Re: calling for the assassination of the President is against the law

2004-07-26 Thread Gil Skillman
At 04:31 PM 7/26/2004 -0400, you wrote:

My recollection is that calling for the assassination of the President is
a serious crime in the United States. [clip] You can't just go around
threatening the President of the United States, even if you're a Senator,
that's a serious crime.
Ah, but note the caveat--it's a serious crime to threaten the President *of
the United States.*  It's unlikely that U.S. law extends a similar
protection to chief executives of other countries. (And apparently, from
Justin's just-now posting, it doesn't.)
Gil


Re: Greed

2004-07-21 Thread Gil Skillman
David S. writes:

Is Marx making an empirical point?  Based upon observation, capitalists
are motivated by greed?  Or is it a definitional point -- under
capitalism, capitalists by definition are motivated by greed.  For
instance, let's hypothesize a man who decides in his youth that there is a
Rembrandt that he loves and wants to own.  So he decides to become rich
enough to buy the Rembrandt and then spends a lifetiime engaging in
capitalist acts until he is sufficiently wealthy to buy the Rembrandt, at
which time he sells his business and buys the Rembrandt.  Now, while we
can criticize this man for being possessive, exclusionary, etc., I would
suggest he is not motivated by greed in the colloquial sense or even in
the sense that Marx seems to be using the term.   So he is not a capitalist?
David Shemano
From a certain theoretical standpoint--and I'm talking mainstream theory,
not Marxist--these questions are irrelevant.  Given competitive markets (or
indeed, just competitive markets for firm equity shares), it can be shown
that, whatever their personal consumption goals, people who own equity
shares in a given firm will want that firm to maximize profits.  So to the
extent that firm managers respond to the concerns of equity holders, they
will act as though greedy--that is, operate the firm so as to maximize
(the expected present value of) profit.  These theoretical results
vindicate and give a precise interpretation for Marx claim that it doesn't
really matter what individual capitalists want to do--Capital wants to
accrue profit (in Marxian terms, surplus value).
Gil


Re: absolute general law of capitalist accumulation

2004-07-19 Thread Gil Skillman
Charles Brown wrote:
 by Devine, James

 Charles writes:

The funny thing is dialectics is logic. So, it is a way of talking about
 things. Formal logic is a linguistic project.
To which Ravi responds:

i am not sure who wrote what, but addressing the above: i would submit
that formal logic is a mathematical project, not a linguistic one (even
wittgenstein might agree). fwiw, i agree with most of the rest of
charles' summation of logic.

For an in-depth defense and exploration of the idea that logic is grounded
in mathematics rather than vice-versa, see G. Spencer-Brown's classic LAWS
OF FORM.  His argument rebuts the notion that formal logic is a linguistic
project:  Spencer-Brown's argument is that, given any consistent
distinction (and thus any specific linguistic structure), and two rules,
(essentially):  1) a double affirmative is equivalent to an affirmative (
Is is = is)  and 2)  a double negative is equivalent to an affirmative (
Not not = is), then certain results unavoidably follow, *whatever* the
distinction or linguistic structure you begin with.
Gil


Re: oops factor

2004-07-17 Thread Gil Skillman
Quoting Dan Scanlan [EMAIL PROTECTED]:

 Checking Your Bill for a New Charge Called 'Oops'

   By David Pogue

 (SF Chronicle, Dec. 4, 2003) -- Every few years, economists identify
 another mutant variation of inflation to keep them awake at night. In
 the 1980s, it was stagflation. Three years ago, it was deflation. And
 now, meet the economic specter of the new millennium: stealth
 inflation.

[clip]

I think this article is on to something.  My own experience with this
phenomenon has been with my VISA credit card company.  I'd had the card for
something like 20 years with no problems or complaints--virtually always paid
on time, etc.--when three or so years ago, suddenly and unilaterally, they
canceled my VISA card and replaced it with a Mastercard. (The subsequently
given rationale was that they'd negotiated a better deal with M-card.)

Problem was, I already had a Mastercard and didn't need another--I wanted the
VISA card I'd always had.  I called and told a customer rep this, and told him
I wanted the same setup I've always had--i.e.,a VISA card with no annual fee,
and no interest charges if the bill is paid on time each month.  He said yep,
no problem, and sent me a new card. Fine.

It wasn't until I got the next bill I found out that it had an annual fee.  So
I call.  They say, oops, it was a mistake, we'll cancel the fee, but we've got
to send you a different card. I say, one without an annual fee, right?  They
say, right, and send me a new card. Great.

Until the next bill, where I see an interest charge, even though I'd paid the
previous bill on time.  So I call, and find out that on that card you
accumulate interest charges immediately, whether or not the bill is paid on
time. They say, oops, sorry, we'll cancel the interest charge, but we have to
send you a new card.  And I say, this one won't have an annual fee or
immediately accumulating interest, right?  And they say, right.  And send me
another new card.  Okay.

Well, at least I haven't had to change cards since then, but there have still
been occasional annoying irregularities always resulting in me being charged
for something I didn't know about, and requiring a phone call to a customer rep
to clear up.  In the latest go-round,for example, I got very busy recently and
did something very unusual:  I entirely forgot to send in the payment for a
monthly bill.  I discovered this when I got the next bill, with, of course, a
hefty late fee and big interest charges.

Oh, well, I think, my fault.  I call a customer rep and ask how much I'd have
to send in right then in excess of the amount on the current bill in order to
catch up with *all* interest charges, so there would be no further accumulation
of interest charges on the next bill, assuming I paid it on time. So the
customer rep calculates a number, I add an additional figure *on top* of that,
and send in my payment. Everything taken care of.

...Except not so much, since there were still additional interest charges on my
next bill.  So again I call, and find out from the customer rep that the
earlier rep had made a mistake in advising me(oops), because it is company
policy to let interest charges that result from late payments accumulate on any
oustanding balances for *two* months, even if everything is paid in full after
*one.*  I see. But she deleted the interest charge.

At some point in the above string of misfeasance I had the urge to get on PEN-L
and ask if others had similar experiences.  But then I thought, nah, probably
just a combination of bad luck, miscommunication, new and untrained customer
reps,etc. But now I'm not so sure. And I'm wondering, in light of the article
Dan forwarded, if others have had something like this experience with their
credit cards.  In the meantime, you can find me in the barter economy.

Gil


Re: absolute general law of capitalist accumulation

2004-07-12 Thread Gil Skillman
Hello, Charles.  Secular meaning over a long period of time.  As dd
points out, economists usually use this in the sense of as opposed to
cyclical.  Gil
Thanks for your comment, Gil. Please excuse a layperson's question, but I
have never quite been able to understand this economist's use of secular.
What is the definition of secular.
Charles
by Gil Skillman
You could certainly point to recent economic phenomena supporting an
affirmative answer to this question.  E.g., in the US, the fact that
significant increases in productivity have helped make it possible for
capitalist firms to make do with their existing workforces rather than
increasing employment in proportion to the increase in national
output.  However, I'd argue that such changes, where they occur, are not
*secular* as Marx's general law requires.
Specifically:  Marx understands his law to apply to the situation of
developed capitalist economies.  His statement of the law implies secularly
or tendentially increasing rates of poverty and unemployment in such
economies.  I don't think we've seen secularly increasing rates of poverty
and unemployment in developed capitalist economies (though I'd be
interested to hear others' assessments of the long-run  trends for these
phenomena), despite overall population growth and consequent increases in
the size of the working class.
-clip-


Re: absolute general law of capitalist accumulation

2004-07-08 Thread Gil Skillman
Concerning Marx's statement of the absolute general law of capitalist
accumulation, Charles asks
Does the empirical generalization suggested below have validity today
nationally or globally ?
You could certainly point to recent economic phenomena supporting an
affirmative answer to this question.  E.g., in the US, the fact that
significant increases in productivity have helped make it possible for
capitalist firms to make do with their existing workforces rather than
increasing employment in proportion to the increase in national
output.  However, I'd argue that such changes, where they occur, are not
*secular* as Marx's general law requires.
Specifically:  Marx understands his law to apply to the situation of
developed capitalist economies.  His statement of the law implies secularly
or tendentially increasing rates of poverty and unemployment in such
economies.  I don't think we've seen secularly increasing rates of poverty
and unemployment in developed capitalist economies (though I'd be
interested to hear others' assessments of the long-run  trends for these
phenomena), despite overall population growth and consequent increases in
the size of the working class.
Part of the problem might be the law itself.  Granting entirely Marx's
premise that capitalist accumulation is accompanied by continuous increases
in the organic composition of capital (implying increasing output per
worker), it doesn't follow that a reserve army will necessarily be
created--rather, just that the aggregate demand for labor power will expand
less quickly than the rate of capital accumulation.
There is another potential problem with Marx's argument that has
unexpectedly far-reaching implications.  Granting Marx's inference that
the general law implies the creation of a (growing) industrial reserve
army (IRA) of the unemployed, it obviously follows that the rate of
accumulation is not constrained by aggregate labor supply.  But then what
is it constrained by?  Specifically, why don't profit-seeking capitalists
increase the rate of accumulation (which can be done profitably, since the
existence of an IRA implies that doing so won't put upward pressure on
wages) to the point where the aggregate labor supply is a binding constraint?
I can imagine a variety of answers to this question, but all of them seem
to create significant difficulties either for the validity of the general
law itself or for the logical coherence of the value theory from which
Marx derives this law.
For example, suppose it's argued that, given the presence of the IRA, the
rate of accumulation is constrained by the total funds capitalists have
available for accumulation--that is, by the magnitude of total profit,
equal to the average money rate of profit times the pecuniary value of the
capital stock.  This implies that the rate of capital accumulation is
constrained by the level of the profit rate. But this is a steadily
diminishing constraint, since the same process of technical change that
creates the IRA also lowers unit production costs and thus raises the
profit rate.   And in any case, rising profit rate or not, so long as the
rate of profit net of the rate of increase in the organic composition
exceeds the growth rate of the labor force, the labor constraint must
eventually be binding, thus tendentially eliminating the IRA.
Gil


Reagan's legacy

2004-06-07 Thread Gil Skillman
Did anyone else see the CNN hagiography?  He was 93 - how many people died
as a
result of his policies?

One of the biggest misrepresentations of the Reagan hagiographers is that
he fostered smaller government (a claim featured in the headline for the
Sunday NY Times article on his death).  What nonsense.  For the 8 years
prior to his administration, federal outlays as a percentage of GDP were
about 20.8%.  For the 8 years of the Reagan administration, the comparable
average was about 22.2%.  How is this smaller government?
The most favorable snapshot supporting the view that Reagan made the
federal government smaller is the comparison between the last Carter budget
year with the last Reagan budget year--but it's also the most telling as to
the true nature of Reagan's impact.  In 1981, federal outlays were 22.2% of
GDP, while in 1989 they were 21.2% of GDP, a percentage point lower.  But
at the same time, military expenditures as a percent of GDP went from 5.1 %
to 5.6%, an *increase* of a half a percentage point. What went down, of
course, were primarily federal expenditures on social welfare---*that's*
the essence of Reagan's legacy:  more for armaments, less for health,
education, housing, and income support.
Gil


Re: More on the labor theory of value

2004-03-26 Thread Gil Skillman
But Michael, number of pages produced is a measure of labor performed,
not labor power. And in Marxian terms, the value produced by labor is to
some extent redundant, since to Marx labor *is* the substance of value,
no?  It would be more accurate to say on the basis of your example that the
British paid by, ahem, the value marginal product of the author's labor.
But Dickens was indeed paid by the word, since his stories were
serialized.  In much the same way, Samuel Clemens was in effect paid by the
page, since his books were sold by subscription, and the book price
increased with its length.  Which explains why a lot of his books --A Tramp
Abroad, e.g.--benefit from significant editing.  Gil
In a way, the violinists' demands are not as strange as they seem.
Richard Biernacki has argued that the Germans and the British had a
different conception of labor -- the Germans historically measured labor
by something like Marx's labor power; the British, by the value produced
by labor.  For example, in German publishers paid authors by the number
of pages they produced rather than by the sales of the books.
--
Michael Perelman
Economics Department
California State University
Chico, CA 95929
Tel. 530-898-5321
E-Mail michael at ecst.csuchico.edu


Re: Intro books/article on equilibrium

2004-03-19 Thread Gil Skillman
Bill,

Which type of equilibrium?  Competitive or non-competitive?  Cooperative or
noncooperative game-theoretic? Static or dynamic?
Gil

A co-worker of mine is interested in equilibrium theory.  I have a few
books at home I plan on lending him, but thought folks here might have
some good suggestions for reading.
Suggestions welcome.

Thanks.

Bill


Re: More conservative Rock-and-Roll stars

2004-03-11 Thread Gil Skillman


OK, all American Rock-and-Roll stars are libertarians.


Bruce Springsteen?
Jackson Browne?
Rage Against the Machine (as in, members of the former)?
Bonnie Raitt?
Gil


Re: quote of the day

2004-03-07 Thread Gil Skillman
That Colin Powell.  What a sense of irony. Gil

I am angry that so many of the sons of the powerful well-placed ...
managed to
wangle slots in Reserve and National Guard units.
--
Michael Perelman
Economics Department
California State University
Chico, CA 95929
Tel. 530-898-5321
E-Mail michael at ecst.csuchico.edu


Re: ketchup, buns and manufacturing

2004-03-07 Thread Gil Skillman
In response to this question from Carrol,


 Doesn't Taco Bell manufacture food? If Wonderbread was sold at the
 factory would it cease to be manufacturing and become service?
dms answers

The answer to that is: NO Taco Bell does not manufacture food.  Pepsico
manufactures something called food products through its Frito Lay (and other
divisions) but Taco Bell no more manufactures tacos than Col. Saunders
manufactures chicken, or the Starbuck's outlet down the street manufactures
coffee, or the Armani Exchange manufactures clothing.
Supermarkets are not food manufacturing enterprises. The clerks stocking,
pricing, checking out food  at the supermarket are not food manufacturing
workers, and Taco Bells, Starbucks, KFC, and Armani are all markets..
IF Wonderbread were sold at the factory, the bread itself would still be
manufactured, (although we would still have an argument about whether or not
it is actually bread.  I vote for legislated requirements a la the baguette
in France).  The separation that capital develops between production and
sales, is  a division of labor  in fact designed to allow non-manufacturing,
circulation, marketing, the opportunity to keep up with production, to
conversely not draw  away from production time, and limit production to the
simple inventory and requirements of the factory outlet.
McDonald's contracts and sub-contracts for its potatos (introducing the
Idaho spuds variety into Poland and Russia to get that authentic
McDonald's flavor across the Elbe.  I am not making this up), but it does
not manufacture the spuds itself.
It's true that fast-food places don't manufacture their own intermediate
goods (which are, in this case, things like potatoes, hamburger patties,
buns, cheese, and whatever that liquid plastic substance is that makes up
their superthick shakes), but then neither does virtually any firm that
everyone would agree *is* in the manufacturing sector.  On the other hand,
in such places labor is certainly applied to these inputs, aided by the use
other intermediate goods in the form of machines, to create products that
didn't exist before (as surely as making Wonderbread is manufacturing, even
if the factory doesn't make the flour, or yeast, or salt, or eggs , or
styrofoam, or whatever else goes into its ingredients).  Not a very
involved manufacturing process, to be sure, but manufacturing in any
case.  What blurs the lines with services is that usually fast-food
joints also heat up the food and put it in a convenient carry-away bag for
you.  But that doesn't negate what went on before the bag is handed to
you.  Think of it as a special instance of just-in-time production.
The real question, it seems to me, is thus not whether manufacturing is
involved in such cases, but rather what is the motive underlying the
proposed switch in classification.  And in this case it seems pretty
clear:  the statistics on losses in manufacturing (by current definition)
jobs are pretty damning for Dubya's domestic economic policy, so a change
in definition would be politically convenient.  But necessarily misleading,
since fast-food jobs are low-wage jobs (as are 6 other of the top 9 or 10
fastest growing occupations in the US).
Gil


Re: Brilliant analysis from a soft rock icon

2004-02-20 Thread Gil Skillman
Mark Farner (of Grand Funk Railroad infame).


Metallica

- Original Message -
From: Michael Perelman [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Friday, February 20, 2004 10:31 AM
Subject: Re: [PEN-L] Brilliant analysis from a soft rock icon
Pat Boone.

On Fri, Feb 20, 2004 at 01:04:56PM -0500, Louis Proyect wrote:
 Davis Meshano wrote:
 Mojo Nixon!  The greatest live performer in the history of rock n'
roll,
 and a libertarian to boot.  I could spend all day quoting Mojo Nixon.

 A libertarian? Wow! That leads to an interesting question. How many
other
 rightwingers made a living as rock-and-rollers? The only one I can think
of
 is Ted Nugent. Maybe you can include Stereolab as well. They were
hanging
 around Frank Furedi's cult for a while. Other than that, there's none
that
 come to mind.


 Louis Proyect
 Marxism list: www.marxmail.org
--
Michael Perelman
Economics Department
California State University
Chico, CA 95929
Tel. 530-898-5321
E-Mail michael at ecst.csuchico.edu


Re: song lyrics and poetry

2004-02-08 Thread Gil Skillman
Hey, let a thousand flowers bloom

(Sung to the tune of Where have all the flowers gone)

Gil

:
Do people find such contributions useful?  Just asking.
--
Michael Perelman
Economics Department
California State University
Chico, CA 95929
Tel. 530-898-5321
E-Mail michael at ecst.csuchico.edu


Re: intermediate microeconomics textbook...

2004-01-29 Thread Gil Skillman
Diane,

Three choices are:  Walter Nicholson's calculus-based text, called
Microeconomic Theory or Intermediate Microeconomic Theory (he has another,
non-calculus-based intermediate text as well), Hal Varian, Intermediate
Microeconomics: A Modern Approach, and Binger and Hoffman, Microeconomics
with Calculus.  The calculus is integrated (heh heh) completely into the
exposition in Nicholson and BH, while in Varian the calculus is all in an
appendix.  The strength of the Varian text comes from his division of the
material into short, manageable chapters.   Gil
Hi!

Can someone recommend an intermediate microeconomic theory textbook
that uses some calculus for advanced undergraduate students?  Some
recommendations on interesting supplemental micro topic
readings/articles would also be helpful.  I don't normally teach this
course, in fact I never teach this course, so my reference point seems
to be Jack Hirshleifer from my undergraduate days :).  I have a few
suggestions from colleagues but each one is different!  Offlist is fine.
Thanks in advance,
Diane


Re: pop quiz Friday

2004-01-23 Thread Gil Skillman
Hmm.  I don't remember if he used exactly these words, but Axel
Leijonhufvud (or Axel the Lionheaded, as we affectionately call him) said
something like this in an interview a year or two ago. I kidded him about
it afterwards.
Gil



Who said it?:

Economists don't know much about how different kinds of markets actually
work.


Re: the evolving exchange value of the human body

2003-12-14 Thread Gil Skillman
From foot-binding to leg-lengthening.  Progress of a sort, I suppose

Gil

A tall order

It's painful and slow, but can make you five inches taller. Jonathan Watts
on the surgical trend sweeping China - leg-lengthening
Monday December 15, 2003
The Guardian
Kong Jing-wen has paid £5,700 to have both of her legs broken and
stretched on a rack. The pretty college graduate is now lying in bed,
clearly still in considerable pain three days after a doctor sawed through
the flesh and bone below her knee to insert what looks an awful lot like
knitting needles through the length of her tibiae.
These giant steel pins are connected by eight screws punched horizontally
through her ankle and calf to a steel cage surrounding each leg. Once the
bone starts to heal, these cages will act like a medieval torture device -
each day over the next few months Kong will turn the screws a fraction and
stretch her limbs more and more until she has grown by 8cm.
Despite the agony, the cost and the inconvenience, the 23-year-old says
she does not regret a thing. It hurts, but it will be worth it to be
taller. I'll have more opportunities in life and a better chance of
finding a good job and husband.
Her parents, who financed the operation and are now at her bedside, agree.
It's an investment in our daughter's future. Because she was short, she
used to lack confidence, but this should change that.
Kong Jing-wen is one of a growing number of perfectly healthy Chinese
young men and women who are willing to break a leg for beauty in order to
rise up the ladder in height-conscious China. The complex and
time-consuming procedure they are willing to endure was initially
developed in Russia for people with stunted growth, mismatched legs or
disfigurements. But these days the operation is increasingly used for
cosmetic purposes.
In part, the popularity of such surgery can be explained by the surge of
interest in fashion and beauty in a country where the rising middle
classes are shaking off a dowdy Maoist cultural legacy and using the
rewards of explosive economic growth to explore cosmetic possibilities.
Shops and magazines in the cities show endless images of long-legged
western models, inevitably putting pressure on young women.
Doctors have been able to pioneer new forms of this surgery because height
is so socially important in China that it is often the first thing
strangers will talk about. It is also listed among the criteria required
on job advertisements. To get a post in the foreign ministry, for
instance, male applicants need not bother applying unless they are at
least 5ft 7in, while women must be at least 5ft 3in. Chinese diplomats are
expected to be tall to match the height of their foreign counterparts.
For more glamorous positions the conditions are even tougher: air
stewardesses have to be over 5ft 5in. But height discrimination is evident
even at ground level: in some places, people under 5ft 3in are not even
eligible to take a driving test. To get into many law schools, women
students need to be over 5ft 1in and men over 5ft 5in. Height requirements
are also frequently mentioned in the personal ads of newspapers and
magazines.
All this has ensured a steady stream of business for osteogenetic surgeons
like Dr Xia Hetao, who has pioneered a height-increasing technique in
Beijing used by about 150 people every year. More and more people want to
be taller, he says. It is so important for the image of an individual or
a company that some people come here in tears begging for an operation.
With a minimum £4,000 price tag attached to the procedure, the patients
are all well-off by Chinese standards. According to employees at Dr Xia's
institute of external skeletal fixation technology, it is not just women
who are prepared to have their legs lengthened - men are just as keen. The
vast majority of patients are job- and spouse-hunters in their 20s, but
teenagers are also among the patients and the oldest person to have the
operation was a 52-year-old woman. She was very wealthy and had
everything else she wanted, so she decided to fix her height which had
always been a concern for her, explained one of the staff.
In many cases, the clients are not even particularly short to begin with.
Dr Xia said one 5ft 8in women asked to grow an inch so that she could
reach the standard needed to qualify as an international fashion model.
But most of the others are under average height and undergo up to two
operations so that they can grow by a maximum of almost five inches.
Each procedure has three stages. First comes the operation in which the
legs are broken and steel pins - 27cm long and 8mm in diameter - are
pushed through the bone. These are fixed to an external frame by eight or
so screws, each of which is 4mm in diameter. Next comes the stretching,
which is carried out over several months (depending on how much the
customer wants to grow) by turning the screws each day and lengthening the
bone at the point where it was broken. When 

