Re: Math

2004-07-21 Thread Doyle Saylor
Greetings Economists,
CB (Charles Brown) writes,
(first),
...Math, grammar and logic are all sets of rules on how to use symbols
then CB writes,
...logic is mathematical and linguistic, but I am curious on the essential
distinction between linguistics and mathematics implied here

To which JD (James Devine) replies,
...it's possible that math might be part of Chomsky's transformational
grammar, i.e., the structure of human language that is inborn (built-in)
in the human brain? In that case, math is linguistic, but not merely
so

Doyle,
Chomsky's transformational grammar?  This is still a debate about what
exactly is inherited.  A better discussion about the issue of inheritance is
found in Gould's book, The Structure of Evolutionary Theory, Belknap,
Harvard press, 2002.  Chapter eight, Species as Individuals in the
Hierarchical Theory of Selection, pages 638 through 644 discuss some of the
problems that Dawkins has with the idea of rule based inheritance.

Since you seem to think grammar is inherited, Let's try to make a
distinction here that most people could understand.  Logic has been treated
as part of mathematics for awhile.  So I won't distinguish between them.
Grammar structures language as is the commonplace.  We might go to
Wittgenstein to get an odd ball view of grammar (Philosophical Grammar,
Wittgenstein, Blackwell, 1974) which parallels JD's conflation of
mathematics and language.  However, mathematics doesn't appear to grammarize
symbols.  There is a case for a low level math instinct in the sense of
babies can count before they can think language.  That is called subitizing.

To understand the difference then between grammar and subitizing it is best
to consider the difference in the labor processes.  The basis for language
is joint attention.  That is at some point babies learn to look at a parents
face and follow their gaze.  So if mom looks at something like a toy the
baby understands something about the object which is a toy.  Or food, or
whatever.  Sharing attention means more or less mind reading.  That is
states of the brain are shared and understood to be shared.

Mom does her brain work in her old familiar ways.  That is incoming to the
occipital lobe mainly for vision, naming things in the temporal lobe, doing
things in the parietal lobe, and organizing and planning what to do with
stuff in the temporal lobe and parietal is done in the frontal lobe.  The
baby does roughly the same sort of stuff.  Babies vary in how they do things
from their parents for various reasons.  The baby learns how to use their
mind from the example of the parents.  Habits of brain work.  Not
necessarily there in terms of a grammar.  Grammar is variable within bounds.
Chomsky like the enlightenment thinkers he has always sprung his own thought
from thinks of this as a universal essence.  However, Gould and others see
this differently.  We may have a tool that can do certain things, the brain.
But what emerges in how we do things must certainly vary.  How can the brain
anticipate email?

A general purpose theory of the work process of brainwork that grammar
implies, presumes that we understand what exactly the brain is doing word by
word.  George Lakoff the linguist looks at where Mathematics comes from.
Like many linguists Lakoff broadly uses metaphor as the basic mechanism of
thought and therefore of mathematics.  In his book, Where Mathematics Comes
From,. Lakoff, Nunez, Basic Books, 2000, gives an extended examination of
all levels of mathematics to trace down how metaphor might be the basis for
mathematics.  Metaphor stands in for field states in the brain.  So for
example at a given time, various fields are connected in the occipital lobe,
temporal lobe, and frontal lobe.  That being the metaphor.

Returning to grammar, language is a representation of between a parent and
child the basic way to use the face and hands to do work in the world.
Mathematics is not confined to that metaphor.  Math does not function in
brain work like plain language acts.  Grammar is not mathematics.  They are
both metaphorical in the sense that sheets of neurons interconnect in
patterns.  But the labor processes are different.  Nor is it possible in my
view to say grammar is inherited.  As most evolutionary theorists would say
there is a wholeness of environment and human beings that does not reduce to
rules.

Let's try to envision that.  If I write this piece I am using a linear
script to describe brain states or metaphorical activity in the brain.
However, the brain states are not linear.  So in the sense I write anything
linearly I am not conceptualizing the process of thinking.  If I
conceptualize thinking that is create symbols that work like thinking, I
might then find ways to do non-grammatical language.  That is not restrict
myself to an a priori limitation to what can be done.
Thanks,
Doyle


math

2004-07-19 Thread Devine, James
[was: RE: [PEN-L] absolute general law of capitalist accumulation]

Charles writes:
CB: I want to go dialectical on y'all and say logic is mathematical and
linguistic, but I am curious on the essential distinction between
linguistics and mathematics implied here.

it's possible that math might be part of Chomsky's transformational grammar, i.e., the 
structure of human language that is inborn (built-in) in the human brain? In that 
case, math is linguistic, but not merely so.

It seems to me that math represents the abstract aspects of reality. But since it 
leaves out the concrete, it must be incomplete.

(oops, I'm going Johnny Cochrane on y'all.)
jd 



math

2004-07-19 Thread Charles Brown
Math, grammar and logic are all sets of rules on how to use symbols.

CB


by Devine, James

[was: RE: [PEN-L] absolute general law of capitalist accumulation]

Charles writes:
CB: I want to go dialectical on y'all and say logic is mathematical and
linguistic, but I am curious on the essential distinction between
linguistics and mathematics implied here.

it's possible that math might be part of Chomsky's transformational grammar,

i.e., the structure of human language that is inborn (built-in) in the
human
brain? In that case, math is linguistic, but not merely so.

It seems to me that math represents the abstract aspects of reality. But
since
it leaves out the concrete, it must be incomplete.

(oops, I'm going Johnny Cochrane on y'all.)
jd


Degrees of Freedom Fw: Re: Eco-Math

2003-07-19 Thread Eubulides
[A lesson worthwhile for those engaged in political economy-ecology. From
the Ecological Society of America...]


- Original Message -
From: Patrick Foley [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Friday, July 18, 2003 5:48 PM
Subject: Re: Eco-Math


 Warren,

 Mathematics is very powerful in physics because the laws of physics are
 simple. Ecology, while ultimately dependent on physics, is far too messy
 to follow simple axioms and provide exact results.

 As Burnham and Anderson point out in their 2002 book, Model Selection
 and Multimodel Inference, the actual number of degrees of freedom in
 ecological models is so large that it might as well be infinite. Our
 attempts to use parsimony as a guide are often just dumb (that's me
 speaking not B and A, I think). Often the most elegant and beautiful
 theory is the correct one in physics. Not so, in ecology.

