This is a beautiful post, Ben! You expose so clearly the pragmatic heft of
Peirce’s concept of truth.

Such considerations cry out to be presented to first-year philosophy
students, most of whom come in thinking that some kind of social
constructivism is the only educated or open-minded or ‘culturally
sensitive’ view of the world – I am currently being reminded.



Frederik I have really appreciated your naming of ‘culturalism’ and
empirical critique of its effect on scientific research also.



Cheers, Cathy



*From:* Benjamin Udell [mailto:bud...@nyc.rr.com]
*Sent:* Monday, 22 September 2014 4:28 a.m.
*To:* biosemiot...@lists.ut.ee; peirce-l@list.iupui.edu
*Subject:* [PEIRCE-L] Re: [biosemiotics:6908] Re: Natural Propositions,



Stan,

If you think that five minutes' investigation would likely at best reach a
trivial truth about a kind of phenomenon, then substitute 'five days' or
'five months' or 'five decades', etc. The point is the sooner or later, not
an incompletable long run.

You're simply not distinguishing between truth and opinion.  If two
traditions arrive at contrary conclusions about the same kind of
phenomenon, the normal logical conclusion about the contrarity is that at
most one of the conclusions is true and true for sound reasons, at most one
is the result of sufficient investigation even though both traditions claim
sufficiency. Peirce's semiotics is logic studied in terms of signs. You
don't distinguish between sufficiency and claims of sufficiency, truth and
claims of truth, and reality and claims of reality. Both traditions'
conclusions might be false, results of insufficient investigation. They
might both be mixes of truth and falsehood, various inaccuracies, and so
on.

Simply accepting contrary conclusions as reflecting two "realities" because
two traditions arrived at them is a defeatist method of inquiry, a form of
'insuccessibilism'. Imagine the swelling mischief if courts treated widely
discrepant testimony from various witnesses as reflecting different
"realities" rather than different perspectives or mistaken or differently
limited observations or memories, or lack of honesty or candor, and so on.
Imagine being an accused defendant in such a court, with one's money,
career, freedom, life, hanging in the balance.

Waiting for the conflicting traditions to resolve their conflicts and
hoping that their resultant conclusion will be the truth, is a method of
inquiry of last resort, that to which a pure spectator is confined. To go
further and _*define*_ truth as the conclusion of any actual tradition or
actual dialogue among actual traditions, underlies the method of authority,
a form of infallibilism. If two traditions don't resolve their argument and
if you for your part have no way to investigate the question itself and
arrive at a conclusion about the subject of their argument, then your
normal logical conclusion would be that you won't know the answer to the
question, not that there are conflicting true answers to the question.

I disbelieve that you ever did physics in either way. I don't see why you'd
want to impose such weak methods on philosophy, or have a semiotics in
which contrary signs about the same object merely reflect different
"realities"; such would turn logic and semiotics into mush. Peirce's theory
of inquiry, which seems to reflect the attitude of scientific research,
does not boil down to 'poll the experts' or 'poll the traditions', instead
it boils down to 'do the science,' by a method actively motivated and
shaped by the idea of putting into practice the fallibilist recognition
that inquiry can go wrong (because the real is independent of actual
opinion) and the 'successibilist' recognition that inquiry can go right
(because the real is the cognizable). To argue about this, as you do, is to
presuppose that there is a truth about this very matter under discussion, a
truth that can be found and can be missed.

Best, Ben

On 9/20/2014 3:46 PM, Stanley N Salthe wrote:

Ben -- Replying to:



The main idea is not that of a long run.  Instead the idea is that of
sufficient investigation. Call it 'sufficiently long' or 'sufficiently
far-reaching' or 'sufficiently deep' or 'sufficiently good' or
'sufficiently good for long enough', or the like, it's stlll the same basic
idea.

S: Then two different traditions might come up with differently sufficient
understandings about one object.  I accept that, and it implies
nominalism.  Sufficiency might be quite different for different traditions.

If in a given case you believe that you've reached the truth about a given
kind of phenomenon after five minutes of investigation, then you believe
that you have reached, after five minutes, the opinion that anybody
sufficiently investigating, over whatever length of time, would reach about
that kind of phenomenon. It's far from automatically preposterous to
believe that.

S: But, I think, pretty 'shallow' and unsophisticated.

There is no absolute assurance that actual inquiry on a given question will
not go wrong for millions of years, remaining insufficient for millions of
years and leaving the actual inquirers not only ignorant but also erroneous
all along the way.

S: OK if the knowledge in question is not important to survival!

 But fallibilism implies not that the objects or findings of inquiry are
unreal and mere figments, but only that they may be unreal and figments,
insofar as the real does not depend on what any actual inquirers think of
it.

S: My position is that 'the real' either is not one thing, or that there
might be several different traditions about it based on different
approaches and knowledges.