Re: the Clinton years

2003-11-17 Thread Gil Skillman
Across his 238 pages Pollin is unambiguous. It was under Clinton he
points out, that the distribution of wealth in the US became more skewed
than it had at any time in the previous forty years. Inside the US under
Clinton the ratio of wages for the average worker to the pay of the average
CEO rose from 113 to 1 in 1991 to 1 to 449 when he quit. In the world,
exclusive of China, between 1980 and 1988 and considering the difference
between the richest and poorest 10 per cent of humanity, inequality grew by
19 per cent; by 77 per cent, if you take the richest and poorest 1 per cent.
I suspect this assessment is myopic at best, and largely beside the point
when it comes to comparing the Clinton and Bush II regimes.  In the US, the
trend toward greater wealth and income inequality began in the 1970s and
continued full-steam through the Reagan and Bush I years, so Clinton
inherited a tendency that was already built into the economy.  A
significant portion of the increase in wealth inequality under Clinton was
due to the stock market bubble, reflective in part of a robust economy that
kept unemployment low, and since burst.  And I'm not sure what Pollin
expected Clinton, or any one President for that matter, to do about the
widening chasm between the richest and poorest 1% or 10% of
humanity--insist that the UN adopt a progressive global income tax?  Force
the Gingrich Congress to increase US foreign aid to poor countries a
thousand fold? Also, what could Clinton  have done to reverse the rising
(pre-tax) ratio of CEO to average worker pay, and how much of a difference
could it have made? Domestically, Clinton did manage to get through a tax
increase on the wealthy and a tax decrease for the middle class.  On the
other hand, to his eternal discredit, he went along with eliminating
welfare as we know it without extracting from the Republicans, who were
desperate to gut the welfare system, significant concessions for workers,
like increased support for education, training, child support, etc., in
return.
Clinton, in other words, was a disappointment, and certainly not a
leftist.  Duh.  But Bush II is an unmitigated, across-the-board disaster,
and I think that those who insist there is no real difference between
Clinton and Bush II are missing a key point.  You think wealth inequality
increased under Clinton?  Clinton didn't call for eliminating the
inheritance tax and dividends tax or for dramatic decreases in income tax
rates on the wealthy.  Bush did, and got them with a sunset clause only as
a political accounting shenanigan, and is now calling to make these tax
decreases permanent.  These regressive changes will surely lock in and
further expand existing wealth inequalities.  Also, the resulting massive
structural deficit in the Federal budget will eventually render Medicare
and Social Security infeasible; these programs would not have been
seriously threatened under Clinton's budget management.
And that is, of course only the beginning.  Clinton favored signing the
Kyoto protocol on global warming.  Bush refused to sign it after saying
that he would, and his administration has since censored reports on the
issue by its own agencies in order to avoid dealing with it.  The Clinton
EPA actively pursued litigation against corporate polluters.  The Bush EPA
abandons much of this effort, raises nonenforcement to standard practice,
leading several career EPA administrators to resign in protest, and
introduces rule changes to let polluters off the hook re installing new
pollution control equipment.  Clinton didn't do much to reduce global
income inequality?  Bush shuts off medical and other aid for the poorest
women in the world on the pretext of opposing abortion.  Speaking of
abortion, Bush has actively abetted the right's efforts to restrict
abortion rights, while Clinton supported and defended these rights.
And I haven't even mentioned the unfolding nightmares in Iraq and
Afghanistan, Ashcroft's various incursions against personal freedoms, the
Bush administration's opposition to affirmative actionthe list goes
on.   In sum, whatever Clinton's (considerable) failings, life is or will
be worse for most people in and out of the US as a result of Dubya's policies.
Gil


Re: the Clinton years

2003-11-17 Thread Gil Skillman
Michael writes:

Gil seems to be saying that Clinton rode the rightward drift that had
come before -- beginning I believe in the Carter years.  Clinton was very
smart.  He knew what was happening.  Instead of putting things right, he
shifted the Dems. even farther to the right.  Sam Smith in his Undernews a
week or so ago, showed that this tactic won him reelection, but also
propelled the Dems. downward.
This assumes that the Dems weren't headed in a rightward direction in any
case.   And again, even granting this point, it remains the case that Bush
II is much worse than Clinton--though perhaps less disappointing, since
Dubya's policies are more or less exactly as one would have expected prior
to his installation by the Supreme Court.

I have only gotton through the first Clinton chapter so far, but Pollin
seems quite balanced.  He is not blaming Clinton, only saying that
things were not going well during the boom.
I don't know who you're quoting here, because I never stated that Bob
Pollin blamed Clinton for the changes.  Indeed, I agree with your
assessment of his book.  As you can see from the rest of my post, my main
issue is with those who would assert that there is no important difference
between Clinton and Bush II.  And I agree that the economic boom of the
1990s benefited workers considerably less in relative income terms than did
earlier, milder expansions--but again, more than the current almost-jobless
economic upswing under Bush.
Gil



 --
Michael Perelman
Economics Department
California State University
Chico, CA 95929
Tel. 530-898-5321
E-Mail [EMAIL PROTECTED]


Re: insurance question

2003-10-27 Thread Gil Skillman
Sitting here just south of the insurance capital of the US, I figured I
should step up on this.  Tell me more, Michael.  What type of
insurance?  Which nation(s)?  For starters, there's The Historian and the
Business of Insurance, edited by O. Westall, specific to insurance in
Great Britain, and Viviana Zelizer, Morals and Markets:  The development
of life insurance in the US Gil

Does anybody know of a nice thumbnail history of insurance?
--
Michael Perelman
Economics Department
California State University
Chico, CA 95929
Tel. 530-898-5321
E-Mail [EMAIL PROTECTED]


Re: Sad Story

2003-08-27 Thread Gil Skillman
I think it was John Marshall who said the power to tax is the power to
destroy.  The same can be said for regulation.  In fact, taxation and
regulation are better than abolition and confiscation.  First, like a frog
in boiling water, creeping taxation and regulation create less resistance
than outright abolition and confiscation, so you will be more
successful.  Second, confiscation requires an assumption of responsibility
to perform the service confiscated, and with responsibility comes failure
and criticism.  Therefore, you are better off regulating and taxing, which
allows you to criticize instead of being criticized.
Further, your nitpicking disagreements with me avoid the point --
ideologically, modern liberalism is in agreement with the fundamental
policy prescriptions of the Communist Manifesto, so Justin's daughter is
correct.  The fact that policy implementation does not entirely reflect
the lliberal wish list does not change that fact.
By David Shemano's reasoning, not only are taxation, regulation and income
redistribution tantamount to abolition of private property and
centralization of economic power in the hands of the state, (the claim of
his previous post), but these forms are tactically superior methods of
abolition and centralization because fewer people oppose them.  Thus
modern liberalism is functionally equivalent to communism.
This assessment is reinforced by a passage from his subsequent post:

For the third time, my serious point, which no one has refuted, let alone
disagreed with, is that the modern liberal sees nothing fundamentally
contentious about the policy prescriptions of the Communist Manifesto. The
modern liberal may disagree at the margin, or have concerns about
practicality, but there is no philosophical opposition.
You must agree, then, David, that the following are the formulations of a
de facto communist.  Right?
To prohibit the use of certain poisonous substances or to require special
precautions in their use, to limit working hours or to require certain
sanitary arrangements, is fully compatible with the preservation of
competition.  The only question here is whether in the particular instance
the advantages gained are greater than the social costs which they
impose.  Nor is the preservation of competition incompatible with an
extensive system of social services
There is no reason why in a society which has reached the general level of
wealth which ours has attained the first kind of security [i.e., that
against severe physical privation] should not be guaranteed to all without
endangering general freedom.  There are difficult questions about the
precise standard which should thus be assured...but there can be no doubt
that some minimum of food, shelter, and clothing, sufficient to preserve
health and the capacity to work, can be assured to everybody...Nor is there
any reason why the state should not assist the individuals in providing for
those common hazards of life against which, because of their uncertainty,
few individuals can make adequate provision.
There is, finally, the supremely important problem of combating general
fluctuations of economic activity and the recurrent waves of large-scale
unemployment which accompany them.  This is, of course, one of the gravest
and most pressing problems of our time...Many economists hope, indeed, that
the ultimate remedy be found in the field of monetary policy...
Gil Skillman


Question

2003-07-07 Thread Gil Skillman
Here's something that's been puzzling me:  it has been said that the U.S.
state governments are in their worst fiscal crisis since the 1930s.  And
yet the US is not in the middle of its worst recession since the
Depression; the Reagan-Volcker recession of the early 1980s, for example,
was much worse in terms of lost GDP and raised unemployment rates.  So what
accounts for the disproportionate severity of the state-level fiscal crisis
relative to the condition of the national economy?  Is it that the Federal
government offers so much less support for services and income supports
that states provide?  Or because state tax rates are often tied to federal
rates, which have been dramatically cut back for the rich?  Some
combination of both, and if so, with what relative weights?  Or is some
other factor involved?  And is there some book or article that spells this
out clearly? Thanks in advance--
Gil


Re: Jazz corruption.

2003-03-20 Thread Gil Skillman
For what it's worth, I think the original connection went 
corruption--brothels and speakeasies and underground clubs--jazz and 
sometimes blues.   A prominent source of corruption was Prohibition, 
during which jazz was the hot dance music of the day.  Nowadays corruption 
has no particular musical connection--cf.Providence RI or swingin' 
Bridgeport, CT.  As for rock n roll, well, different clientele.  Were he 
alive today, I suspect Boss Tweed wouldn't be into heavy metal.

Ethnomusicologically,

Gil


is there a correlation between corruption and jazz? it makes sense for 
Chicago and New Orleans...

what is the explanation of this correlation, if it exists?

why doesn't this correlation work for rock n roll, or does it? did it work 
for Baroque music, back when Bach was hot?

If the mayor stamps out corruption, does that also strike a blow against 
creative music?

enquiring minds want to know...

Jim Devine [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
  http://bellarmine.lmu.edu/~jdevinehttp://bellarmine.lmu.edu/~jdevine

JKS writes:
 [Kansas City] was one of the crookedest places on the planet, and 
accordingly a capital of jazz. Charlie Parker hailed from there, had his 
first gigs in Jay McShann's band.



Re: Bush ultimatum

2003-03-13 Thread Gil Skillman
Excerpting from Jim's post:

Bush said Sunday during his weekly radio address. This madman has every 
intention of firing back at our troops when we attack his country.
Yeah, how crazy is that?  Firing back at troops who attack your country?

Who knows, if he's *really* crazy he'll order a preemptive first strike on 
the country that's threatening him with weapons of mass destruction.

Gil



Re: labor economics text

2003-02-18 Thread Gil Skillman
Funny you should ask.  Yes there is, entitled _Labor Markets and Employment 
Relationships_, but unfortunately it won't be published until winter 
semester next academic year.

Gil



is there such a thing as a good labor economics textbook?

Jim Devine [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
  http://bellarmine.lmu.edu/~jdevinehttp://bellarmine.lmu.edu/~jdevine




Re: RE: Today's quiz

2003-02-12 Thread Gil Skillman


 Since you guys think
you are so hot, try this one:

Now I am prowling through the backyard and I am hiding under the car
and I've gotten out of everything I've gotten into so far and I eat when
I am hungry and I travel alone.


Hint, everybody:  notice how a lot of the phrase rhymes, sort of like song 
lyrics.

Virtuously,

Gil



Triplethink!

2003-02-11 Thread Gil Skillman

Ravi writes, among other things:



the background is russell's attempt to derive mathematics from logic
based on richard dedekind and gottlob frege's formalisms. but in the
attempt, russell discovered in inherent paradox arising from frege's
notion of a function. russell wrote to frege: let 'w' be the predicate:
to be a predicate that cannot be predicated of itself. can 'w' be
predicated of itself? from each answer its opposite follows. likewise
there is no class (as a totality) of those classes, which, each taken as
a totality, do not belong to themselves.

the most common example of this paradox is expessed as: consider the set
S of all sets that do not belong to (are not members of) themselves. is
S a member of itself?

russell attempted to avoid the circularity by introducing a theory of
types, but then came godel's incompleteness demonstration and the end of
the golden age of mathematics-logic ;-).



Well, perhaps not.  It's possible that Russell's attempt to derive 
mathematics from logic was doomed to fail because he got the problem 
exactly backward:  logic is best understood as a province of mathematics, 
not vice-versa.  George Spencer-Brown, who is either a genuinely brilliant 
weirdo or a brilliantly weird genius, depending on your point of view, 
established this point in his (in)famous book _Laws of Form_, in which he 
develops an arithmetic that yields, as a special case, the Boolean 
algebra that formalizes formal logic.  However, the beauty of 
Spencer-Brown's arithmetic is that it is not limited to Boolean 
algebra.  This allows him to derive from his arithmetic a third category of 
truth-value--imaginary--that is not allowed in the Boolean universe, and 
that makes it possible to sidestep the logical knots posed by 
self-referential paradoxes.  He has a neat little preface to the first 
American edition of the book in which he likens the logical problem posed 
by self-referential paradoxes to the mathematical problem posed by the 
equation x-squared plus 1 equals 0.  The solution mathematicians came to 
adopt with respect to the latter, of course, was to define imaginary 
numbers.  As Spencer-Brown points out, convincingly to me, one can do a 
similar thing, offering similarly expansive possibilities, with truth 
values of propositions.
_
___   |
Gil |  |


PS:  You'll find a lot written about Spencer-Brown's work, both positive 
and negative, if you do a web search.  It's my take that his work deserves 
neither the extreme condemnations nor the extreme commendations one finds.



Re: short vs. long-run contracts

2003-01-30 Thread Gil Skillman
If the paper Sabri refers to is the 1991 J. Ec. Theory paper by these three 
authors, the point of the Fudenberg et al. paper is a bit more specific, 
and correspondingly less silly, than Sabri's short summary would 
suggest.   Here's the abstract:

   Long-term contracts are valuable only if optimal contracting 
requires commitment to a plan today that would not
   otherwise be adopted tomorrow. The authors show that commitments 
are unnecessary and, hence, short-term
   contracts are sufficient if (1) all public information can be used 
in contracting, (2) the agents can access a bank on
   equal terms with the principal, (3) recontracting takes place with 
common knowledge about technology and
   preferences, and (4) the frontier of expected utility payoffs 
generated by the set of incentive compatible contracts is
   downward sloping at all times.

You may think that the above is not a very interesting thing to know--in 
the context of labor markets, which Fudenberg et al aren't specifically 
talking about, conditions (2) and (3) seem empirically doubtful at best-- 
but that's a different indictment than the one Sabri suggests.

Gil




Sabri writes: Did you know about Fundenberg, Holmstrom and Milgrom paper 
about long
versus short term contracts, for example? Using heavy mathematics
they prove that there is no difference between having a long
term contract and a sequence of short term contracts. That means,
don't worry, be happy, even when you have no job security. 

I haven't seen that paper, but it's prima facie absurd. The equivalent 
theory in finance says that there is no difference between having a 
long-term bond and a sequence of short-term bonds rolled over from period 
to period. (This is the expectations hypothesis, for issues such as 
treasury bills  bonds that don't differ in terms of inherent risk.) But 
it doesn't work in the real world, despite the fact that financial markets 
are 100 times more like the idealized market than labor-power markets are. 
Long-term bonds have to pay higher interest rates than the average of 
actual and expected short-term bonds to compensate financial investors for 
extra risk  illiquidity.

Of course long-term labor contracts may involve fewer pecuniary rewards 
than similar short-term contracts, because the latter have the 
non-pecuniary benefit of security. But that doesn't make them the same.

Jim Devine [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
  http://bellarmine.lmu.edu/~jdevinehttp://bellarmine.lmu.edu/~jdevine




Re: RE: Trotskyism alive and well

2003-01-09 Thread Gil Skillman
Jim writes:


are you sure it isn't the National Institute _for_ Drug Abuse?


Jim Devine [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
  http://bellarmine.lmu.edu/~jdevinehttp://bellarmine.lmu.edu/~jdevine

No, that would be *Prescott Bush's* great-granddaughter.

Gil






 -Original Message-
 From: Michael Perelman 
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]]
 Sent: Thursday, January 09, 2003 12:40 PM
 To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 Subject: [PEN-L:33685] Trotskyism alive and well


 Flash.  I do not want to reignite the debates over Trotsky, but
 the Bush administration just appointed his great granddaughter,
 Nora Volkow, to head up the national Institute on Drug Abuse.


 --

 Michael Perelman
 Economics Department
 California State University
 Chico, CA 95929

 Tel. 530-898-5321
 E-Mail [EMAIL PROTECTED]







Oh!...uh...

2002-11-06 Thread Gil Skillman
(Was: uh-oh ii)


Will the Republicans quickly overreach themselves?  How much long-term damage
can they do in two years?  Will the Democrats ever wake up?


I think Michael's questions are quite apt.  To the second question, the 
Repubs can do a great deal of damage in two years, in terms of further and 
more permanent tax cuts to the wealthy, corporate favors, further 
evisceration of environmental protections, appointment of neanderthal 
judges, etc.  And the experience of Dubya's first months in office 
indicates the likely answer to the first question--the pigs will be eagerly 
oinking at the troughs in no time.  As for the third question, perhaps the 
adverse election results will finally shock the Demos into realizing that 
they're not going to succeed by acting like pseudo-Republicans.  If they're 
going to lose anyway, they might as well lose by addressing the issues, 
providing real alternative, and potentially energizing the alienated and 
marginalized who right now see now real choices.

Granting that this were to happen--which seems uncertain at best--that's 
when the hard work begins.  I agree with Jim that the left needs to reduce 
its sniping within ranks and increase its focus on the task of grassroots 
organizing.  But I think there's an at least equally difficult task that 
has to be faced, that of crafting a set of positions that both addresses 
left concerns and is strategically viable, i.e. that Democrats can win 
with.  I think the immediate problem here is that the Repugs--amply aided 
by Democrats posing as Republicans--have so distorted the premises of the 
debate on a social issues that it has become increasingly difficult to make 
a principled case for what are, to me at least, obvious priorities (a 
national health care system, for example) without getting gunned down by 
myopic diatribes against raising taxes (and the like).  To fight against 
such divide-and-conquer strategies, the Dems have to build coalitions 
across what should have been their natural constituencies all along.  This 
means they would have to abandon their narrow, tactically-driven politics 
for broader strategic considerations based on some hard thinking about 
progressive policy alternatives.

[An idiosyncratic illustration of this point:  I just finished talking to a 
colleague in political science who teaches courses on public policy.  He 
routinely goes out and searches web sites for representative positions 
across the political spectrum on major policy issues.  He said that when he 
looked recently for policy statements on health care provision, he found 
loads and loads of stuff from the right, but almost nothing from the 
left--or what passes as the left in contemporary US politics--that was 
newer than 1996.]

Easier said than done, of course.  And I also realize the above sounds 
hopelessly reformist and middle of the road.   But the political center of 
gravity in the US has shunted so ridiculously far to the right that I think 
this is where the left in this country has to begin.

Gil


 



Re: Re: Oh!...uh...

2002-11-06 Thread Gil Skillman
In response to my comment


   To the second question, the
 Repubs can do a great deal of damage in two years, in terms of further and
 more permanent tax cuts to the wealthy, corporate favors, further
 evisceration of environmental protections, appointment of neanderthal
 judges, etc.


Carrol writes


Aren't you describing the first six years of Clinton, until Monica
hogtied him and saved social security. He could still kill a lot of
people, though, in his last two years.


Since Clinton is an example _par excellence_ of a pseudo-Republican 
Democrat, this characterization is necessarily true up to a point.  (It is 
unforgivable, for example, that Clinton went along with welfare reform, 
and, having done so, didn't at least use his considerable political clout 
to get something tangible in return)

But only up to a point.  Even Clintonesque pseudo-Democrats would most 
probably not have: repealed the estate tax or given nearly as huge a share 
of the income tax cuts to the most wealthy; repudiated the Kyoto accord; 
chopped away so relentlessly and insidiously at enforcement of 
environmental laws; invoked anti-abortionism as an excuse for not 
supporting embryo use in medical research or for removing US support for 
international family planning efforts; sicced the Feds on marijuana-using 
cancer patients in California or euthanasia-seeking terminal patients in 
Oregon; had the imperialist gall to formulate or issue a preemptive-strike 
national security policy; or used Saddam Hussein as a political excuse to 
sidestep domestic issues such as corporate malfeasance.  Clinton's judicial 
appointments (when they weren't held up by Repubs in the Senate), while 
only moderate, were at least not Pickering neanderthals.  Etc.  And let's 
not forget that Bush is only getting started.  Now that the Republicans 
control both houses of Congress, the depredations of his first two years 
are likely to get significantly worse. Expect at minimum an immediate 
effort to make the estate tax repeal permanent, e.g.

Gil



Re: raising min wage

2002-09-18 Thread Gil Skillman

Mat, for some sources, check out:

Zavodny, Madeline, Why Minimum Wage Hikes May Not Reduce Employment,
  _Economic Review_, Federal Reserve Bank of Atlanta, 1998, 83(2), pp. 
18-28.
Card and Krueger, _Myth and Measurement_ 1995  (reporting empirical studies 
in which they find that raising state-level min. wage levels was associated 
with *reduced* unemployment, but you should also check out the followup 
literature on this book.)
Rebitzer, James B; Taylor, Lowell J. The Consequences of Minimum Wage Laws: 
Some New Theoretical Ideas..
[Journal Article] Journal of Public Economics. Vol. 56 (2). p 245-55. 
February 1995.

Basic argument:  The claim that raising the minimum wage tends to reduce 
unemployment only obtains generically as a theoretical matter under 
perfectly competitive market conditions.  Given either monopsony power or 
efficiency wage-type conditions in the labor market--for which there is 
evidence--raising the minimum wage need not increase unemployment or 
inefficiency, and in fact may reduce it.  Finally, just as a footnote to 
this argument, I have a paper showing that raising the minimum wage may 
raise the number of *people* employed (and reducing hours worked per 
person) in the (typical) presence of quasi-fixed costs.  If you're 
interested I'll forward it to you directly.

Gil






I'm trying to collect a list of arguments for raising the minimum wage,
especially those that apply in 'developing' nation contexts.  Fairness,
equity, social justice arguments and/or efficiency/economic/macro
arguments are all fine.  Do people know of any good articles, books,
websites that catalogue these arguments?  Also, I'd be interested in any
newer or less well known arguments people may have. (send on or off
list--I'll collect the ones I get off list and submit them at the end).
Also I'd be interested in counter-arguments to the usual arguments
against raising minimum wages. Thanks, Mat




Re: dead economists

2002-08-26 Thread Gil Skillman

Ellen, here you go:

The ideas of economists and political philosophers, both when they are 
right and when they are wrong, are more powerful than is commonly 
understood.  Indeed the world is ruled by little else.  Practical men, who 
believe themselves to be quite exempt from any intellectual influences, are 
usually the slave of some defunct economist. Madmen in authority, who hear 
voices in the air, are distilling their frenzy from some academic scribbler 
of a few years back.

Defunctionally yours,

Gil




Anybody have handy the famous Keynes quote about
dead economists?

Ellen




Marx: Institutionalist and Pure Theorist

2002-08-08 Thread Gil Skillman

[Was:  Time for Economics]

Re this exchange:


Rob writes:it's Marx who is the institutionalist par excellence.

absolutely! I wish the folks who try to reduce Marx to neoclassical 
economics would see this.