 Patrick Foley (ecologist and recovering mathematician)
 [EMAIL PROTECTED]

 Warren W. Aney wrote:

 How useful and basic is mathematics in the field of ecology?  I'm not
 talking about just using mathematics (and statistics) to describe,
model,
 and test.  I'm talking about the basic idea posed by Edward O. Wilson
that
 there is a natural body of mathematics that will serve as a natural
language
 for biology and hints that mathematics may even provide a bridge that
 unifies all sciences (Consilience, pp. 103-104, 212-214).
 
 An article by Max Tegmark in the May issue of Scientific American
discusses
 the correspondence between mathematics and physics (and, presumably,
natural
 sciences in general) and how it goes back to Greek philosophy:
 
 According to the Aristotelian paradigm physical reality is fundamental
and
 mathematical language is merely a useful approximation.  According to
the
 Platonic paradigm, the mathematical structure is the true reality and
 observers percieve it imperfectly. (page 49)
 
 Elsewhere in the article Tegmark says that scientists discover
mathematical
 structures rather than create them and quotes physicist Eugene P.
Wigner:
 the enormous usefulness of mathematics in the natural sciences is
something
 bordering on the mysterious.
 
 I guess I tend to have an Aristotelian view of mathematics, but E. O.
Wilson
 probably has advanced to the Platonic view.  I could expand on this,
but I'd
 like to hear other viewpoints instead.
 
 Warren W. Aney
 Senior Wildlife Ecologist
 
 
 


CEPR: Paying the Bills in Brazil: Does the IMF's Math Add Up?

2002-09-26 Thread Robert Naiman


September 25, 2002

Center for Economic and Policy Research

Paying the Bills in Brazil:
Does the IMF's Math Add Up?

By Mark Weisbrot and Dean Baker

Executive Summary (full paper is at www.cepr.net)

The IMF has recently approved a $30 billion loan
to Brazil, with the idea that the government
should eventually be able to stabilize its growing
public debt burden at a sustainable level. This
paper looks at the trajectory of the country's
debt to assess whether such an outcome is likely.
The evidence indicates that Brazil is extremely
unlikely to reach a sustainable level of debt
service, and return to a normal growth path, until
a partial default has allowed the country to write
off some of its debt.

Brazil's public debt rose from 29.2 percent of GDP
in 1994 to nearly 62 percent of GDP at present.
(See Figure 1). The budget deficit is currently
running at about 6 percent of GDP for 2002. The
real interest rate on Brazil's debt has averaged
16.1 percent over the last eight years
(1994-2001). With interest rates at this level,
deficits quickly grow through time; as this year's
deficit increases next year's interest burden, the
debt burden becomes explosive.

The paper examines several possible scenarios for
Brazil's debt (see Figure 2):

·Assuming a 16.1 percent
annual real interest rate for the future, the same
as its average over the last eight years: This
scenario is explosive, with the debt-to-GDP ratio
quickly reaching implausible levels.[2] By 2009,
the debt is projected to exceed 100 percent of
GDP. It would be more than 188 percent of GDP by
2016. Of course these levels would not be reached;
along this path, financial markets would demand
ever higher risk premiums, which would raise the
interest rate to higher levels yet, and default
would cut short the process of accelerating debt
accumulation.

·The implicit real interest on
the public debt for the first six months of 2002
was 15.5 percent, or 33.5 percent at an annual
rate. If we take an extremely conservative
estimate for the 2nd half of the year, and project
an annual rate of 21.0 percent for the year 2002,
the debt is rapidly explosive. If we assume annual
interest rates at the (underestimated) 21.0
percent rate for 2002, the ratio of debt-to-GDP
would reach more than 100 percent in 2007. By
2012, the ratio of debt-to-GDP would pass 200
percent. On this path, which may best represent
Brazil's current situation, the financial markets
will very quickly give up hope that Brazil will be
able to repay its debt in full.

·Assuming, as an optimistic
scenario, that the real interest rate falls to 10
percent over the next two and a half years and
stays at this level (real rates this low were
achieved only once in the last eight years): the
debt-to-GDP ratio will still rise to extremely
high levels. By the end of 2010 it would reach
almost 80 percent of GDP. By 2016, it would have
grown to almost 90 percent of GDP. As in the other
scenarios, these projections assume that the
interest rate does not rise, even though the
debt-to-GDP ratio grows substantially. This is
almost impossibly optimistic, as investors would
surely become increasingly concerned about the
probability of default as the debt-to-GDP ratio
continued to rise.

The paper also considers the possibility of
stabilizing the debt-to-GDP ratio by running
larger primary budget surpluses (see Figure 3).
This would require such huge primary budget
surpluses that it would not be potentially
achievable.

There is also the possibility that the central
bank could switch to a much lower short-term
interest rate policy -- the nominal rate is
currently still high at 18 percent -- and thereby
eventually lower the interest burden of the debt.
This would be difficult for a number of reasons,
including the exchange rate risk, and the risk of
default -- which is difficult to reverse now that
the debt-to-GDP ratio is so high. But in any case,
a trajectory that includes a new central bank
policy with much lower short-term interest rates
is not on the agenda, and is definitely not part
of the IMF's current loan agreement. Therefore the
projections included in this paper would cover the
range of possibilities that could be expected if
Brazil continues its current policies.

On the basis of current policies, as well as past
and present economic data, a scenario under which
Brazil's debt burden stabilizes at a sustainable
level would have to be regarded as an extremely
low-probability event. It would depend on Brazil's
economic and fiscal policy meeting targets that
could not be regarded as plausible, and/or a world
in which international financial markets behaved
very differently than they have in the past. If
the IMF cannot produce a credible intermediate or
long-range projection under which Brazil could
stabilize its debt service at a sustainable level,
then the purpose of this $30 billion loan
agreement is questionable.




Re: Do the math. I

2000-02-08 Thread Timework Web

Max Sawicky wrote,

 But suppose it is the ratio of net of tax income?
 In Walker's example, the ratio changes from
 (9/8)*(rich inc/poor inc) to (91/82) * (rich/poor).
 The latter is smaller, which could be taken to
 mean "more" progressivity.  Or less inequality.

The dictionary definition Roger gave didn't say anything about the ratio
of net of tax incomes nor did it say anything about the ratio of changes
in rates. The principle of progressive taxation was introduced in
economics, I believe, by Boisguilbert from the perspective of the revenue
collecting state. Boisguilbert argued that revenues would be more
bountiful and less oppressive if taxes were assessed according to the
ability to pay. The ratio of net of tax incomes Max brings up is a
secondary effect, but as Max's example shows, one doesn't need a
progressive tax rate structure to lower the ratio. Whether a lower ratio
of after tax incomes is "progressive" in some other sense is a question I
won't go into. It is not progressive taxation.

