RE: Analogous Secular Interests

2012-04-20 Thread Douglas Laycock
Bob’s point 1 means the issue won’t arise very often. But when a non-theist has 
a deeply held moral commitment that is analogous to similar religious 
commitments, he ought to be protected.

 

On point 2, the lack of a sacred text is just a matter of proof, and not in 
itself so important. The lack of an organized body with systematic teachings is 
the bigger proof obstacle. But as most list members know, nontheistic objection 
to military service was protected as a matter of statutory interpretation in 
the Vietnam-era cases.  I fear it would be a tougher sell to today’s Court, 
although Justice O’Connor endorsed those cases, apparently as a matter of 
constitutional law, in her concurring opinion in Kiryas Joel.

 

On point 3, the parsonage allowance is not a protection for conscience and 
really presents a quite different set of issues. It does not relieve a burden 
on the exercise of religion, and it is not part of a neutral general category; 
it is probably a longstanding Establishment Clause violation. But it is also 
likely that no one has standing to challenge it, especially after Arizona v. 
Winn.

 

It is not available to all employees of the church, but only to ministers. So 
it should not be available to the whole staff of FFRF. But if there are 
employees whose job is to teach a non-theistic belief system to followers, or 
perhaps to proselytize the unconverted, they should be eligible for the 
parsonage allowance. That’s how I would set up the claim if I were representing 
FFRF. 

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of b...@jmcenter.org
Sent: Thursday, April 19, 2012 2:15 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Analogous Secular Interests

 

Marty, 

  

I'm very curious about your reference to analogous secular interests in your 
recent accommodation and pork post. I would appreciate some elaboration. 

  

#1 - This concept occasionally came up at the American Humanist Association 
during the three years that I served as staff attorney. The big impediment is 
that nontheists don't have sincerely held religious beliefs, e.g., with 
respect to foods, clothing, birth control, death penalty. Instead, our 
(atheists, agnostics, freethinkers, secular humanists) notions of these items 
are based on personal preference, personal philosophy or (personal) reason. 
Altho secular humanism was mentioned in a footnote in Torcaso v. Watkins 
(1961) as being a religion, its lack of a sacred text or creed make it very 
difficult -- at law -- to be similarly situated. For example, Jewish men wear 
yarmulke, Muslim women a hijab or Sikh men a turban. But a Humanist? In one 
discussion I had, the question was whether a person (any person) who wanted to 
a baseball style cap at work where persons of religion where allowed to wear 
head coverings as an accommodation of religion. The Humanist hypothetically 
wanted to wear the cap simply because (a) he liked it or (b) he was bald -- 
neither a sincerely held religious belief. If a head covering is a head 
covering is a head covering, is not the Humanist entitled to the same civil 
rights as a Jew, Muslim or Sikh? 

  

#2 - Perhaps a better example would a Humanist who objected to serving in the 
military and killing on humanism grounds. The belief could be sincerely held -- 
but not universally held by Secular Humanists. And again, no sacred text to 
confirm.

  

#3 - An interesting case is currently being litigated in Wisconsin by the 
Freedom From Religion Foundation in which it is arguing that its Atheist 
personnel (whom the FFRF board authorized a housing allowance) are entitled to 
take the Section 107 parsonage housing allowance exemption on their federal 
income tax returns. 

  

Bob Ritter 

Jefferson Madison Center for Religious Liberty 

A Project of the Law Office of Robert V. Ritter 

6809 Kincaid Avenue  

Falls Church, VA 22042  

703-533-0236   

  


On April 12, 2012 at 7:15 PM Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote: 

Just a slight emendation to Doug's post, with which I think he'll agree:  Yes, 
virtually every Justice has concluded that religious accommodations *can be* 
constitutional, at least if they alleviate significant state-imposed burdens on 
religious exercise, as the Ohio prison accommodation would appear to do here.

 

But that doesn't mean all such accommodations *are* constitutional.  In 
particular, serious constitutional questions can be raised where the 
accommodation imposes a significant burden on third parties, and perhaps also 
where analogous secular interests are not treated equally (the latter concern 
being most acute where the accommodation creates a discrepancy in the treatment 
of other first amendment interests, such as speech and assembly). 

 


RE: Statement on Religious Liberty from USCCB

2012-04-20 Thread Finkelman, Paul paul.finkel...@albanylaw.edu
In fairness to the others on the list, I think people who are posting things 
should actually their names and even give an affiliation, if they have one.   I 
have no idea who Bob is.



