Dear Frederick, lists,

Frederik's recent post (see below) touches again on the problematic fact that FOL sanctions the bad argument from 1 to 2:

1.  There is some married woman who will suicide if her husband fails.
2.  If every married man fails then some married woman will suicide.

The Peircean diagnosis is FOL's principle according to which to say that "there is some one individual of which one or other of two predicates is true is no more than to say that there either is some individual of which one is true or else there is some individual of which the other is true." (CP 4.569, NP 224-25)

A remedy in response to this diagnosis is to suppose, contrary to the problematic logical principle, that an individual, call it "a", can be such that for some predicate "F" it is true that a is F or not F, while it is false that a is F and false that a is not F. On this remedy the universe of discourse contains such (at least partially) indeterminate individuals.

Suppose the married woman referred to in 1 and 2 is partially indeterminate in the following way. It is true that she will suicide if her husband fails, but on the basis of the failure of all married men, she has no disposition to suicide and no disposition to refrain from suicide . In case of such large scale failure she might grow to have one or the other disposition; perhaps she would be influenced by what suicides occur among the other wives. But this partially indeterminate married woman is such that, if every married man fails, then she will or will not suicide, and yet it is false that she will suicide and false that she will not suicide.

Given this remedy, 1 is true and 2 is false and the argument from 1 to 2 can be properly classified as invalid.

On this approach, logical theory is changed by partially suspending the law of excluded middle. There is no change in the propositional logic truth table interpretation of the conditional. In this way it departs from Frederik's interpretation. (NP 225)

However it resembles Frederick's interpretation in recognizing that the logical remedy has an "ontological correlate." (NP 225) Besides fully determinate individuals, there must be some which are at least partially indeterminate. There may be a closer resemblance, if natural classes can be construed as partially indeterminate individuals.

An indeterminate individual in the sense used here may be what Peirce finds in "the old logics" and calls an "individuum vagum." (CP 3.92-94) In this case Ben's recent posts in connection with this CP text would be brought into more explicit connection with NP by recognizing the connection between the individuum vagum and the bankruptcy/suicide problem.

Reference to indeterminate individuals construed as subjects of a disjunctive predicate, e.g. "F or not F", but where it doesn't follow that the subject is F or that it is not F, resemble some accounts of "merely confused supposition" which appear in medieval logic in the 13th century and thereafter. So the remedy I've sketched may add to the story of Peirce's association with Scotus.

My characterization of indeterminate individuals is based on Richard Smyth's work. ( _Reading Peirce Reading_, especially pp. 151-68) As far as I know he did not explicitly apply his analysis to the bankrupt/ suicide problem, but what he does say about this problem seems to invite the application. (RPR 95-96) So my suggested remedy may have importance for those with an interest in his work.

There are several ways, then, in which the remedy I've sketched might be worth consideration. Others will know where it needs correction or whether it needs to be bypassed, having been put forward and assessed already but in a form I haven't recognized. I would very much appreciate any comments which bring such shortcomings to light.

Best,

Charles Murray
On Mar 9, 2015, at 8:16 PM, Frederik Stjernfelt wrote:

Dear Ben, lists,

I strongly appreciate the persistent work Ben has been doing in tracing out, over many postings, the implications of Peirce's problems with the "strange rule". I think Ben is quite correct in locating the ambiguity in the quantifier "some", taken to mean sometimes "a certain one", sometimes "some - one or several". But I think there may lie a further reason behind this - linked to Ben's reinterpretation in terms of modal logic where a necessity operator distinguishes the two cases otherwise identified by the "strange rule". When introducing his discussion of the "strange rule" in the April 1906 note, Peirce connects it to a modal observation: " … I soon discovered, upon a critical analysis, that it was absolutely necessary to insist upon and bring to the front, the truth that a mere possibility may be quite real." Why does he do that, as the bankruptcy-suicide inference is ordinary first order logic without any modal semantics on the surface? I think it is because what Peirce would like to catch is the meaning of that sentence (taken in ordinary language) that there is a causal- tendency link between the bankruptcy of husbands and the suicides of their wives. So that the wife-suicide is a "real possibility" actualized by the husband-bankruptcy. This is obviously indicated by saying that a "certain one" wife commits suicide if HER husband etc. This is not full necessity, but "real possibility" (because other wives with bankrupt husbands may escape suicide even if threatened by it as a real possibility). So - I think - Peirce's idea is that the strange rule equates the "mere possibility" of "There is some married woman who will commit suicide in case A husband fails in business." with the real possibility in the claim connecting the two: "There is some married woman who will commit suicide in case HER husband fails in business." - which he did not like because he wanted to distinguish those two types of possibilities. Of course, real possibility is not logic, it is material ontology not even captured by standard modal logic. As Ben rightly indicated, this unease comes from reading more (ordinary language) meaning into logical expressions than their formal definition allows for. But simultaneously, this excessive meaning is scientifically important - the mature Peirce, after 1897, seeing "real possibilities" as implied by scientific laws, regularities, tendencies, patterns etc., regarding how certain predicates, more or less strongly, determine others. This can not be logically expressed in any simple way, and I think that was what tormented Peirce …

Best
F

Den 18/02/2015 kl. 15.41 skrev Benjamin Udell <bud...@nyc.rr.com>:

Peirce said "there is some one individual of which one or other of two predicates is true" ABOUT a specific proposition that he was discussing. So you need to read that specific proposition in order to understand what Peirce meant by "there is some one individual" etc.: "There is some married woman who will commit suicide in case her husband fails in business." which, Peirce finds, turns out to be equivalent to "if every married man fails in business some married woman will commit suicide".


-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .





-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .




Reply via email to