Frederik, Lists,

You say:  "Peirce saw thought as an argument chain whose resting points were 
propositions."

For the sake of sorting through some of the disagreements that have been voiced 
about what kinds of signs or representamens may be found in the physical, 
chemical, biological or social parts of nature, let me try to provide a quick 
summary of the position that is established in the normative sciences:

Peirce establishes this much in the speculative grammar and critical logic:
1) thought is an end directed inference chain whose resting points are 
decisions; 
2) conscious thought is realized in greater degrees when the inferences are 
self controlled argument and argumentation chains directed towards ends that 
are held to be good for their own sake (e.g., towards the truth), where the 
resting points are dicisigns that take symbolic forms and are called 
propositions.  Those inference chains that appear to embody final causes that 
are held by the mind that interprets them to be good for their own sake are 
argument and argumentation chains because the mind that does the interpretation 
is able to consciously evaluate those arguments by examining the degree to 
which they serve the larger aims.  The highest levels of self-control involve 
the evaluation and criticism of the leading principles of inquiry and the 
larger ideals that animate those principles.

Based on this understanding of inference and argument, we have reason to adopt 
the following as regulative ideas in our methodeutic: 
3) all regularities—wherever they are found--may be conceived as inference 
chains.  Those inference chains that are no longer evolving in their embodied 
regularities no longer appear to be changing towards some end and may, at that 
point in time, be conceived simply as mechanical causes.  They can be thought 
of as mechanical because the inferences all seem to have a demonstrative form 
and the synthetic inferences that involve continued growth do not appear to be 
present.  Those regularities that are still evolving may reasonably be supposed 
to involve something like an end (more or less determinate), where the end is 
one of the things that may be undergoing evolution.  Those processes that are 
merely finious, but not entirely final, may be conceived as inference chains 
where the resting points are representamens that may have a structure that is 
similar in some respects to a dicisign.  Those inference chains that appear to 
embody final causes may be conceived as thoughts that are directed towards some 
natural end, where the resting points of the chains are dicisigns.  When the 
interpretants of this process involve only the lower degrees of self-control, 
we may reasonably suppose that there is a quasi-mind that serves as 
interpreter.  Consequently, we may conceive of all regularities as inference 
chains where the evolution of those regularities involve greater and lesser 
degrees of control over the processes that are involved in the modification and 
adaptation of those regularities in relation to ends that are more or less 
determinate, where those ends themselves have something like a life 
history—some are dying or are dead, and some are alive are growing.

These regulative ideas are put to use in metaphysics as Peirce tries to 
articulate the assumptions we should adopt as we seek to explain all of the 
basic kinds of things that call out for explanation in the special sciences.  
The goal is to keep the door of inquiry open by avoiding any explanatory move 
that will make it impossible to explain what needs to be explained.

--Jeff



Jeff Downard
Associate Professor
Department of Philosophy
NAU
(o) 523-8354
________________________________________
From: Frederik Stjernfelt [stj...@hum.ku.dk]
Sent: Thursday, September 25, 2014 6:48 AM
To: biosemiot...@lists.ut.ee; Peirce List
Subject: [PEIRCE-L] Re: [biosemiotics:6952] Re: Natural Propositions

Dear John, lists,
I think you're right - Peirce saw thought as an argument chain whose resting 
points were propositions.
Best
F

Den 22/09/2014 kl. 18.46 skrev John Collier 
<colli...@ukzn.ac.za<mailto:colli...@ukzn.ac.za>>
:

At 01:41 PM 2014-09-13, Frederik wrote:
Dear Sung, lists -
To take thought to be but the result of thinking is an idea that may lead us 
astray - especially if you take thinking in all its aspects to be a 
psychological process only.
Thought is not determined by thinking only but, importantly, by the object of 
thought and the structure of sound reasoning.
So, you might as well say that thought is the result of the norms of reasoning 
and the features of the object thought about. Thinking then is the process 
combining these - but not the process producing thought as such. Just like the 
TV-series you watch is not the product of the printing of the DVD only. Or the 
meal you prepare in your casserole is not only the product of the cooking 
process - but also of the objects you add to the casserole and the recipe you 
follow.
Best
F

I agree with what you say here, but I was wondering if it does not go further. 
Frege used "thought" to refer to propositions, as I understand him, and I am 
not clear whether Peirce did the same. (I studied with a number of Frege 
experts, but never had a Peirce expert on my committee, though my thesis does 
make homage to Peirce.) I am thinking in particular of a peculiar passage that 
Vinicius Romanini brought to my attention:

() if, for example, there be a certain fossil fish, certain observations upon 
which, made by a skilled paleontologist, and taken in connection with chemical 
analyses of the bones and of the rock in which they were embedded, will one day 
furnish that paleontologist with the keystone of an argumentative arch upon 
which he will securely erect a solid proof of a conclusion of great importance, 
then, in my view, in the true logical sense, that thought has already all the 
reality it ever will have, although as yet the quarries have not been opened 
that will enable human minds to perform that reasoning. For the fish is there, 
and the actual composition of  the stone already in fact determines what the 
chemist and the paleontologists will one day read in them. () It is, therefore, 
true, in the logicians sense of the words, although not in that of the 
psychologists, that the thought is already expressed there (EP2: 455).

This passage makes much more sense to me, and fits much better my information 
based ontology, if "thought" means what I would mean by "proposition".

John

Frederik wrote:

"Thinking, in this sense, may be the object of,            (6729-1)
psychology thought not so ."


Can you separate thinking and thought?  Isn't the latter the result of the
former?  If so, why can't the latter be the object of psychology as well ?

With all the best.

Sung

________________________________
John Collier                                     
colli...@ukzn.ac.za<mailto:colli...@ukzn.ac.za>
Philosophy, University of KwaZulu-Natal, Durban 4041 South Africa
T: +27 (31) 260 3248 / 260 2292       F: +27 (31) 260 3031
Http://web.ncf.ca/collier
<http://web.ncf.ca/collier>
-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .




Reply via email to