Re: Anti-discrimination, legislative compromise, and strict scrutiny

2015-02-25 Thread Alan E Brownstein
​My question is a bit different than the one Hillel posed. Suppose the 
religious exemption permitting discrimination on the basis of sexual 
orientation in places of public accommodation/employment is broader than 
exemptions provided to religious objectors who believe they are required to 
discriminate on the basis of race, gender, or religion. Does that exemption 
discriminate on the basis of faith or denomination in that it provides greater 
protection to religious objectors whose beliefs prohibit them from serving or 
hiring gays and lesbians than it provides to religious objectors whose beliefs 
prohibit them from serving or hiring women, or African-Americans, or Jews? What 
standard of review should be applied to this challenge?


There are lots of cases in which members of religions that require the use of 
marijuana argued that the government discriminated on the basis of religion 
when it granted an exemption for the ritual use of peyote but refused to grant 
an exemption for the ritual use of marijuana. They almost always lost. The 
courts adjudicating these cases weren't always clear what standard of review 
they were applying or even whether they were applying a standard of review at 
all. But they seemed to think it was necessary to explain why an exemption for 
marijuana use was different and less justified than an exemption for peyote 
use. And these discussions typically involved an argument that an exemption for 
marijuana use was more dangerous and created more problems for law enforcement 
than an exemption for peyote use.


Should a similar analysis apply here? And if so, what arguments should a court 
accept to justify providing greater protection to religious objectors to civil 
rights laws protecting gays and lesbians than are provided to religious 
objectors to civil rights laws protecting women , racial minorities, or 
religious minorities? There is, of course, an argument that civil rights laws 
protecting African-Americans have a unique value and purpose in light of 
American history. But what about laws prohibiting gender and religious 
discrimination?


Alan






From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu  
on behalf of Doug Laycock 
Sent: Wednesday, February 25, 2015 7:01 AM
To: 'Law & Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: RE: Anti-discrimination, legislative compromise, and strict scrutiny

Strict scrutiny would not be triggered under Smith/Lukumi, principally because 
the legislated exemptions are for religious objectors, do not discriminate on 
the basis of faith or denomination, and are a reasonable legislative effort to 
exempt the cases where the claim to religious exemption is strongest. 
Therefore, they do not imply a value judgment that secular reasons for 
exemption are more important than religious reasons for exemption. They imply 
only a judgment that religious reasons for exemption are stronger in very small 
businesses that generally are personally run by the owner than in larger and 
generally more impersonal businesses. Of course that generalization is not 
perfect, and the precise line drawn between large and small is inevitably 
arbitrary. But there is no discrimination between religious and secular.

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Hillel Y. Levin
Sent: Wednesday, February 25, 2015 5:53 AM
To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Anti-discrimination, legislative compromise, and strict scrutiny

Friends:

As you are likely aware, the LDS church recently announced support for 
legislation prohibiting discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation in 
Utah, so long as such legislation included religious accommodations. LDS 
leaders were not explicit about the precise contours of the accommodations they 
seek, but I have the distinct sense that they would insist on broader 
accommodations than have been written into law elsewhere.

Suppose that supporters of anti-discrimination legislation were able to accept 
a compromise with LDS leaders that included accommodations for some for-profit 
service providers/employers/landlords so long as gays and lesbians could find 
alternative providers without much difficulty. (Similar to pharmacist 
conscience clauses with respect to dispensation of contraception in some 
states.) Alternatively, suppose that categorical exceptions were carved out for 
small businesses and small-time landlords. Hypothetically, what if businesses 
with fewer than 20 employees were excluded from coverage, as were landlords 
with fewer than 5 properties.

Now suppose that a religious objector who did not meet the criteria for the 
religious accommodation or categorical exception sued under the FEC. Given the 
exceptions built into the compromise le

Re: Anti-discrimination, legislative compromise, and strict scrutiny

2015-02-25 Thread Hillel Y. Levin
I'm not sure I agree that it is a rule with no exceptions. But let's assume
you are right about that. Let's also assume that a state RFRA, and thus
strict scrutiny, applies. The asserted compelling interest is having a
police force that appears professional and approachable, and does not
appear disheveled, and recognizing that an arbitrary line must be drawn.
How does this fare under strict scrutiny? Could any rule limiting beard
length pass strict scrutiny?