Jim Devine [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
  http://bellarmine.lmu.edu/~jdevinehttp://bellarmine.lmu.edu/~jdevine

Obviously Marx closely studied the historical development of capitalist and 
pre-capitalist institutions.  But in his theoretical treatment of surplus 
value and its surface appearances as profit and interest, he intended his 
analysis to be as stringently institution-free as any (neo)classicist might 
desire, taking as given only the defining elements of the capitalist mode 
of production--and those, only in their purest, hypothetically most fully 
developed form.  Thus he writes in the _Resultate_:

Classical economics regards the versatility of labour-power and the 
fluidity of capital as axiomatic, and it is right to do so, since this is 
the tendency of capitalist production which ruthlessly enforces its will 
despite obstacles which are in any case largely of its own making.  At all 
events, in order to portray the laws of political economy in their purity 
we are ignoring these sources of friction...
[K.I, Appendix, Penguin ed., p.1014]

Correspondingly, in the final footnote of Ch. 5, Marx indicates his intent 
to observe the phenomenon of the formation of capital on the basis of the 
exchange of commodities in its purity... [K.I. p269]

And similarly in K.III he says

Important as the study of frictions of this kind [i.e., those which 
inhibit the equalization of wages and working hours across production 
sectors] is for any specialist work on wages, they are still accidental and 
inessential as far as the general investigation of capitalist production is 
concerned and can therefore be ignored.  In a general analysis of the 
present kind, it is assumed throughout that actual conditions correspond to 
their concept, or, and this amounts to the same thing, actual conditions 
are depicted only in so far as they express their own general type.

So far as I know, only this self-consciously and stringently 
*non*-institutionalist aspect of Marx's analysis has ever been investigated 
in neoclassical terms.





  making.




Just the facts, comrade

2002-08-04 Thread Gil Skillman

[Was:  the D of P, then abstraction vs. concreteness]

Re

 Sorry, Jim, this is not worth responding to. Your arguing in favor of 
workers democratic socialism is akin to Justin arguing in favor of market 
socialism. I am not in the business of countering one abstraction with 
another. I prefer to post those boring snippets of facts and history that 
Carrol Cox finds so completely irrelevant. When you stumble across some 
interesting data about the Cuban revolution in your peregrinations at your 
campus library, please share them with pen-l. In the meantime, I am moving 
on to other more fruitful topics

and


I am opposed to idealism, not abstractions. If we were discussing an 
abstraction like commodity, we might get somewhere--although without my 
participation. Notions, however, such as workers democratic socialism is a 
platonic ideal, more or less how Dudley Moore viewed Bo Derek in 10.

and

I am not interested in your theoretical points. Nor Justin's. That is the 
whole point. I am interested in unearthing useful data, like the fact that 
Malaysia is the number one tin producer in the world. You don't have to 
work at Columbia to glean such information, but I am afraid that vaporous 
gab about freedom, democracy and workers socialism on pen-l is a form of 
procrastination that gets in the way of useful digging.

Facts cannot of themselves establish grounds for action, personal or social 
(that's the so-called is-ought distinction in a nutshell).  To achieve 
the latter, you have to hook the facts up to some value judgment (what 
the facts also depends on a value judgment, as Jim said, but let that 
be).  Value judgments can be entirely subjective, as for instance if 
someone says that a set of facts is useful just because he/she considers 
them useful.  Alternatively, the value judgment in question can be derived 
from a given set of principles.   The latter is an abstraction.  So,  to 
insist on an exclusive focus on the facts while yet accepting facts as 
possible grounds for given actions is necessarily either to assert that 
this is so just because someone says so, or to invoke an (implicit) 
abstraction.

Of course, one always has the option of refusing to reveal or discuss the 
abstraction on which one's principled choices are made, and/or of refusing 
to discuss the abstractions that might inform the principled choices of others.

Gil








Just the facts, comrade

2002-08-04 Thread Gil Skillman

Pardon:  substitute the word ideal for every instance of the word 
abstraction in my previous post under this heading.

Abstractly,

Gil




Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: : liberalism

2002-08-01 Thread Gil Skillman

Michael writes:

  I would only add that in
these debates nobody seems to learn anything from anybody else -- at
least, you can pretty well predict what the few participants in such
debates will write.

To be sure, most postings in most PEN-L debates appear as predictable 
rehearsals of existing positions.  But for what it's worth, that doesn't 
mean that no learning is going on, despite the occasionally frustrating 
lack of anything that looks like progress or  meetings of minds. Among the 
things I've gotten from past PEN-L debates in which I've participated 
are:  finding out the range of possible arguments against a given position 
(and possible responses); references to relevant literature (particularly 
useful); and offline correspondences that often *do* end up going 
somewhere.  On the first point, for those who enter given debates seriously 
and in good faith, positions and counterpositions can be developed much 
more rapidly than via the traditional route of published exchanges in 
journals. I think that's been a real contribution of this medium, despite 
its drawbacks.

Gil 




Re: Re: Drudgery

2002-07-26 Thread Gil Skillman


The Wall Street Journal today had a front page story about women
in Mali, whose use of mechanized grinding machines has given them
time to improve their lives and become literate.

What's the point of this? Did the cotton gin enable slaves to improve 
their lives and become literate?
The application of machines to work is a complex issue, let's treat it 
that way.

As I read Michael's post, the point was that Mali women's use of mechanized 
grinding machines has given them time to improve their lives and become 
literate.  No attempt to draw more general conclusions about the social 
consequences of machinery, or to minimize the complexity of this issue, was 
made.  Indeed, in light of well-known instances of less progressive 
applications of machinery to work (e.g., the role of the cotton gin in US 
slavery), this item serves if anything to highlight the complexity of the 
issue.







Re: Re: Re: Re: Drudgery

2002-07-26 Thread Gil Skillman


OK. Labor saving devices save time and labor. This time and labor can be 
invested in other (possibly worthwhile) projects. I'm on my fifth day of 
not smoking and I'm irritable and I wanted to find out why Michael was 
telling me that the world is round.


Oh...Well, I can't help you on that one, Joanna, but you have my empathy 
and cheers on the non-smoking effort.




Re: On median voters and minority rights

2002-07-15 Thread Gil Skillman

Where I wrote

 This is way off the mark. I'm not referring to any model of voting, 
silly, neoclassical, or otherwise, other than to note that if a majority 
rule choice obtains, then the preferences of the voter with median 
preferences among the available options will generally be satisfied. This 
is obvious in the case of a vote between two choices (e.g., Pepsi vs. Coke, 
the case we were talking about), since in any majority vote the median 
voter *must* be on the winning side. Of course, with more extensive sets of 
alternatives a majority choice may not exist in the first place.


This reminds me of a former colleague of mine who objected to my use of 
the phrase the theory of comparative advantage. It's not a theory, he 
would say (and probably still does), since it's true by definition (or 
something like that). When this kind of rhetoric comes up, it's time to 
cut the cards (and count them, too), just as when someone says it's 
self-evident that...

Actually, the median voter rule _is_ a model or part of a model of 
majority voting, in that it assumes that the spectrum of voters' 
preferences is single-peaked (since otherwise the equilibrium can be unstable).

Rather, the equilibrium might not exist in the first place, as opposed to 
being unstable.  I already addressed this possibility in my final 
statement above (which Jim elides from his reply.)  But *if* a 
majority-rule equilibrium existed--that is, an unambiguous choice by the 
majority, with no cycles of vote-switching-- that choice would correspond 
to the wishes of some median voter. (On this point see Jim's own comment 
below about the practical interpretation of the meaning of the phrase 
median voter, which is the sense in which I originally used the 
term.)  Such a choice always exists (if we include the possibility of 
indifference) in the two-alternative case of Coke vs. Pepsi we were 
talking about to begin with (that's why Arrow posits the existence of at 
least *3* alternatives in his theorem).  If people are willing to make a 
choice between Pepsi and Coke, then preferences are as single-peaked as 
they need to be.

  Unlike voting under actually-existing capitalism, it's assumed that each 
 voter has equal power,  so that the median voter is exactly half-way 
 down the list of voters -- rather than corresponding to half-way down a 
 list where the preferences of some (rich) individuals are, in effect, 
 counted many times. Perhaps the median-voter model would apply better 
 with socialism than with capitalism.

Right, that's the hypothetical case we were talking about to begin with, in 
a democratic socialist regime.  We weren't talking about the 
pseudo-democracy that arises under capitalism, so I don't know why Jim 
brings this up here.



However, in line with the orthodox economist's gut-level and _a priori_ 
assumption of methodological individualism, it assumes that the only 
interaction between the voters is in the voting itself, so that the act of 
voters _talking_ to each other in order to convince each other is 
forgotten. That is, in the model, I am not allowed to convince Joanna that 
her preferences are wrong, while she can't change her preferences. This 
fits with the timelessness of the standard model: Her preferences at time 
t may not be satisfied even though they may be satisfied at time t+1, 
when the vote actually takes place.

And since I wasn't referring to any model in the first place, I wasn't 
ruling out this possibility, nor was I assuming a static or one-shot world 
in which people can't talk before voting.  Again, Jim is imposing this 
model interpretation--I wasn't.


Further, the identity of the median voter would likely change, as issues 
and preference distributions change over time, so that Gil becomes the 
median voter in time t+2.

Perhaps, and nothing I said ruled out this possibility, since I never 
suggested a world in which the identity of the median voter was frozen.

  (Horrors!) For example, if anyone decides not to vote or non-voters 
 suddenly start voting, that also would also change the nature of the 
 median voter.

Great.  Same comment as above.


  This point implies that since the entire set of voters determines who 
 the median voter is, saying the median voter decides is pretty much the 
 same as saying the majority decides, adding little or no content.

Right. I agree. It's *Jim* who's been making this big, and now evidently 
pointless by his own estimation, deal about the meaning of the phrase 
median voter.  I originally meant it in the sense he now 
suggests:  suppose the majority insisted on Pepsi when you favored 
Coke--would that be an acceptable instance of eliminating fake variety?

Joanna _per se_ is forgotten, so she no longer seems like some sort of 
dictatorial arbiter of taste. This point is reinforced if preferences are 
distributed in a single-peaked way, since there would be a large number of 
people with preferences similar to the current median voter's.

The market as a preference aggregator?

2002-07-11 Thread Gil Skillman

I agree with Justin that it's a bit of a stretch to think of the market 
as a mechanism for aggregating individual preferences into a social 
preference ordering.  It's more appropriate to think of the market as a 
mechanism of social *choice*, i.e. as something that selects *particular* 
outcomes given particular initial conditions (including individual 
preferences), rather than something that yields a social preference 
ranking based on individual preferences.  The difference, plainly put, is 
that social preference orderings have to be combined with social constraint 
sets--the set of what's socially feasible at any given historical 
moment--in order to yield actual outcomes. To treat the market as a social 
preference ordering, for example, you'd have to read social preference 
from a given pairwise comparison as society prefers the allocation that 
constitutes a market equilibrium over the one that doesn't, and if they 
both constitute market equilibria, society is indifferent.  Not clear that 
that makes any sense.

But supposing that the market is understood as a social preference 
aggregator, then I agree with Gar that Arrow's theorem would apply.  I 
understand Arrow's impossibility theorem a little differently, though--as I 
read it, it states that there is no coherent (i.e., complete and 
transitive) social preference ordering over choice sets with at least three 
alternatives that simultaneously satisfies

(U)  Universal domain:  any possible array of (coherent) individual 
preference orderings is permissible;

(P)  Pareto principle:  if all individuals (weakly) prefer any some 
allocation A over some other allocation B, then the social ordering will 
also reflect this (weak) preference;

(I)  Independence of irrelevant alternatives:  the social ranking of any 
two feasible allocations does not depend on what other allocations are 
included in the choice set;

(N)  Nondictatorship:  the social ordering will not simply reflect the 
preferences of any single individual.

The most obvious way in which the market mechanism, understood in the above 
sense, would fail as a social welfare function is with respect to (U) , 
since it will not generally be true that for any two allocations, at least 
one will constitute a market equilibrium (however that might be 
defined--perfectly competitive or otherwise, e.g.).  Fulfillment of 
condition (I) is also problematic given the possibility of income effects 
on individual choices.

On the whole, it's probably more accurate and less confusing to say that 
markets don't aggregate preferences, but rather translate given arrays of 
individual preferences into social outcomes.

Gil






people should realize that Arrow's theory is a critique of _all_ collective
decision-making mechanisms, not just democracy. It also applies to markets.
Can you think of a method of collective choice that isn't subject to the
theorem?

Um, how so? The theorem says you can't have: nondictatorship, 
independence of irrelevant alternatives, independence of order of choice, 
and, dammit, one other thing I can't recall, all together. It's a theorem 
in voting theory. These things are irrelevant to markets. Of course a 
market with dictatorship (a monopoly) is distorted, but the independence 
conditions simply don't matter to formulating a market model.




 * Universality. The voting method should provide a complete ranking 
 of all alternatives from any set of individual preference ballots.
 * Monotonicity criterion. If one set of preference ballots 
 preference ballots would lead to an an overall ranking of alternative X 
 above alternative Y and if some preference ballots are changed in such a 
 way that the only alternative that has a higher ranking on any preference 
 ballots is X, then the method should still rank X above Y.
 * Criterion of independence of irrelevant alternatives. If one set 
 of preference ballots would lead to an an overall ranking of alternative 
 X above alternative Y and if some preference ballots are changed without 
 changing the relative rank of X and Y, then the method should still rank 
 X above Y.
 * Citizen Sovereignty. Every possible ranking of alternatives can be 
 achieved from some set of individual preference ballots.
 * Non-dictatorship. There should not be one specific voter whose 
 preference ballot is always adopted

Note that voting in this context is simply a means of aggreating 
individual preference into social choice. A market in which everyone has 
the same number of dollars would be a democratic vote by this criteria - 
one in which multiple choices are made by multiple voters.

Note also that uneven distribution of money , short of severe monopoly 
does not resove the paradox, any more than uneven distribution of voting 
powers (where some people were allowed to vote multiple times) would 
resolve the paradox in any other election - short of dictatorship.





On median voters and minority rights

2002-07-11 Thread Gil Skillman

Was: variety of something or other...

Consumer advisory:  no repetitions of earlier arguments are advanced in the 
following post.

Where I wrote:

  They do?  So if Joanna were the median voter on the Pepsi vs. Coke 
 question, that would be all right with you?  
Jim responds

democracy is more than this kind of silly model of voting (the median 
voter rule). I highly recommend Lars Udehn's book (1996. The Limits of 
Public Choice: A Sociological Critique of the Economic Theory of Politics. 
London: Routledge), for a great (logical and empirical) critique of the 
whole neoclassical theory of politics.

This is way off the mark.  I'm not referring to any model of voting, 
silly, neoclassical, or otherwise, other than to note that if a  majority 
rule choice obtains, then the preferences of the voter with median 
preferences among the available options will generally be satisfied.  This 
is obvious in the case of a vote between two choices (e.g., Pepsi vs. Coke, 
the case we were talking about), since in any majority vote the median 
voter *must* be on the winning side.  Of course, with more extensive sets 
of alternatives a majority choice may not exist in the first place.

In any event, democracy does not mean simply majority rule. It also 
involves minority rights. People value rights for themselves as 
individuals, so they are willing to grant rights to others... In fact, 
they might decide to allow markets under certain circumstances.

Sure, but to the extent that minority rights are guaranteed, there is 
correspondingly less assurance that what you've called fake variety will 
be excluded, since there is no way to ensure that minorities wouldn't 
exercise their rights by demanding alternatives that the majority would 
consider trivially different.   To use one of your examples, suppose a 
minority insists that, for them, Dodges are strictly better than Plymouths; 
what then?

Also, my point was (and is) that _all_ societies put limits on what kind 
of products are available to consumers. The question is how this decision 
should be made: should it be made by a self-perpetuating state 
bureaucracy? by a class of hereditary nobles? by a self-perpetuating class 
of rich people? or should it be made democratically?

As stated in this general and abstract form, of course the latter.  But 
things get more difficult when the meaning of democracy is tested in 
concrete cases.  For example, suppose that, under the socialist regime of 
your choice, a super-majority votes to return to a capitalist 
system.  Would you regard this as an adequate warrant for re-establishing 
capitalism?

Gil




Re: markets profit maximization

2002-07-10 Thread Gil Skillman

Subject to a significant caveat, I agree with Jim's central point that cost 
minimization is a less restrictive and thus more general behavioral notion 
than profit maximization.  The caveat is that, for enterprises that don't 
attempt to maximize profits, you can't know what counts as a cost, or 
what constraints there are on attempts to minimize costs,  until you know 
what the *specific* goals of the enterprise are.  Cost minimization in 
this context thus has no more general predictive content than utility 
maximization.

Two examples:  first, compensation to labor suppliers counts as a cost to 
capitalist firms, but is presumably part of the objectives of worker-owned 
firms.  Second, although the standard (and central) implication of cost 
minimization is that contingent input demands are inversely related to 
their respective relative prices, idiosyncratic constraints (e.g., 
attention to Justice for Janitors) may prevent this inverse relationship 
from arising.  Relatedly, it would be difficult to assess the prediction 
empirically, since it may be difficult to determine what output to hold 
constant when measuring contingent input demand.

On a separate point, in theoretical terms there is a close connection 
between market competition and profit-maximizing behavior in the following 
sense:  take a bunch of potential firm owners that care about lots of 
different things (such as income risk or the power to practice 
discrimination, say) *including* income.  Obviously, in general no 
coalition of these would-be owners would unanimously agree on the single 
goal of profit maximization.  The latter is guaranteed if you add two 
components to your market story:  first, that ownership shares in firms are 
freely traded; and second, that markets for firm shares are competitive 
in the specific sense that each firm is small relative to the market for 
its shares.  Other things equal, the chances for the latter condition are 
increased if share  buyers are mobile, that is can easily get into and out 
of given asset markets and make transactions.

This may help explain, for example, why traditional capitalist firms are 
focused on a single goal such as profits while the goals of not-for-profit 
and worker-owned firms are more difficult to characterize.

Finally, re the exchange between Doug and Justin, I would think the key 
normative issue doesn't concern markets *per se* but the operation of 
certain types of markets.  Example: supposing that for-profit suppliers 
could somehow be banned (or at least discouraged, say by limiting volume of 
purchases or sales), what would be the fundamental objection against the 
activities intermediated by e-Bay?

Gil






It's useful to think about an alternative way that an individual or 
organization might make decisions. For example, a not-for-profit 
institution (such as my university) has what's called a mission 
statement (promote liberal arts education, serve Catholic faith and the 
Judeo-Christian tradition, preserve a student-centered university 
community, promote justice, etc.) This represents a very complicated set 
of goals that must be interpreted by the Board of Trustees. But it's not 
reduced to a single number like profit that's maximized. Instead, they try 
to live up to these various goals as best they can (though my experiences 
is that justice is short-changed) while _minimizing costs_. My experience 
on the budget committee is that the university expresses this kind of 
procedure as follows: they take the number of students as given, along 
with a lot of their other operations (that serve their mission statement), 
and then try to _balance the university's budget_  by raising tuition, 
finding ways to cut costs, or whatever.

This kind of cost-minimizing behavior does not contradict markets, so 
markets can exist without profit maximization. A market with no-one in it 
but multi-goaled cost minimizers would be a lot like a market where all 
participants are individual consumers (i.e., human beings) or maybe Marx's 
story of simple commodity production. It would not have the incessant 
accumulate-to-compete and compete-to-accumulate drive that a capitalist 
market has.




Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: markets profit maximization

2002-07-10 Thread Gil Skillman

The problem with this line of argument is that for every seemingly trivial 
example of product differentiation one can come up with, you can also point 
to product differences that seem trivial to the average consumer/would-be 
voter and yet are critical to some.  Some people find no difference between 
oysters and mussels; others are deeply allergic only to mussels.  Aspirin 
is fine for most people but gives some bleeding ulcers.  The sugar 
substitute aspartame is a boon to some--particularly diabetics--but causes 
migraine-like headaches in others. Personally, I've found only one shaving 
cream that doesn't make me sneeze.  Etc., etc.  In light of such cases it 
is perhaps less obvious what products count as essentially 
identical,  and maybe even less obvious that all decisions on this score 
should be made collectively.

Gil

At 01:22 PM 07/10/2002 -0700, you wrote:
Enormous amounts of resources are spent to market products that are
essentially identical.  Maybe you don't get phone calls from the phone
companies 

Say what!!! You don't think there's a difference between Pepsi and 
Coke? .not to mention the difference between Microsoft and Microsoft?

I'm shocked! Shocked!!!

Joanna





Re: variety in capitalist markets

2002-07-10 Thread Gil Skillman

Even more basically, who gets to decide what counts as adequate variety 
and what counts as fake variety?  Coke and Pepsi are apparently identical 
to Joanna but not to you.  Should she get to determine which one you drink 
(or if you drink colas at all)?

Gil


[was:RE: [PEN-L:27843] Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: markets  profit 
maximization]

the key question is whether a socialist economy would provide adequate 
variety of consumer products without fake variety. (BTW, Coke does taste 
different from Pepsi, but a Dodge is pretty much the same as a Plymouth.)

Jim Devine [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
  http://bellarmine.lmu.edu/~jdevinehttp://bellarmine.lmu.edu/~jdevine


  -Original Message-
  From: Gil Skillman 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]]
  Sent: Wednesday, July 10, 2002 1:59 PM
  To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
  Subject: [PEN-L:27843] Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Re:
  markets  profit
  maximization
 
 
  The problem with this line of argument is that for every
  seemingly trivial
  example of product differentiation one can come up with, you
  can also point
  to product differences that seem trivial to the average
  consumer/would-be
  voter and yet are critical to some.  Some people find no
  difference between
  oysters and mussels; others are deeply allergic only to
  mussels.  Aspirin
  is fine for most people but gives some bleeding ulcers.  The sugar
  substitute aspartame is a boon to some--particularly
  diabetics--but causes
  migraine-like headaches in others. Personally, I've found
  only one shaving
  cream that doesn't make me sneeze.  Etc., etc.  In light of
  such cases it
  is perhaps less obvious what products count as essentially
  identical,  and maybe even less obvious that all decisions
  on this score
  should be made collectively.
 
  Gil
 
  At 01:22 PM 07/10/2002 -0700, you wrote:
  Enormous amounts of resources are spent to market products that are
  essentially identical.  Maybe you don't get phone calls
  from the phone
  companies 
  
  Say what!!! You don't think there's a difference between
  Pepsi and
  Coke? .not to mention the difference between Microsoft
  and Microsoft?
  
  I'm shocked! Shocked!!!
  
  Joanna
  
 




Re: Re: Re: markets profit maximization

2002-07-10 Thread Gil Skillman

Seems plausible.  I should have added that an important consideration in 
figuring out what firms try to do is the agency problem, i.e. the issues 
that come with the separation of ownership and control.   Firm owners may 
want strict profit maximization, and yet their managers favor (for example) 
non-cost-minimizing plush offices with a view.

Gil


I have seen studies indicating that firms do not aim at cost minimization,
so much as labor cost minimization; and that engineers are trained to work
the same way.  Anne Carter was the first source I saw; later a Dutch
economist Boone.

  --
Michael Perelman
Economics Department
California State University
Chico, CA 95929

Tel. 530-898-5321
E-Mail [EMAIL PROTECTED]




Re: RE: Re: variety in capitalist markets

2002-07-10 Thread Gil Skillman

Jim writes


obviously, these decisions cannot be made by Joanna alone. Instead, such 
decisions -- what is adequate variety? what products are allowed? -- have 
to be made democratically by the population as a whole, and following 
democratic principles more profound than those that prevail in the U.S.

They do?  So if Joanna were the median voter on the Pepsi vs. Coke 
question, that would be all right with you?  How about if the median voter 
decided that aspirin were a good enough pain reliever...or that no 
substitutes for aspartame (or something like it) were necessary...or that 
mussels were essentially identical to oysters...or that peanuts were 
preferable to pretzels on airline flights?  These decisions are 
unobjectionable so long as they're made democratically?  Or to use 
Justin's example, suppose the (adult-consensual) pursuit of someone's 
sexual preferences depended on the use of goods that were democratically 
deemed to be unnecessary and/or undesirable?  That's appropriate?  I guess 
I'm asking if you see any place here for what in political language would 
be called minority rights,  and if so, what implications would that have 
for the scope of democratic will in the determination of product variety?