 Since in the after-tax case the two are getting
 the same electricity, while the ratio of rich
 after-tax to poor after-tax has declined, it
 is reasonable to say a rate cut is progressive
 because the result is "more" progressive   

I assume Max means the two are consuming the same amount of electricity as
before -- which is only the ceterus paribus assumption. It could be that
the change in rates also changes the consumption patterns, depending on
the elasticities of demand. The two are NOT "getting the same  
electricity" in the sense of the wealthy and poor customer consuming the
same amount as each other.

I repeat, progressive taxation has to do with rate structures, not the
ratios of after-tax income. To extend the label of progressive to the
latter is to argue by analogy, but the analogy is flawed. The
progressivity of the rate structure is FROM THE PERSPECTIVE of the
revenue collecting state, which is a single entity. The analogical
"progressivity" of after-tax incomes is from the separate perspectives of
the rich and poor consumers. Thus to label the latter "progressive" is to
impose an interpersonal comparison of utility. It is a violent
simplification of a much more complicated case.

Progressive taxation is a simple matter of arithmetic. Progressive second
order effects is not.

The Tricky Devil



RE: Do the math. II

2000-02-08 Thread Timework Web

Roger Odisio wrote,
  
 The clearest way to see the effect . . .

The key word here is "effect". The illustration you gave, Roger, is not of
a flat-rate reduction but of a lump-sum rebate. Under the circumstances, a
lump-sum rebate _would_ be progressive in the strict sense that I
use. Unfortunately, it doesn't illustrate the case we've been talking
about.

 In a tax system with two tiers, which do you think is more
 progressive--when the poor pay 1% of their income and the rich pay 40%,
 or when the poor pay 2% and the rich pay 80%.  Or are these the same
 because the ratio of rates stays the same?

This two tier tax system is too abstract for me to touch. Say the "poor"
earn $10,000 a year and the "rich" earn $15,000. Neither tax system could
be considered progressive because neither respects the principle of
ability to pay. Your underlying point here is a valid one: that
judging progressivity simply by the ratio of rates is an over
simplification. But I don't think one corrects for the over simplification
by adding false analogies and even more over simplifications.


Tom Walker



Re: RE: Do the math. II

2000-02-08 Thread Roger Odisio

Tom Walker wrote:

 Roger Odisio wrote,

  The clearest way to see the effect . . .

 The key word here is "effect". The illustration you gave, Roger, is not of
 a flat-rate reduction but of a lump-sum rebate. Under the circumstances, a
 lump-sum rebate _would_ be progressive in the strict sense that I
 use. Unfortunately, it doesn't illustrate the case we've been talking
 about.

An electricity price reduction is the same thing as a lump sum rebate in this
context; each has the same effect on disposable income. And a price
reduction/lump sum rebate is precisely what we *are* talking about.  Gene
asked whether it was correct to claim that a reduction in electricity prices
would be progessive as to to income.  I said yes, and I see you agree.  Case
closed?

RO



Re: Do the math. II

2000-02-08 Thread Timework Web

Roger Odisio wrote,

 An electricity price reduction is the same thing as a lump sum rebate in
 this context; each has the same effect on disposable income.

No. The lump-sum rebate in your example was without regard to levels of
consumption. The poor consumer received the same $200 as the rich
consumer, even though the rich consumer consumes more electricity
(although a smaller proportion of the rich consumer's income).

 And a price reduction/lump sum rebate is precisely what we *are* talking
 about.  Gene asked whether it was correct to claim that a reduction in
 electricity prices would be progessive as to to income.  

A price reduction would distribute savings according to the quantity of
electricity consumed. Thus, as Gene pointed out, the wealthy consumers --
who, it is assumed, consume more electricity -- would save more money in
absolute terms.

To my recollection, Gene did not ask if the reduction would be
"progressive as to income" (whatever that means). He asked whether it
would be like a progressive taxation.

 I said yes, and I see you agree.  Case closed?

See my next message, "Fuck the math, do the history."


Tricky Devil



Re: Re: Do the math. II

2000-02-08 Thread Roger Odisio

Tom Walker:

 Roger Odisio wrote,

  An electricity price reduction is the same thing as a lump sum rebate in
  this context; each has the same effect on disposable income.

 No. The lump-sum rebate in your example was without regard to levels of
 consumption. The poor consumer received the same $200 as the rich
 consumer, even though the rich consumer consumes more electricity
 (although a smaller proportion of the rich consumer's income).

  And a price reduction/lump sum rebate is precisely what we *are* talking
  about.  Gene asked whether it was correct to claim that a reduction in
  electricity prices would be progessive as to to income.

 A price reduction would distribute savings according to the quantity of
 electricity consumed. Thus, as Gene pointed out, the wealthy consumers --
 who, it is assumed, consume more electricity -- would save more money in
 absolute terms.

 To my recollection, Gene did not ask if the reduction would be
 "progressive as to income" (whatever that means). He asked whether it
 would be like a progressive taxation.

While it is of course true that wealthier customers get more savings because
they consume more electricity, that changes nothing about the conclusion.

Do you know anything about the difference in electricity consumption by income
group compared to the spread of the income distribution itself?  Poor families
typically consume roughly  400-500 kwh/ mo., while on average wealthier
families use about 500-800 kwh/mo. (one point being that more sophiscated
buyers usually make better use of ways to conserve electricity and use it more
efficiently, thus preventing usage gaps betwen rich and poor from widening
further).   I'll assume you know something about the fact the spread in income
difference between rich and poor is much larger than that.  (And, no, I don't
mean between $10,000 and $15,000--the last bit of bullshit you used to avoid
addressing which tax system I posited was more progressive.)

The point being, that yes, a price reduction will mean more dollars to
wealthier customers, but, in considering possible progressivity, that effect
is swamped by the larger spread between the income of the poor and wealthy.
The savings for the wealthy are less as a percentage of income, which was my
point and leads to the answer of the question Gene asked.

RO



Re: Fuck the math. Do the history!