And what about my initial question. Assume there is a RFRA in place in the
state. Can an arbitrary limit on the size of the business comport with
strict scrutiny?

On Wed, Feb 25, 2015 at 10:47 AM, Doug Laycock 
wrote:

> That’s not even a rule with exceptions. As you describe it, it’s a
> generally applicable rule that no beard can be longer than one inch. If
> it’s enforced even handedly against religious and secular beards, i.e.,
> enforced as written, it is insulated from attack under the Free Exercise
> Clause, even if the rule is entirely pointless and unnecessary, or serves
> only the most modest of aesthetic interests. That of course is the problem
> with *Smith*.
>
>
>
> Douglas Laycock
>
> Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
>
> University of Virginia Law School
>
> 580 Massie Road
>
> Charlottesville, VA  22903
>
>  434-243-8546
>
>
>
> *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
> religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Hillel Y. Levin
> *Sent:* Wednesday, February 25, 2015 10:33 AM
> *To:* Law & Religion issues for Law Academics
> *Subject:* Re: Anti-discrimination, legislative compromise, and strict
> scrutiny
>
>
>
> Thanks Doug.
>
>
>
> Would the same logic apply to beard length regulations on city police
> forces? Suppose there was a legislative (or reasoned department) judgment
> that well-kept beards are an acceptable exception to the general "clean
> shaven" policy, and that in order to effectuate that judgment, they provide
> that beards must be no longer than one inch. This will be true for people
> with skin conditions, people with religious reasons for facial hair growth,
> and people who enjoy the warmth or look of the beard. There is thus no
> value judgment whatsoever, and an admittedly arbitrary line is drawn in
> order to prevent members of the force from looking disheveled.
>
>
>
> Along comes a religious objector who claims that his beard must be 1.25
> inches long, or one who claims that his religion prohibits him from ever
> shaving. (Assume sincerity, and indeed, there are such religious practices.)
>
>
>
> Does strict scrutiny apply? Does it pass strict scrutiny?
>
>
>
> On Wed, Feb 25, 2015 at 10:01 AM, Doug Laycock 
> wrote:
>
> Strict scrutiny would not be triggered under *Smith/Lukumi*, principally
> because the legislated exemptions are for religious objectors, do not
> discriminate on the basis of faith or denomination, and are a reasonable
> legislative effort to exempt the cases where the claim to religious
> exemption is strongest. Therefore, they do not imply a value judgment that
> secular reasons for exemption are more important than religious reasons for
> exemption. They imply only a judgment that religious reasons for exemption
> are stronger in very small businesses that generally are personally run by
> the owner than in larger and generally more impersonal businesses. Of
> course that generalization is not perfect, and the precise line drawn
> between large and small is inevitably arbitrary. But there is no
> discrimination between religious and secular.
>
>
>
> Douglas Laycock
>
> Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
>
> University of Virginia Law School
>
> 580 Massie Road
>
> Charlottesville, VA  22903
>
>  434-243-8546
>
>
>
> *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
> religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Hillel Y. Levin
> *Sent:* Wednesday, February 25, 2015 5:53 AM
> *To:* Law & Religion issues for Law Academics
> *Subject:* Anti-discrimination, legislative compromise, and strict
> scrutiny
>
>
>
> Friends:
>
>
>
> As you are likely aware, the LDS church recently announced support for
> legislation prohibiting discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation
> in Utah, so long as such legislation included religious accommodations. LDS
> leaders were not explicit about the precise contours of the accommodations
> they seek, but I have the distinct sense that they would insist on broader
> accommodations than have been written into law elsewhere.
>
>
>
> Suppose that supporters of anti-discrimination legislation were able to
> accept a compromise with

RE: Anti-discrimination, legislative compromise, and strict scrutiny

2015-02-25 Thread Doug Laycock
Every religious exemption will have a boundary. And it will have somebody
just outside that boundary who is not all that much different from the last
person just inside that boundary. The body creating the exemption may try to
draw the boundary narrowly, as in the original HHS proposals about the
contraception mandate, exempting pretty much only the church itself. Or they
may try to draw it broadly and inclusively, as in the Title VII exemption
for any religious organization. It's a boundary either way, and with the
Title VII boundary, we get cases like the King Kamehameha schools, which
hired only Protestant teachers under the terms of its endowment, but which
the Ninth Circuit said wasn't really religious enough to qualify any more. 

