Frederik, Howard, lists,

I've gone back and read Howard's post *"*RE: [biosemiotics:6635] Re: [PEIRCE-L] Natural Propositions" Sat, 06 Sep 2014 20:59:06 -0400 https://list.iupui.edu/sympa/arc/peirce-l/2014-09/msg00124.html .

I just don't see much psychologism in Howard's views, even though he claims that psychologism has its place and seems to regard himself as at least partly psychologistic. He doesn't claim that psychology establishes the validity of a deductive inference or the ampliative character of a non-deductive inference (its conclusion's claiming something that its premisses do not claim). That would be psychologism.

Instead mostly Howard focuses on heuristics, creativity in inference, etc., as the place for psychological understanding of inference. I just wouldn't call that psychologism. It's not the traditional meaning of the word 'psychologism.'

Inferential statistics is a field that focuses on induction. I don't think that there will be such a field focusing on abductive inference except for the special sciences themselves; they are where abductive hypothetical explanations are explicitly formalized (key heuristical guesses in the processes of more general classes of research are often not made explicit at all). So, for example, chemistry is the place to learn the particulars of plausible chemical hypothesis generation. Deductions _/from/_ hypotheses - those are mathematical. The methodeutical level, the selection and strategizing of hypotheses for testability and actual testing, is complex and not strictly abductive. The special science concerned with mind or intelligent behavior is psychology, and it does seem to be the most general place for the riddles of _/how/_ one generates cogent guesses, plausible hypotheses, etc., which generation is heavily context-dependent, belief-laden, etc., thus lending itself more to idioscopic study than to cenoscopic or mathematical study.

In "Logical Machines" Peirce wrote: "Every reasoning machine, that is to say, every machine, has two inherent impotencies. In the first place, it is destitute of all originality, of all initiative. It cannot find its own problems; it cannot feed itself. It cannot direct itself between different possible procedures." (I should note that Peirce here does not use the word "reasoning" in the sense that he gives it elsewhere, that of conscious deliberate inference.) Of course now there are computer programs that learn. These of course are not mere implementations of propositional logic. So far I've hard of no computer programs that do creative mathematics. What general way would there be for a computer program to recognize that a deductive result is surprising or nontivial? There could be specific algorithms of course, that would work up to a point. The traditional categorical syllogisms are ways to ensure a modicum of seeming novelty in a valid deduction.

I'm not aware of any general useful mathematization of the new aspect or the nontrivial aspect which a worthwhile deduction's conclusion brings to its premisses, aspects in whose universal absence no mind would bother with deduction. The 'novel' aspect has sometimes been called psychological. Peirce expected there to be no way to quantify verisimilitude in the sense of the likeness of the inductive conclusion to the sample data, the sense in which the conclusion seems a more veteran version of the sample, the opposite of seeming novel. Now, I'm not saying that nontriviality, novelty, and verisimilitude are, like Peirce's version of natural simplicity, forms of appeal to inborn instinct. They seem forms of appeal to something that has come to be called 'intuition' - not in Peirce's sense of 'intuition', but rather in a loosened sense of 'instinct' - developable but not necessarily inborn in a particular form attuned to idiosocopic nature. I don't know what Peirce would have thought of this, but I would not rule out that psychology in Peirce's broad sense, also called by him psychognosy, may have something essential to contribute to the understanding, for example, of the "aspectual" or perspectival nontriviality or 'depth' (in the sense of the diametrical opposite of triviality) that guides pure mathematical research. One might further note that each of these seemingly psychological aspects seems to _/compensate/_ for the formal character of its respective mode of inference. I don't think there's any psychologism in my views. In other words, I'm granting as much of Howard's claims as I can understand of them (he obviously knows a great deal more about things like AI than I do), and arguing that they're not psychologistic, and that Howard may be mistaken in regarding himself as having tendency properly called 'psychologistic'. We may be arguing over words, as Jon Awbrey worries.

In his above-cited post, Howard says, "The evidence so far leads me to think embodied cognition is most important." I'd say, important for what? There are different objectives of research, different guiding research interests, especially across classes of research that differ vastly in scope, and various people value objectives variously.

Frederik is pursuing the very idea of application of cenoscopic semiotics to biology. This requires him to discuss semiotics at a very cenoscopic level, more general in scope than reflects the usual interests of biologists. The development and application of some of mathematical analysis to physics requires some pure-mathematical work and understanding of mathematical analysis more general in scope than reflects the usual interests of physicists. A better example might be work in theoretical statistics for the purpose of application in special sciences. Where these examples that I've offered seem to fall shortest is that they don't reflect complications arising from the reflexivity involved in philosophy and psychology, complications that vaguely seem to me to be playing a role in the present discussion.

Best, Ben

On 9/10/2014 6:40 AM, Frederik Stjernfelt wrote:

Dear Howard, lists -


Reality certainly is too complex for any one model. That is one of the reasons we have disciplines.

I have never said anything against the discipline of psychology which has many merits and many important tasks. My claim is just that logic and psychology have different objects and different tasks. So I remain as anti-psychologistic as ever. For anti-psychologism is not at all against psychological research - it is against the erroneous belief that issues of truth, reasoning and validity of thought should be reducible to psychology (Peirce, of course, was also interested in psychology and even counts as an early pioneer in experimental psychology for his and Jastrow's investigation of subliminal perception).

A reason why I think it is important now again, after 100 years, to address the issue of anti-psychologism is discussed in the conclusion of ch. 2 of NP - namely the fact that neuropsychological research in many cases proves to reintroduce psychologism via the back door. To preempt misconceived counterarguments - this does not imply any scepticism on my part vis-a-vis the neurosciences as such. Quite on the contrary, I follow recent neuroscience with interest, even enthusiasm. But scientific progress sometimes blind researchers to believe that their claims have vaster applicability than warranted by data. For instance, when we hear investigators of the reward system of the brain claim to be able to explain economics from such study, or when investigators of Broca's and Wernicke's areas claim that language as such can be explained from the functions of those brain structures, or when scholars of neuroaesthetics may claim that beauty and art are explainable from brain findings, I think elementary ontological misconceptions are involved - and that the error, again, lies in psychologism in a new garb.

The progresses of neuroscience made possible by the development of brain imaging techniques during recent decades - PET, fMRI, MEG etc. - are important, among other things, for their charting of how the human brain processes economics, language, art etc. But that is not at all the same as claiming that these phenomena unilaterally depend on particularities of the human brain.

For my own part, I am currently involved in a project experimentally investigating joint diagrammatical reasoning - how people collectively solve diagrammatical tasks by communicating (http://jointdiagrams.org). This gives many interesting findings, but I do not think those findings should be interpreted as reducing diagrams to psychological processes.

Best
F


Den 10/09/2014 kl. 03.37 skrev Howard Pattee <hpat...@roadrunner.com <mailto:hpat...@roadrunner.com>>
:

At 04:20 PM 9/9/2014, Frederik  wrote:
Dear Howard, list
This [complementarity of models] is an important issue. I do not think it is a choice between a psychological and a non-psychological model which must compete. It is a distinction between two levels of description . . .

HP: That helps. As you all know, Stan and I believe that reality is too complex for one model. Adequate models of reality require complementary hierarchical levels. So I infer that you can also accept psychological models and are not as anti-psychologistic as you sound in/NP/or as Peirce obviously was/./

Enough of that, Onward to Dicisigns.

Howard


-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .




Reply via email to