Hello Gary F, John S, Helmut, Kirsti, List,

I take John to be asking a good question about whether or how the part/whole 
distinction might or might not apply to the account of relations and 
relationships as it is applied in the normative science of semiotics. Given the 
context of our discussion, we can ask similar questions about how the 
distinction should be applied in the formal logic of the EG.


In asking "what practical  difference would it make," I take John to be asking 
the very same kind of thing that Peirce asked in his account of relations and 
relationships when he moves from the first (i.e., familiarity) and second 
(logical) grades of clarity, to a third pragmatic grade of clarity (see The 
Logic of Relatives starting at CP 3.456 and also 6.318 below).


Starting with the texts, I see that Peirce applies the distinction in a number 
of places to the account of relations and relationships.  Here are several 
relevant passages (note:  words both underlined and in bold are my emphasis):


1.  CP 2.316. Let us now proceed to compare the conclusions from the abstract

definition of a Dicisign with the facts about propositions. The first 
conclusion is that every proposition contains a Subject and a Predicate, the 
former representing (or being) an Index of the Primary Object, or Correlate of 
the relation represented, the latter representing (or being) an Icon of the 
Dicisign in some respect. Before inquiring whether every proposition has such 
parts, let us see whether the descriptions given of them are accurate, when 
there are such parts. The proposition "Cain kills Abel" has two subjects "Cain" 
and "Abel" and relates as much to the real Objects of one of these as to that 
of the other. But it may be regarded as primarily relating to the Dyad composed 
of Cain, as first, and of Abel, as second member. This Pair is a single 
individual object having this relation to Cain and to Abel, that its existence 
consists in the existence of Cain and in the existence of Abel and in nothing 
more. The Pair, though its existence thus depends on Cain's existence and on 
Abel's, is, nevertheless, just as truly existent as they severally are. The 
Dyad is not precisely the Pair. The Dyad is a mental Diagram consisting of two 
images of two objects, one existentially connected with one member of the pair, 
the other with the other; the one having attached to it, as representing it, a 
Symbol whose meaning is "First," and the other a Symbol whose meaning is 
"Second." Thus, this diagram, the Dyad, represents Indices of Cain and Abel, 
respectively; and thus the subject conforms to our conclusion.


2. CP 4.173 A part of a collection called its whole is a collection such that 
whatever is u of the part is u of the whole, but something that is u of the 
whole is not u of the part. (174) It is convenient to use this locution; 
namely, instead of saying A is in the relation, r, to B, we may say A is an r 
to B, or of B; or, if we wish to reverse the order of mentioning A and B, we 
may say B is r'd by A. If a relation, r , is such that nothing is r to two 
different things, and nothing is r'd by two different things, so that some 
things in the universe are perhaps r to nothing while all the rest are r, each 
to its own distinct correlate, and there are some things perhaps to which 
nothing is r, but all the rest have each a single thing that is r to it, then I 
call r a one-to-one relation. If there be a one-to-one relation, r, such that 
every unit of one collection is r to a unit of a second collection, while every 
unit of the second collection is r'd by a unit of the first collection, those 
two collections are commonly said to be in a one-to-one correspondence with one 
another. . . .


3. CP 2.311 This latter Object may be distinguished as the Primary Object, the 
other being termed the Secondary Object. The Dicisign in so far as it is the 
relate of the existential relation which is the Secondary Object of the 
Dicisign, can evidently not be the entire Dicisign. It is at once a part of the 
Object and a part of the Interpretant of the Dicisign. Since the Dicisign is 
represented in its Interpretant to be an Index of a complexus as such, it must 
be represented in that same Interpretant to be composed of two parts, 
corresponding respectively to its Object and to itself [the Dicisign]. That is 
to say, in order to understand the Dicisign, it must be regarded as composed of 
two such parts whether it be in itself so composed or not. It is difficult to 
see how this can be, unless it really have two such parts; but perhaps this may 
be possible. Let us consider these two represented parts separately. The part 
which is represented to represent the Primary Object, since the Dicisign is 
represented to be an Index of its Object, must be represented as an Index, or 
some representamen of an Index, of the Primary Object. The part which is 
represented to represent a part of the Dicisign is represented as at once part 
of the Interpretant and part of the Object.


4. CP 4.564  In the first place, the most perfectly analytical system of 
representing propositions must enable us to separate illative transformations 
into indecomposable parts. Hence, an illative transformation from any 
proposition, A, to any other, B, must in such a system consist in first 
transforming A into AB, followed by the transformation of AB into B. For an 
omission and an insertion appear to be indecomposable transformations and the 
only indecomposable transformations. That is, if A can be transformed by 
insertion into AB, and AB by omission in B, the transformation of A into B can 
be decomposed into an insertion and an omission.