 

So judgments about the importance of religious practices are inevitable,
however much the Court would like to avoid them. The Court is certainly
right that judges should not make threshold judgments about centrality,
defining some folks as exempt and others as having no claim because of a
yes-no judgment about centrality. Centrality is a continuum, not a
dichotomous variable. Specific legislative exemptions are stuck drawing
yes-no lines for lack of any good alternative.  And if it's line reasonably
distinguishes more and less intensely religious contexts, without
discriminating between faiths, it does not imply a value judgment about
religion and should not trigger strict scrutiny.

 

In applying the compelling interest test in any sensible fashion, the courts
inevitably balance the government interest against the religious interest,
and the importance of the religious practice inevitably matters. To borrow
and reverse Scalia's example in Smith, courts would not protect the practice
of throwing rice at weddings to the same extent that they would protect the
practice of getting married in church. Sometimes the Court describes the
compelling interest test in terms of balancing, and Congress described it
that way in the debates on RFRA. The comments about not judging centrality
should not be read to negate all this. And if they are so read, they are
simply mistaken. 

 

Signing off for a big block of teaching.

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of David Cruz
Sent: Wednesday, February 25, 2015 10:51 AM
To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Anti-discrimination, legislative compromise, and strict
scrutiny

 

Is it permissible under current law for government actors to assess whether
"religious reasons for exemption are stronger in very small businesses that
generally are personally run by the owner than in larger and generally more
impersonal businesses" (emphases added)?  I thought plenty of cases
including Thomas forbid government to judge the "importance" or "centrality"
sincere religious claims.  Doug, are you talking about some notion of
secular "strength" of religious reasons?

 

David B. Cruz

Professor of Law

University of Southern California Gould School of Law

Los Angeles, CA 90089-0071

U.S.A.

 

 

From: Doug Laycock mailto:dlayc...@virginia.edu> >
Reply-To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics
mailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu> >
Date: Wednesday, February 25, 2015 at 7:01 AM
To: 'Law & Religion issues for Law Academics' mailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu> >
Subject: RE: Anti-discrimination, legislative compromise, and strict
scrutiny

 

Strict scrutiny would not be triggered under Smith/Lukumi, principally
because the legislated exemptions are for religious objectors, do not
discriminate on the basis of faith or denomination, and are a reasonable
legislative effort to exempt the cases where the claim to religious
exemption is strongest. Therefore, they do not imply a value judgment that
secular reasons for exemption are more important than religious reasons for
exemption. They imply only a judgment that religious reasons for exemption
are stronger in very small businesses that generally are personally run by
the owner than in larger and generally more impersonal businesses. Of course
that generalization is not perfect, and the precise line drawn between large
and small is inevitably arbitrary. But there is no discrimination between
religious and secular. 

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as

Re: Anti-discrimination, legislative compromise, and strict scrutiny

2015-02-25 Thread David Cruz
Is it permissible under current law for government actors to assess whether 
“religious reasons for exemption are stronger in very small businesses that 
generally are personally run by the owner than in larger and generally more 
impersonal businesses” (emphases added)?  I thought plenty of cases including 
Thomas forbid government to judge the "importance" or "centrality" sincere 
religious claims.  Doug, are you talking about some notion of secular 
“strength” of religious reasons?

David B. Cruz
Professor of Law
University of Southern California Gould School of Law
Los Angeles, CA 90089-0071
U.S.A.


From: Doug Laycock mailto:dlayc...@virginia.edu>>
Reply-To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics 
mailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu>>
Date: Wednesday, February 25, 2015 at 7:01 AM
To: 'Law & Religion issues for Law Academics' 
mailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu>>
Subject: RE: Anti-discrimination, legislative compromise, and strict scrutiny

Strict scrutiny would not be triggered under Smith/Lukumi, principally because 
the legislated exemptions are for religious objectors, do not discriminate on 
the basis of faith or denomination, and are a reasonable legislative effort to 
exempt the cases where the claim to religious exemption is strongest. 
Therefore, they do not imply a value judgment that secular reasons for 
exemption are more important than religious reasons for exemption. They imply 
only a judgment that religious reasons for exemption are stronger in very small 
businesses that generally are personally run by the owner than in larger and 
generally more impersonal businesses. Of course that generalization is not 
perfect, and the precise line drawn between large and small is inevitably 
arbitrary. But there is no discrimination between religious and secular.