It should be pointed out that there's nothing radical at all about a 
government restricting the consumption of an item. After all, marijuana is 
illegal in the U.S. Also, governments have said a lot about what 
adequate variety is: the Pentagon, for example, has tried to veto the 
merger of military-industrial firms so as to allow the P to choose.

What's radical is subordinating the government -- and thus the market -- 
to democratic will.

Well, I agree it's *one* version of what's radical.  But certainly not 
the only.  It would also be radical to subordinate government and certain 
*types* of market activities to democratic will.

The illegalization of marijuana has proven extremely hurtful to some--minor 
users serving long prison terms, law-abiding sufferers of glaucoma or the 
effects of chemotherapy--who would perhaps not find it comforting if this 
ban were in fact the expression of democratic will (which perhaps it 
is).  I'm not sure this example is the best starting point in the case for 
extending the reach of collective decisionmaking to *all* would-be market 
transactions.

Gil




Marx and value: common ground?

2002-07-03 Thread Gil Skillman

Jim,
I'm going to sidestep for now the part of our exchange dealing with
Marx's putative association of a bourgeoise system of
ethics and the hypothetical condition that commodities
exchange at their respective values and focus on the part of our
exchange dealing with Marx's justification for invoking the latter
condition. Frankly, I don't see much distance between what you
argue on this point and what I've been saying. 
Where I wrote
But the fact remains that Marx *is* making a deductive argument here,
and he advertises it as such. He isn't simply asserting that surplus
value *can* be explained on the basis that commodities exchange at their
values, as you suggest; he's insisting that the explanation *must* be
made on this basis. This reading is nicely corroborated in the sentence
just before the passage you cite from Chapter 5: The transformation
of money into capital *has to be developed* on the basis of the immanent
laws of the exchange of commodities, in such a way that the
starting-point is the exchange of equivalents. [I, 268-9, emphasis
added]
The claim is reiterated in the
final footnote of the chapter, where Marx 
says If prices actually differ from values, we *must*
first reduce the 
former to the latter, i.e., disregard this situation as an
accidental 
one in order to observe the phenomenon of the formation of
capital on 
the basis of the exchange of commodities in its
purity... [emphasis 
added] 
Now, clearly Marx isn't saying this assumption has
to be made, must 
be imposed, to satisfy the demands of etiquette, or on
ethical grounds, 
or because somebody will break your legs if you don't; Marx
is saying 
that this conclusion is *logically* entailed by the argument
he develops 
in the chapter. And as I pointed out, this argument is
logically 
invalid. 
you respond
I read the has
to be made and the must as part of his argument that
the force of abstraction is the equivalent in political
economy of the microscopes and chemical reagents of the physical sciences
and that the force of abstraction _must_ replace both of
these (emphasis added). (I found a beaten-up old copy: this is on the
second page of the Preface to the 1st German edition.) 

So Marx was saying that we must use his method, which
involves assuming value = price, if we want to get beyond
appearances.
But isn't it true that the *justification* he gives specifically for
incorporating the value = price assumption in the application
of his method is the one he develops in Chapter 5, to which you refer
below? If so, we can focus on that justification. If not,
could you refer me to the passage in the preface to the first German
addition where he asserts that this assumption is an integral component
of his method, and explains why? 
Of course, since
he did so, we don't have to apply his method exactly. But it helps to
understand what he was doing.

The must also follows because assuming unequal
exchange didn't explain surplus-value's rise: one commodity seller's M'
 M corresponded to another's M'  M. Since the assumption of price
not equalling to value wasn't enough, there must be something else, as
special commodity (labor-power) which has a use-value of producing
surplus-value.
Doesn't this say, in other words, that price-value disparities are not of
themselves *sufficient* to account for surplus value's
rise? Does this statement say anything at all, one way or the
other, concerning whether price-value disparities might under any
conditions be *necessary* for the existence of surplus value? I'm
not asking if *you* understand them to be necessary or not, or whether
Marx proves they're unnecessary in some subsequent chapter or some other
work. I'm asking if Marx's argument in chapter 5, which you've just
summarized, speaks at all to the question of the *necessity* of
price-value disparities for the existence of surplus value, and if so,
where?
Gil



Thus sprach Marx: interpretation or characterization?

2002-07-03 Thread Gil Skillman

Where I wrote:


Gil Skillman responded:  I know he said this.  And I pointed out
that the argument on which he bases this claim is logically
invalid.

Andrew writes


First, I object to the term pointed out.

In your post, you (a) impute to me an argument I've never made, suggesting 
that you hadn't actually read what I wrote, (b) rebut that fictitious 
argument with a passage from Marx that I had just cited in support of my 
real argument,reinforcing that suggestion, and (c) categorically 
reassert Marx's conclusion while ignoring the substantive criticism I made 
concerning the logic supporting that conclusion, further reinforcing the 
suggestion.  And now you object because I use the phrase pointed out?  If 
our situations were reversed, whom would you have said had the greater 
cause for grievance?

But all right, I'll accept this criticism and claim only that I argued... 
rather than pointed out...

  What you did was (a)
*assert* logical invalidity and (b) offer an *interpretation*
under which his argument seems to be logically invalid.   So what
is at fault?  The text?  Or your interpretation?

Granting (a), I must disagree with (b). If we're using the English language 
in the same way (and I have no reason as yet to suspect that we aren't), 
and you're not raising an issue here concerning the English translation 
from the original German (and I presume that you're not, though please 
inform me otherwise), then I am offering more than simply an 
interpretation of what Marx argues, I'm offering a *characterization* of 
what he has argued, to wit:  both in the body of chapter 5 and in the final 
footnote where he recapitulates the main part of the argument in summary 
form, Marx argues that surplus value must be explained on the basis that 
commodities exchange at their respective values, on the grounds that 
price-value disparities are not of themselves *sufficient* to account for 
the existence of surplus value.  This is a characterization of what he 
*did* say in Chapter 5.  I take it you do not deny that he makes this claim 
(perhaps among others).

I also assert that nowhere in the chapter does Marx make an argument one 
way or the other as to whether price-value disparities are under any 
conditions *necessary* for the existence of surplus value.  This is a 
characterization of what he *did not* say in Chapter 5.  If you think that 
characterization is false, then you can demonstrate its falsity by pointing 
to a passage, in the English translation or the German original, in which 
Marx *does* make a representation with respect to necessity.  In that case, 
it will not be just a matter of us having differing interpretations; it 
will be that I've made a false characterization.  If, on the other hand, 
you can point to no such passage, then it cannot simply be the case that 
you have a different interpretation of what Marx wrote (again assuming 
that we're interpreting English--as opposed to Marx's argument--in the same 
way, and that the translation from German is adequate) , since in fact he 
*didn't* write anything on this point; it will be the case that you are 
putting forward a different argument than the one Marx in fact makes in 
Chapter 5.  Which is fine; perhaps we can discuss your new argument, once 
we agree on what
Marx did and did not write in the chapter.

   It seems to me,
and to basically everyone who has thought about interpretive
adequacy, that when a text seems not to make sense, the initial
presumption (as Georgia Warnke puts it) must be that the critic
has misunderstood it.

You're assuming that which you cannot possibly know, i.e. that I didn't 
make just such an initial presumption when I first advanced this argument 
ten years or so ago.  This strikes me as a presumption at least equal in 
audacity to that implicit in using the phrase pointed out rather than 
asserted.  At any rate, I have given at length, in this forum and many 
others, my grounds for now rebutting this presumption.  I doubt that those 
who have thought about issues of interpretative adequacy would deny that 
this initial assumption is indeed rebuttable by criticisms made in good 
faith, which is what I understand myself to be offering.

The value theory debate would generate more light and less heat if
Marx's critics would respect this point and practice a little
humility.  Instead of saying one has proved this error, pointed
out that claim to be logically invalid, etc., one could simply say
that  one has not yet succeeding in reading the text in such a way
that it makes sense.  That would invite others to work together to
try to read text in such a way that it does makes sense.  Of
course, one advances one's career by drawing attention to others'
insufficiencies, not by drawing attention to one's own.  But if
one's goal is to further knowledge, not advance one's career, the
less spectacular but more objective and modest way of putting
things is preferable.

If there's heat being generated here

Re: please modify your browsers

2002-07-03 Thread Gil Skillman

Yikes!  Sorry, Doug, this was a default setting. I'll see about changing 
it.  Gil




[no subject]

2002-07-01 Thread Gil Skillman

Where I wrote
There's no reason
to think that Marx understands a bourgeois system of ethics
to embrace the notion that every commodity sells at its [labor]
value, and some significant reasons to believe to the contrary.
First, Marx associates the former primarily with *formal* (as opposed to
quantitative) equality in the exchange relationship (and the bourgeoise
political economist par excellence, Adam Smith, did not insist that
commodities should exchange at their [labor]
values);
Jim responds
what Smith thought is
indeed a non sequitur, since Marx was dealing with mid-19th century
bourgeois thought (especially Ricardo, with Lockean moral overtones, as
when the businessman asserts that his property arose from his own
labor). Marx himself cited obscure thinkers such as Mercier de la
Riviere who represented the crude political economy of his
time...
Uh, Jim, Mercier de la Riviere published the work cited by Marx in 1767,
9 years before Smith published the Wealth of Nations. And the other
contemporary economists Marx cited in his Ch. 5 discussion
are Condillac (1776) and Le Trosne (1777). You were
saying...?
Anyway, my basic point still holds--there is no evident basis for
believing that Marx associated any ethical connotations, bourgeoise or
otherwise, with the condition that commodities exchange at their
respective values.
Later, where I wrote
In KI, Chapter 5,
Marx advances arguments *justifying* his subsequent assumption that
commodities exchange at their respective values. He doesn't actually
invoke this assumption analytically until the beginning of KI, Ch. 6,
[i.e., immediately after the quote above.] that is, *after* he's
justified this stipulation. The passage that Jim quotes here is the
conclusion of the argument intended to justify this assumption, not the
assumption itself. 
Jim responds
I don't think that
Marx presents his ideas that way, like some sort of deductive process. As
I've said before and for brevity's sake will not repeat at length, that
part of CAPITAL should best be seen as written like a
mystery.
I won't dispute that this part of CAPITAL reads like a mystery to you,
Jim. But the fact remains that Marx *is* making a deductive
argument here, and he advertises it as such. He isn't simply asserting
that surplus value *can* be explained on the basis that commodities
exchange at their values, as you suggest; he's insisting that the
explanation *must* be made on this basis. This reading is nicely
corroborated in the sentence just before the passage you cite from
Chapter 5:
The transformation of money into capital *has to be developed* on
the basis of the immanent laws of the exchange of commodities, in such a
way that the starting-point is the exchange of equivalents. [I,
268-9, emphasis added]
The claim is reiterated in the final footnote of the chapter, where Marx
says
If prices actually differ from values, we *must* first reduce the
former to the latter, i.e., disregard this situation as an accidental one
in order to observe the phenomenon of the formation of capital on the
basis of the exchange of commodities in its purity... [emphasis
added]
Now, clearly Marx isn't saying this assumption has to be
made, must be imposed, to satisfy the demands of etiquette,
or on ethical grounds, or because somebody will break your legs if you
don't; Marx is saying that this conclusion is *logically* entailed by the
argument he develops in the chapter. And as I pointed out, this
argument is logically invalid. 
Gil




And for what it's
worth, as he painstakingly spells out in the final 
footnote of Chapter 5, Marx justifies this assumption on the
basis that 
price-value disparities are incidental to the
existence of surplus value. The warrant he gives for this conclusion,
developed at length in the body of Chapter 5, is that price-value
disparities are not of themselves *sufficient* to account for the
existence of surplus value.

I'm quite familiar with that quotation. He doesn't see
value/price deviations as contradicting his theory of exploitation.
Instead, he ignores them as part of his mode of presentation.

One could, with exactly parallel logic, conclude that
the presence of 
oxygen in the earth's atmosphere is incidental
to the existence of human life on the planet, since it is not of itself
sufficient to account for the existence of human life...


no, that's a false analogy, since in CAPITAL volume I, Marx
shows that exploitation can exist _despite_ an assumed price/value
equality. No-one has shown that life on earth can exist despite a
hypothesized lack of oxygen. 

JD 


Thus sprach Marx

2002-07-01 Thread Gil Skillman

Where I wrote

Gil Skillman wrote:

Now, clearly Marx isn't saying this assumption [exchange of equivalent 
values] has to be made, must be imposed, to satisfy the demands of 
etiquette, or on ethical grounds, or because somebody will break your legs 
if you don't; Marx is saying that this conclusion is *logically* entailed 
by the argument he develops in the chapter.  And as I pointed out, this 
argument is logically invalid.

Andrew responds


If the conclusion is that surplus-value can arise only if commodities 
exchange at their values, it is indeed invalid.
   But this isn't what he said.

I know.  I never suggested otherwise.

  He said that exchange of equivalents must be assumed, not because 
 surplus-value cannot arise otherwise, but IN ORDER TO OBSERVE the 
 phenomenon of the formation of capital on the basis of the exchange of 
 commodities IN ITS PURITY... (my emph.)

I know he did.  I quoted this same passage (see PEN-L 27449).

  And he said that this must be the starting point of analysis because the 
 implications of the contrary assumption reduce to those of the exchange 
 of equivalent values, and thus the contrary assumption doesn't move the 
 analysis forward.

I know he said this.  And I pointed out that the argument on which he bases 
this claim is logically invalid.

Gil




Re: BLS Daily Report

2002-06-26 Thread Gil Skillman

I'm sorry to hear this.  This posting has been a reliable and informative 
aspect of PEN-L for a long time.  Thanks, Dave.

Gil

is no more.  There are apparently valid concerns here at BLS that prevent me
from forwarding it, or any part of it, on a regular basis.  I hope that it
has been of assistance to you.  This is the last message.

Dave




Re: LTV and income disparity

2002-06-25 Thread Gil Skillman

Hi, Nancy. To get right to the point, the labor theory of value
does not of itself imply a zero-sum conflict in the distribution of
social income. The reason for this is that, even if the total
potential labor expenditure in an economy is fixed, the total product of
that labor--and thus the total social income--need not be fixed, so that
there's potentially more for all. A fixed labor expenditure can
translate into progressively higher levels of total output due to, for
example, technical progress. This growth in labor productivity would be
reflected in a lower average quantity of labor embodied in each
commodity. A corollary of this is that richer rich does not of
itself imply poorer poor. Of course the latter outcome may happen
in any case, but not for reasons that have specifically to do with the
operation of Marx's theory of value. 
That said, the responses to your comment, based on the supposed
implications of supply and demand, aren't particularly
on the mark, and to the extent they are, they beg the question. Off
the mark, because an increase in demand, understood in either a
micro or a macro sense, need not translate into
an increase in total income. For example, an increased demand for
vintage coins won't increase social income as standardly measured; and an
increase in *aggregate* demand may only increase the price level without
increasing *real* income. Question-begging, because the answer
doesn't explain what led to an increase in demand in the first
place. 
For what it's worth,
Gil

I am on
another listserve, ANTHRO-L, which sometimes turns political -- there are
a few good marxist anthropologists on it. a few months ago, i was
discussing the gap between the rich and the poor in terms of the labor
theory of value. to me, it seems self-evident that the richer the rich
get, the poorer the poor will get. Since value is based on labor-power,
there can be only a finite amount of it in the world, whether it is
stored up as capital or circulating as money. 
There were many and great objections to my statement -- too involved to
summarize here, but mainly centered around the idea that value is created
by the market dynamic of supply and demand -- the more demand, the more
value; the less demand, the less value. Suffice it to say that I didn't
know enough about the labor theory of value to be able to meet all their
arguments. In the meantime, I have brushed up on the idea of the
fetishism of commodities, and do understand a little bit more. 
but i wondered if anyone of the many who know more about marxism would be
willing to comment: does the LTV show that the rich and the poor are
directly connected in that the more the rich get, the less the poor get?
If so, why? If not, why not? 
thanking you all in advance for any enlightenment you might bring to the
question, 
nancy brumback 
new college of california 
766 valencia st. 
san francisco, CA 94110 
415-437-3405 
[EMAIL PROTECTED]



Re: RE: Re: RE: Brenner

2002-06-14 Thread Gil Skillman

Re this portion of the recent exchange on Brenner between Justin and
Jim:
(Justin:)
When I say Marx officially regards certan phenomena as
surface, I means that when he talks value theory. he suggests that thesea
re in need of value theoretical explanation. As Gil Skillman has (to my
mind but not yours) shown, there is another strain in Marx that does not
require invocation of value theory, what Gil calls historical materialist
explanation. ... 

(Jim:)
I still wonder about
this word official. If anyone is pushing the idea of
official views, it's Gil, since he seems to want us to apply
only the official methodology of the hegemonic school of economics, i.e.,
the methodological individualism of neoclassical economics (including
game theory). (For something to be official, there has to be
an officialdom. The NC economics hierarchy is the most obvious
officialdom among economists, rewarding those who toe the line (use the
methodology, agree with the main propositions) with publication and
tenure and punish those who disagree.) Gil, please correct me if I'm
wrong in my impression of your methodological slant. 

With respect to Justin's comment, I've actually argued something
stronger: not only is value theory *unnecessary* to ground any of
Marx's valid substantive claims (concerning, e.g., the systemic basis for
exploitation, or the role of labor power commodification, with or without
the subsumption of labor under capital, in the process of capitalist
exploitation), but Marx's use of value theory (in K.I, in particular) is
in fact *counterproductive* to his explicit analytical purposes, since it
obscures both the systemic basis of capitalist exploitation and the
significance of the distinction between labor power and labor in the
process of capitalist exploitation. 
I should quickly add that these are *hindsight* judgments--that is, they
only become clear once you stand in the analytical terrain Marx first
established using his value theory. So, for example, I'm not
denying that *Marx* found it necessary to use value theory as a
foundation to achieve his valid insights. 

With respect to Jim's comment, I've never, ever claimed any sort of
unique validity for the analytical methodology of mainstream economics
(featuring, I suppose, the notions of individual optimization and
equilibrium or strategic consistency). I wonder if you could point
to any published or unpublished statement of mine, Jim, that indicates
the contrary. Rather I've argued against the reverse fetish,
involving the categorical rejection of theoretical results achieved
within this framework on the ground that it is un or
non or anti Marxist. In this connection I
would note that, so far as I can tell, no analytical claim of Marx's in
_Capital_ depends on the premise that people don't optimize; or take
market prices as given; or freely move among potential exchange partners;
or other negations of putatively neoclassical
assumptions. To the contrary, Marx sometimes explicitly *embraces*
these conditions within the scope of his argument. 

Jim comments further
When Marx says
that surface phenomena are in need of value-theoretic
explanation (which is, in my view, an accurate portrayal of his
views), he's saying that we can't simply look at supply and demand and
other microphenomena (prices, individual profits, etc.) We have to look
at them in the context set by the capitalist mode of production. In
modern lingo, he's saying we have to look at the macrofoundations of
microeconomics. If you look at just the prices, individual profits,
supply  demand, etc., as NC economists do, you end up suffering from
commodity fetishism.

I don't follow this argument. On one hand, I don't see the basis
for the claim that value-theoretic explanation is tantamount
to providing the macrofoundations of microeconomics.
Why is it *necessary* to invoke Marx's value categories in order to
establish such foundations? On the other hand, NC economists
*don't* just look at the prices, individual profits, supply 
demand, any more than Marx does; these entities and magnitudes are
grounded in their analytical fundamentals, just as Marx claims to ground
these phenomena in value terms. 

Gil



Re: Inheritance tax is Marxist

2002-06-13 Thread Gil Skillman



Democratic foes of repeal advocate the redistribution of wealth, ``an
old Marxist idea that has been rejected everywhere in the world but
still has appeal'' in the United States, Sen. Phil Gramm, R-Texas, said
Tuesday as debate began.

Good old Gramm, past master in the uses of the Big Lie in political 
rhetoric.  Gramm's comment is, of course, stunningly and redundantly 
contrary to fact, most obviously because most other developed countries 
engage in much more redistribution of wealth than the US (though I was 
distressed to learn that Italy has repealed its inheritance tax).  Second, 
redistribution of wealth is not only not a specifically Marxist idea 
(much too timid a social change from a Marxist standpoint), but it's one 
that obviously precedes Marx (e.g., an article in the most recent American 
Prospect notes that pre-Marxist James Madison wrote in favor of progressive 
redistribution to combat social stratification).

Propagandist Gramm has also been flogging the death tax chestnut, even 
arguing the immorality of taxing death, oblivious to the fact that 
although 100% of the U.S. population (eventually) die, only 2% pay the 
inheritance tax.

And yet Democrats largely cede the moral high ground to reactionary 
ideologues like Gramm by not challenging such absurd claims.

Gil




Re: RE: P.S.

2002-05-12 Thread Gil Skillman


When I said...

 For what it's worth, mainstream theory suggests another possible
explanation for positive interest rates besides time (and possibly risk)
preference, although it is not one that is typically emphasized:  interest
represents a scarcity rent for capital.  This latter explanation is both
plausible and consistent with the now much-reinforced empirical finding of
interest-inelastic savings.

Jim wrote:

This may be a much-reinforced empirical finding, it is not treated as such
by the intermediate macro textbooks, at least not all of them. There's one I
read -- was it Abel  Bernanke? -- that (1) said that saving is
interest-inelastic and then (2) consistently drew the supply of saving as
upward-sloping, matching the downward slope of the demand for saving curve
(i.e., investment demand). They did the same for the supply of labor[power]
curve.


Yes, and quite a surprise, isn't it, that textbooks are slow in catching up 
with reality?  Hall  Taylor is the intermediate macro text I have on hand, 
and it notes that the evidence favors a 0-elasticity savings supply 
function.  Since that edition the results of a multi-country study was 
published, I believe in Review of Economics  Statistics, that strongly 
corroborated this funding.


BTW, the inelastic saving supply curve fits with Keynes' idea that interest
and profits represent quasi-rents, i.e., temporary scarcity rents. Of
course, that doesn't quite explain why savings never lose their scarcity
value, so that the interest rate zooms to zero.

I agree, and take the latter sentence as a legitimate critical comment on 
the former. To label interest or profit as quasi-rents is to posit that in 
the long run,  these returns can be expected to disappear--or, speaking 
more generally, fall to their reservation or opportunity cost 
levels.  This is clearly what Adam Smith had in mind when he spoke of the 
natural rate of profit, and argued the actual profit rates would tend 
toward their respective natural levels.  But this need not be the case, 
as Marx's analysis in KI, Ch. 25 illustrates.

He adds: I should have said that mainstream theory suggests another
possible explanation for positive interest rates that, like explanations
based on time or risk preferences, is consistent with the operation of
competitive and complete markets.  Of course nothing ensures that the
relevant markets in which interest rates arise have these nice properties.
Leaving that restriction aside, mainstream theory could adduce explanations
based on market power (e.g., collusive rate-setting) or contractual
imperfections (e.g., efficiency interest rates, as in the Stiglitz/Weiss
model of credit rationing).

