not purchase) birth control;
it offers them prescription drug coverage as an additional employee benefit,
which, like money, they are free to use to purchase (or not purchase) birth
control.  If Belmont Abbey is forbidden from practicing religious
discrimination, then it's hard to make the argument that under RFRA it is
entitled to practice sex discrimination.  I would think its best argument is
the question which has divided the few courts that have considered it, and
that is the ques

Re: EEOC says Catholic College Discriminated by Removing Contraceptive Coverage from Health Insurance

2009-08-17 Thread Perry Dane

Michael Masinter wrote:


Contraceptives prevent pregnancy, and only women get pregnant.
Denying contraceptive coverage to men does not expose men to
pregnancy, but denying coverage to women does expose women to
pregnancy.


Let's tease out the issues here.  It's possible that denying 
coverage for contraceptives violates the PDA because of its 
consequences for the risk of unwanted pregnancy, a risk whose effect 
is uniquely borne by women.  If that's true, though, it shouldn't 
matter who is using the contraceptives, men or women.  Let's call 
this the "PDA argument."


But, as I understand it, the EEOC didn't make the PDA 
argument, at least as such.  Instead, it wrote that "By denying 
prescription contraception drugs, Respondent (the college) is 
discriminating based on gender because only females take oral 
prescription contraceptives"?   Let's call this the "straightforward 
argument."  This was the argument to which I was responding.


The consequences of the two arguments are obviously very 
different.  For example, the straightforward argument would apply, 
but the PDA argument would not, if an employer denied coverage for 
some other type of treatment that was directed only at women, such 
as, say, post-menopausal hormone therapy.  Conversely, the PDA 
argument would apply, but the straightforward argument would not, if 
(counterfactually) there were equally-available prescription 
contraceptive pills for both men and women, and an employer denied 
coverage for both types of contraceptives.


I've already suggested why the straightforward argument 
doesn't impress me -- it penalizes Belmont Abbey for institutional 
decisions made by someone else, and it doesn't give an honest account 
of the best description of what Belmont Abbey is doing.  The PDA 
argument strikes me as stronger in principle, but I'm not sure 
(though this is far from the area of my expertise) that the text or 
policy of the PDA can support the weight of it.


Perry



***
Perry Dane
Professor of Law

Rutgers University
School of Law  -- Camden
217 North Fifth Street
Camden, NJ 08102

d...@crab.rutgers.edu
Bio: www.camlaw.rutgers.edu/bio/925/
SSRN Author page: www.ssrn.com/author=48596
Academia.edu page: http://rutgers.academia.edu/PerryDane

Work:   (856) 225-6004
Fax:   (856) 969-7924
Home:   (610) 896-5702
***


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


Re: EEOC says Catholic College Discriminated by Removing Contraceptive Coverage from Health Insurance

2009-08-17 Thread Perry Dane

Michael Masinter also argues that Belmont Abbey

may have difficulty demonstrating that the resolution of that claim 
in favor of plaintiffs substantially

burdens the free exercise of religion


because an


individual female employee makes the choice to purchase birth
control pills, and whether she does so with the proceeds of her
employer paid salary or her employer paid prescription drug benefits,
she is doing so with funds traceable to her employer, who does not
condition employment on refusing to use birth control or on refusing
to pay for birth control with funds that are proceeds of employment


This is essentially the old argument that "money is 
fungible."  But there are two problems here.  First, law and practice 
are full of instances in which this sort of argument doesn't 
govern.  Cf. much of establishment clause doctrine.  Or consider the 
fact that my school will not reimburse me out of state funds for 
buying alcohol at business meals, but has no problem if I use part of 
my salary to buy alcohol at such meals, and even (I am told) has no 
problem reimbursing me out of gift funds.


More to the point:  Belmont Abbey clearly thinks that there 
is a religiously significant difference between directly and 
indirectly paying for contraception.  And our doctrine of religious 
liberty strongly insists that we not second-guess such judgments, as 
long as they are sincere.   Michael's argument sort of reminds me of 
someone telling an observant Jew that it must be OK to turn on an 
electric light on the Sabbath because, after all, that's not 
"work."  Lots of religious beliefs and doctrines follow forms of 
logic, and make fine distinctions, that don't necessarily convince outsiders.


Perry


***
Perry Dane
Professor of Law

Rutgers University
School of Law  -- Camden
217 North Fifth Street
Camden, NJ 08102

d...@crab.rutgers.edu
Bio: www.camlaw.rutgers.edu/bio/925/
SSRN Author page: www.ssrn.com/author=48596
Academia.edu page: http://rutgers.academia.edu/PerryDane

Work:   (856) 225-6004
Fax:   (856) 969-7924
Home:   (610) 896-5702
*** 


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.