 On the other hand, do you really believe that there are no cases where
we've reached truths about general characters of things, done good
statistical studies on the distributions of such characters, and so on?

S: I would not think NO cases, but, given different language traditions
surviving simultaneously, the world will be constructed by each via
different models.  So, given the learned fact one one must not tease
certain snakes, different traditions will construct different mythologies
about this.  Our own tradition, involving concepts of evolution and
chemistry is particularly elaborate, requiring a highly educated priesthood
to come up with an -- or even more than one -- understanding.



STAN





On Sat, Sep 20, 2014 at 2:31 PM, Benjamin Udell <bud...@nyc.rr.com> wrote:

Stan, list,

The main idea is not that of a long run.  Instead the idea is that of
sufficient investigation. Call it 'sufficiently long' or 'sufficiently
far-reaching' or 'sufficiently deep' or 'sufficiently good' or
'sufficiently good for long enough', or the like, it's stlll the same basic
idea.

If in a given case you believe that you've reached the truth about a given
kind of phenomenon after five minutes of investigation, then you believe
that you have reached, after five minutes, the opinion that anybody
sufficiently investigating, over whatever length of time, would reach about
that kind of phenomenon. It's far from automatically preposterous to
believe that.

There is no absolute assurance that actual inquiry on a given question will
not go wrong for millions of years, remaining insufficient for millions of
years and leaving the actual inquirers not only ignorant but also erroneous
all along the way. But fallibilism implies not that the objects or findings
of inquiry are unreal and mere figments, but only that they may be unreal
and figments, insofar as the real does not depend on what any actual
inquirers think of it. On the other hand, do you really believe that there
are no cases where we've reached truths about general characters of things,
done good statistical studies on the distributions of such characters, and
so on?

The idea that we can succeed in inquiry does not drive us to the idea that
we can't fail in it. Peirce was both a fallibilist and, to coin a word, a
successibilist (he opposed radical skepticism and held that the real is the
cognizable). Peirce took these ideas as presuppositions to reasoning in
general and shaping scientific method. He regarded such presuppositions as
collectively taking on the aspect of hopes which, in practice, we hardly
can doubt. Really, one can reasonably believe that sharks have a general
character without knowing a great deal about sharks. They would be like
other kinds of things where investigation revealed only over time certain
definite characters common to members of a kind, some of which characters
also distinguish the kind, the characters together parts of a complex
character called the general nature of the kind.

Best, Ben

On 9/20/2014 10:03 AM, Stanley N Salthe wrote:

Ben -- You asserted

>But "real" in a Peircean context just means capable of being objectively
investigated such that various intelligences would converge sooner or
later,  but still inevitably, on the same conclusions, rather than on some
set of mutually incompatible conclusions.

Regarding suppositions about actual phenomena -- like, say, the nature of
sharks -- since 'the long run' is NOT now, how can we know which version
from different cultures is 'real'?  This is the basic reason one must be a
nominalist.

STAN

On Fri, Sep 19, 2014 at 10:31 PM, Benjamin Udell wrote:

Howard, lists,

Epistemologies are not claims about special concrete phenomena in the sense
that they and their deductively implied conclusions would be directly
testable for falsity by special concrete experiments or experiences. That's
also true of principles of statistics and of statistical inference, yet
such principles are not generally regarded as requiring a leap of faith.
Mathematics is also not directly testable by special concrete experiments,
yet mathematics, whether as theory or language, is not generally regarded
as requiring a leap of faith. What mathematics requires is leaps of
transformational imagination in honoring agreements (hypothetical
assumptions) as binding. Two dots in the imagination are as good an example
of two things as any two physical objects - better, even, since more
amenable for mathematical study. Some sets of mathematical assumptions are
nontrivial and lead inexorably, deductively, to nontrivial conclusions
which compel the reasoner. If you think that mathematics is _*merely* _
symbols, still that's to admit that mathematical symbols form structures
that, by their transformabilities, model possibilities.

Contrary to your claim, physical laws are not physical forces and do not
depend like forces on time and rates. Instead physical laws _*are* _ those
dependences on time and rates and are expressed mathematically, which is to
say that some mathematics is instantiated in the actual, although you think
that mathematical limit ideas of absolute continuity and absolute
discreteness should be instantiated like photons, rocks, trees, or Socrates
in order for mathematics to be real. But "real" in a Peircean context just
means capable of being objectively investigated such that various
intelligences would converge sooner or later,  but still inevitably, on the
same conclusions, rather than on some set of mutually incompatible
conclusions. You think that some sort of dynamicism is a safer and more
skeptical bet than realism about generals and modalities. But the idea that
varied intelligences will not tend toward agreement about mathematical
conclusions is no safe bet.