*
Paul Finkelman, Ph.D.
President William McKinley Distinguished Professor of Law
Albany Law School
80 New Scotland Avenue
Albany, NY 12208

518-445-3386 (p)
518-445-3363 (f)

paul.finkel...@albanylaw.edumailto:paul.finkel...@albanylaw.edu
www.paulfinkelman.comhttp://www.paulfinkelman.com
*


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of b...@jmcenter.org [b...@jmcenter.org]
Sent: Thursday, April 19, 2012 11:13 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Statement on Religious Liberty from USCCB


Catholics have gone from being persecuted in the U.S. (early years of our 
nation) to their hey day in the 1950's when the Knights of Columbus pushed for 
inserting under god * into the Pledge of Allegiance (1954) to being in 
today's melting pot (pluralistic society) -- one of many. The Conference of 
Catholic Bishops is a big bully AND wrong headed. It's excruciatingly difficult 
for them to play by the rules that others, including nontheists, must follow. 
They are fighting a war of survival (due to their religion's irrelevance in the 
modern era), not of religious liberty.



The bishops reference to MLK is an insult. MLK fought for equality, not 
preferential treatment as the bishops are seeking. I doubt that there will be 
significant civil disobedience because Catholics are being asked to act like 
their neighbors, no more, no less.



As extreme as the bishops appear to be, I'm surprised that they haven't turned 
to the Declaration of Independence to justify a call for revolution to 
overthrow our secular form of government established in 1789 and return to 
pre-Enlightenment times.



* It was painful for me yesterday to hear daughter's first grade class recite 
the Pledge with under god. If the bishops are really interested in religious 
liberty, let's strip all the advancements (or establishments) of religion out 
of federal, state and local governments. I've considered challenging the 1954 
Pledge, but the Supreme Court did a job my friend Mike Newdow ( Newdow v. Elk 
Grove (2004)) and the 4th Circuit (where I live) thinks that god is a 
patriot. There will be a Resurrection of that fight sometime between 40 days 
and 40 years.



Bob

On April 13, 2012 at 6:47 AM Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:

The Conference of Catholic Bishops just issued this major Statement on 
Religious Liberty:

http://usccb.org/issues-and-action/religious-liberty/upload/Our_First_Most_Cherished_Liberty.pdf

I'd be curious to hear what others think of it.  Its basic thrust is that 
religious liberty is now acutely under attack in the U.S., in a way it has 
not been in quite a while.  Indeed, what is at stake is no less than  
whether America will continue to have a free, creative, and robust civil 
society—or whether the state alone will determine who gets to contribute to the 
common good,  and how they get to do it.  Do you think they've made the case 
for such an indictment?

Furthermore, it quotes liberally from Dr. King's letter from the Birmingham 
jail, and urges citizens to have the courage not to obey the laws that 
allegedly are presenting this profound threat.  (What are the odds there will 
be much civil disobedience of the laws they have in mind? -- not a rhetorical 
question.)  And it invokes  Lincoln at Gettysburg in asking for a fast for a 
new birth of freedom in our beloved country.

Thoughts?


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Mothers leaving ultra-religious groups, and religious upbringing as a factor in custody disputes

2012-04-20 Thread Richard Foltin
The religious status quo could also be a non-observant or explicitly atheistic 
or agnostic household, which would also have to be respected under the rule 
that Eugene supports. The alternative is for the courts to determine which 
religions are extremist, a questionable role for the judiciary. 

Richard T. Foltin
Director of National and Legislative Affairs 
Office of Government and International Affairs
p: 202-785-5463,  f: 202-659-9896
folt...@ajc.org
  
   
Join us at the AJC Global Forum 2012, May 2-4 in Washington, D.C.
REGISTER NOW
Take Action with AJC by visiting the Action Center 
NOTICE
This email may contain confidential and/or privileged material and is intended 
for the sole use of the intended recipient(s). If you are not the intended 
recipient, please be advised that you have received this email in error and 
that any use, disclosure, copying, distribution or other transmission is 
prohibited, improper and may be unlawful.  If you have received this email in 
error, you must destroy this email and kindly notify the sender by reply 
email.  If this email contains the word CONFIDENTIAL in its Subject line, then 
even a valid recipient must hold it in confidence and not distribute or 
disclose it. In such case ONLY the author of the email has permission to 
forward or otherwise distribute it or disclose its contents to others.


-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
Sent: Friday, April 20, 2012 9:24 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Mothers leaving ultra-religious groups, and religious upbringing 
as a factor in custody disputes

I don't think it is a difficult question but disagree that the rule is sound.   
The standard should be the best interest of the child.  Stability in an 
extremist religion is often not in the child's best interest, especially if the 
child is a girl.   
For example, the FLDS.  The best interest of the child can also trump 
mainstream religions depending on the facts of the case.  The focus must be the 
child.

