On 3/7/07, Mitchell Porter <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> wrote:

From: "Stathis Papaioannou" <[EMAIL PROTECTED]>

>But the problem with ontological type arguments is that they allow you to
>conjure up anything you like by simply defining it as existing. If there
is
>a physical reality, things don't work like that. Statements of
mathematics
>and logic, however, are necessarily true (or false). This is what I meant
>by
>saying that mathematical structures exist necessarily: not that "17 is
>prime" means you may meet a prime-looking number 17 walking down the
>street,
>but that 17 is necessarily prime, and not even God can change that. So
*if*
>there is no separate physical reality, and what we always thought of as
>physical reality is just mathematical reality, it would solve the problem
>of
>why something rather than nothing exists, or why God exists, or why God
>made
>the world.

I haven't seen this line of argument before. But you could equally say
"A bachelor is necessarily unmarried", and thereby "deduce" that the
existence of bachelors is apriori necessary. And you can get away from
the apparent ontological commitment of saying "17 is prime" by playing
Russell's game of rearranging the natural-language statement of a
proposition
in order to reveal its true logical form, and announcing that what's
*really*
being said is "*If* 17 existed, *then* it would necessarily be prime". You
don't
get the existence of anything for free, that way.


This is so if there is a real physical world as distinct from the
mathematical plenitude. If there is no such separate physical world, then it
isn't possible for something to be blessed with this quality of existence,
because everything that is logically consistent exists. Of course, then you
have to explain why we find ourselves in a corner of the Plenitude where the
familiar laws of physics apply, rather than my keyboard suddenly turning
into a fire breathing dragon (the failure of induction). The easy answer is
to invoke the anthropic principle: we observe only those universes which
give rise to observers like us. The difficult answer is to try to define
some measure on the mathematical structures in the Plenitude and show that
orderly universes like ours thereby emerge. See this paper for an example of
this sort of reasoning:

http://parallel.hpc.unsw.edu.au/rks/docs/occam/

Then there is the question of what it means to implement a computation. If
>you look at it the right way, anything could be a computation. This has
>been
>given by John Searle as a reductio ad absurdum against computationalism,
>and
>explored by several other authors (eg. Hilary Putnam, David Chalmers,
Greg
>Egan). The usual counterargument is that in order to map a computation
onto
>an arbitrary physical process, the mapping function must contain the
>computation already, but this is only significant for an external
observer.
>The inhabitants of a virtual environment will not suddenly cease being
>conscious if all the manuals showing how an external observer might
>interpret what is going on in the computation are lost; it matters only
>that
>there is some such possible interpretation. Moreover, it is possible to
map
>many computations to the one physical process. In the limiting case, a
>single state, perhaps the null state, can be mapped onto all
computations.

It's an odd sort of mapping! Look at it from the other direction. Suppose
that in reality, we have an object sitting there, doing nothing - in the
'null state'. You say that all possible computations are being implemented
there. What are you doing, reinterpreting the null state from moment to
moment so as to make it 'mean' whatever you want it to mean? This is
angels-dancing-on-a-pin stuff. At least functionalists insist that there's
structure on *both* ends of the mapping.


You could put a constraint on what counts as an implementation of a
computational or mental state if you insist on interaction with an
environment. A coal-digging robot has the coal-digging experience when it is
actually digging for coal, and as per functionalism it would have the same
experience if its program were run on different hardware with the same
result. You could find such a robot left behind by an alien civilization and
through trial and error work out what it's supposed to do. However, what if
you put the environment inside the computer, with no inputs? If you found
such an alien computer, it would be impossible to determine what it was
thinking about without extra information, like trying to determine what an
alien string of symbols means. There is, of course, the originally intended
meaning, but once we remove the constraint of environmental interaction,
what is there left for the computer itself, or for an external observer, to
distinguish between the original meaning and every other possible meaning it
may have had?

The problem is with the physical supervenience thesis that usually goes
together with computationalism. If we consider that mind is generated by
computation on an abstract machine, we can keep computationalism and drop
physical supervenience. This would also answer Tim Maudlin's objection to
the supervenience thesis in his 1989 paper "Computation and Consciousness".

Stathis Papaioannou

-----
This list is sponsored by AGIRI: http://www.agiri.org/email
To unsubscribe or change your options, please go to:
http://v2.listbox.com/member/?list_id=11983

Reply via email to