2000-02-08 Thread Roger Odisio

Tom Walker:

 I sense a lot of associative confusion on the issue of
 "progressive" taxation. There are two connotations of progressive that are
 being mixed up here. There is also an intimate historical connection
 between the uses of the two connotations. One meaning of progressive is
 the arithmetic one in which rates become higher as ability to pay
 increases. The other has to do with the distributive justice that
 presumably results from a system of progressive taxation. What Roger, Max
 the two neo-classical economists and others seem to be arguing is that the
 hypothetical rate decrease increases distributive justice, therefore it is
 progressive (in the latter sense). I won't have anything to do with that
 argument because it brings in too many undefined variables. We might as
 well discuss the Laffer curve -- because that's where shoot from the hip
 backformations take us.

Typical email gambit, I see.  Create a strawman position (Max, I, and others
aren't merely answering the "arithmetic" question about progressivity, but
"seem to be arguing" for some claim of distributive justice), attribute it to
others, and whack away.  But you've added a novel twist, at least.  That
strawman you've created is so unworthy, you say, you refuse to talk about it!

I can't think of anything further I could possibly want to say on the topic of
progressivity, Tom, including in response to whatever it is you can dream up
to say about my last two messages.  Bye.

RO




Re: Do the math. II

2000-02-08 Thread Timework Web

Roger Odisio wrote,
  
 mean between $10,000 and $15,000--the last bit of bullshit you used to
 avoid addressing which tax system I posited was more progressive.)

Getting testy now, are we?

Max has an income of $100. Roger has an income of $10. I give Max $2 and
Roger $1. Roger thinks this is a progressive distribution because the $1 I
give him represents 10% of his income but the $2 I give to Max represents
only 2% of Max's income. Roger is happy because he believes that now he is
'relatively' better off. Max is happy because he _is_ absolutely better
off. The income gap between Max and Roger has now grown from $90 to $91
but Roger's income is now 10.78% of Max's instead of only 10%. That's
progress, folks!

 The point being, that yes, a price reduction will mean more dollars to
 wealthier customers, but, in considering possible progressivity, that
 effect is swamped by the larger spread between the income of the poor
 and wealthy. The savings for the wealthy are less as a percentage of
 income, which was my point and leads to the answer of the question Gene
 asked.

Ignoring for the sake of sophisticated analysis the inconvenient piece of
tricky Tom Walker devil bullshit that the income spread has become even
larger AFTER the "progressive" redistribution than it was before. 

Tom "bullshit" Walker



email gambit (was fuck the math . . .)

2000-02-08 Thread Timework Web

I haven't had so much fun since a bunch of latter-day Anarcho-Pagans
called me provocateur and police agent. O.K., O.K. I can see I'm not
welcome here. Unless I get positive feedback from other subscribers, Pen-l
won't have me to kick it around anymore. *That's* my gambit. I'm not in it
for the gratuitous abuse.

Roger Odisio wrote,
  
 Typical email gambit, I see.  Create a strawman position (Max, I, and
 others aren't merely answering the "arithmetic" question about
 progressivity, but "seem to be arguing" for some claim of distributive
 justice), attribute it to others, and whack away.  But you've added a
 novel twist, at least.  That strawman you've created is so unworthy, you
 say, you refuse to talk about it!

 I can't think of anything further I could possibly want to say on the
 topic of progressivity, Tom, including in response to whatever it is you
 can dream up to say about my last two messages.  Bye.


Tom Walker



Re: email gambit (was fuck the math . . .)

2000-02-08 Thread Eugene Coyle

Tom, don't go!

Behind the original question I posed about "progressive taxation"  was a
motive.  In preparation for someday attacking the analysis that is going to
defend  the California de-regulation as a form of "progressive taxation."  I
wanted to check to see if there was any basis for claiming, as the economists
are, that a drop in electric rates was progressive because small users spend
more of their income on electricity than do large users, and thus were going
to get a more "progressive" impact from the (supposed) future drop in
electric rates.

I thought that was a ridiculous claim, and still do, but wanted to check
about the definition of "progressive taxation" used by mainstream economics.

For my purposes, which is to attack a forthcoming report, I've learned
that I should attack on the substance of what they are doing rather than on
the basis of a single, unequivocal, well-agreed-upon definition of
progressivity.  It seems to me that a change that widens the dollar gap
between money in the hands of the poor and the rich is not "progressive."
(By the way, I never suggested that it is bad for the poor to cut their
electric rates -- seems as if somebody erroneously inferred that.)

 I opened my Schumpeter's History of Economic Analysis and learned that
there are even worse positions available to those who see things differently
than I do in this discussion.  Nobody has yet brought up the marginal utility
of money as a reason for calling such a change progressive.  The marginal
utility of money for the rich is much lower than for the poor, hence one
would have to give them a huge electric rate cut to give them a sum of money
than would have the same marginal utility as a small rate cut for the poor.
How did we miss getting that argument?

There are other bases for attacking the forthcoming study, and I will use
those.  One thing the authors do is produce forecasts of the increase in
electric consumption for various classes of customers, and for the state as a
whole.  They only produce numbers for rate cuts.  I asked them if they were
assuming fully reversible preference functions -- which baffled them.  They
had no idea of the assumptions behind elasticity studies.  Surely, I said,
consumption wouldn't go back to its original level if any rate cuts were
reversed.   After a little discussion they replied "We're only looking at
rate cuts, not increases."  So much for Berkeley Ph.Ds in economics off to
another prestige department and looking for publications.  Just run
regressions and get the grants.

Gene Coyle



Timework Web wrote:

 I haven't had so much fun since a bunch of latter-day Anarcho-Pagans
 called me provocateur and police agent. O.K., O.K. I can see I'm not
 welcome here. Unless I get positive feedback from other subscribers, Pen-l
 won't have me to kick it around anymore. *That's* my gambit. I'm not in it
 for the gratuitous abuse.

 Roger Odisio wrote,

  Typical email gambit, I see.  Create a strawman position (Max, I, and
  others aren't merely answering the "arithmetic" question about
  progressivity, but "seem to be arguing" for some claim of distributive
  justice), attribute it to others, and whack away.  But you've added a
  novel twist, at least.  That strawman you've created is so unworthy, you
  say, you refuse to talk about it!

  I can't think of anything further I could possibly want to say on the
  topic of progressivity, Tom, including in response to whatever it is you
  can dream up to say about my last two messages.  Bye.

 Tom Walker




RE: Re: Do the math. II

2000-02-08 Thread Max Sawicky


Over on LBO they're arguing about who is
more psychotic.  I think both sides are
winning.  So this debate compares
well.  I would be sorry to see either TW
or RO go.  Neither of them has called me
an insect yet.

On the substance of the matter . . . TW said:

Max has an income of $100. Roger has an income of $10. 

First thing I want to know is who told
Walker my income.

