Is that accurate? It may vary, but I thought the privilege could be claimed for 
any confidential communication made to a clergy member in his/her professional 
capacity as a spiritual advisor. The person seeking that counsel need not 
necessarily be a co-communicant. I don't think this is just hair-splitting. 
It's not analogous to a statement that men as well as women can seek medical 
care for pregnancy. 

> On Dec 4, 2013, at 10:56 PM, "Levinson, Sanford V" <slevin...@law.utexas.edu> 
> wrote:
> 
> Free speech doctrine, for better or worse, presumably protects (almost) 
> everyone.  What is distinctive about the “clergy-penitent privilege” is that 
> it protects only a particular subset of people, i.e., those who claim some 
> religious identity, as against secularists who have the same desire to 
> unburden themselves to sympathetic listeners but can’t assume that it is 
> protected in the same way.  Aren’t we back to the conundra involving 
> “conscientious objection” and the Seeger and Welch cases.  There the Court 
> could adopt Paul Tillich and say that secularists, too, have “ultimate 
> concerns” equivalent to religious commitments.  Can one imagine a similar 
> move with regard to clergy privileges?  I support such cases as Rosenberger 
> (assuming, at least, one version of the facts in that case, which may or may 
> not be entirely correct) and Widmar v. Vincent on “equality” grounds, i.e., 
> those who are religious should not be selected out for worse treatment than 
> those who are secular.  If I can use a facility for meetings of my philosophy 
> club, then I think that others should be free to use the facility for 
> meetings of the “Good News Club.”  But it is telling that we’re talking about 
> a “privilege” that is denied to each and every secular person (unless they 
> can afford a shrink, though even there the privilege is significantly more 
> constrained than is the case with a priest), and “equality” arguments go by 
> the boards. 
>  
> sandy
>  
> From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
> [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein
> Sent: Wednesday, December 04, 2013 11:35 PM
> To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics
> Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties
>  
> Much of free speech law involves protecting speech that burdens third 
> parties; for example, the victims of hate speech suffer emotional distress as 
> do the mourners at funerals tormented by the Westboro Church, and speech that 
> does not quite violate Brandenburg can incite violence. Further, the cost to 
> the public in protecting speech can be extraordinarily high. cities incurred 
> tens of thousands of dollars in police and other costs while trying to 
> maintain order during Operation Rescue protests. Criminal procedure rights 
> can make it more difficult to apprehend and punish people who commit crimes. 
> Property rights can make it more difficult to protect the environment. Rights 
> have always been expensive politcal goods.
>  
> It is true that the Establishment Clause imposes some constitutional 
> constraints on the costs government may incur or impose on third parties in 
> protecting religious liberty. Arguing that free exercise rights or statutory 
> religious liberty rights should only be protected in situations in which 
> doing so imposes virtually no costs on either the public or third parties, 
> however, would treat religious liberty differently than almost all other 
> rights and dramatically undermine their utility for people attempting to 
> exercise such rights.
> From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
> on behalf of Christopher Lund [l...@wayne.edu]
> Sent: Wednesday, December 04, 2013 5:53 PM
> To: 'Law & Religion issues for Law Academics'
> Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties
> 
> I think Marc’s point is solid and underappreciated.  Following up on it, does 
> anyone know of any literature that tries to think about “burdens on third 
> parties” across constitutional rights?  We accept such burdens as a matter of 
> course with defamation law, as Marc notes.  Yet we also accept them in other 
> contexts.  Guns would be one obvious example.  But also think of, for 
> example, busing during the Civil Rights Era.  White suburban families had to 
> accept busing of their kids to distant and sometimes difficult schools, 
> because desegregation was that important.  Or think about abortion: I think 
> the Court was right to hold spousal consent and notification laws 
> unconstitutional, but there are real issues of third-party harms there too.
>  
> Best, Chris
>  
>  
>  
> _______________________________________________
> To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
> To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
> http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
> 
> Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
> private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
> people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
> forward the messages to others.
_______________________________________________
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.
_______________________________________________
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Reply via email to