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Anti-discrimination, legislative compromise, and strict scrutiny

2015-02-25 Thread Doug Laycock
That’s not even a rule with exceptions. As you describe it, it’s a generally 
applicable rule that no beard can be longer than one inch. If it’s enforced 
even handedly against religious and secular beards, i.e., enforced as written, 
it is insulated from attack under the Free Exercise Clause, even if the rule is 
entirely pointless and unnecessary, or serves only the most modest of aesthetic 
interests. That of course is the problem with Smith.

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Hillel Y. Levin
Sent: Wednesday, February 25, 2015 10:33 AM
To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Anti-discrimination, legislative compromise, and strict scrutiny

 

Thanks Doug. 

 

Would the same logic apply to beard length regulations on city police forces? 
Suppose there was a legislative (or reasoned department) judgment that 
well-kept beards are an acceptable exception to the general "clean shaven" 
policy, and that in order to effectuate that judgment, they provide that beards 
must be no longer than one inch. This will be true for people with skin 
conditions, people with religious reasons for facial hair growth, and people 
who enjoy the warmth or look of the beard. There is thus no value judgment 
whatsoever, and an admittedly arbitrary line is drawn in order to prevent 
members of the force from looking disheveled. 

 

Along comes a religious objector who claims that his beard must be 1.25 inches 
long, or one who claims that his religion prohibits him from ever shaving. 
(Assume sincerity, and indeed, there are such religious practices.)

 

Does strict scrutiny apply? Does it pass strict scrutiny?

 

On Wed, Feb 25, 2015 at 10:01 AM, Doug Laycock mailto:dlayc...@virginia.edu> > wrote:

Strict scrutiny would not be triggered under Smith/Lukumi, principally because 
the legislated exemptions are for religious objectors, do not discriminate on 
the basis of faith or denomination, and are a reasonable legislative effort to 
exempt the cases where the claim to religious exemption is strongest. 
Therefore, they do not imply a value judgment that secular reasons for 
exemption are more important than religious reasons for exemption. They imply 
only a judgment that religious reasons for exemption are stronger in very small 
businesses that generally are personally run by the owner than in larger and 
generally more impersonal businesses. Of course that generalization is not 
perfect, and the precise line drawn between large and small is inevitably 
arbitrary. But there is no discrimination between religious and secular. 

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546  

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
<mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu>  
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
<mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu> ] On Behalf Of Hillel Y. Levin
Sent: Wednesday, February 25, 2015 5:53 AM
To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Anti-discrimination, legislative compromise, and strict scrutiny

 

Friends:

 

As you are likely aware, the LDS church recently announced support for 
legislation prohibiting discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation in 
Utah, so long as such legislation included religious accommodations. LDS 
leaders were not explicit about the precise contours of the accommodations they 
seek, but I have the distinct sense that they would insist on broader 
accommodations than have been written into law elsewhere. 

 

Suppose that supporters of anti-discrimination legislation were able to accept 
a compromise with LDS leaders that included accommodations for some for-profit 
service providers/employers/landlords so long as gays and lesbians could find 
alternative providers without much difficulty. (Similar to pharmacist 
conscience clauses with respect to dispensation of contraception in some 
states.) Alternatively, suppose that categorical exceptions were carved out for 
small businesses and small-time landlords. Hypothetically, what if businesses 
with fewer than 20 employees were excluded from coverage, as were landlords 
with fewer than 5 properties. 

 

Now suppose that a religious objector who did not meet the criteria for the 
religious accommodation or categorical exception sued under the FEC. Given the 
exceptions built into the compromise legislation, would strict scrutiny 
automatically apply, under the theory that with the compromise legislation, the 
law is not generally applicable? And if so, how would the case come out, given 
that the compromise legislation necessarily drew somewhat arbitrary lines?

 

I am aware that the question

Re: Anti-discrimination, legislative compromise, and strict scrutiny

2015-02-25 Thread Hillel Y. Levin
Thanks Doug.