 . . . I give Max $2 and
Roger $1. Roger thinks this is a progressive distribution because the $1 I
give him represents 10% of his income but the $2 I give to Max represents
only 2% of Max's income. Roger is happy because he believes that now he is
'relatively' better off. Max is happy because he _is_ absolutely better
off. The income gap between Max and Roger has now grown from $90 to $91
but Roger's income is now 10.78% of Max's instead of only 10%. That's
progress, folks!


There are different ways to measure equality
and progressivity, some pretty arcane.
An issue in these measures is comparability,
part of what has been discussed here.
They can easily give contradictory results.

The metric upon which TW casts aspersions
is one such.  It is often used because it
is simple.  If there's a better one, especially
if it is equally simple, I'd be thrilled to
learn of it.  Or equally thrilled to learn
something new, like why such measures are
unimportant.

The income ratio in the example is ten to one.
Suppose the incomes were $10,000 and $100,000.
Then following the example, the poor person
gets $1,000, the rich $2,000.  Does anyone
doubt the well-being of the poor one is
enhanced more than the rich, or that the
outcome is less unappealing?  Suppose we
went backwards.  The poor income goes
from $10K to $9K, the rich from $100,000
to $98,000.  Who has suffered more harm?

A relative closing of the gap looks good
when incomes are increasing, even though
the higher income goes up more than the
lower, unless you use tiny numbers.  Then
it looks like an exercise in triviality.
But it's the direction that matters.

More problematic is when the gap narrows
(however you like -- relatively, absolutely,
etc.) when incomes are going down.  How
worthwhile is distribution in the context
of declining real incomes?  This is not
necessarily far-fetched.

Let a hundred turds fester.

mbs



RE: Do the math II

2000-02-08 Thread Timework Web

Max, you butterfly, you. I would agree that the outcome in the example you
give seems "less unappealing". That is perhaps because we can imagine what
it is like to have an income of $10,000 and what it would feel like to get
a $1000 boost. We can also imagine how unimportant a $2000 windfall might
seem if our income was $100,000. But we can play another numbers game and
say that an allocation of $300 to Roger and $2700 to Max is still, just
barely, "more progressive" than the original income ratio. And then we
could argue (as Gene suggested) that given the difference in marginal
utility of income between Roger and Max, the latter distribution would be
subjectively "fairer" but still "progressive". Where do we want to draw
the line on this?

So far, it's 4-1 for me to stay. Unless the nays rally for a comeback,
I'll stick around.

 The income ratio in the example is ten to one.
 Suppose the incomes were $10,000 and $100,000.
 Then following the example, the poor person
 gets $1,000, the rich $2,000.  Does anyone
 doubt the well-being of the poor one is
 enhanced more than the rich, or that the
 outcome is less unappealing? 


Tom Walker



Re: email gambit (was fuck the math . . .)

2000-02-08 Thread Brad De Long

I haven't had so much fun since a bunch of latter-day Anarcho-Pagans
called me provocateur and police agent. O.K., O.K. I can see I'm not
welcome here. Unless I get positive feedback from other subscribers, Pen-l
won't have me to kick it around anymore. *That's* my gambit. I'm not in it
for the gratuitous abuse.

Roger Odisio wrote,
  
  Typical email gambit, I see.  Create a strawman position (Max, I, and
  others aren't merely answering the "arithmetic" question about
  progressivity, but "seem to be arguing" for some claim of distributive
  justice), attribute it to others, and whack away.  But you've added a
  novel twist, at least.  That strawman you've created is so unworthy, you
  say, you refuse to talk about it!

  I can't think of anything further I could possibly want to say on the
  topic of progressivity, Tom, including in response to whatever it is you
  can dream up to say about my last two messages.  Bye.


Tom Walker

I'll provide some positive feedback...


Brad DeLong



Re: email gambit (was fuck the math . . .)

2000-02-08 Thread Michael Perelman

Our system has been down.  I have not been able to follow this thread.  The
mail I am reading is also out of order, but it seems that Roger is going over
the top with Tom.  please stop.

Timework Web wrote:

 I haven't had so much fun since a bunch of latter-day Anarcho-Pagans
 called me provocateur and police agent. O.K., O.K. I can see I'm not
 welcome here. Unless I get positive feedback from other subscribers, Pen-l
 won't have me to kick it around anymore. *That's* my gambit. I'm not in it
 for the gratuitous abuse.

 Roger Odisio wrote,

  Typical email gambit, I see.  Create a strawman position (Max, I, and
  others aren't merely answering the "arithmetic" question about
  progressivity, but "seem to be arguing" for some claim of distributive
  justice), attribute it to others, and whack away.  But you've added a
  novel twist, at least.  That strawman you've created is so unworthy, you
  say, you refuse to talk about it!

  I can't think of anything further I could possibly want to say on the
  topic of progressivity, Tom, including in response to whatever it is you
  can dream up to say about my last two messages.  Bye.

 Tom Walker

--
Michael Perelman
Economics Department
California State University
Chico, CA 95929

Tel. 530-898-5321
E-Mail [EMAIL PROTECTED]



Re: Re: email gambit (was fuck the math . . .)

2000-02-08 Thread Roger Odisio

Michael Perelman wrote:

 Our system has been down.  I have not been able to follow this thread.  The
 mail I am reading is also out of order, but it seems that Roger is going over
 the top with Tom.  please stop.

Could you please explain what you mean by "it seems that Roger is going over the
top with Tom'', Michael, so I could at least try to understand what you are
accusing me of, or find objectionable?

Particularly since you admit you haven't followed the thread and have only read
things out of order.  Perhaps I could (gently) suggest that you read the thread
in sequence before you reach judgments like this.  And then, at least, please
make a clear statement of the problem.  Seems elementary, doesn't it?

Moreover, you don't seem to have noticed that I had already said I had said all I
was going to say on the topic.  Your asking me to stop was unnecessary.

RO



Do the math.

2000-02-07 Thread Timework Web

Roger Odisio wrote,

 By my reading, only a couple posts by Tom Walker seem to quarrel with
 it. (the definition of progressivity)

I don't quarrel with the definition, only with applying the term to
a situation where it doesn't apply. Be humble. Do the math. 

 "Increasing in rate as the taxable amount increases: a progressive
 income tax."

The definition refers to the rate and the taxable amount. Not to the
_change_ in the rate as a proportion of the taxable amount. Speed and
acceleration are different things. Size and growth are two different
things. A rate and a change in a rate are also two different things. 