This sort of assumption that religious status quo is a social good is an 
unconstitutional preference for religion.
This is a good example of when the application of a neutral generally 
applicable principle can serve the greater good more directly than a religious 
preference.

Marci

Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
New York, NY 10003

On Apr 20, 2012, at 9:09 AM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

 There's an interesting op-ed at 
 http://blog.nj.com/njv_guest_blog/2012/04/among_nj_orthodox_jewish_women.html 
 that faults the child custody law preference for stability of religious 
 upbringing:  When women leave arranged marriages in the ultra-Orthodox Jewish 
 community -- and leave ultra-Orthodoxy more general -- they may sometimes 
 lose custody of their children on the grounds that the person who remains 
 within the community is more able to provide stability of religious 
 upbringing.  
 
 I'm inclined to say that this rule (which of course could equally apply to 
 fathers who leave a religious community as well, though I don't know how 
 relatively frequent such departures are) is a sound one, for children who are 
 old enough to have some experience with the religion and thus some stake in 
 stability of religious upbringing.  To be sure, the rule does create some 
 pressure against departing the faith, since often someone who leaves the 
 group can no longer raise the children in the same religious environment even 
 if she's willing to, because the group might no longer accept her; but this 
 seems in this situation to be an acceptable and denominationally neutral rule 
 (especially if it is equally applied to a parent who moves into a 
 ultra-religious community which disrupts the stability of the children's 
 nonreligious, or only mildly religious, upbringing).  But I still thought I'd 
 mention the op-ed, in case people think it's a difficult and interesting 
 question.  
 
 Eugene
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To subscribe, 
 unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To subscribe, unsubscribe, 
change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to 

RE: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment Clause challenge

2012-04-20 Thread West, Ellis
Marty, I recently read a piece by Charles Haynes in the Feb. 2012 issue of 
Report from the Capital (Baptist Joint Committee), in which he pointed out that 
secular, even anti-religious groups, with the help of courts, were using the 
principle of equal treatment as a way of dealing with, if not stopping, 
various kinds of gov't aid to religion, e.g., Gideons' distributing Bibles in 
public schools and Christmas crèches on public property.  In other words, 
according to the principle, if the Gideons can distribute Bibles in the schools 
and crèches can be placed on public property, then pagan literature can also 
be distributed in the schools and messages of atheism displayed in front of 
gov't buildings.  Question: how likely is it that such secular groups and 
others, e.g., vegetarians, will try to use equal treatment and these 
aforementioned precedents to obtain exemptions from valid, secular laws that 
are more or less equal to those that religious person/groups can now obtain 
under RFRA and RLUIPA, and what are their chances of being successful?

Ellis M. West

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Wednesday, April 18, 2012 9:43 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment Clause 
challenge

I think there's rough consensus here:

Decisions such as Amos, Texas Monthly and Cutter establish that an effort to 
alleviate a substantial state-imposed burden on religious exercise -- as RFRA 
and RLUIPA do by terms -- is not the sort of impermissible religious purpose or 
objective that has itself been deemed fatal in other contexts.  Nevertheless, 
such accommodations might still violate the First Amendment, on their face or 
as applied, if they impose undue substantial burdens on third parties, or if 
they give religion a preference in speech or assembly, or (possibly -- this 
suggested in Texas Monthly) if the burden being alleviated is not materially 
different in kind from burdens on analogous secular actors that the state does 
not endeavor to alleviate.

That is to say, the constitutional analysis for such accommodations is best 
considered not in Lemon terms, but with regard to the discrete set of cases 
dealing with such accommodations, such as those listed above, as well as 
Thornton v. Caldor, Welsh/Gillette/Seeger, etc.
On Mon, Apr 16, 2012 at 7:50 PM, Marci Hamilton 
hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
Eugene-- that does not respond to my point.   Cutter is a narrow opinion saying 
RLUIPA does not on its face violate the Establishment Clause.  It does not say 
that every program considered under RLUIPA is safe from Establishment Clause 
attack.

Marci

On Apr 16, 2012, at 5:54 PM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
Well, Ellis was arguing that the issue was whether RFRA and 
RLUIPA ... are secular in purpose and effect.  I read Cutter as concluding 
that they are, though indeed particular accommodations implemented out of a 
desire to avoid RLUIPA litigation might not be.