I don't think that these latter explanations that orthodox theory could
adduce help us with the question at hand. They are microeconomic
explanations, that don't explain the general (macro) rate of interest,
perhaps as measured by the yield on a minimum-risk corporate bond (or by an
average of empirically-existing interest rates). Rather, they explain
differences of interest rates between different lenders or markets.

Maybe, but not necessarily, so long as most markets for interest-bearing 
assets exhibit these features in some degree.  A parallel case is the 
relationship between the wage curve ( a micro notion) and the Phillips 
curve (macro) discussed by Blanchard and Katz.

If I understand Marx's theory correctly, it explains the general interest
rate within the framework of the supply of and demand for loanable funds,
though of course it adds some twists by putting this market into a societal
context (while not assuming full employment as the original theories of
loanable funds did). Interest is one piece of the surplus-value, so that if
workers aren't dominated in society and thus exploited, there is no
production available with which to pay interest. The concept of interest
arises because of the division of labor that has developed historically
between industrial capital and money-lending (banking) capital. The
industrial capitalists are willing to share some of the surplus-value that
they've pumped from their workers with the banking capitalists because the
latter provide the service of financial intermediation. (Marx saw that
service as unproductive, but that's another issue, one I won't touch.) In
this view, the long-run equilibrium interest rate -- a.k.a. the natural
rate of interest of Wicksell _et al_ -- would depend on the relative
institutional power of industrial capital and banking capital and would thus
change between historical eras.

This is consistent with a (bilateral) monopoly story, unless Marx was 
insisting that the relative institutional power struggles took place 
entirely at the collective, political level.

Gil




JD




Revelation

2002-05-12 Thread Gil Skillman




  Presley is also the world's expert on the economics of Dennis
Robertson.

===

Who is Dennis Robertson?

Ian

It's time to end the masquerade.  *I* am Dennis Robertson, and I would like 
to state for the record that Presley has gotten it all wrong.  Also, I'd 
like to know M. Perelman's qualifications as a critic of my prose stylings.

Harrumph,

Dennis Gil Skillman Robertson




Re: pop quiz time

2002-05-10 Thread Gil Skillman

It sounds like Keynes, except he would have criticized (neo)classical 
economics rather than mainstream economists; the latter phrasing sounds 
more recent.  For what it's worth, mainstream theory suggests another 
possible explanation for positive interest rates besides time (and possibly 
risk) preference, although it is not one that is typically 
emphasized:  interest represents a scarcity rent for capital.  This latter 
explanation is both plausible and consistent with the now much-reinforced 
empirical finding of interest-inelastic savings.  Gil



[who said it?]

...confusion forces practical economists to explain the determination of
interest by opportunity cost reasoning - a particular rate of interest
being set by the 'pure' rate yielded by the riskless government bonds,
with inflation, risk, and administrative cost premia added. But there is
no watertight justification for the perpetual existence of this 'pure'
rate. Interest exists because it is there; it is still held up by its own
theoretical bootstraps. The failure of mainstream economics to explain
adequately the existence of interest betrays the fact that it is merely a
theoretical concept with no true basis in reality. It is a figment of our
collective imaginations.




P.S.

2002-05-10 Thread Gil Skillman

Sorry, that previous answer to Ian's pop quiz was too truncated.  I should 
have said that mainstream theory suggests another possible explanation for 
positive interest rates that, like explanations based on time or risk 
preferences, is consistent with the operation of competitive and complete 
markets.  Of course nothing ensures that the relevant markets in which 
interest rates arise have these nice properties.  Leaving that 
restriction aside, mainstream theory could adduce explanations based on 
market power (e.g., collusive rate-setting) or contractual imperfections 
(e.g., efficiency interest rates, as in the Stiglitz/Weiss model of 
credit rationing).  Gil


It sounds like Keynes, except he would have criticized (neo)classical 
economics rather than mainstream economists; the latter phrasing sounds 
more recent.  For what it's worth, mainstream theory suggests another 
possible explanation for positive interest rates besides time (and 
possibly risk) preference, although it is not one that is typically 
emphasized:  interest represents a scarcity rent for capital.  This latter 
explanation is both plausible and consistent with the now much-reinforced 
empirical finding of interest-inelastic savings.  Gil



[who said it?]

...confusion forces practical economists to explain the determination of
interest by opportunity cost reasoning - a particular rate of interest
being set by the 'pure' rate yielded by the riskless government bonds,
with inflation, risk, and administrative cost premia added. But there is
no watertight justification for the perpetual existence of this 'pure'
rate. Interest exists because it is there; it is still held up by its own
theoretical bootstraps. The failure of mainstream economics to explain
adequately the existence of interest betrays the fact that it is merely a
theoretical concept with no true basis in reality. It is a figment of our
collective imaginations.





The uses of game theory

2002-04-25 Thread Gil Skillman


A while back someone asked about the usefulness of game theory.  Below is a 
site that should, um, restore your faith in the power of this analytical 
framework.  Amazing! Gil

http://207.67.219.101/objective/gametheory.html




Re: Nash equilibrium's relevance

2002-04-11 Thread Gil Skillman

Jim writes

In the article below, Varian explains Nash equilibrium. As an expert in game
theory, he points out that it's not a realistic prediction of how people
play most actual real-world games.

If so, why is Nash's equilibrium used for all sorts of things, such as
electricity regulation? (If I remember, the movie mentioned that.) Is it
that Nash equilibrium is basically a normative concept and that it's applied
to improve the efficiency of electricity regulation (or what not) rather
than to be an accurate description of the way the world works?

My take on this is that Nash equilibrium or one of its refinements--e.g. 
the notion of perfect equilibrium developed by Nash's co-Nobelist 
Selten--provides a plausible reference point, or starting point, for 
thinking coherently about social outcomes in which strategic considerations 
may arise.  Although it's doubtful that people are unboundedly 
(individually) rational, as the theory requires, it's at least plausible 
that their behavior *approximates* this ideal in many settings.  Certain 
economic experiments have shown, for example, that outcomes approach the 
Nash prediction as people become more familiar with the game being 
played.  And for what it's worth, the global overfishing problem (see the 
front-page NYTimes article from a day or so ago) seems in many respects 
like a classic instance of a suboptimal outcome to a prisoners' 
dilemma-style problem.

Granting that predictions of the simple Nash equilibrium are often not 
realized in practice, though, it doesn't follow that Nash's basic notion of 
equilibrium in a noncooperative setting--i.e., each actor seeks to realize 
some objective given that all other players are attempting to seek their 
respective objectives--is faulty.  It may just need tweaking.  One 
possibility is to abandon the notion of selfish preferences, as eg. Mathew 
Rabin has done by introducing fairness considerations into individual 
objective functions.  Another possibility is to introduce bounded 
rationality in decisionmaking (as opposed to imperfect or incomplete 
information, which  has already been done--showing how to deal with the 
latter was part of co-Nobelist Harsanyi's contribution).

Gil







(BTW, it seems quite a major theme in orthodox economics -- which puts a lot
of value on a strong distinction between normative and positive
economics -- that normative and positive matters are all mixed up in an
ideologically convenient way. For example, the famous Walrasian
(Arrow-Debreu) model is really a normative model, since it is based on all
sorts of unrealistic assumptions, including the existence of God (the
Auctioneer). But then that model is applied to describe -- and worse,
prescribe -- real-world matters.)

--

New York TIMES/April 11, 2002

What, Exactly, Was on John Nash's Beautiful Mind?

By HAL R. VARIAN

So what did John Nash actually do? Viewers of the Oscar-winning film A
Beautiful Mind might come away thinking he devised a new strategy to pick
up girls.

Mr. Nash's contribution was far more important than the somewhat contrived
analysis about whether or not to approach the most beautiful girl in the
bar.
What he discovered was a way to predict the outcome of virtually any kind of
strategic interaction. Today, the idea of a Nash equilibrium is a central
concept in game theory.

Modern game theory was developed by the great mathematician John von Neumann
in the mid-1940's. His goal was to understand the general logic of strategic
interaction, from military battles to price wars.

Von Neumann, working with the economist Oscar Morgenstern, established a
general way to represent games mathematically and offered a systematic
treatment of games in which the players' interests were diametrically
opposed. Games of this sort - zero-sum games - are common in sporting events
and parlor games.

But most games of interest to economists are non-zero sum. When one person
engages in voluntary trade with another, both are typically made better off.
Although von Neumann and Morgenstern tried to analyze games of this sort,
their analysis was not as satisfactory as that of the zero-sum games.
Furthermore, the tools they used to analyze these two classes of games were
completely different.

Mr. Nash came up with a much better way to look at non-zero-sum games. His
method also had the advantage that it was equivalent to the von
Neumann-Morgenstern analysis if the game happened to be zero sum.

What Mr. Nash recognized was that in any sort of strategic interaction, the
best choice for any single player depends critically on his beliefs about
what the other players might do. Mr. Nash proposed that we look for outcomes
where each player is making an optimal choice, given the choices the other
players are making. This is what is now known as a Nash equilibrium.

At a Nash equilibrium, it is reasonable for each player to believe that all
other players are playing optimally - since these beliefs are actually

Re: RE: Re: Re: RE: Nash, Harsanyi and Selten

2002-03-22 Thread Gil Skillman


That would be *quadrature* of the circle (constructing a line equal in
length to the circumference of any given circle).  Squaring circles is
impossible.

I once circled a square, though (warily).   

Gil




Re: game theory

2002-03-21 Thread Gil Skillman

Jim writes

Why is it that game theory focuses only on the 2x2 matrix type of game (or
the N-person game)? 

(it doesn't)

or am I wrong to think that it is so one-tracked in its
mind? 

In a word, yes.  The 2X2 games are primarily just used for illustrative
purposes.




Re: RE: Re: game theory

2002-03-21 Thread Gil Skillman

Jim writes

yes, but do three- or four-person games ever produce useful results? are
other game metaphors used besides I move and you move of the standard
prisoner's dilemma box?  

Re the first question: for the most part, analyses of games that
generically feature several players are not limited to the three- or
four-person case.  Re the second question, yes, abundantly. Game theory
has provided the microfoundation for much, maybe most, of modern
microeconomics, and as such has been developed way, way beyond its simple
roots.

I know about games such as the dollar auction, which probably can be
modelled using standard game-theory tools, but it's hardly ever mentioned
outside of books such as Poundstone's PRISONER'S DILEMMA. That book also
mentions various other games, including one invented by John Nash that
involved movement of pieces on boards divided into hexagonal spaces. (It was
sold commercially for awhile and seems the basis of Avalon-Hill-type war
games.) Are any of these various non-standard games given any kind of
attention? How about, as I mentioned in my original missive in this thread,
card games such as solitaire?


Am I right to say that game theorists concentrate only on the simplest
possible games, because those are the easiest to analyze? 

In general, no.  They may start with the simplest cases, but usually extend
the results to the most general case possible.  For example, the analysis
of strategic bargaining models started with the bilateral, 2-player case,
but now has been extended to the n-player case.  Grab any recent graduate
text on game theory, Jim (Fudenberg and Tirole, and Myerson, are two good
ones), you'll see how general the development has been.

Gil




Re: Reply to Skiilman and RV on Roemer

2002-03-20 Thread Gil Skillman

Miychi writes

In debate between Skilllaman and RV on Roemer, It is unclear that whether
exploitaion is ³forced² or²voluntary². In reality, based upon sepatation
from
means of production, workers are ³ forced² to work at least to maintain
their physical condition. This unclearness result from, I think, Roemer¹s
idea of coupon ownership of firms by ³citizen²(what is ³citizen²?). And this
unclearness lead to Roemer¹s(and skillman and RV?) ³market socialism without
revolutionary action. In order that revolutionary act emerges, opression
must be presumed. And in order that oppression emerges, capital must have
compelling power to people to work. Roemer(and skillman and RV?)was caught
in problem of ownership and can¹t see oppresionin exploitaion

Capitalist exploitation involves, at the very least, coercion at the level
of *class*, in the sense that the representative worker has no choice but
to perform surplus labor for a capitalist (whether paid in the form of
profit or interest on a production loan) or suffer a loss in well-being,
the size of the loss depending on the existing distribution of means of
production. (For example, if workers were totally expropriated, which Marx
takes as the relevant case in K.I, a worker must choose between producing
surplus labor for a capitalist or starving.)  Justin develops this idea of
class-level exploitation in an Economics  Philosophy article from several
years ago.   Since this point is entirely consistent with Roemer's
analysis, there's no unclearness about the connection of exploitation to
separation [of workers] from the means of production--indeed, that's the
basic idea behind DOPA.  The reason that RV haven't focused on this is
because it's not a point of contention.

Gil




Re: Nash, Harsanyi and Selten

2002-03-20 Thread Gil Skillman

In response to this comment from me

Relatedly, a generic insight provided by
Nash noncooperative equilibrium is that the interactions of rational
self-interested actors need not--under some conditions, probably
won't--lead to socially rational outcomes.

Charles writes

CB: This seems to rather directly contradict Adam Smith, doesn't it ? Isn't 
this the opposite of the fundamental classical proposition put forth by Adam 
Smith on The Invisible Hand and all that ?


I'd say rather that the game-theoretic results I mentioned speak more to
the Adam Smith of Book 5 than of Book 1 of Wealth of Nations.  

Gil




Re: Re: Nobel Prize

2002-03-20 Thread Gil Skillman


No, noncommunication is a condition of game theory. Co-cnspirators are 
treated as a single actor for purposes of the game. jks

Strictly speaking, cooperative game theory doesn't address the possibility
of communication one way or another, since strategies and information sets
aren't model in that framework.  Noncooperative games, in the modern
definition, are simply games in which strategic choices are spelled out and
analyzed explicitly.  These could include communication.  

Gil




Re: bounced from Mike Yates

2002-03-19 Thread Gil Skillman

Michael, here are two recent references:

Daron Acemoglu and Jaume Ventura, The World Income Distribution, NBER
Working Paper 8083, January 2001.  Acemoglu and Ventura develop and offer
evidence for a new neoclassically-based theory, but give references for the
standard neoclassical account.

Matthew Higgins  and Jeffrey Williamson, Explaining Inequality the World
Round: Cohort Size, Kuznets Curves, and Openness, NBER Working Paper 7224,
July 1999

There is also a literature, although I can't pull up any references at the
moment, on the failure of the convergence hypothesis, that involves
adding additional factors--like social capital and human capital--to the
(problematic, as we know) aggregate production function for national
economies.  You could pull that off of EconLit.

Gil





I am working on a book to be titled Naming the System: Inequality and
Labor in the Global Economy.  I am working on a chapter which aims to
lay out the neoclassical thoery's answers to such questions as why there

is such a large gap between the GDPs per capita in rich and poor
countries and why this gap is getting larger; why there is so much
inequality in income, wealth, etc in every capitalist country; why most
people have such crappy jobs worldwide; why there are crises; why there
is so much unemployment and underemployment; etc.  If anyone has any
tips as to how I should present the neoclassical answers, for a general
audience, I would appreciate hearing from you.  You can reply to
[EMAIL PROTECTED] or to the list.  I check the archives every day.

Michael Yates




--

Michael Perelman
Economics Department
California State University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Chico, CA 95929
530-898-5321
fax 530-898-5901





Re: Roemer and Exploitation

2002-03-19 Thread Gil Skillman

I look forward to addressing Roberto's new set of comments on this thread
after reading them carefully.  But insofar as the exchange is already
lengthy, involved, and possibly of limited general interest, I'll follow
through on my earlier promise by responding offline.  Gil

Following a thread of discussion on Roemer's theory of exploitation. In 
reply to G. Skillman's comments (PEN-L, 11-3, 20:44).

Let us start with the points of agreement:

1) Differential Ownership of Productive Assets (DOPA) is certainly necessary 
to have exploitation, at least in Roemer's model. (And I say it in my paper.) 

2) If profits persist, then given Roemer's Fundamental Marxian Theorem, 
exploitation persists, too. This is not under discussion.

Now back to the differences:

SKILLMAN WRITES: despite some (certainly regrettable) *verbal* carelessness 
by Roemer in explaining the meaning of his formal conclusions, the latter 
show that differential ownership of *scarce* productive assets (DOSPA) is 
the necessary (and, subject to a caveat mentioned in my earlier post, 
sufficient) basis for capitalist exploitation, not simply differential 
ownership of said assets (DOPA).


RV: I don't think it is a mere matter of verbal carelessness. Roemer's 
research program is aimed at finding a more general definition of 
exploitation based on DOPA (and not DOSPA, see Chapter 7 of GTEC) such that 
Marx's surplus labour definition is redundant. (The emphasis on DOPA is 
indirectly confirmed by Roemer's post-GTEC studies based on equality of 
opportunity etc.) In order to do this he has to prove that DOPA and 
exploitation are equivalent, i.e. DOPA is necessary and sufficient for 
exploitation to occur. 
If we agree that this is not the case and that his careless verbal claims 
are not well-grounded, this is perfect for me, then we have to re-consider 
the careless verbal claims that his DOPA-based definition of exploitation 
substitutes Marx's. 

In any case, as regards DOSPA:

(a) it does not do the same job as DOPA: one has to provide a 'scarcity' 
mechanism through which profits, and therefore exploitation, are made 
persistent. But then Roemer's normative claim regarding the role of 
inequality in ownership must be changed accordingly, in order to take this 
other mechanism into account. This is not a neutral change because in 
principle the mechanism guaranteeing persistence would be normatively as 
relevant as the initial DOPA, and therefore the claim that inequalities in 
endowments are the only relevant thing would need to be qualified. Indeed, 
the scarcity qualifier becomes the positively and normatively interesting 
thing.

(b) Roemer's models are NOT static models, they are dynamic models analysed 
in a steady state and under extremely stringent assumptions. Hence, if DOSPA 
is the relevant condition, then one must conclude that GTEC does not provide 
a general theory of persistent exploitation. Indeed scarcity is not 
discussed at all, and no mechanism guaranteeing persistence is provided in 
GTEC, nor can it be inferred from Roemer's models. As noted below, arguably 
no such a mechanism can be introduced in Roemer's models without 
substantively changing Roemer's research program and methodology.

In particular:

SKILLMAN quotes Roemer (p. 9) Suppose, now, there is a limited stock of 
seed corn.  By 'limited' I mean there is not enough to employ the whole 
population in the [capital-intensive] technique.  And also Roemer (p. 10) 
It is important to notice that for this example to work [i.e., to exhibit 
exploitation] there must be an industrial reserve army--that is, more 
producers available than seed corn to employ them. *For if, instead, seed 
corn were in excess relative to the labor supply, then the work week in the 
[capital-intensive] technique would be bid down to three days* [thereby 
eliminating exploitation in this example]. (Emphasis added) And Roemer (p. 
11) Indeed, the following are requirements for this example to work: (1) a 
class of propertyless producers [that's differential ownership], *in 
relative abundance to the supply of capital which can employ them* [that's 
capital scarcity]  (emphasis added). ALSO similar explicit caveats in _Value 
Exploitation and Class_ (pp !
18-19) and _Free to Lose_. (p. 23)  

RV: I like these quotations very much. Assume, for the sake of the argument, 
that they support Skillman's claim that Roemer had DOSPA rather than DOPA in 
mind. Then one has to conclude that Roemer is a very bad model builder given 
that (a) in NO MODEL of GTEC disequilibrium in the labour market is allowed; 
(b) more strongly, given the subsistence constraint, disequilibrium in the 
labour market (unemployment) simply *cannot* be easily included in Roemer's 
model. 

Thus Roemer has been again regrettably careless in making his 
methodological points regarding walrasian models: if an industrial reserve 
army is fundamental to have persistent exploitation, how can we reconcile 
disequilibrium in 

Nash, Harsanyi and Selten

2002-03-19 Thread Gil Skillman

[Was:  Re: Nobel prize]

In response to this comment by Justin,

 But Nash  Harsanyi made real contributions to economics.

Jim writes

you think? As far as I know, there's no reason to think that the Nash
equilibrium applies in reality (and I'm not familiar enough with Harsanyi's
work to say anything). It's just one possible result. The main contribution
of game theory in general seems to be as a way to describe possible
conflictual or cooperative situations, rather than to predict real-world
results in a consistent way. (It's a little like all those 2x2 conceptual
boxes that litter sociology books.) But since I'm no expert on game theory,
I am willing to be corrected.

First, there are *two* Nash equilibria (something that the recent film on
Nash bollixes considerably, in addition to misrepresenting the main one),
one for noncooperative games and a bargaining solution for certain types
of cooperative games.  Both have served as foundations for the application
of game theory to (particularly mainstream) economics, but Nash's
noncooperative solution has probably had the greatest impact, because it
allowed generalization of noncooperative game analysis beyond the generally
unrealistic focus on *zero-sum* games in Von Neumann  Morgenstern's
classic from the previous decade. In fact, I don't think it's too much to
say that game theory has revolutionized microeconomics, thanks in part to
the refinements introduced by Harsanyi (especially concerning games of
incomplete information) and Selten (who made it possible to deal with
issues of credible strategies in contexts where strategic interactions
are played out over time).  

Applicability of Nash equilibrium to real-world concerns, particularly
those that matter to progressive economists, is necessarily a more
controversial issue.  On one hand, issues of conflict and strategic
interaction of the general sort addressed by Nash are central to Marxian
and institutionalist economics.  Relatedly, a generic insight provided by
Nash noncooperative equilibrium is that the interactions of rational
self-interested actors need not--under some conditions, probably
won't--lead to socially rational outcomes.  On the other hand, game
theory was originally framed as an extension of decision theory, and
therefore carried all of the latter's ahistorical, un-socially constructed
baggage (which is not to say that appropriately constructed game-theoretic
models aren't relevant to analyses of particular settings).  More recently,
pushed in part by experimental results that challenge the generality of
predictions based on purely rational Nash equilibrium, game theorists have
been shaking off these restrictions by considering the impact of
evolutionary preferences and norm-based behavior.  But even these
developments owe a clear debt to Nash's work.

So I'd say, yeah, Nash (as well as Harsanyi and Selten) have made real
contributions to economics, even the sort of economics that concerns folks
on this list.  

Gil




Re: Re: Re: Re: Roemer and Exploitation

2002-03-13 Thread Gil Skillman

Rakesh writes

I also had written the following on which Gil did not comment:


To say that additional capital is increasingly in short supply vis a 
vis  the new and displaced laboring population as accumulation 
progresses only means that in the course of accumulation the 
primordial source of this capital, surplus value, becomes 
progressively more scarce, too small, in relation to the already 
accumulated mass of capital

I skipped this because my response would have been redundant:  i.e.,
whether or not surplus value becomes progressively more scarce...in
relation to the already accumulated mass of capital  has no particular
relation one way or another to the question of whether labor is subsumed
under capital, and thus no particular reason to venture into the hidden
abode of production.  Again, there's no reason to think that the
possibility that surplus value becomes progressively more scarce can't be
demonstrated in the context of the appropriate empirically motivated
Walrasian model.  

Gil replies:


I rid, I mean read, this statement as corresponding to Marx's KI/25
analysis of the general law of capitalist accumulation, to the effect
that any rise in wages above subsistence due to demand pressures from
capital accumulation is necessarily self-limiting, since the resulting loss
in profit leads to a corresponding reduction in the rate of accumulation.
(This self-limitation is further reinforced by tendentially rising OCC.)

But I don't see why anyone has to venture into the hidden mode of
production to yield *this* particular point.


which point exactly? the point in the excised paragraph above about 
the primordial source of capital?

Yes, necessarily, since it's equivalent to the point I answered explicitly.