As the example I just posted shows, a.) 18% is twice as much as 9% and
b.) 20% is twice as much as 10%. By the way, you can pick any numbers to
do the illustration because it's the relationship between the numbers that
stays the same.


Tom Walker



Spinhead math 101: lesson two

2000-02-04 Thread Timework Web

It may not be immediately clear to everyone why taking a ratio of a ratio
is not an acceptable way of assessing the "progressivity" of a rate
change. So let me give another example:

Sometimes governments announce tax or spending changes relative to a
previously projected change. Thus, the diminution of a previously
announced tax increase might be announced as if it were a "tax cut".

Suppose deregulation would enable the utility companies to forego rate
_increases_ that otherwise were projected? Suppose those foregone rate
increases were of the same magnitude as the rate decreases projected in
Gene's question. The effect of such a non-change in rates would be EVEN
MORE PROGRESSIVE (using the two economists' logic) than the decrease in
rates that they were talking about. Imagine that! More progress from
standing still.

Using these kinds of subtle spin techniques one can easily cook up a
"progressive" rate change that is structurally regressive but
nominally "progressive" because it is less regressive than another
projected rate change.

In plain language: compared to a banana, an orange is an apple. Not.



Tom Walker



teaching math (or maths to Mig Fiona) (fwd)

1998-03-27 Thread michael

Forwarded message:
From [EMAIL PROTECTED] Fri Mar 27 14:08:56 1998
Delivered-To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Delivered-To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Date: Fri, 27 Mar 1998 09:07:27 -0500 (EST)
From: Gunder Frank [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: Sing Chews [EMAIL PROTECTED], D Shniad [EMAIL PROTECTED],
whitney howarth [EMAIL PROTECTED],
Michael Perelman [EMAIL PROTECTED],
Marianne Brun [EMAIL PROTECTED],
Wally Goldfrank [EMAIL PROTECTED],
Albert J Bergesen [EMAIL PROTECTED],
Pat Lauderdale [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Subject: teaching math (or maths to Mig  Fiona) (fwd)
Message-ID: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
MIME-Version: 1.0
Content-Type: TEXT/PLAIN; charset=US-ASCII
X-Status: 
X-UID: 575




~~
Andre Gunder Frank   
University of Toronto
96 Asquith Ave Tel. 1 416 972-0616 
Toronto, ONFax. 1 416 972-0071
CANADA  M4W 1J8Email [EMAIL PROTECTED] 

My home Page is at: http://www.whc.neu.edu/whc/resrchcurric/gunder.html

~~

-- Forwarded message --
Date: Fri, 27 Mar 1998 12:35:17 +0100
From: Paulo Frank [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: Mig [EMAIL PROTECTED], Fiona Godfrey [EMAIL PROTECTED],
gunder [EMAIL PROTECTED], nancy [EMAIL PROTECTED],
Gabriel Gutierrez [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Subject: teaching math (or maths to Mig  Fiona)

 From: Andrea Hoffmann [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 
 Teaching Math in 1950:
  A logger sells a truckload of lumber for $100. His cost of
  production is 4/5 of the price. What is his profit?
 
  Teaching Math in 1960:
  A logger sells a truckload of lumber for $100. His cost of
  production is 4/5 of the price, or $80. What is his profit?
 
  Teaching Math in 1970:
  A logger exchanges a set "L" of lumber for a set "M" of money. The
  cardinality of set "M" is 100. Each element is worth one dollar.
  Make 100 dots representing the elements of the set "M". The set "C",
  the cost of production contains 20 fewer points than set "M".
  Represent the set "C" as a subset of set "M" and answer the
  following question: What is the cardinality of the set "P" of
  profits?
 
  Teaching Math in 1980:
  A logger sells a truckload of lumber for $100. His cost of
  production is $80 and his profit is $20.
  Your assignment: Underline the number 20.
 
  Teaching Math in 1990:
  By cutting down beautiful forest trees, the logger makes $20.
  What do you think of this way of making a living? Topic for class
  participation after answering the question: How did the forest birds
  and squirrels feel as the logger cut down the trees?
  There are no wrong answers.
 
  Teaching Math in 1996:
  By laying off 402 of its loggers, a company improves its stock price
  from $80 to $100. How much capital gain per share does the CEO make
  by exercising his stock options at $80? Assume capital gains are no
  longer taxed, because this encourages investment.
 
  Teaching Math in 1997:
  A company outsources all of its loggers. They save on benefits and
  when demand for their product is down, the logging work force can
  easily be cut back. The average logger employed by the company
  earned $50,000, had 3 weeks vacation, received a nice retirement
  plan and medical insurance. The contracted logger charges $50 an
  hour. Was outsourcing a good move?
 
  Teaching Math in 1998:
  A logging company exports its wood-finishing jobs to its Indonesian
  subsidiary and lays off the corresponding half of its US workers
  (the higher-paid half). It clear-cuts 95% of the forest, leaving the
  rest for the spotted owl, and lays off all its remaining US workers.
  It tells the workers that the spotted owl is responsible for the
  absence of fellable trees and lobbies Congress for exemption from
  the Endangered Species Act. Congress instead exempts the company
  from all federal regulation. What is the return on investment of the
  lobbying costs?
 -
 Anyone want to speculate on Teaching Math in 2000?
 :-)




-- 
Michael Perelman
Economics Department
California State University
Chico, CA 95929

Tel. 530-898-5321
E-Mail [EMAIL PROTECTED]





[PEN-L:11533] Re: Intuition in Math Reasoning

1997-07-30 Thread Romain Kroes

Wojtek Sokolowski wrote:
 
 
 Therefore, the mystification of mathematics in modern economics can be
 compared to cargo cults that spread on some Pacific isalands after World War
 II.  The Americans established air bases on those islands, and to buy the
 aborigines' loyalty, they  showered them with goodies which, of course, they
 transpored by air.  After the war, the Gringos left, and the trickle of
 goodies dried up.  To reverse their fortune, the aborigines started to
 emulate what the Gringos did -- building aircraft carrying the goodies to
 the islands.  Except that lacking the proper materials, the aborigines built
 those aircraft from sticks and straw.
 

I like very much the metaphor above. Actually, it suits the economists.
All attempts to construct an original axiomatic basis in economics
remain still uncompleted, and mainly the marxist one. The 28th january
1884, Engels wrote to Lavrov:

"The Third book, capitalist production taken as a whole, exists in two
draftings which have been written before 1869 ; later, there are only a
few notes and a notebook full of equations to calculate the numerous
ways of surplus-value rate changing into profit rate."