5. CP 3.493 For the purpose of this algebra, I entirely discard the idea that 
every compound relative consists of an antecedent and a consequent part. I 
consider the circle round the antecedent as a mere sign of negation, for which 
in the algebra I substitute an obelus over that antecedent. The line between 
antecedent and consequent, I treat as a sign of an "operation" by itself. It 
signifies that anything whatever being taken as correlate of the first written 
member -- antecedent or consequent -- and as first relate of the second written 
member, either the one or the other is to be accepted.


6. CP 6.318. I have, since 1870, written much about the logic of relations. In 
those writings, I have usually restricted the terms "relations" and 
"relationships" to existential relations and relationships. By a relationship I 
understand the conception of a fact about a set of things abstracted from the 
representation of the things themselves or, in other words, a predicate which 
requires more than one subject to complete a proposition, or conception of a 
fact. A "relation" only differs from a "relationship" in that one of the 
subjects is regarded as being taken account of first, and is usually called the 
subject nominative, while the others are called the direct and indirect 
objects. In other words a relation is a predicate requiring one subject 
nominative and one or more objects in a definite sequence. In my earlier papers 
[in Volume 3] I use the conception of relation chiefly; in my later ones that 
of relationship. The difference is little more than trifling. An existential 
relation or relationship is distinguished from others by two marks. In the 
first place, its different subjects all belong to one universe; which 
distinguishes it very strikingly from such relations as that which subsists 
between a thing and its qualities, and that which subsists between portions of 
matter and the form into which they are built; as for example between the cells 
of a living body and the whole body, and often times between the different 
singulars of a plural and the plural itself. In the second place, an 
existential relation or relationship differs from some other relations and 
relationships in a respect which may be described in two ways, according as we 
employ collective or distributive forms of expression and thought. Speaking 
collectively, the one logical universe, to which all the correlates of an 
existential relationship belong, is ultimately composed of units, or subjects, 
none of which is in any sense separable into parts that are members of the same 
universe. For example, no relation between different lapses of time -- say, 
between the age of Agamemnon and that of Homer -- can be an existential 
relation, if we conceive every lapse of time to be made up of lapses of  time, 
so that there are no indivisible units of time.


7. CP 3.576. By a seed (granum) of an existential relation is to be understood 
an existing individual which not only stands in that relation to some 
correlate, but to which also some relate stands in that relation. By a spike of 
a relation is to be understood any collection of seeds of it of which it is 
both true that every one of them stands in that relation to some one of them; 
and it is also true that to every one seed of the spike some seed of the spike 
stands in that same relation. Thus, two spikes of the same relation may have 
common seeds, or one may even be a part of another. A simple spike is a spike 
not containing any other spike as a part of it.


Looking at these seven passages, it seems clear to me that Peirce is applying 
the distinction between part and whole to the relations and relationships that 
are found in the science of semiotics and in the formal logic of the EG. What 
is more, he applies the distinction in his both his logical (i.e., 2nd level of 
clarity) and in his pragmatic (i.e., 3rd level) definitions and explanations of 
how the correlates are related to one another in both degenerate and genuinely 
dyadic and triadic relations. Having said that, he is being remarkable careful 
about when and how the distinctions should be applied.


It is possible that Peirce is mistaken in applying the distinction between part 
and whole the way he does to semiotic relations and relationships but, for my 
part, I don't see anything that stands out as a clear error on his part. As 
such, my aim is to follow his lead in the proper use of these terms--at least 
when I'm trying to interpret his texts.


Yours,


Jeff



Jeffrey Downard
Associate Professor
Department of Philosophy
Northern Arizona University
(o) 928 523-8354
________________________________
From: Helmut Raulien <h.raul...@gmx.de>
Sent: Friday, December 22, 2017 10:36:32 AM
To: jerry_lr_chand...@icloud.com
Cc: Peirce List; John F Sowa
Subject: Aw: Re: [PEIRCE-L] Lowell Lecture 3.6

Jerry, John, List,
you wrote:
"
> If anybody asked me "Do relations have parts?",
> I would say "What do you mean? Why are you asking
> that question? What would you do with the answer?”
Very well stated from the CSP spirit of inquiry perspective!
".
I dont understand this. If anybody asks, if relations have parts, why can this 
not be an intrinsically motivated question? Why does the CSP spirit suggest, 
that this question must be extrinsically motivated, so that the asker does not 
just want to know the answer, because he/she finds it interesting, but has 
obscure motives, and wants to use the answer for something weird, something 
other than just gaining knowledge? Ok, you can always ask: Why do you want to 
gain knowledge? That is always a good question, I admit. But: If the knowledge 
gainer shares this knowledge, then I think it is clear to see, that she/he just 
wants to commit to the scientific progress, and is not Dr. No, or Frankenstein.