   For example, Marx's argument
holds if it's true that the only funds for accumulation come from the
retained earnings of capitalists.  This result could certainly be generated
by the appropriate (and empirically motivated) Walrasian intertemporal
model. I took this issue up in my response to Roberto Veneziani when I
suggested there was no necessary connection between the economic conditions
leading to the subsumption of labor under capital (i.e., capital's reign
over the hidden mode of production and those capable of explaining the
persistent scarcity of capital in the face of capital accumulation.

How do you explain persistent scarcity? What do you mean by scarcity? 

Re the second question,  you first: what did you mean by the phrase
progressively more scarce in the paragraph you appended at the top of
your post?  It's likely we mean very much the same thing by this term.

The first question is not at issue.  What *is* at issue is whether the
appropriate explanation can be couched in Walrasian terms.  In your post
23776, you suggested it could not be.

You refer at some point to capital constrained equilibrium--is this a 
well understood defintion of scarcity to the economic theorists on 
the list?   Are these questions taken up in your formal reply to 
which Roberto V has referred?

I think so, but you'd have to ask the other economic theorists on the list
re the first question.  On the second, yes.

By the way, what do you make of Keynes' argument about the 
relationship between the declining marginal efficiency of capital as 
capital becomes less scarce though not necessarily less physical 
productive?  What is the connection between the scarcity to which you 
refer and Keynes' nebulous idea of capital scarcity (or the lack 
thereof)?

Re the second question, roughly speaking, a condition of capital scarcity
implies the marginal efficiency of capital is strictly positive.   On the
first question, I suspect the distinction Keynes is alluding to involves
the difference between *physical* and *revenue* productivity.  An
investment may lead to a new machine being built, but not necessarily to
any money being made from the use of the new machine.


  I took this issue up in my response to Roberto Veneziani when I
suggested there was no necessary connection between the economic conditions
leading to the subsumption of labor under capital (i.e., capital's reign
over the hidden mode of production and those capable of explaining the
persistent scarcity of capital in the face of capital accumulation.

I am not suggesting a necessary connection.

If there is no necessary reason to refer to the hidden mode of production
in discussing reasons for persistent capital scarcity, then I believe I've
answered your criticism of the Walrasian framework that prompted this exchange.

Exactly.  And *given* such socially-determined differences [in time 
preferences--rb], I show that one
can account for the persistence of capitalist exploitation.

Well, this very concept of time preferences surely needs unpacking.

For some purposes, at least, I would surely agree.

Gil




Re: Marx vs. Roemer

2002-03-13 Thread Gil Skillman

Continuing the discussion with Charles.  Fast forward to...


CB: (Again, just because we are doing a fine tooth comb treatment, surplus 
value and capital are not entirely identical, but it may not matter. I'm 
not trying to be picky, but I am thinking that as you are doing a very fine 
graded analysis,  these types of details cause a question mark to sort of 
popup in one's mind)

GS:No, that's fine, it's better to make these choices explicit.  As far as I
can tell, capital in the passage I cited above is shorthand for the
transformation of money into capital, a phrase that Marx uses in the
passages immediately preceding and immediately following the one I cite.
Again as far as I can tell, Marx uses the transformation of money into
capital as a corollary of creation of surplus value--compare, for
example, his usage of surplus value at the top of p. 268 and the
near-parallel use of transformation of money into capital near the bottom. 

^^^

CB: Page 268 : Is that in Chapter 5 ? 

Yes, the penultimate page of Ch. 5 in the Penguin or Vintage edition.

 I hesitate, because it seems that the creation of surplus value is in 
production. I have more that idea that in M-C...P...C'-M', the 
surplus-values are created at P. The transformations of money into capital 
occurs at M-C and then again at M'-C'', no ?

As I read Marx, although the creation of surplus value *requires* the
production of new value, surplus value literally does not exist--is not
created-- until the *completion* of the circuit of capital bracketing the
P in your expression above. In other words, at the step P...C'  in your
expression, surplus value does not yet exist.  Consequently, the creation
of surplus value at least implies the transformation of money into capital.

Foundation for these claims:  

In Chapter 4, Marx defines surplus value as the increment (delta M = M'
minus M) arising from the circuit of capital, insofar as this increment
corresponds to the valorization [Verwertung, Marx's coinage] of the value
originally advanced. (pp 251-2).  To me, this means that by definition the
creation of surplus value involves something more than just production of
new commodities.  [Notice, for example, that he didn't define surplus value
as (delta C = C' minus C).]  This view is corroborated in Marx's discussion
near the end of Chapter 5, when he asks rhetorically But can surplus-value
originate [note the verb!--GS] anywhere else than in circulation...? and
adds The commodity-owner can create value by his labour, but he cannot
create values which can valorize themselves.  But then it is incorrect to
assert that the creation of surplus value is in production.  The creation
of surplus value is in production *and* circulation.

Fast forward...

GS: No, I'm saying that Marx's Chapter 5 argument demonstrates the claim that
price-value disparities are not sufficient to explain the existence of
surplus value.  But he makes no demonstration one way or the other
concerning the claim price-value disparities are not necessary for the
existence of surplus value, leaving open the possibility that they *might*
be necessary, at least under some conditions.  Since no claim has been made
about necessity, one cannot validly infer that price-value disparities are
incidental to the existence of surplus value, as Marx does in the
conclusion of Chapter 5.  If A is necessary for B, then it is certainly not
incidental to B, whether or not it's sufficient for B.  

^^^

CB: OK ,so Marx says and demonstrates that they are not sufficient, but 
doesn't address whether they are necessary, so they might be necessary.  

To say price-value disparities are a necessary condition of surplus-value 
would be to say surplus value implies ( in the sense of modus ponens) 
price-value disparities, correct ?

For at least some instance of the general formula of capital M--C--M', yes.

  Not price-value disparities, not surplus 
value. And in such a case , we would not say that price-value disparities 
are incidental to surplus-value. Is that what you are saying ?

Your statement is certainly true, but I'm actually saying something more
basic:  since Marx does not even consider the claim not price value
disparities, not surplus value in his Chapter 5 argument, his inference
price value disparities are incidental to surplus-value cannot be
entailed by that argument.  He's asserted a conclusion that does not follow
logically from his premises.




Re: Defending civilised values by torture

2002-03-12 Thread Gil Skillman

Talk about your axis of evil!  No wonder the US has so little global
credibility:  it keeps trying to have its moral cake and eat it, too.  On
the one hand, we're waging a war on terrorism,  which is used to justify
the amazing cloak of secrecy over our military's actions.  On the other,
the prisoners captured in this war are yet somehow not prisoners of
war?  What?  On one hand, the US is the land of rights and liberty,
fighting the evil foes of same.  On the other, the US hands over these
prisoners to regimes that are *certain* to violate those rights in the
extreme.  I wonder if Amnesty International might be petitioned to
investigate and raise the visibility of these violations? 

Gil


US sends suspects to face torture

Duncan Campbell in Los Angeles
Tuesday March 12, 2002
The Guardian

The US has been secretly sending prisoners suspected of al-Qaida connections
to countries where torture during interrogation is legal, according to US
diplomatic and intelligence sources. Prisoners moved to such countries as
Egypt and Jordan can be subjected to torture and threats to their families
to extract information sought by the US in the wake of the September 11
attacks.
The normal extradition procedures have been bypassed in the transportation
of dozens of prisoners suspected of terrorist connections, according to a
report in the Washington Post. The suspects have been taken to countries
where the CIA has close ties with the local intelligence services and where
torture is permitted.

According to the report, US intelligence agents have been involved in a
number of interrogations. A CIA spokesman yesterday said the agency had no
comment on the allegations. A state department spokesman said the US had
been working very closely with other countries - It's a global fight
against terrorism.

After September 11, these sorts of movements have been occurring all the
time, a US diplomat told the Washington Post. It allows us to get
information from terrorists in a way we can't do on US soil.

The seizing of suspects and taking them to a third country without due
process of law is known as rendition. The reason for sending a suspect to
a third country rather than to the US, according to the diplomats, is an
attempt to avoid highly publicised cases that could lead to a further
backlash from Islamist extremists.

One of the prisoners transported in this way, Muhammad Saad Iqbal Madni, is
allegedly linked to Richard Reid, the Briton accused of the attempted shoe
bomb attack on an American Airlines flight from Paris to Miami in December.
He was taken from Indonesia to Egypt on a US-registered Gulfstream jet
without a court hearing after his name appeared on al-Qaida documents. He
remains in custody in Egypt and has been subjected to interrogation by
intelligence agents.

An Indonesian government official said disclosing the Americans' role would
have exposed President Megawati Sukarnoputri to criticism from Muslim
political parties. We can't be seen to be cooperating too closely with the
United States, the official said.

A Yemeni microbiology student has also been taken in this way, being flown
from Pakistan to Jordan on a US-registered jet. US forces also seized five
Algerians and a Yemeni in Bosnia on January 19 and flew them to Guantanamo
Bay after the men were released by the Bosnian supreme court for lack of
evidence, and despite an injunction from the Bosnian human rights chamber
that four of them be allowed to remain in the country pending further
proceedings.

The US has been criticised by some of its European allies over the detention
of prisoners at Camp X-Ray in Guantanamo Bay, Cuba. After the Pentagon
released pictures of blindfolded prisoners kneeling on the ground, the
defence secretary, Donald Rumsfeld, was forced to defend the conditions in
which they were being held.

Unsuccessful attempts have been made by civil rights lawyers based in Los
Angeles to have the Camp X-Ray prisoners either charged in US courts or
treated as prisoners of war. The US administration has resisted such moves,
arguing that those detained, both Taliban fighters and members of al-Qaida,
were not entitled to be regarded as prisoners of war because they were
terrorists rather than soldiers and were not part of a recognised, uniformed
army.







Re: marx's proof regarding surplus value and profit

2002-03-12 Thread Gil Skillman

Michael writes:

One more short, but obvious point regarding profit and surplus value.
Marx did offer one simple proof of the role of surplus value in the
creation of profit.  Suppose, he says, that we take the working class as a
whole.  If the working-class did not produce anymore than it consumed,
profits would be impossible.

Michael, no one disputes that surplus *labor* is a necessary condition for
both the existence of profit and the existence of surplus value.  It does
not follow from this that surplus value has a role in the creation of
profit.  It could with equal (non-) logic be said that profit has a role
in the creation of surplus value.  Similarly, it does it follow that
value... is  fundamental to price, in the sense that prices and profits
depend on what happens in the sphere of value.   

Gil




Re: Re: Roemer and Exploitation

2002-03-12 Thread Gil Skillman

Hello, Rakesh.  You write in part

Production (P) is explanatorily fundamental to the scarcity of DOPA 
(S) and thus the persistence of exploitation (E).

That is, P=E implies P+S=E

It's into the hidden abode of production one must enter to explain 
the persistence of scarce DOPA relative to labor, no?

Walrasianism Marx is not suited for that kind of investigation, is it?

I'm going to tread lightly here, because we both know from our mutual
experience on OPE-L that we're probably not going to end up agreeing in any
case.  All I want to do, therefore, is address your question in good faith
by indicating the  grounds for an alternative viewpoint that allows for the
relevance of Roemer's analysis to Marx's Volume I argument concerning the
persistence of exploitation.  I don't thereby assume that you'll find these
logical grounds appealing or relevant.  

You suggest above that Production (P) is explanatorily fundamental to the
scarcity of DOPA 
(S) and thus the persistence of exploitation (E), and suggest further that
Walrasianism Marx is not suited for that kind of investigation.  

The basis you offer for the first statement is  

It is the scarcity of surplus labor in the production process that 
ensures the relative scarcity of capital with respect to labor: the 
diminishing flow of surplus value relative to rising minimum capital 
requirements constrains and discourages the rate of accumulation that 
would be needed as the OCC rises to absorb not only a growing 
population but also the proletarians, artisans and peasants 
continously displaced by technological change and the expansion of 
commodity production.

I rid, I mean read, this statement as corresponding to Marx's KI/25
analysis of the general law of capitalist accumulation, to the effect
that any rise in wages above subsistence due to demand pressures from
capital accumulation is necessarily self-limiting, since the resulting loss
in profit leads to a corresponding reduction in the rate of accumulation.
(This self-limitation is further reinforced by tendentially rising OCC.)   

But I don't see why anyone has to venture into the hidden mode of
production to yield *this* particular point.  For example, Marx's argument
holds if it's true that the only funds for accumulation come from the
retained earnings of capitalists.  This result could certainly be generated
by the appropriate (and empirically motivated) Walrasian intertemporal
model. I took this issue up in my response to Roberto Veneziani when I
suggested there was no necessary connection between the economic conditions
leading to the subsumption of labor under capital (i.e., capital's reign
over the hidden mode of production and those capable of explaining the
persistent scarcity of capital in the face of capital accumulation.

(1) differences in preferences are the typical neoclassical argument 
to justify differences in wealth, and Roemer explicitly rejects this 
sort of argument. See for instance, the discussion about differences 
in rates of time preference in Roemer 1981, p.85, and Roemer, 1982, 
p.12. (A particularly detailed discussion is in Free to loose, but 
I do not have the reference because I left my copy in Italy!!).

Gil, what are the page numbers here, do you know?

pp 60-63.  But I want to take exception to the sense of RV's objection
here.  I agree emphatically with RV and Roemer that differences in (time)
preferences cannot legitimately be used to justify differences in wealth.
I never suggest they could be.  Rather, wealth-induced differentials in
time preference are invoked in my model to *explain*, not justify,
persistent exploitation, and this is entirely consistent with Roemer's
discussion, where he says:

Marxists and left-liberals view rates of time preference as socially
determined.  Therefore in their view it is not possible to justify
exploitation and inequality by appealing to different rates of time
preference, for those differences arose from prior conditions of inequality
and oppression.  

Exactly.  And *given* such socially-determined differences, I show that one
can account for the persistence of capitalist exploitation.

Gil




Re: marx's proof regarding surplus value and profit

2002-03-12 Thread Gil Skillman

Charles, you write

CB: Your argument for this is probably in your previous posts, but could you 
reiterate it ?  Does it follow from something else that surplus value is a 
necessary condition for profit ?  Marx makes surplus value part of the 
definition of profit.


First things first:  where does Marx make surplus value part of his
definition of profit?


 It could with equal (non-) logic be said that profit has a role
in the creation of surplus value.  Similarly, it does it follow that
value... is  fundamental to price, in the sense that prices and profits
depend on what happens in the sphere of value.   

^^^

CB: Is that does not follow...  ?

Yes

Gil




Re: urpe@assa

2002-03-12 Thread Gil Skillman

Mathew, the URPE@ASSA coordinator is Mieke Meurs at American University.  I
can look up her e-mail address if you need it.  The deadline is generally
not until May or June, so you're not under the gun here.  If Mieke doesn't
send an announcement directly to PEN-L, I'll forward the announcement when
I get it.  Nothing has been sent out yet, as far as I know.  Gil

Does anyone know the details on submitting session proposals for the
URPE meetings at ASSA, D.C., 2003--deadline, who to send it to, e-mail,
etc.?





Re: Roemer and Exploitation

2002-03-11 Thread Gil Skillman

I'd like to continue the exchange with Roberto Veneziani (RV) concerning
the meaning of Roemer's formal results and the impact of his excellent
paper, Exploitation and Time on that meaning, but before doing so I want
to make a couple of things clear up front.  First, we start from a position
of greater agreement than has been typical for PEN-L discussions of
Roemer's work.  As he states,  RV agrees that his paper should not be taken
as demolishing Roemer's contribution (which listmembers will recall was
my original point in discussing RV's paper), while, as I've already stated,
I think that RV has made a valid and important contribution that compels a
significant reassessment of Roemer's claims. 

I also think it represents the most serious attempt to extend Roemer's
microfoundational Marxist model to a genuinely intertemporal setting
since my working paper from a few years ago (recently revised and presented
at the last ASSA conference). Indeed it's superior to my paper in at least
two respects:  first, RV's model offers the most immediate extension of
Roemer's static model to a dynamic framework, including in particular the
representation of preferences, which turns out to be a key sub-issue
relating to the main one (see below); second, my paper restricts attention
to myopic equilibria in which actors optimize in each period on the basis
only of *current* market conditions rather than the full intertemporal
stream of market conditions.  This reduces the multiplicity of equilibria,
which is analytically handy, but RV's more general equilibrium treatment is
more in the spirit of Roemer's approach.

Having said all this, I still believe that RV's paper modifies rather than
contradicts Roemer's fundamental point about the systemic basic of
exploitation in exchange economies (including capitalism), once that point
is properly understood.
Which leads me to my second prefatory point.  I realize that much what I'll
say will be controversial, at least to members of this list, and I don't
presume that my comments are going to convince anybody about the
relevance of Roemer's results for Marxian political economy.  Therefore no
one should fear that this is the start of a long debate, since I agree with
Michael that such e-mail debates cannot hope to resolve any serious
differences. I hope at most to raise interesting questions for those of us
who engage the theoretical underpinnings of Marxian PE, understood broadly.
 Those who believe they already know the answers to the questions can, of
course, tune out.  

Now, on to the substance.  In his post, RV focuses on the first of my two
major points about his paper, concerning what I understand to be the proper
interpretation of Roemer's formal results concerning the systemic basis of
exploitation in class-based exchange economies.  My basic argument here is
that despite some (certainly regrettable) *verbal* carelessness by Roemer
in explaining the meaning of his formal conclusions, the latter show that
differential ownership of *scarce* productive assets (DOSPA) is the
necessary (and, subject to a caveat mentioned in my earlier post,
sufficient) basis for capitalist exploitation, not simply differential
ownership of said assets (DOPA).  For what it's worth, I first make this
point in my 1995 Econ  Phil article.

In my earlier post, I point to two bases in GTEC for this assessment. The
first comes right in the introduction, when Roemer offers a simple version
of his subsistence model which illustrates the central concepts his
theory.  In setting up the model, he says (p. 9) Suppose, now, there is a
limited stock of seed corn.  By 'limited' I mean there is not enough to
employ the whole population in the [capital-intensive] technique.  This is
what he, and I, mean by scarcity in this context--economic scarcity in
the specific sense of having a capital-constrained rather than a
labor-constrained equilibrium.  

What is Roemer's own assessment of the role of scarcity in his analysis?
he makes this plain on the next two pages:

p. 10 It is important to notice that for this example to work [i.e., to
exhibit exploitation] there must be an industrial reserve army--that is,
more producers available than seed corn to employ them. *For if, instead,
seed corn were in excess relative to the labor supply, then the work week
in the [capital-intensive] technique would be bid down to three days*
[thereby eliminating exploitation in this example]. (Emphasis added)

p. 11 He repeats:  Indeed, the following are requirements for this example
to work:  (1) a class of propertyless producers [that's differential
ownership], *in relative abundance to the supply of capital which can
employ them* [that's capital scarcity]  (emphasis added).

He makes similar explicit caveats in _Value Exploitation and Class_ (pp
18-19) and _Free to Lose_.  Let me quote from the latter:

What are the features of the economy described in the preceding section
that have caused exploitation to emerge?  Two are 

Re: Re: Marx vs. Roemer

2002-03-11 Thread Gil Skillman

CB writes

CB: To be more precise, Marx's position is that labor is the only source of 
new value, exchange-value.  Individual capitalists may increase or lose 
some of their share of the total surplus value by various buying and 
selling of all types among themselves. Marx's recognizing this does not 
contradict his basic proposition that labor is the only source of new 
value, exchange-value.

and JKS replies

Right, so you have profit taht is generated by possession of monoply 
advantages that does not represent value in Marx's sense. Note that this 
profit is not a result of redistribution of SV, a point that can be made if 
we imagine a situation with two capitalists, one of whom acquires a monopoly 
and behaves as monopolists due. His monopoly rent is not redistribute from 
the other guy, it's due rather to his possession of the monopoly (Marx's 
point): so, profits without value that are therefore NOT due to the 
expoloitation of labor--rather to the exploitation of consumers. Right, Gil?

I'm not sure, given some syntactical and spelling oddities in your
statement above.  Let me try to address that point directly:  

1)  Although monopoly power (or perhaps more to the point, monopsony power
exercised by capitalists in markets for labor power) may increase the rate
of surplus value, other things equal, it is not necessary for the
*existence* of surplus value in Marx's analytical framework.

2)  What *is* necessary for the existence of surplus value, by Marx's
stipulation, is that new value is produced subsequent to, and dependent on,
the initiation of a circuit of capital (denoted M--C--M'). Since value
magnitudes are determined by socially necessary labor time expended in
production, surplus value therefore cannot arise merely from the
redistribution of value that existed prior to the initiation of the
circuit.  Thus, the mere existence of monopoly power in commodity markets
is also not *sufficient* to account for the existence of surplus value as
Marx defines the term.

3)  It does not, however, follow from (1) or (2) that disparities between
commodity values and their respective prices are incidental to the
existence of surplus value, as Marx explicitly claims at the end of Volume
I, Chapter 5.  What Marx affirms in Chapter 5 is that such disparities are
not *sufficient* of themselves to account for the existence of surplus
value.  However, this leaves entirely open the possibility that particular
price-value disparities might be *necessary* (and therefore not
incidental!) to the existence of surplus value, *and Marx doesn't address
this possibility one way or another in Chapter 5.*  The reason this is
potentially relevant is that Marx stipulates *two* conditions for the
existence of surplus value:

A) As noted above, new value must be produced subsequent to, and financed
by, the initiation of a circuit of capital.

B)  A portion of the newly produced value must be appropriated by someone
(i.e., the capitalist) *other* than the one(s) who created that value (cf
Marx's discussion of the leather and boots example on p. 268 (Penguin
ed.)).  

Granting that *targeted* price-value disparities cannot, by definition,
account for condition (A), Marx's argument in Chapter 5 entirely fails to
address whether they might in any case be *necessary* for condition (B).
And since he does not consider this possibility, he cannot validly conclude
at the end of Chapter 5 that price-value disparities are merely disturbing
incidental circumstances which are irrelevant to the actual course of the
process.  [p. 269, footnote]

NB, I'm making no claims here about the significance of this lacuna
vis-a-vis Marx's Volume I argument.  If the reader feels that this logical
deficiency is unimportant in the larger scheme of things, so be it.

Gil





Re: Re: Re: Marx vs. Roemer

2002-03-11 Thread Gil Skillman

Shane writes in response to Justin:

A monopolist is able to get an above-average rate of return on its capital.
Nonmonopolists (except, perhaps, in Lake Woebegone..) must therefore
receive a below-average return on their capital.  

This does not necessarily follow.  Suppose, for example, that capitalists
enjoy monopoly (more accurately, monopsony) wage-setting power in
markets for labor power due to the empirically relevant fact that workers
face significant costs of job search (this is a typical feature of search
models; see for example the survey article on monopsony in labor markets by
Boal and Ransom in the J. of Econ Lit, 1997).  Then more monopsony power,
and thus more surplus value, for one capitalist does not imply less for any
other capitalist.  Rather it implies that workers as a class perform more
surplus labor.

[I could have made an exactly parallel point using markets for credit
extended directly to value producers, per Roemer's isomorphism theorem, but
obviously this introduces an extra complication, so I won't go there.]