So, 14 years before Marx's death, "The Capital" was already, and for
ever, an uncompleted work. If his pages of equations had enabled their
author to transform the "Mehrwertsrate" in a "Profitrate", the
mathematical notebook would have been followed by new writings
concluding or rectifying the "Third book", and by a publishing. Not only
Marx didn't go on writing, but he died without having told anyone about
the state of his work. The 2nd april 1883 (Marx was dead the 14th
march), Engels wrote to the same Lavrov:

"Tomorrow, I'll have at last some hours to spend on revewing all the
manuscripts the Mohr has left us (...) But he always hided from us the
state of his works ; he knew that once aware of what was ready to be
published, we'd have violeted him until he consents."

And this silence lasted 14 years! Due to dogmas and neuroses
accompanying the value accumulation process, to the merchants struggle
for contending with the political institutions for power, and to the
awfully effective scholastic and working consensus by which the ad hoc
ideology can reproduce, neoclassical economists are unable to overcome
the lesser epistemologic obstacle. But because of a paralyzing
devoutness, Marxists never tried, too, to go beyond the conceptual
contradiction against which Marx came up. Except Rosa Luxemburg (by the
way, a woman who readily confessed she was hopeless at mathematics... )

But all that doesn't mean that an economic science, using mathematics,
can't be. It only means that an original economic tool, taking place
beside the other social sciences (and no more above them), is still
ahead ... 

Sincerly,

Romain Kroes
(Warning : Engels letters translation here is of mine, and from a french
version, the only one I had handy)






[PEN-L:11534] Re: Re: Intuition in Math Reasoning

1997-07-30 Thread James Devine

Romain Kroes writes: ... because of a paralyzing devoutness, Marxists
never tried, too, to go beyond the conceptual contradiction against which
Marx came up. 

what specific conceptual contradiction are you talking about? the
"contradiction" of the so-called "transformation problem"? 

neoclassical economists are unable to overcome the lesser epistemologic
obstacle.

what obstacle? how do they overcome it?

As for "paralyzing devoutness," assuming that you're talking about the
"transformation problem," you should look at:
_Marx_and_Non-equilibrium_Economics_ (editors: Alan Freeman,  Guglielmo
Carchedi; Cheltenham [England]  Brookfield, Vt.: Edward Elgar, 1996). This
book defends Marx's approach to the transformation without any devoutness
at all. In fact, they attack the devoutness of the neoclassical and
neoclassical-Marxist belief in equilibrium.


in pen-l solidarity,

Jim Devine   [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Econ. Dept., Loyola Marymount Univ.
7900 Loyola Blvd., Los Angeles, CA 90045-8410 USA
310/338-2948 (daytime, during workweek); FAX: 310/338-1950
"As far as the laws of mathematics refer to reality, they are not
certain; as far as they are certain, they really do not refer to
reality." -- Albert Einstein. 






[PEN-L:11547] Re: Re: Intuition in Math Reasoning

1997-07-30 Thread Romain Kroes

James Devine wrote:
 
  what specific conceptual contradiction are you talking about? the
 "contradiction" of the so-called "transformation problem"?
 
 neoclassical economists are unable to overcome the lesser epistemologic
 obstacle.
 
 what obstacle? how do they overcome it?
 
 As for "paralyzing devoutness," assuming that you're talking about the
 "transformation problem," you should look at:
 _Marx_and_Non-equilibrium_Economics_ (editors: Alan Freeman,  Guglielmo
 Carchedi; Cheltenham [England]  Brookfield, Vt.: Edward Elgar, 1996). This
 book defends Marx's approach to the transformation without any devoutness
 at all. In fact, they attack the devoutness of the neoclassical and
 neoclassical-Marxist belief in equilibrium.
 

Why didn't Marx succeed in transforming his surplus-value rate in a
profit rate ? Because he had postulated that the profit issued of
productivity gains (the "relative surplus-value") were globally nil.
That is global accumulation were impossible, from a growing
productivity. 

Now, what are we observing, today ? A poursuit of profit related to the
lowering of the work sharing part in the product unit. The contradiction
is : work is actually the only supply of wealth, but capitalist
accumulation of value depends on the productivity gains. What Marx gave
as a "surplus-value rate" is a relative one, and what he gave as a
"relative surplus-value" is globally capitalizable. So Marx could not
explain the "enhanced capital reproduction", as Rosa Luxemburg realized
it (Die Akkumulation des Kapitales, 1913). 

That's the reason why I put forward the idea of an "epistemologic
obstacle", since we are facing a conceptual inversion. 

As for equilibrium, I don't think it's a matter of believing or not.
Equilibrium is a concept : the decretionary reference to stability. For
exemple : the equilibrium can be defined as being the zero price index.
But it's from the capitalist point of vue. If, on the other hand, one
prefers the employment rate and the welfare state, as references of
equilibrium, one has to consider that price index has been invariably
positive for more than fifty years, and to explain that both
equilibriums (money and growth) have become incompatible. And this is
the point where we meet Rosa Luxemburg intuition...

Salut et fraternite

Romain Kroes

P.S.- Although that discussion and your company are highly fascinating,
I must move away from my computer, up to 25th august. But I'll come back
on the Pen-L.






[PEN-L:11439] Re: Male Chauvanist Math

1997-07-24 Thread JayHecht

In a message dated 97-07-24 02:01:53 EDT, you write:

 
 1. Marx tended to minimize concerns for the immediate adverse impact of 
 capitalism on women and children because he focused on what he believed to
be 
 the inherent impact of capitalism dynamics in the long run on their 
 situatio 

Bob,

Read the stuff on the working day - hardly a concern with LR dynamics!

Also, my sister was a math major at Queens College in the early 1970's.  On
the first day of a Differential Calculus class, the prof turned to my sister
(and the 3 other female students) and said, "what are you doing here? your
never going to need this stuff while your raising your kids!!"

   More to the point:  The use of econometrics in is to emphasize central 
tendencies and often long run tendencies.  This "makes sense" if one can 
ignore the immediate situation or the deviations from the central 
tendencies. 

I work for an insurance company and do econometric forecasting/research.  I
don't consider myself an "econometrician" but I know how to use the tools.
 The strenghts of econometrics are also its weaknesses (which neither
radicals nor NCs nor others who use the stuff pay attention to):  its a
flexible set of tools that are capable of giving "soft" and "hard" results.
 For example, when I want to establish "credibility" in a rate trend, I can
use a host of techniques.  The point is that math, stats, and other quant
techniques are systems of knowledge that are made to be manipulated (but also
need to be understood).  Unfortunately,  I'm not paid to be concerned with
"long run central tendencies," rather I need to get a short run projection
for a defined objective.