I can imagine, that there are simple relations that donot have parts, but there 
are also composed relations, that consist of other relations, which are their 
parts (given that I may use the term "parts" in this functional way, but maybe 
not, this still has got to be discussed, or is already, and I might have missed 
it).

Best,
Helmut


22. Dezember 2017 um 17:55 Uhr
 "Jerry LR Chandler" <jerry_lr_chand...@icloud.com>

List, John:

Comments inserted within text:

> On Dec 22, 2017, at 9:38 AM, John F Sowa <s...@bestweb.net> wrote:
>
> On 12/22/2017 7:50 AM, g...@gnusystems.ca wrote:
>> for instance, you can say that a dicisign has subject(s) and predicate, but 
>> in late Peircean semeiotics, the analysis into these “parts” is somewhat 
>> arbitrary, and in some cases, so is the choice of whether it has one 
>> “subject” or several.
>
> But that doesn't answer the question whether a sign has parts.
>
> A sign is a triadic relation. But it's not clear whether
> you can or should say that a relation has parts. For example,
> consider the dyadic relation greater-than or its symbol '>'.
>
> If you write "7 > 2", that statement has three symbols,
> and it expresses a relationship between 7 and 2.
> But those three symbols aren't parts of the relation.
>
Well stated!
But, this is traditional mathematical usage because of the role of 
well-defined, separate, clear and distinct symbols of the orderly display of 
numbers that must be aligned in sequence along a one-dimensional geometric line.

The formation of collections of pairs of atoms generates relations that depend 
on symbols as parts of the molecule (Mereology). This is essential to the 
emergence of the whole, as in the formation of chiral centers. The alignment of 
the parts of the chiral molecule are in space. This proven by well-defined 
emanations necessary for the patterns of x-ray diffraction of the sinsign.

In the material world of the chirality of molecular genetics, the symbols where 
A is the symbol for adenosine and G is the symbol for guanosine, the three 
symbols,

A > G

makes no logical sense.

In other words, the mathematization of symbols is dependent of the symbol 
system under inquiry.

(A few days ago, John referenced the paper by Church on semantics and syntax 
which is highly relevant to this discussion.)

> That particular relationship has 7 and 2 as parts, but the
> relation named greater-than can "have" infinitely many
> relationships. And as Aristotle observed, "have as part"
> is only one of many ways of "having”.

A chemical example of this is the abductive set of isomers of a given molecular 
formula, such as was discussed for Pastuer's chiral forms of tartaric acid.
>
> One might say that the *extension* of greater-than is an
> infinite set of pairs. But that does not imply that
> greater-than has infinitely many parts.

Agreed.
>
> The *intension* of greater-than is defined by axioms
> (several statements with multiple symbols). But those
> axioms aren't considered "parts" of the relation.

Agreed.
Abstractly, this is one component of the “alphabetic” sign system for chemical 
notation. The composition of the names of the parts (as names of atoms) 
generates a new name for the molecule that is the "difference that makes a 
difference” between atoms and molecules. The new name must give an exact 
accounting of the spatial organization of the parts, as with tartaric acid and 
virtually all other biochemicals.
>
> In summary, I would avoid using the word 'part' to
> describe any relation, including the sign relation.
Agreed.
>
> If anybody asked me "Do relations have parts?",
> I would say "What do you mean? Why are you asking
> that question? What would you do with the answer?”

Very well stated from the CSP spirit of inquiry perspective!

>From my perspective, I would suggest that John assertions are closely tied to 
>the general problem of taxonomy / categorization / classification / order and 
>organization which are intrinsic to the mathematization of natural sorts and 
>kinds, as well as a host of other problems associated with the bare 
>grammatical usage of the term “part” in the context of philosophy and public 
>rhetoric.

Cheers

Jerry


>
> John
>
> -----------------------------
> PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON 
> PEIRCE-L to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu 
> . To UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu 
> with the line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
> http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .
>
>
>
>


-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .




-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .




Reply via email to