> On Jan 7, 2017, at 6:52 PM, Jon Alan Schmidt <jonalanschm...@gmail.com> wrote:
> With reference to individuals, I shall only remark that there are certain 
> general terms whose objects can only be in one place at one time, and these 
> are called individuals.  They are generals that is, not singulars, because 
> these latter occupy neither time nor space, but can only be at one point and 
> can only be at one date. (W2:180-181; 1868)
> 
> Peirce noted here that "the character of singularity" is itself a general, 
> which seems to render nominalism--the view that everything real is singular, 
> so nothing real is general--effectively self-refuting.  He defined an 
> individual as a collection of singulars joined across places and times, which 
> is thus general when taken as a whole.  Furthermore, absolute singulars are 
> "mere ideals," such that (ironically) an individual is really a continuum as 
> Peirce came to understand that concept decades later.  Consequently, anything 
> that we cognize about individuals is necessarily general, rather than 
> singular.  

I agree that this definitely tends to make nominalism self-refuting which I see 
as a problem rather than a strength.

While I’m not quite sure how to deal with this issue, I suspect that this 
arises out of Peirce’s conception of infinity as opposed to say Cantor’s. 
Peirce thinks through it by division while Cantor tends to think through it in 
terms of sets of individuals. Since for Peirce any ‘individual’ is formed from 
two cuts, that implies a line that can itself be further cut. It’s really not 
set theory.

I’m not sure how Peirce viewed number theory or even how much he knew of it 
given how much is from the 20th century. Certainly his father Benjamin Peirce 
had worked on the roots of number theory. If we think of number theory to 
arithmetic of integers in terms of sets that would appear to lead to thinking 
of individuals not as a collection of singulars. 

I did some Googling, since this is an area of Peirce’s thought I’m ignorant on. 
He did write on number theory in the paper “Logical Studies of the Theory of 
Numbers” around 1890. That paper seems to be somewhat similar to what Hilbert 
later did (his 10th problem). That is he was looking for an algorithm that 
would tell us if there are proofs. He thought we should do this by reducing 
equations to boolean algebra but that appears to merely be a hypothesis of what 
one might be able to do. 

I couldn’t find an online copy of that paper. The closest was this discussion 
of the paper by Irving Anellis.

http://www.iupui.edu/~arisbe/menu/library/aboutcsp/ANELLIS/csp&hilbert.pdf 
<http://www.iupui.edu/~arisbe/menu/library/aboutcsp/ANELLIS/csp&hilbert.pdf>

I’ll confess right up that I just am not at all sure how Peirce viewed 
mathematics. Given my own background in mathematics this is pretty embarrassing 
as you’d think I’d know something about this. I assume he’s somewhat platonic 
about mathematical objects. That is more akin to Godel than the logicists or 
the constructivists. Yet honestly if someone told me he was a logicist or a 
constructivist I’d not be at all shocked either. Those seem just as likely a 
way to conceive of in his philosophy, although he’d probably then argue that 
the structures of constructure or logic are themselves real independent of 
human thought as possibilities.

Going back to infinity along with Cantor and Dedekind, Peirce asserted that 
Dedekind’s cut actually came from Peirce. Apparently before publishing on that 
Peirce had sent Dedekind a paper on such approaches. In contrast to their 
approaches Peirce saw a problem that needed to be solved. (Relating to the 
other thread, this suggests that he was thinking along metaphysical lines in 
what we’d today call modal realism) That is Peirce saw the issue tied to the 
logic of possibility. Peirce saw their approach as “inchoate” which brings to 
mind that quote on metaphysics we’ve been discussing in the other thread.

Generality is, indeed, an indispensable ingredient of reality; for mere 
individual existence or actuality without any regularity whatever is a nullity. 
Chaos is pure nothing. (“What Pragmatism Is,” CP 5.431 1905)

The continuum is a General. It is a General of a relation. Every General is a 
continuum vaguely defined. (“Letter to E. H. Moore,” NEM 3.925 1902)

Continuity, as generality, is inherent in potentiality, which is essentially 
general. (...) The original potentiality is essentially continuous, or general.
(“Detached Ideas on Vitally Important Topics,” CP 6.204-5 1908)

The possible is general, and continuity and generality are two names for the 
same absence of distinction of individuals. (“Multitude and Number,” CP 4.172 
1897)

A perfect continuum belongs to the genus, of a whole all whose parts without 
any exception whatsoever conform to one general law to which same law conform 
likewise all the parts of each single part. Continuity is thus a special kind 
of generality, or conformity to one Idea. More specifically, it is a 
homogeneity, or generality among all of a certain kind of parts of one whole. 
Still more specifically, the characters which are he same in all the parts are 
a certain kind of relationship of each part to all the coordinate parts; that 
is, it is a regularity. (“Some Amazing Mazes,” CP 7.535 note 6 1908)

The key to Peirce’s metaphysics which seems wrapped up in these investigation 
of continuity and the metaphysics of individualism is the idea that to be 
requires a repetition which demands that it not be singular in a strong sense.

 
-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .




Reply via email to