Eugene

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
Sent: Monday, April 16, 2012 1:33 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment Clause 
challenge

Cutter only addressed the facial Establishment  Clause attack on the prison 
provisions of RLUIPA.  It did not protect any particular program or exemption 
from attack

Marci

On Apr 12, 2012, at 7:19 PM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
Maybe it would and maybe it wouldn't, but I don't think that 
makes the purpose religious, or makes the effect primarily the advancement of 
religion (whatever primary effect might mean); it just suggests that the 
policy might prove counterproductive relative to the secular government purpose.

As to RLUIPA being secular in purpose and effect, the Supreme 
Court unanimously said in Cutter that RLUIPA is constitutional.  Maybe one can 
imagine contrary arguments, but they didn't impress any of the Justices, even 
Stevens.

But even if RLUIPA didn't exist, the no-pork policy would be 
permissible for the reasons Doug mentions.  Likewise, a uniform vegetarian diet 
policy would also be constitutionally permissible.

Eugene

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of West, Ellis
Sent: Thursday, April 12, 2012 2:39 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment Clause 
challenge

I should 

Re: Mothers leaving ultra-religious groups, and religious upbringing as a factor in custody disputes

2012-04-20 Thread hamilton02

The alternative is to focus on what is in the best interests of the child, 
e.g., education, health.  Not being forced to
get married at 13 and have children...   

Marci


The religious status quo could also be a non-observant or explicitly atheistic 
r agnostic household, which would also have to be respected under the rule that 
ugene supports. The alternative is for the courts to determine which religions 
re extremist, a questionable role for the judiciary. 
Richard T. Foltin
irector of National and Legislative Affairs 
ffice of Government and International Affairs
: 202-785-5463,  f: 202-659-9896
olt...@ajc.org




 
Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.com




-Original Message-
From: Richard Foltin folt...@ajc.org
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Fri, Apr 20, 2012 8:32 am
Subject: RE: Mothers leaving ultra-religious groups, and religious upbringing 
as a factor in custody disputes


The religious status quo could also be a non-observant or explicitly atheistic 
r agnostic household, which would also have to be respected under the rule that 
ugene supports. The alternative is for the courts to determine which religions 
re extremist, a questionable role for the judiciary. 
Richard T. Foltin
irector of National and Legislative Affairs 
ffice of Government and International Affairs
: 202-785-5463,  f: 202-659-9896
olt...@ajc.org
 
  
oin us at the AJC Global Forum 2012, May 2-4 in Washington, D.C.
EGISTER NOW
ake Action with AJC by visiting the Action Center 
OTICE
his email may contain confidential and/or privileged material and is intended 
or the sole use of the intended recipient(s). If you are not the intended 
ecipient, please be advised that you have received this email in error and that 
ny use, disclosure, copying, distribution or other transmission is prohibited, 
mproper and may be unlawful.  If you have received this email in error, you 
ust destroy this email and kindly notify the sender by reply email.  If this 
mail contains the word CONFIDENTIAL in its Subject line, then even a valid 
ecipient must hold it in confidence and not distribute or disclose it. In such 
ase ONLY the author of the email has permission to forward or otherwise 
istribute it or disclose its contents to others.

Original Message-
rom: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
n Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
ent: Friday, April 20, 2012 9:24 AM
o: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
c: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
ubject: Re: Mothers leaving ultra-religious groups, and religious upbringing as 
 factor in custody disputes
I don't think it is a difficult question but disagree that the rule is sound.   
he standard should be the best interest of the child.  Stability in an 
xtremist religion is often not in the child's best interest, especially if the 
hild is a girl.   
or example, the FLDS.  The best interest of the child can also trump mainstream 
eligions depending on the facts of the case.  The focus must be the child.
This sort of assumption that religious status quo is a social good is an 
nconstitutional preference for religion.
his is a good example of when the application of a neutral generally applicable 
rinciple can serve the greater good more directly than a religious preference.
Marci
Marci A. Hamilton
aul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
enjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
eshiva University
ew York, NY 10003
On Apr 20, 2012, at 9:09 AM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
 There's an interesting op-ed at 
 http://blog.nj.com/njv_guest_blog/2012/04/among_nj_orthodox_jewish_women.html 
hat faults the child custody law preference for stability of religious 
pbringing:  When women leave arranged marriages in the ultra-Orthodox Jewish 
ommunity -- and leave ultra-Orthodoxy more general -- they may sometimes lose 
ustody of their children on the grounds that the person who remains within the 
ommunity is more able to provide stability of religious upbringing.  
 