Another way of putting this is that Marx's remark in Chapter 5 to the
effect that The capitalist class of a given country, taken as a whole,
cannot defraud itself, (p. 266, top, Penguin ed.)  is *doubly* a red
herring, first because fraud is not at issue in any case, and second
because the issue is not whether capitalists exploit *each other*, but
rather whether they as a class exploit *workers.*

The economic process
determining these different returns to different capitals is a process of
distributing the value of the total surplus product among the various
claimants to that surplus value.  Marx's Law Of Value applies  to the
aggregate surplus as produced.  Because Marx defined value as
a determinate quantity of labor time and capital as *capitalized*
surplus value  he was able to view the capitalist system as a dynamic
entity subject to quantitatively determined laws of motion such
as the Law of the Falling Tendency of the Rate of Profit which
has been shown both to be empirically true and to be a strict
consequence of the fundamental social relationships defining a
capitalist economic system.

For what it's worth, I'd say the empirical relevance of this law remains
an open question, as does the sense in which it is a strict conseqeuence
of the fundamental social relationships defining a capitalist system.





Re: RE: Re: Re: Re: Marx vs. Roemer

2002-03-11 Thread Gil Skillman

At 03:04 PM 3/11/02 -0800, you wrote:
Shane [Mage] writes in response to Justin:A monopolist is able to get an
above-average rate of return on its capital. Nonmonopolists (except,
perhaps, in Lake Woebegone..) must therefore receive a below-average return
on their capital.

Gil writes: This does not necessarily follow.  Suppose, for example, that
capitalists enjoy monopoly (more accurately, monopsony) wage-setting
power in markets for labor power

Shane Mage can talk for himself, but I think that it's a big mistake -- or
even a rhetorical bait and switch -- to suddenly change over to talking
about monoposony in labor-power markets. I read Shane as talking about
monopoly in product markets, not monopsony. 

I don't think it's a mistake, because in Chapter 5, where this issue
arises, Marx makes no distinctions about *which* commodity markets he's
talking about. If the argument holds for the expression of price-setting
power in one commodity market, it should hold for the expression of
price-setting power in *any* commodity market (including the commodity
called labor power).


(BTW, Marx wasn't familiar with the concept of monopsony as far as I can
tell. But he assumed at one point in volume III that it didn't apply, in
that he assumed that Smith's concept of compensating wage differentials did
apply and that the rate of surplus-value equalizes between sectors. True
monopsony is a microeconomic phenomenon which would cause the monopsonistic
industry to enjoy an above-average rate of surplus-value. In theory if the
monopsonist is large enough as part of the economy, it might tilt class
relations in favor of capital, raising the rate of surplus-value overall.) 

Yes, that's my point.

Gil continues:  ... due to the empirically relevant fact that workers face
significant costs of job search (...). Then more monopsony power, and thus
more surplus value, for one capitalist does not   imply less for any other
capitalist.  Rather it implies that workers as a class perform more surplus
labor.

You'd think that in a neoclassical world, the capitalists would also face
search costs in their efforts to hire employees. This would give the
employees who currently have jobs a little bit of monopoly power vis-a-vis
their employers. There's no reason in the neoclassical world for the
monopsony power of the employers to _a priori_ exceed the monopoly power of
the employees, so that we've got a indeterminate bilateral monopoly
situation. 

There's also no necessary grounds in neoclassical terms for insisting on
bilateral search costs.  The point here is theoretical possibility, not
generality.

So there's no reason in the neoclassical world for workers to
perform more surplus-labor.

There is, in the entirely neoclassical scenario of one-sided search costs.
Again, the issue is about theoretical possibility, not generality.

But what if it's normal for job vacancies to be less in number than job
seekings, i.e., if there's Keynesian cyclical unemployment? In that case --
where there is a non-neoclassical situation of persistent excess supply
(a.k.a. reserve army) of labor-power, the workers would be at the
disadvantage that Gil refers to. 

I don't believe that persistent excess supply...of labor-power has any
necessary connection to *Keynesian* unemployment, per se.  Marx, for
instance, talks about the former in V. I, Ch. 25 without making any evident
reference to the latter.  And if so, there's nothing essentially
non-neoclassical about the former condition.  One can establish that
condition in the context of a suitable intertemporal neoclassical model.

Strictly speaking, that doesn't have to be Keynesian: it could be due to
the cut-back in accumulation that occurs whenever profits are squeezed by
high wages, in a version of Marx's KI/25 story.

I agree, which is why, in my reading, this aspect of Marx's KI/25 chapter
is not inconsistent with a neoclassical framework.

 That is the capitalist
hammerlock -- their class control over the accumulation process and of the
production process -- would _ensure_ that normally the bilateral monopoly
story doesn't apply, so that instead Gil's capitalist monopsony story
applies. 

I would say further that *as a class* capitalists might enjoy a
hammerlock...over the accumulation process even in the absence of
monopsony, understood as wage-setting power by *individual* capitalists.

 [I could have made an exactly parallel point using markets for credit
extended directly to value producers, per Roemer's isomorphism theorem, but
obviously this introduces an extra complication, so I won't go there.]

are you saying that lending money gives the lender monopsony power?

No.

 doesn't the borrower have the ability to cheat? 

Maybe, but you don't need to posit the ability to cheat in order to make my
point--for example, you can assume perfectly complete contracting conditions.

 Another way of putting this is that Marx's remark in Chapter 5 to the
effect that The capitalist class of a given 

Re: Veneziani on Roemer, Marx, and Skillman

2002-03-10 Thread Gil Skillman

Lest it be forgotten, this now extensive and multi-named thread began with
my simple suggestion, in response to a P.S. in a post by Sabri, that
Roemer's work raised issues that were of relevance to Marx's analysis in
Volume I of Capital.  This  modest assessment was not intended as a
referendum on  Marx's general method and theoretical framework, nor as a
defense of Roemer's general analytical method, despite Jim Devine's evident
interest in enlarging the discussion to embrace these much larger issues.
Nor were these larger questions engaged by my subsequent suggestion, in a
response to Andrew K, that Veneziani's work, whatever its considerable
merits, did not serve to demolish Roemer's contribution. Given these
rather humble claims, I'm somewhat astonished that Jim took it upon himself
to contact Roberto Veneziani concerning my comments on the latter's paper
(noting that Jim has not been equally zealous in contacting Roemer to get
his assessment of the much more extensive and negative critical comments
that have been  made here about his work, e.g.).  It suggests to me that
Jim might be taking this discussion way too seriously.

That said, though, I think Jim did a real service to PEN-L in enlisting
Veneziani.  I indicated my opinion of the quality of his theoretical work
in an earlier post.  Although I think it's unlikely to engage the interest
of most listmembers, I look forward to discussing the set of issues raised
by Roberto's paper.  Since, as he notes in his recent post, his initial
response (conveyed by Jim below) were made before he was aware of my full
comments, I'll not address the remarks below, but instead respond directly
to his separate posting.  

Gil


Concerning the thread with a similar name to the title of this message,
Roberto Veneziani sends me the following comments  corrections (which I've
renumbered):

[begin quote]
1) I agree that price = value is only fairness in exchange and that this is
Roemer's and not Marx's view. I have tried to clarify this in the new
version. All references to value pricing as fair pricing have been
eliminated. 

2) Your summary of the main conclusions of the paper is perfect, except on
one issue, namely that Roemer's story of exploitation self-destructs ...
due to accumulation, including worker's accumulation (your message). I
agree that in accumulation models or in a subsistence economy with non-zero
savings Roemer's theory breaks down immediately. (Roemer himself
acknowledged the knife-edge properties of his accumulation models.) You have
forcefully shown this in your paper with Prof. Dymski, and I did not want to
just provide mathematical clothes to your convincing logical and economic
argument. My point is that even in the most favourable case to Roemer's
theory, i.e. in an interior Reproducible Solution with NO SAVINGS and NO
ACCUMULATION [in short, in a solution with no savings] the theory does not
work. I think this result is rather strong because it falsifies Roemer's
claim (in his reply to your EP critique) that his models prove that DOPA
[the differential ownership of productive assets, i.e., wealth inequality]
is logically primary and exploitation and classes emerge prior to
accumulation, etc. And it falsifies the claim at what he considers to be the
relevant level of abstraction.

3) Given that my results obtain only thanks to the POSSIBILITY of savings,
and with no actual savings by either capitalists or workers, they do not
undermine Marx's vol.I/ch.25 argument. These results only undermine
microfounded - analytical marxist - models, by showing that they are
unable to model Marxian exploitation as a persistent phenomenon, and raise
doubts about Roemer's narrow definition of exploitation and classes.
Actually, as shown in an unpublished paper by Prof. Skillman, if the
Walrasian framework is retained, the only way to have persistent
exploitation is to assume that agents have different time preferences,
i.e. the typical result of neoclassical models, where differences in wealth
are due to differences in preferences.
[end quote]

[My comment:] if persistent exploitation is based on different classes
having different time preferences, we have returned to the theory that Marx
was attacking in his discussion of primitive accumulation and other
matters, i.e., that the rich are rich because they are forward-thinking,
while the poor are poor because they are short-sighted.

Roberto says that he may be joining pen-l soon.

Jim Devine [EMAIL PROTECTED]  http:/bellarmine.lmu.edu/~JDevine 
Science is a way of trying not to fool yourself. -- Richard Feynman.





Re: RE: Roemer and Veneziani

2002-03-05 Thread Gil Skillman

Jim, you write

I haven't read Veneziani's paper, but the possibility of workers' saving
doesn't undermine Marx's theory Marx does discuss workers' saving in volume
III (though I can't find the quotes, since my copy of CAPITAL that's been
marked up is at work) It's often assumed that the classical
(Smith/Ricardo/Marx/etc) assumption was that workers didn't save, but
that's not true for Marx

We're on the same page here  I didn't say Marx never talks about worker
saving  To the contrary, I anticipated your remark above when I said that
one can find potential responses to the issues raised by Roemer in Volume
III, the Resultate, or Theories of Surplus Value  What I did say is that
Marx doesn't discuss this possibility and its consequences in his
discussion of the general law of capital accumulation in Volume I,
Chapter 25  

 The thing is that, as Sweezy says in his THEORY OF
CAPTIALIST DEVELOPMENT, is that workers' saving is for use-value, not for
accumulation of power and wealth What Sweezy described (before Modigliani,
BTW) is what's now described as life-cycle saving, delaying some
consumption to retirement and the like (Some is to buy consumer durables,
such as houses)

I don't see the significance of this point  I'm not suggesting that worker
saving is tantamount to capital accumulation *by workers*, and I don't see
why that possibility is relevant  The immediate *purpose* of saving
shouldn't alter its potential impact on the rate of capital accumulation in
market economies, so long as workers don't put their savings in their
mattresses or piggy banks  If they deposit it in banks, it becomes
available to capitalists for accumulation  To suggest otherwise, in the
context of Marx's Chapter 25 argument, is to presume that when capitalists
can no longer accumulate out of retained earnings, they can't borrow money
to invest  But they do systematically rely on the credit system, as Marx
also acknowledges in Volume III

Let me take that point a step further  Marx states in Ch 21 of Volume III
(p 478, Penguin ed) that the interest rate of loan capital is determined
by supply and demand Thus, additional saving, *whatever* its source,
should by Marx's own analysis lower the interest rate and promote
accumulation  

 The existence of unemployment and similar threats to the
security of workers makes it extremely hard for any but a very small number
of workers to save enough to cross the line between life-cycle and similar
saving for use-value on the one hand, and capitalist accumulation on the
other Further, small savers face extreme barriers to becoming large savers
because of their lack of the ability to diversify In any event, almost
no-one becomes a capitalist -- ie, running others' lives by owning
sufficient means of production -- by saving Usually, luck or theft plays a
bigger role

I agree that both of these considerations would raise obstacles to workers
accumulating capital on their own  But again, so far as I can see, that's
not the relevant issue in capitalist economies, the world Marx is
considering in Volume I Chapter 25  Indeed, the threat of unemployment and
other sources of uncertainty is a *spur* to saving, other things equal,
promoting the potential impact of worker saving on the interest rate of
loanable funds, described above


More importantly, Marx isn't talking about workers as individuals as much as
workers as a class A small number of workers can become capitalists without
abolishing the proletariat as a _societal institution_ The institution is
refreshed (as it were) by the downward mobility of those capitalists who
lose out in the battle of competition (like one of my grandfathers, by the
way) So a class without direct access to the means of subsistence and
production who are dependent for their survival on those who do control such
is reproduced over time, even if there is some turnover of personnel 

Same point as above

(Also, as Sweezy pointed out, a lot of workers' saving is cancelled out on
the aggregate level by other workers' dissaving So the workers don't save
assumption makes sense as a simpifying approximation on the aggregate
level) 

Two comments:

First, this ignores Veneziani's key contribution, which is to indicate that
the mere *possibility* of saving leads to a tendentially declining rate of
exploitation  Again assuming that workers don't hoard--put their savings
in their mattresses--then a similar argument should apply in Marx's
scenario  Conversely, if it were true that this reality--that dissaving
cancels out saving-- rescues Marx's account, then incorporating it also
rescues Roemer's, since he also allows for the possibility of dissaving  

Second, even if this were valid, it's not part of Marx's account in Volume
I, Chapter 25  The possibility of working class differentiation such that
some workers save and some dissave is a possible *implication* of his
argument there  But to establish this argument *in the first place* he
needs to argue that workers don't save, 

Kism as progressive yet contradictory

2002-03-05 Thread Gil Skillman

[Was: : [PEN-L:23525] Re: Re: Re: Re: Wade vs Wolf ]

Doug writes

[Capitalism is] awful, but I guess it beats slavery or feudalism But it's
also 
a deeply contradictory system, producing wealth and possibility 
alongside poverty and oppression A friend of mine who spent a few 
years as a reporter in Vietnam interviewed Nike workers who told her 
that they prefer their sweatshop jobs to what they would have been 
doing otherwise - things like chasing rats in rice paddies (not much 
fun to be a woman on the farm) Anticapitalists - and I'm one - often 
overlook that sort of thing And capitalism often produces great 
booms, though PEN-Lers seem to prefer talking about busts Which kind 
of begs the question of just how capitalist China is, and what 
lessons it might hold for other poor countries

I think this is an important point, with critical implications for theory
and praxis  Marx's scientific case for socialism and communism argued
that these were reached *through* capitalism, which acted, in historical
perspective, as a progressive engine for developing the forces of
production and, he argued, class consciousness  

But it is also a contradictory system, and these contradictions rebound on
those who are active in opposing its oppressive tendencies  Consider the
case of political action against sweatshop labor  On one hand, sweatshops
abuse and exploit workers  On the other, they often offer opportunities
that are superior to the even more abusive and exploitative alternatives
many workers face (I say this fully aware of the fact that workers are
often coerced or misled into sweatshop labor)  Sweatshops also typically
(though not always) operate at low margins of profit  So suppose that
anti-sweatshop regulations designed to curb their abuses drive many out of
business  Is that good or bad, on balance?  

I think there is a coherent progressive stance that would involve neither
laissez-faire nor attempts to ban sweatshops outright  But the point is
that the contradictory nature of the system seems to dictate nuanced,
middle ground responses to certain capitalist excesses, so long as the
responses aren't calculated to overthrow the system itself

Another critical point touched on by Doug's comment concerns the connection
between contradiction and capitalist crisis (wow, what alliteration)  It
is traditional in Marxist analysis to read the system's contradictory
nature as translating into ever more destructive crises--the other half of
Marx's scientific socialist vision  But, at least so far, the historical
record is far from decisive on this point Is US capitalism weaker than it
was before 9/11?  Before 1980?  Before 1932?  Is global capitalism weaker
than it was in the early 20th century?  What if the traditional thesis is
not true, and instead the system's contradictions translate into a
non-tendential series of crises and at least temporarily adequate systemic
adaptations to same?  Does this destroy the possibility that capitalist
laws of motion create a revolutionary class?

Gil




A role for static analysis?

2002-03-03 Thread Gil Skillman

[Was:  Re [PEN-L:23396] Re: Some questions]

Sabri, you write

When I said I looked at, I literally meant it It is always
difficult to deduce from e-mails what exactly the author has in
mind, nor it is easy to tell whether the author is making a joke
or not This is a very funny medium

Indeed so  For what it's worth, I wasn't joking, though given the
limitations of the medium I wasn't expecting to induce any cathartic
insights, either

On the other hand, keep in mind that we mathematicians suffer
from a major problem when we face mathematical books: we skip the
words and look at the equations Sometimes this is a serious
handicap but sometimes not

We mathematical political economists look at both  But I'm not sure what
the equations _per se_ have to do with this issue 

 The reason why I was not impressed
with Roemer's work was essentially because of this:

(1) Since Roemer's economic analysis, even of an idealized
capitalist economy, is based on a static economic model, 

Whether or not that's a sufficient condition to be not impressed with a
work in political economy is a judgment call, of course  I'm certainly not
insisting one must be impressed by Roemer's work  But there exist many
very insightful contributions to the understanding of capitalism that are
based on essentially static conditions  This would include Marx's analysis
of the basis of surplus value in Chapters 1-7 of Capital Volume I, which
incorporates no dynamic elements whatsoever  Is his analysis here
therefore unimpressive?

Gil




Rigor mortis?

2002-03-03 Thread Gil Skillman

[Was: RE: Re: Some questions] 


Hello, Michael.  You write:

Putting a premium on rigor seems to be one of the silliest ideas ever
proposed in economics.  Take reality, remove all of the concrete aspects,
represent that husk of reality as a mathematical equation, and see what
comes of it.  All the while, make sure that you structure this model so
that nothing conflicts with the conventional wisdom.

At least Keynes, and even Marshall, were contemptiuos of this sort of
economics.

Who can doubt that many economists have too often emphasized mathematical
rigor over relevance and common sense?  On the other hand, the dangers of
misplaced or misleading abstraction are not unique to rigorous formal
analysis.  Verbal analyses have no built-in protections against remov[ing]
all concrete aspects from a problem, representing the resulting husk as
a simplified by cogent picture of reality, and in such way as to subtly
reinforce the conventional wisdom.  If anything, I think verbal analyses
of complex systems might be more prone to to the possibility
fundamental-yet-persuasive misrepresentations of reality, given the
ambiguities inherent in everyday language.  Check Sabri on this:  as he
says, he skips the words and reads the equations.  

At least Keynes, and even Marshall, were contemptiuos of this sort of
economics.

Were they contemptuous of the the use of formal rigor in economic analysis,
or its misuse?  If the former, that seems a shame, since rigorous analysis
has, I think, promoted understanding of the conditions under which
Marshallian- or Keynesian-style arguments work.  Here's an example:  in
Marshallian terms, Keynesian unemployment exists when the real wage rate
fails to adjust downward to its market-clearing level, and lowering the
wage rate would therefore reduce unemployment.  Keynes raises the
possibility that lowering the real wage rate might instead *raise* the
unemployment rate, other things equal.  Question:  under what economic
conditions is the Marshallian analysis appropriate, and under what
conditions does the Keynesian outcome obtain?  This would seem to be a
relevant question with powerful real-world consequences.  Now, I guess if
you're a genius like Keynes, you don't need to distill a messy and complex
reality down to a formal system in order to pursue the answer to this, but
for the rest of us it seems to help.  The answer to this question I have in
mind may not be the only one, it may not be the right one, but it makes
sense, isn't obviously empirically irrelevant, and I can't imagine having
anything more than a vague intuitive grasp of it without the use of a
formal system.  

Gil



Roemer, by the way, is very good to his grad students from the reports
that I get.

On Sun, Mar 03, 2002 at 08:02:14AM -0500, Drewk wrote:
 
 For some reason, Roemer is regarded as a paragon of rigor, but he

-- 
Michael Perelman
Economics Department
California State University
Chico, CA 95929

Tel. 530-898-5321
E-Mail [EMAIL PROTECTED]





Roemer and Veneziani

2002-03-03 Thread Gil Skillman

[Was: Re: [PEN-L:23400] RE: Re: Some questions]

Roemer's Analytical foundations of Marxian economic theory
should be understood as part of an ideological attack on, and
effort to suppress, Marx's ideas in their original form

If ideological attack on can be read as a synonym for critical
assessment of, then I might agree with this claim  Otherwise I confess I
don't see it  Roemer hasn't burned any of Marx's books, and he doesn't
suggest people shouldn't read Marx  To the contrary, I would guess a large
number of people have gone back and read Marx more closely in light of
Roemer's analysis  So I also don't see any basis for the suggestion that
Roemer's book constitutes an effort to suppress Marx's ideas in their
original form  Intellectual engagement, even if misguided, does not
constitute suppression

For some reason, Roemer is regarded as a paragon of rigor, 

If there is a problem, it isn't with Roemer's formal reasoning from given
assumptions to specific conclusions, by and large  I agree that he is
occasionally less than careful in his *verbal* representations of what he's
accomplished with his formal analysis, but even here the problem seems to
be inconsistency rather than persistent misrepresentation  For example, in
the paper cited below, Veneziani reproduces a passage from _ A General
Theory_  in which Roemer appears to suggest that differential class
ownership of the means of production, all by itself, is a sufficient
condition for the existence of exploitation  But he doesn't really mean
this, as he makes quite clear in the corresponding theorem and his
introductory comments:  you need differential class ownership *plus*
scarcity of the means of production

but he
actually resorts to a blatant bait-and-switch in order to try to
put over many of the work's major results, including the claim
that one can show that exploitation is the source of profit
without the concept of value  His notion of reproducibility is
a lynchpin of the book  Well, on p 19 or so, Roemer first says
(rightly) that a certain condition is *sufficient* for
reproduction to occur, but in the next breath, he declares it
(falsely) to be a *necessary* condition  It is just a very
restrictive, special-case condition that he smuggles in because he
can't produce his results in any other way  In other words, what
he's saying is completely false

Could be  I looked for the offending passage on pp 19--21 and couldn't
find it  Does this charge have to do with the necessity claims re the
maximal profit rate atop p 21?  In any case, even if his statement is
false, I don't see what this has to do with the charge of suppression, or
for that matter, of an ideologically motivated attack on Marx 

Roberto Veneziani of the London School of Economics, in his
Exploitation and Time, has demolished Roemer's claims regarding
the role of differential ownership of productive assets
Veneziani shows that Roemer's argument falls apart once one moves
into a multiperiod context

Veneziani's paper provides a very useful and interesting contribution to
this literature, and does appear to establish that some refinement of
Roemer's basic claim about the systemic basis of exploitation is called
for  But having read the paper closely and discussed it at length with the
author, I think the paper is very far from having demolished Roemer's
claims regarding the role of 'differential ownership of productive assets,'
 properly understood  (I also suspect that Veneziani has overstated the
impact of his formal results in this connection, but note I don't infer
from this that he is guilty of an ideological attack on Roemer
representing an effort to suppress [Roemer's] ideas in their original
form )  Furthermore, to the extent it compromises Roemer's analysis, it
*necessarily* also calls into question Marx's analysis of the general law
of capital accumulation in VI, Ch 25 of Capital, since Veneziani's
results depend on the possibility that *all* individuals, not just the rich
ones, can save, a possibility that Marx evidently rules out, or at least
fails to discuss 

Details:

1)  First things first:  despite the passage from GTEC cited by Veneziani,
Roemer doesn't really assert that mere differential ownership of the means
of production (DOMP) is of itself sufficient for the existence of
exploitation  As Roemer quite explicitly explains elsewhere in GTEC, the
means of production must also be *scarce* for exploitation to arise  In
any case, his formal results on this point are unambiguous  The relevant
theorem is 22, which asserts the equivalence of the existence of
exploitation with *the possibility of positive profits* (PPP), not mere
DOMP  Since, in this formal system, the profit rate is (also) a shadow
price, this is equivalent to asserting the equivalence of exploitation with
differential ownership of *scarce* means of production (DOSMP)  So in any
case, Veneziani hasn't established anything fundamental about the
conditions for exploitation that Roemer didn't 