So the question is, again, do you think that numbers can be objectively
investigated as numbers? - such that (individually, biologically, etc.)
various intelligences, proceeding from the same assumptions, would reach
the same conclusions. If you do think so, then you are a nominalist or
anti-realist in name only.



*One man, two votes, for Dominic Frontiere*

Rigid bodies, and incompletely but sufficiently rigid bodies, although able
to go through transformations that leave them, e.g., rotated 180 degrees,
and so on, still cannot change their chirality or handedness in that manner
(except in an eldritch elder Outer Limits episode). Opposite-handed but
otherwise equivalent objects conform to the mathematics of their
mirror-style equivalence as inexorably as a dynamic process follows dynamic
laws. Phenomenologically, forces are like sheriffs enforcing the physical
laws. Yet there are mathematical rules that physical phenomena respect
without forces pushing one around when one attempts to defy them, such as
the lack of a non-deformative continuous transformation into a chiral
opposite. Sometimes mathematics rules by 'smart power'.

The idea that mathematics' real end is to help physics, with which your
wording suggests agreement, was put forth by some positivists, one of whom
went so far as to say that mathematicians who thought themselves to have
some other or broader purpose should discount their subjective feelings
about it as merely illusory and due to their choice of profession.

I could go on, but the question  is, do you think that numbers can be
objectively investigated as numbers? If so, then you are a nominalist or
anti-realist in name only, and a realist in the Peircean sense. If not,
then you do not believe that there is a reliable mathematical expression of
physical phenomena.

Best, Ben

On 9/18/2014 11:42 PM, Howard Pattee wrote:

At 10:39 AM 9/18/2014, Benjamin wrote:


Only humans (at least here on Earth) do sociology, psychology, biology,
chemistry, or physics. I have no evidence that elementary nature does even
simple physics, or even wears a lab coat.


HP: I agree. These are all fields in which humans make models of their
experiences. They may agree on their models but still disagree on different
epistemologies, realism, nominalism, eliminative materialism, and so on.
These epistemologies are *interpretations *of their models with respect to
what they believe exists or what they believe is real.

Epistemologies are not empirically decidable, e.g., not falsifiable. True
belief in any epistemology requires a leap of faith. There are degrees of
faith, skepticism being at the low end. In my own view as a physicist,
nominalism requires a much safer leap of faith than realism. However, I
often think realistically. I see no harm in it as long as I don't  see it
as the one true belief.


BU: Being alive, instantiating life, is far from enough to do biology.
Instantiating mathematical structure is far from enough to do mathematics.


HP: Again, I agree. That does not mean that "doing math" is the same as
"doing physics". Mathematics is the best *language* that we use to describe
physical laws. There is an inexorability in physical laws that does not
exist in the great variety of mathematical concepts and rules.


> [HP] No one has discovered a point or a triangle or a number, the
infinite or the infinitesimal, in Nature

BU: In your sense, nobody has discovered a physical law in nature either.
Rules, constraints, norms, distributions, etc., are not animals,
vegetables, minerals, or particles. Therefore by your standards they are
not real.


HP: Here I disagree. You are not distinguishing mathematical *rules* from
physical *laws* . Mathematics provides the most exact *symbolic language*
in which the laws are described. Symbolic rules are not like physical
material forces. Specifically, laws are inexorably time and rate-dependent.
Logic and mathematics do not involve time and rates. That is why I say that
"only humans do mathematics" (manipulate symbols), which they do at their
own rates. Humans cannot "do forces and laws". Forces act at the lawful
rates whether we like it or not.


By saying that X is "real," Peirce means that X is objectively investigable
as X. You won't use the word "real" in that way.


HP: I do not understand. What I call real depends only on my epistemic
assumptions, and I am not at all sure that defining "real" is important to
have a good model. What we need to understand is what Wigner called the
"unreasonable effectiveness" of our mathematics in describing laws. There
is no good reason for this effectiveness. Wigner quotes Peirce: " . . . and
it is probable that there is some secret here which remains to be
discovered."

Peirce, as a chemist (1887) also agreed with Hertz's epistemology (1884):
“The result that the chemist *observes* is brought about by* nature*
[Hertz: “the image of the consequents of nature”]; the result that the
mathematician observes is brought about by the associations of the* mind* .
[Hertz: “consequents of images in the mind”] . . . the power that connects
the conditions of the mathematicians diagram with the relations he
*observes* in it is just as occult and mysterious to us as the power of
Nature that brings about the results of the chemical experiment." [W:6, 37,
Letter to Noble on the Nature of Reasoning, May 28, 1987. (1897)]

Hertz: "As a matter of fact, we do not know, nor have we any means of
knowing, whether our conception of things are in conformity with them in
any other than this *one* fundamental respect [Peirce's "power that
connects"].

Howard
-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .




Reply via email to