Would the same logic apply to beard length regulations on city police
forces? Suppose there was a legislative (or reasoned department) judgment
that well-kept beards are an acceptable exception to the general "clean
shaven" policy, and that in order to effectuate that judgment, they provide
that beards must be no longer than one inch. This will be true for people
with skin conditions, people with religious reasons for facial hair growth,
and people who enjoy the warmth or look of the beard. There is thus no
value judgment whatsoever, and an admittedly arbitrary line is drawn in
order to prevent members of the force from looking disheveled.

Along comes a religious objector who claims that his beard must be 1.25
inches long, or one who claims that his religion prohibits him from ever
shaving. (Assume sincerity, and indeed, there are such religious practices.)

Does strict scrutiny apply? Does it pass strict scrutiny?

On Wed, Feb 25, 2015 at 10:01 AM, Doug Laycock 
wrote:

> Strict scrutiny would not be triggered under *Smith/Lukumi*, principally
> because the legislated exemptions are for religious objectors, do not
> discriminate on the basis of faith or denomination, and are a reasonable
> legislative effort to exempt the cases where the claim to religious
> exemption is strongest. Therefore, they do not imply a value judgment that
> secular reasons for exemption are more important than religious reasons for
> exemption. They imply only a judgment that religious reasons for exemption
> are stronger in very small businesses that generally are personally run by
> the owner than in larger and generally more impersonal businesses. Of
> course that generalization is not perfect, and the precise line drawn
> between large and small is inevitably arbitrary. But there is no
> discrimination between religious and secular.
>
>
>
> Douglas Laycock
>
> Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
>
> University of Virginia Law School
>
> 580 Massie Road
>
> Charlottesville, VA  22903
>
>  434-243-8546
>
>
>
> *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
> religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Hillel Y. Levin
> *Sent:* Wednesday, February 25, 2015 5:53 AM
> *To:* Law & Religion issues for Law Academics
> *Subject:* Anti-discrimination, legislative compromise, and strict
> scrutiny
>
>
>
> Friends:
>
>
>
> As you are likely aware, the LDS church recently announced support for
> legislation prohibiting discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation
> in Utah, so long as such legislation included religious accommodations. LDS
> leaders were not explicit about the precise contours of the accommodations
> they seek, but I have the distinct sense that they would insist on broader
> accommodations than have been written into law elsewhere.
>
>
>
> Suppose that supporters of anti-discrimination legislation were able to
> accept a compromise with LDS leaders that included accommodations for some
> for-profit service providers/employers/landlords so long as gays and
> lesbians could find alternative providers without much difficulty. (Similar
> to pharmacist conscience clauses with respect to dispensation of
> contraception in some states.) Alternatively, suppose that categorical
> exceptions were carved out for small businesses and small-time landlords.
> Hypothetically, what if businesses with fewer than 20 employees were
> excluded from coverage, as were landlords with fewer than 5 properties.
>
>
>
> Now suppose that a religious objector who did not meet the criteria for
> the religious accommodation or categorical exception sued under the FEC.
> Given the exceptions built into the compromise legislation, would strict
> scrutiny automatically apply, under the theory that with the compromise
> legislation, the law is not generally applicable? And if so, how would the
> case come out, given that the compromise legislation necessarily drew
> somewhat arbitrary lines?
>
>
>
> I am aware that the question of what triggers strict scrutiny is subject
> to considerable debate in the literature, and that those who require a
> showing of animus to trigger Lukumi's strict scrutiny would not find any
> here. But for those who do not believe that animus is required, how would
> this come out?
>
>
>
> My sense is that this difficulty might stand in the way of any legislative
> compromise.
>
>
>
> --
> Hillel Y. Levin
> Associate Professor
>
> University of Georgia
> School of Law
> 120 Herty Dr.
> Athens, GA 30602
> (678) 641-7452
> hle...@uga.edu
> hillelle...@gmail.com
> SSRN Author Page:
> http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=466645
>
>
>
> ___

RE: Anti-discrimination, legislative compromise, and strict scrutiny

2015-02-25 Thread Doug Laycock
Strict scrutiny would not be triggered under Smith/Lukumi, principally because 
the legislated exemptions are for religious objectors, do not discriminate on 
the basis of faith or denomination, and are a reasonable legislative effort to 
exempt the cases where the claim to religious exemption is strongest. 
Therefore, they do not imply a value judgment that secular reasons for 
exemption are more important than religious reasons for exemption. They imply 
only a judgment that religious reasons for exemption are stronger in very small 
businesses that generally are personally run by the owner than in larger and 
generally more impersonal businesses. Of course that generalization is not 
perfect, and the precise line drawn between large and small is inevitably 
arbitrary. But there is no discrimination between religious and secular. 