 I'm inclined to say that this rule (which of course could equally apply to 
athers who leave a religious community as well, though I don't know how 
elatively frequent such departures are) is a sound one, for children who are 
ld enough to have some experience with the religion and thus some stake in 
tability of religious upbringing.  To be sure, the rule does create some 
ressure against departing the faith, since often someone who leaves the group 
an no longer raise the children in the same religious environment even if she's 
illing to, because the group might no longer accept her; but this seems in this 
ituation to be an acceptable and denominationally neutral rule (especially if 
t is equally applied to a parent who moves into a ultra-religious community 
hich disrupts the stability of the children's 

Re: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment Clause challenge

2012-04-20 Thread Marty Lederman
I think there's rough consensus here:

Decisions such as Amos, Texas Monthly and Cutter establish that an effort
to alleviate a substantial *state-imposed* burden on religious exercise --
as RFRA and RLUIPA do by terms -- is not the sort of impermissible
religious purpose or objective that has itself been deemed fatal in other
contexts.  Nevertheless, such accommodations might still violate the First
Amendment, on their face or as applied, if they impose undue substantial
burdens on third parties, or if they give religion a preference in speech
or assembly, or (possibly -- this suggested in Texas Monthly) if the burden
being alleviated is not materially different in kind from burdens on
analogous secular actors that the state does not endeavor to alleviate.

That is to say, the constitutional analysis for such accommodations is best
considered not in Lemon terms, but with regard to the discrete set of cases
dealing with such accommodations, such as those listed above, as well as
Thornton v. Caldor, Welsh/Gillette/Seeger, etc.

On Mon, Apr 16, 2012 at 7:50 PM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:

 Eugene-- that does not respond to my point.   Cutter is a narrow opinion
 saying RLUIPA does not on its face violate the Establishment Clause.  It
 does not say that every program considered under RLUIPA is safe from
 Establishment Clause attack.

 Marci

 On Apr 16, 2012, at 5:54 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

 Well, Ellis was arguing that “the issue” was whether “RFRA
 and RLUIPA ... are secular in purpose and effect.”  I read *Cutter *as
 concluding that they are, though indeed particular accommodations
 implemented out of a desire to avoid RLUIPA litigation might not be.

 ** **

 Eugene

 ** **

 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Marci Hamilton
 *Sent:* Monday, April 16, 2012 1:33 PM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Cc:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment
 Clause challenge

 ** **

 Cutter only addressed the facial Establishment  Clause attack on the
 prison provisions of RLUIPA.  It did not protect any particular program or
 exemption from attack

 ** **

 Marci

 On Apr 12, 2012, at 7:19 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
 

 Maybe it would and maybe it wouldn’t, but I don’t think
 that makes the purpose religious, or makes the effect primarily the
 advancement of religion (whatever “primary effect” might mean); it just
 suggests that the policy might prove counterproductive relative to the
 secular government purpose.

  

 As to RLUIPA being “secular in purpose and effect,” the
 Supreme Court unanimously said in *Cutter* that RLUIPA is
 constitutional.  Maybe one can imagine contrary arguments, but they didn’t
 impress any of the Justices, even Stevens.

  

 But even if RLUIPA didn’t exist, the no-pork policy would
 be permissible for the reasons Doug mentions.  Likewise, a uniform
 vegetarian diet policy would also be constitutionally permissible.

  

 Eugene

  

 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [
 mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edureligionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 *On Behalf Of *West, Ellis
 *Sent:* Thursday, April 12, 2012 2:39 PM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* RE: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment
 Clause challenge

  

 I should have added to the post below that the policy might create as much
 conflict as it eliminates, just as would a vegetarian diet.

  

 Ellis M. West

 Emeritus Professor of Political Science 

 University of Richmond, VA 23173

 804-289-8536

 ew...@richmond.edu

  

 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [
 mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edureligionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 *On Behalf Of *West, Ellis
 *Sent:* Thursday, April 12, 2012 5:21 PM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* RE: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment
 Clause challenge

  

 Sure avoiding litigation is a secular purpose, but only if one assumes
 that RFRA and RLUIPA, the basis of the litigation, are secular in purpose
 and effect, but that is precisely the issue.  Suppose these two laws did
 not exist.  Then would the prison policy in question be secular in nature?
 The avoidance of conflict might also be a secular purpose, but it would
 justify all kinds of exemptions, not just religion-based exemptions,
 because persons object to all kinds of laws for all kinds of reasons.  For
 example, as Prof Levinson suggested in an earlier post, it would justify a
 uniform vegetarian diet for all prisoners.

  

 Ellis M. West

 Emeritus Professor of Political Science 

 University of