Re: Re: RE: Roemer and Veneziani

2002-03-03 Thread Gil Skillman

Doug, 

What!  Throw out these classics, when you could sell them on e-Bay for big
bucks?  Perverse

Gil

I was just cleaning out the bookshelves, trying to make room for new 
arrivals in a cramped Manhattan apartment, and came across two issues 
of the RRPE, one from the late 70s, the other from the early 80s One 
promised an article on The Rate of Profit, the other, new approaches 
to value theory Plus ca change

The issues are on their way to the dump

Doug





Re: Some questions

2002-03-02 Thread Gil Skillman

Sabri writes, among other things, 


PS: I looked at Roemer's Analytical foundations of Marxian
economic theory but was not particularly impressed It looks
like Varian's Microeconomic analysis By the way, Varian is
definitely better than Roemer when it comes to using TeX, that
software mathematicians use to write their papers and books

I think you underestimate the significance of Roemer's contribution, Sabri,
taking into account the book you refer to and, perhaps more centrally,
Roemer's _General Theory of Exploitation and Class_ (GTEC)  Start off by
granting that there's a considerable distance between what his titles seem
to promise--analytical *foundations* of Marxian economic theory and a
*general* theory of exploitation and class As Devine and Dymski point
out in the Ec  Phil article Jim refers to in his post, the sense in which
the latter book provides a general theory is, ironically, very specific,
in fact more normative than positive:  Roemer means that he develops an
overarching definition of exploitation that has at least three specific
manifestations, ie feudalist, capitalist, and socialist exploitation  As
DD point out, it's very *un*-general in that 

(1) since Roemer's economic analysis, even of an idealized capitalist
economy, is based on a static economic model, he can't explain how capital
scarcity and thus capitalist exploitation persists in the face of capital
accumulation

(2) since Roemer's economic analysis is based on a market model with
perfect contracting conditions (including, in effect, the ability to
specify and enforce exactly the labor to be performed), it can't explain
why capitalist exploitation is typically based on the subsumption of labor
under capital--ie, direct capitalist control of the production process  

But granting these legitimate points does not establish that Roemer has not
made a significant contribution, nor that he is a bad economist, as
opposed perhaps to a bad title chooser for his books  These points
establish rather that the level of abstraction that Roemer adopts in GTEC
corresponds formally to the level of abstraction adopted by Marx *up to*
Part 7 of Capital, volume I, since Marx (a) does not consider the existence
or effects of aggregate capital accumulation until then, and (b) never
claims one way or the other in Volume I that subsumption of labor is
*necessary* for the existence of capitalist exploitation--rather he
*assumes* that capitalist exploitation proceeds on this basis, under the
historically given conditions specific to the capitalist mode of production   

[A historical footnote:  Marx defines and discusses the significance of
formal and real subsumption in the work now known as the Resultate, ie
Results of the Immediate Process of Production, included as an appendix to
the Penguin edition of V I  Apparently this material was originally
intended for inclusion in Vol I, but was removed by Marx in an 11th-hour
decision prior to publication  The only remnant of this discussion left in
Volume I is a passing reference in Chapter 16 (p 645) to formal and real
subsumption, which does not even offer definitions of these terms]  


To that extent, Roemer's analytical framework is at least formally relevant
to Marx's level of abstraction prior to Part 7 of Volume I--that is, to a
system of commodity exchange that supports circuits of capital (represented
by M--C--M') as well as the circuit of commodity exchange for final use
(C--M--C)  And with respect to that level of abstraction, Roemer derives
the following significant results:

(1)  Putting aside the possibility (as Marx does in Volume I) that
subsumption of labor under capital is somehow necessary for the
appropriation of surplus value, differential class ownership of (scarce)
means of production is both necessary and sufficient for the existence of
surplus value and thus capitalist exploitation  Of course, as DD point
out, this entirely begs the question of how either either the scarcity or
unequal ownership of non-human productive assets persists, but that
qualification doesn't invalidate the claim, as far as it goes  As DD also
point out, formal subsumption seems to be somehow *necessary* for
exploiting labor under the capitalist mode of production, but again, Marx,
like Roemer, does not address this issue one way or the other in Volume I  

(2)  Contrary to Marx's claims in Ch 5 of Volume I, under conditions that
are at the very least *necessary* for the existence of surplus value and
thus capitalist exploitation, the scenario in which all commodities
exchange at their respective values cannot be considered the pure case of
commodity exchange, in any meaningful, non-tautological sense of the term,
and price-value disparities cannot be considered entirely incidental to
the existence of surplus value  


As an illustration of point (2), imagine a scenario of simple commodity
exchange, ie one in which there are only self-employed commodity
producers and no capitalists or circuits of 

Re: Re: Dornbusch: Argentina must surrender sovereignty on financial issues!!!!

2002-03-02 Thread Gil Skillman

In this context, let us not forget that a committee of central bankers
runs a significant aspect of the US economy.  Nor forget European nations'
fears that consolidation of the EU would mean they all march to the
economic tune of the Bundesbank.  There's a common theme at work here.  

Gil

 
I hope people read the piece.  Although the formatting on Alan's post is
not easy, the URL is clear.  They come right out an say that a committee
of central bankers should come in and run the place.

Does anyone here know about the Austrian experience that they discuss.
 -- 
Michael Perelman
Economics Department
California State University
Chico, CA 95929
a
Tel. 530-898-5321
E-Mail [EMAIL PROTECTED]





Re: a lesson from Japan?

2002-02-25 Thread Gil Skillman

But let us not forget that Japan has faced some serious constraints in
digging itself out of its deflationary spiral, constraints that the US
doesn't necessarily face.  Among them:

1)  The link from loose monetary policy to expansion-creating loans has
been disrupted by the high percentage of non-performing loans held by
Japanese banks (now 35% or so); compare that to less than 10% (I think) for
the US economy.

2)  Free trade logic says Japan should have allowed significant devaluation
of its currency, but this has consistently been opposed by the US, who
doesn't want to see the resulting upswing in its trade deficit w/ Japan.
Since the US Congress carries a big stick in the form of credible threats
of quotas, this policy avenue has been more or less off limits.  The yen
has only come down relative to the dollar in the last 10 months, and that
only about a 10% fall.  

3)  The current US macro situation isn't yet near Japan's deflationary trap
(with near-zero interest rates and falling prices)--the inflation rate is
very small but still positive; thus so far as I know there aren't reports
of households or firms putting off spending due to expectations of lower
future prices.  To the contrary, industrial production and retail sales are
picking up.  What additional shock could the burst bubble have that will
reverse these gains?

In light of the above it would have been insightful to also have
comparative before-and-after data on deflation, unemployment, and real
interest rates.

On the other hand, the US has dramatically higher levels of household debt
and bankruptcy rates.  But who knows how to factor that in to the mix.

Gil


MARCH 4, 2002/BUSINESSWEEK 

ECONOMIC TRENDS [by Michael J. Mandel] 

A Lesson from Japan...

Post-boom blues can be delayed

With consumer spending strong and productivity soaring, the U.S. seems to
have escaped the worst effects of the popping of the stock market bubble.
But history suggests it may be too soon to relax, since it can take
considerable time for even a steep market decline to be felt in the real
economy.

Consider Japan, where the stock market plummeted by 35% from the end of 1989
to August, 1990. Nevertheless, Japanese consumer spending, productivity
growth, output growth, and business investment stayed strong well into 1991.
It was only then--about 18 months after the financial collapse started--that
the economy slowed sharply.

For example, in the boom years of 1988 and 1989, Japanese consumer spending
rose at a nearly 5% rate. In the 18 months after the bubble popped, consumer
spending continued to rise at a 3.5% rate--slower, but still impressive
(table). Growth of gross domestic product was also quite good, averaging
4.2% over the same period.

Moreover, Japanese productivity, measured as output per worker, rose at a
decent 2.2% clip between the end of 1989 and the middle of 1991. Output per
hour, the productivity measure the U.S. uses, likely rose at an even faster
rate, since hours worked per person fell sharply in this period.

Surprisingly, Japanese economic performance in this post-bubble period was
actually better than the U.S. has shown recently. For example, since the
Standard  Poor's 500-stock index started decisively downward in the summer
of 2000, U.S. productivity has risen at a 1.8% rate, slower than the
Japanese productivity growth in the early 1990s.

That doesn't mean the U.S. is going to fall into a Japan-like stagnation.
But the Japanese example is cautionary: After a bubble pops, good macro
numbers are no guarantee of future performance. 


Table: After the Bubble: Japan and the U.S.

 6 QUARTERS  6 QUARTERS
 BEFORE EQUITY   AFTER EQUITY
 BUBBLE POPPED*  BUBBLE POPPED*
  ---
   ANNUALIZED RATE OF GROWTH

REAL CONSUMER SPENDING
JAPAN   4.9 3.5
U.S 5.0 3.2

PRODUCTIVITY**
JAPAN   3.8 2.2
U.S 3.1 1.8

* For Japan, measured from the end of the fourth quarter, 1989.
For the U.S., measured from end of the second quarter, 2000.

** Japanese productivity measured as output per worker. U.S. productivity
measured as nonfarm business output per hour.



Jim Devine [EMAIL PROTECTED]   http://bellarmine.lmu.edu/~jdevine





Macro, micro, and Marx's method

2002-02-24 Thread Gil Skillman

[Was:  Transformation Tsurris]

Jim raises a number of interesting issues that go well beyond the simple
point I suggested re Marx's V. III transformation of commodity values into
prices of production.  I react to some of these points below.  Those not
interested in metatheoretical/pedagogical issues respecting Marx's analysis
in Capital should hit the delete key now.  

1.  Macro vs. Micro in Marx

Jim writes

Unlike modern orthodox economics which starts with so-called
microfoundations and tries to explain all macro phenomena, Marx started
(in volume I) with macro issues, the conflict in production between
abstract capital and abstract labor (since he abstracts from the use-value
of all commodities except labor-power) on the level of capitalist society as
a whole. That is, he uses his law of value to break through the confusions
implied by commodity production, i.e., the fetishism of commodities, to
focus on what he thought was most important, the societal capital/labor
relationship _in general_. 

Of course, Marx wrote before a clear line of demarcation between macro-
and micro-economics was established in mainstream analysis, so it's no
surprise that Marx didn't pay much respect to a theoretical boundary line
that didn't as yet exist. And for a reason detailed below, drawing a strict
micro/macro partition is necessarily harder to do in Marxland than
Mainstreamland.  

Applying standard definitions retroactively, though, one can see where and
how Marx crosses the line in _Capital_.  By these definitions, Marx's
starting point in V. I.  is apparently micro in nature, in the specific
sense that no reference to any economic aggregate is made in initiating his
argument.  He starts by describing capitalist wealth as a collection {a
collection, note, not an aggregate; he's introduced no basis for
aggregating heterogeneous commodities as yet}.  He then introduces a
qualitative distinction between the use value and exchange value of
individual commodities, and a claim about the quantitative relation (i.e.,
equality) among exchanged bundles of commodities.  Both of these are
essentially micro claims; again, no reference to any economy-wide
*aggregate* is required to make them.   

A truly macro relation (again, by standard distinctions) doesn't emerge
until Marx's statement of the macro money identity (MV=PT) in Chapter 3.
But Marx doesn't make immediate use of this identity, and macro
considerations, again subject to the caveat below, don't arise again until
Part 7 of V. I.  

What's the caveat?  Consistent with Jim's comments above and below, the
conventional (from a mainstream standpoint) boundary between micro and
macro is obscured because Marx deals with aggregates that tend to be
ignored or at least de-emphasized in mainstream theory--i.e., aggregates at
the level of class.  Issues at this level are in the conventional sense
micro since they deal with questions of distribution and economic
interests of class actors; yet they bear immediate macro consequences
since class distribution affects, among other things, the rates of
accumulation and growth and the level of unemployment.  Thus I read Jim's
comments as consistent with the prospect that micro and macro
conditions are simultaneously determined in Marx, whatever his choice of
emphasis. 

...This abstraction means that he actively ignores -- abstracts from --
differences amongst heterogeneous capitals, including the technical
differences such as those represented by the organic composition of
capital and social differences such as those represented by the rate of
surplus-value, so that prices and values are proportional (as this
literature notes). In other words, he starts with the average capitalist
exploiting the average worker. (Unfortunately, rather than explaining this
clearly, he simply uses the 19th century British cotton textile industry as
representing the average. That's confusing, since it probably wasn't the
average industry.) At this level, we see the general conditions of the class
struggle determining the rate of surplus-value and the mass of
surplus-value. (General conditions of class struggle in turn depend on the
rate of accumulation, political institutions, etc., which in turn depend on
previous conditions of the class struggle, which in turn depend on ... a
long historical process.)

In volume III, he moves away from the macro level to address the issues how
the participants in the capitalist system see things and respond
(microfoundations) so that suddenly issues like supply and demand become
relevant (having been irrelevant at the volume I level of abstraction). 

But it's intriguing, isn't it, how repeatedly issues of demand and supply
come up explicitly in Marx's Vol.I, chapter 25 discussion of the general
law of capital accumulation (e.g., pp 763, 769, 792, Penguin ed.)?  In
fact, I don't know how you can even talk about this law without talking
about the implications of accumulation for the demand for labor power
relative to 

Re: On the necessity of socialism

2002-02-22 Thread Gil Skillman

In response to Doug's (tongue-in-cheek?) comment

Never. It was a ruse devised by the bourgeoisie to occupy the 
attention of otherwise smart and knowledgeable Marxian economists on 
something addictively divisive but politically irrelevant.

Charles writes

Charles:  Isn't it worse than that ?  Marx asserts as principle the 
insolubility of the transformation problem.  The unsystematic relationship 
between value and prices is symptomatic of the basic anarchy of capitalist 
production. If the problem were solved , Marx would be refuted.

Depends on what you think the transformation problem refers to.  As I
read Marx, the problem, as he posed it in Chapter 9 of Volume III, lies
in showing that aggregate prices equal aggregate values and aggregate
surplus value equals aggregate profits even if commodities exchange at
prices of production which are disproportional to their values (which is
the general case).  Issues have been raised with the logic of Marx's
original demonstration, and interpretations of his value theory have been
offered that get around these issues at the cost of raising others.  But
the real question, it seems to me, is whether anything at all that is
critical to Marxist political economy hinges on this demonstration.  And I
agree with Doug's negative response to this question.

Gil




The famous PEN-L debate

2000-12-14 Thread Gil Skillman

Hello Jim,

I was trolling through the Web when I came across this blurb from you
extolling a new book, From Capitalism to Inequality:

"Chapter three ... is crystal-clear. If we'd read this chapter
   beforehand, the famous PEN-L debate with Gil Skillman over
   volume I of Capital would not have happened."—Jim Devine 

Intrigued (and pleased to hear that the debate is "famous"), I shelled out
the $20 to order a copy and waited anxiously to receive it.  But when I got
the book and read Chapter 3, I found only a rehash of the very same
arguments in Capital that I had been criticizing as logically incoherent,
with no attempt at all to come to grips with that criticism.  Indeed, the
rehash in this book had much less nuance than Marx's original argument, so
it's very hard for me to see how the "crystal-clear" analysis you extol in
Chapter 3 would have obviated the debate.  Could you please direct me to
the points in the chapter that you believe successfully anticipate and
address my argument?

In curiosity, Gil

 




[PEN-L:10187] Re: Re: John Lloyd article on Russian collapse

1999-08-18 Thread Gil Skillman


Worse even. GDP, or some approximation of it, has fallen by half in 
Russia, about twice as bad as the U.S. during the Depression - but 
social indicators are much worse, with life expectancy falling and 
the population shrinking. I don't think there's any precedent for a 
falling population in a modern country not at war.

Although I certainly agree that the West has played a key role in turning
Russia into a socio-economic basket case, there may be more here than meets
the eye.  First, concerning the statistics, there is a potential double
measurement problem.  The USSR might have overstated GDP and understated
negative social indicators, while the underground (and thus undermeasured)
economy is probably a much bigger factor in present-day Russia.  Second,
population is now shrinking in very modern and not-at-war Japan, and has
been shrinking in the non-war past (it may still be true) of very modern
Scandinavia.

Gil






[PEN-L:9819] Re: Re: Re: Hayek on Keynes

1999-08-03 Thread Gil Skillman

In response to the passages I cited from _Road to Serfdom_, Doug writes

Hayek is clear that these welfare measures should remain pretty 
minimal, and not interfere with work discipline.

Yes, according to his personal value judgment.  But as the passages cited
(particularly the one from p. 37) make clear, the Hayek of 1944 granted
that as a matter of *principle* the degree of state intervention in these
areas was purely a matter of costs vs. benefits, so long as any such
intervention supplemented rather than "replaced" the mechanism of market
competition.  Keynes probably couldn't have disagreed with this statement
of principle, and given his shared antipathy to Marxism noted by other
listmates, that was plausibly sufficient for his endorsement.

On another note, Doug, I've checked on the Blaug quote with a colleague,
Bill Barber, who does history of thought.  He agrees that general
equilibrium was pretty much a dead letter by the turn of the century, but
disagrees with the date that Blaug associates with its revival.  Barber
places the latter in the 40s rather than the 30s, which was my sense as well.  

But Keynes had also written about state manipulation of investment. 
There's a lot that's vague and contradictory about his writings on 
the topic, but it's clear he was talking about at least some 
encroachments on the sacred power of capitalists over investment. At 
the moment he was endorsing RtS, 1944, he was designing Bretton 
Woods, with its capital controls and fixed exchange rates. He'd 
recently written his essay on national self-sufficiency, and idea 
Hayek finds nightmarish (for rather congenially internationalist 
reasons, I've got to admit). So the endorsement of a mild welfare 
state was enough to win JMK over?

Doug







[PEN-L:9813] Re: Hayek on Keynes

1999-08-03 Thread Gil Skillman

I'm coming rather late to this thread, but I thought I'd add my $.02 since
I've just been dealing in depth with this book in a course last semester on
the political economy of socialism.

I just pulled my ancient copy of Hayek's Road to Serfdom down from 
the shelf, and noticed this jacket blurb from J.M. Keynes: "In my 
opinion it is a grand book... Morally and philosophically I find 
myself in agreement with virtually the whole of it; and not only in 
agreement with it, but in deeply moved agreement." Since Hayek seems 
to regard any kind of planning or welfare state measures as the first 
steps in the title's path, this would presumably include most of what 
the world now thinks of as Keynesian - not to mention "the somewhat 
comprehensive socialization of investment" and the "euthanasia of the 
rentier." Does anyone know what this is all about?


Well, one possible explanation is that, at least as of 1944, Hayek granted
the legitimacy of state intervention to a remarkable extent, subject
primarily to the qualification that such interventions "supplement" rather
than "replace" market competition.  Thus, for example, he conceded the
appropriateness of health and safety regulations:

Though all such controls of the methods of production impose extra costs
(i.e. make it necessary to use 
more resources to produce a given output), they may well be worthwhile.
To prohibit the use of certain 
poisonous substances or to require special precautions in their use, to
limit working hours [!!--GS] or to 
require certain sanitary arrangements, is fully compatible with the
preservation of competition.  The only
question here is whether in the particular instance the advantages gained
are greater than the social costs
which they impose. [RtS, p. 37]

and allowed more generally that governments might legitimately provide
good or correct externalities:

There are, finally, undoubted fields where no legal arrangements can
create the main condition on which the 
usefulness of the system of competition and private property depends:
namely, that the owner benefits from 
all the useful services rendered by his property and suffers for all the
damages caused to others by its use
In all these instances there is a divergence between the items which
enter into private calculation and those
which affect social welfare; and whenever this divergence becomes
important, some method other than 
competition may have to be found to supply the services in question.  Thus
neither the provision of signposts
on the roads, nor, in most circumstances, that of the roads themselves can
be paid for by every individual
user.  Nor can certain harmful effects of deforestation, ...or of the
smoke and noise of factories be confined to 
the owner of the property in question or to those who are willing to
submit to the damage for an agreed 
compensation.  In such instances we must find some substitute for the
regulation by the price mechanism.
(p. 39).

Accordingly, he sanctioned governmental macroeconomic intervention:

There is, finally, the supremely important problem of combating general
fluctuations of economic activity and
  the recurrent waves of large-scale unemployment which accompany
them.  This is, of course, one of the 
gravest and most pressing problems of our time.  But though its solution
will require much planning in the 
good sense, it does not--or at least need not---require that special kind
of planning which according to its 
advocates is to replace the market. (p. 121)

[He goes on to say that monetary policy is completely compatible with the
tenets of 19th-century liberalism, 
but that classical liberals should "watch their step" in using fiscal
policy measures--but not necessarily avoid 
them entirely.]

He also did not rule out certain activities of the welfare state:

Nor is the preservation of competition incompatible with an extensive
system of social services--so long as the  
 organization of these services is not designed in such a way as to
make competition ineffective over wide fields.
(p. 37)

  .including the provision of a minimum income.

There is no reason why in a society which has reached the general level of
wealth which ours has attained 
the first kid of security ("security against severe physical privation,
and the certainty of a given minimum of 
sustenance for all') should not be guaranteed to all without endangering
general freedom. (p120).

In light of these passages it's not so hard to understand Keynes's
endorsement.  My sense is that Hayek subsequently became much more
conservative re the appropriate range of state activities.  Gil






[PEN-L:9716] Re: Gen. Equilibrium

1999-07-29 Thread Gil Skillman

Doug, I can't tell from your post what you're taking issue with:  that gen
eq was revived in the 1930s?  That it was considered "everybody's
economics"?  What? Gil

Mark Blaug writes in Economic Theory in Retrospect (5th ed., p. 290):

"Utility theory was gradually deprived of all its bite and reduced 
from cardinal to ordinal utility and from ordinal utility to 
'revealed preference'; cost theories of value were shown, not to be 
wrong, but only valid in special cases; and general equilbrium 
virtually disappeared by 1900, only to be revived in the 1930s by 
Hicks and Samuelson as 'everybody's economics'"

This isn't the story you get from Keynes or modern post-Keynesians; 
what's up here?

Doug







[PEN-L:9661] Re: FW: reprint of Kennedy essay

1999-07-27 Thread Gil Skillman

Jim, Judging from the magazine's website, they're lefty and write
critically of Clinton, the Kosovo war, US poverty policy, etc.   Gil


-Original Message-
From: Editor, Albion Monitor [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: [EMAIL PROTECTED] [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Date: Monday, July 19, 1999 4:35 PM
Subject: reprint of Kennedy essay


Hello,

One of our readers forwarded to us your essay, "JFK Jr and the Hubris of
the Rich," which apparently appeared on a mailing list. Although it's quite
unusual for us to solicit material like this, we'd like to reprint it in
the Albion Monitor as a letter to the editor. While junior will likely be
eulogized to the heavens this week, your essay gives a perspective that
most won't see.

Please let us know by Tuesday noon (Pacific time) whether we can reprint it
in this manner.

Thanks,
Jeff Elliott
-
 "Empty wagons make the most noise."  -- Farmer's Almanac, 1881
 [EMAIL PROTECTED]   Jeff Elliott   Editor, Albion Monitor
 (707) 823-0100 vhttp://www.monitor.net/monitor

Anyone know about the content and perspectives of this magazine?

Jim C







  1   2   >