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Hillel Y. Levin
Sent: Wednesday, February 25, 2015 5:53 AM
To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Anti-discrimination, legislative compromise, and strict scrutiny

 

Friends:

 

As you are likely aware, the LDS church recently announced support for 
legislation prohibiting discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation in 
Utah, so long as such legislation included religious accommodations. LDS 
leaders were not explicit about the precise contours of the accommodations they 
seek, but I have the distinct sense that they would insist on broader 
accommodations than have been written into law elsewhere. 

 

Suppose that supporters of anti-discrimination legislation were able to accept 
a compromise with LDS leaders that included accommodations for some for-profit 
service providers/employers/landlords so long as gays and lesbians could find 
alternative providers without much difficulty. (Similar to pharmacist 
conscience clauses with respect to dispensation of contraception in some 
states.) Alternatively, suppose that categorical exceptions were carved out for 
small businesses and small-time landlords. Hypothetically, what if businesses 
with fewer than 20 employees were excluded from coverage, as were landlords 
with fewer than 5 properties. 

 

Now suppose that a religious objector who did not meet the criteria for the 
religious accommodation or categorical exception sued under the FEC. Given the 
exceptions built into the compromise legislation, would strict scrutiny 
automatically apply, under the theory that with the compromise legislation, the 
law is not generally applicable? And if so, how would the case come out, given 
that the compromise legislation necessarily drew somewhat arbitrary lines?

 

I am aware that the question of what triggers strict scrutiny is subject to 
considerable debate in the literature, and that those who require a showing of 
animus to trigger Lukumi's strict scrutiny would not find any here. But for 
those who do not believe that animus is required, how would this come out?

 

My sense is that this difficulty might stand in the way of any legislative 
compromise. 



-- 
Hillel Y. Levin
Associate Professor

University of Georgia
School of Law
120 Herty Dr.
Athens, GA 30602
(678) 641-7452
hle...@uga.edu <mailto:hle...@uga.edu> 
hillelle...@gmail.com <mailto:hillelle...@gmail.com> 
SSRN Author Page: http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=466645

 

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Anti-discrimination, legislative compromise, and strict scrutiny

2015-02-25 Thread Hillel Y. Levin
Friends:

As you are likely aware, the LDS church recently announced support for
legislation prohibiting discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation
in Utah, so long as such legislation included religious accommodations. LDS
leaders were not explicit about the precise contours of the accommodations
they seek, but I have the distinct sense that they would insist on broader
accommodations than have been written into law elsewhere.

Suppose that supporters of anti-discrimination legislation were able to
accept a compromise with LDS leaders that included accommodations for some
for-profit service providers/employers/landlords so long as gays and
lesbians could find alternative providers without much difficulty. (Similar
to pharmacist conscience clauses with respect to dispensation of
contraception in some states.) Alternatively, suppose that categorical
exceptions were carved out for small businesses and small-time landlords.
Hypothetically, what if businesses with fewer than 20 employees were
excluded from coverage, as were landlords with fewer than 5 properties.

Now suppose that a religious objector who did not meet the criteria for the
religious accommodation or categorical exception sued under the FEC. Given
the exceptions built into the compromise legislation, would strict scrutiny
automatically apply, under the theory that with the compromise legislation,
the law is not generally applicable? And if so, how would the case come
out, given that the compromise legislation necessarily drew
somewhat arbitrary lines?

I am aware that the question of what triggers strict scrutiny is subject to
considerable debate in the literature, and that those who require a showing
of animus to trigger Lukumi's strict scrutiny would not find any here. But
for those who do not believe that animus is required, how would this come
out?

My sense is that this difficulty might stand in the way of any legislative
compromise.


-- 
Hillel Y. Levin
Associate Professor
University of Georgia
School of Law
120 Herty Dr.
Athens, GA 30602
(678) 641-7452
hle...@uga.edu
hillelle...@gmail.com
SSRN Author Page:
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=466645
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.