   Finally, I object to the characterization of my wife as the "Willie Mays"
of hospital accounting:  Mays had to endure overt racisim from a crowd of
people that was in his face everyday.  My wife's situation - while difficult
- was no where near as traumatic (even though in the beginning of her career
she regularly worked 80 hour weeks)

Jason

  





[PEN-L:11417] Male Chauvanist Math

1997-07-23 Thread Robert Cherry

Jay Hecht wrote:

"In fact, it was quite evident that the hospital practice at this
particular Big 6 succeeded because the women supplanted the incompetent
males!"

This can be explained in a simple Becker (neoclassical) manner:  Prior to 
the hiring of women, incompletent males were hired.  However, once access 
was extended, capitalist accounting firms were able to hire the most 
productive workers which included many women.  Generally, in the first 
stages of integrating the workforce, very talented women are hired.  
Not surprisingly, just as in baseball in the 1950s, this would include some 
exceptional players.  In a sense, Jay's wife may be the Willie Mays of 
hospital accounting!!

   More to the point:  The use of econometrics in is to emphasize central 
tendencies and often long run tendencies.  This "makes sense" if one can 
ignore the immediate situation or the deviations from the central 
tendencies.  Professional men have a greater willingness to do this because 
they rarely experience (though they may empathize with) the downsides -- 
adverse side effects -- of public policies.  A few examples:

1. Marx tended to minimize concerns for the immediate adverse impact of 
capitalism on women and children because he focused on what he believed to be 
the inherent impact of capitalism dynamics in the long run on their 
situation.  While I believe he was absolutely correct in his 
prognostications, it is unlikely that many of his contemporary working class 
woman would have been so focused on long run dynamics.

2. Paul Krugman makes a somewhat similar point about the present dynamics in 
newly emerging industrialized countries where women are being exploited in 
the capitalist process rather than in the more feudalistic structures that 
previously dominated their employment.  There is a certain logic and 
"truth" in what Krugman states because as a central tendency capitalism on 
average is improving the economic wellbeing of women.  However, within this 
dynamics there are women who will necessarily experience not the central 
tendency but the worst abuses.  Again, it is more likely that men will focus 
on the central tendency rather than the worst abuses.

   This is the same when we look at economic analysis which posits a 
"typical" household or "typical" firm.  Here an example could be NAFTA where 
it may be true that on average a typical household would benefit from the 
increased world specialization with lower consumer prices.  However, it makes 
a difference whether the typical household is comprised of upper-income 
professionals or lower-income blue collar workers when we look closely at the 
employment effects (which in the aggregate may net out to zero).  Again, do 
we focus on the central tendency (male professionals??) or on the adverse 
consequences to particular subgroups (female blue collar??).

Robert Cherry/Brooklyn College

 





[PEN-L:11402] Re: Intuition in Math Reasoning

1997-07-23 Thread Wojtek Sokolowski

At 02:56 AM 7/23/97 -0700, you wrote:
It's relevant that Keynes doesn't condemn, here, the use of mathematics
in economics (as for him, he rather liked to have recourse to them up to
tautology), but that he implicitly accuses the lack of a conceptual
basis in economics, so much so that "the back of the head" is nothing
but a rough substitute for it.

Economics aren't yet a true science, although such a tool has never been
so necessary as nowadays. That's the reason why econometrics ask
mathematics to fill the conceptual gap. This matter is economically the
most important one, but I'm afraid it doesn't interest the most of
economists...


In this context, it is revealing to examine the etymological roots of the
word "mathematics" - it derives from the ancient Greek and means "what is
already known" - based on Heidegger's interpretation, that suggest mere
cataloguing of information acquired through other means, rather than
discovering new information.  

Intuition or insight, on the other hand, denoted in classical philosophy a
cognitive faculty of direct acquisition of new information.  In that aspect,
it was comparable to experience, except that intuition was more valuable
than experience because it allowed the inquiring mind to directly access the
'essences of things' rather than their appearences.

This distinction between formal deduction (as in mathematics) and intution
forming the basis of deduction (that's how we comprehend axioms) was still
present in post Kartesian thought (cf. Baruch Spinoza).  In essence, formal
deduction was considered a vastly inferior to intuition form of knowledge,
until modern times, when it became a tool of natural sciences perceived as
successful.

Therefore, the mystification of mathematics in modern economics can be
compared to cargo cults that spread on some Pacific isalands after World War
II.  The Americans established air bases on those islands, and to buy the
aborigines' loyalty, they  showered them with goodies which, of course, they
transpored by air.  After the war, the Gringos left, and the trickle of
goodies dried up.  To reverse their fortune, the aborigines started to
emulate what the Gringos did -- building aircraft carrying the goodies to
the islands.  Except that lacking the proper materials, the aborigines built
those aircraft from sticks and straw.

regards,
wojtek sokolowski 
institute for policy studies
johns hopkins university
baltimore, md 21218
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
voice: (410) 516-4056
fax:   (410) 516-8233

POLITICS IS THE SHADOW CAST ON SOCIETY BY BIG BUSINESS. AND AS LONG AS THIS
IS SO, THE ATTENUATI0N OF THE SHADOW WILL NOT CHANGE THE SUBSTANCE.
- John Dewey







[PEN-L:11395] Re: Intuition in Math Reasoning

1997-07-23 Thread romain_kroes

It's relevant that Keynes doesn't condemn, here, the use of mathematics
in economics (as for him, he rather liked to have recourse to them up to
tautology), but that he implicitly accuses the lack of a conceptual
basis in economics, so much so that "the back of the head" is nothing
but a rough substitute for it.

Economics aren't yet a true science, although such a tool has never been
so necessary as nowadays. That's the reason why econometrics ask
mathematics to fill the conceptual gap. This matter is economically the
most important one, but I'm afraid it doesn't interest the most of
economists...

Sincerly

Romain Kroes

Laurence Shute wrote:
 
 Does this help any?  From the General Theory (pp 297-98):
 
 "It is a great fault of symbolic pseudo-mathematical methods of formalising
 a system of economic analysis, such as we shall set down in section VI of
 this chapter, that they expressly assume strict independence between the
 factors involved and lose all their cogency and authority if this
 hypothesis is disallowed; whereas, in ordinary discourse, where we are not
 blindly manipulating but know all the time what we are doing and what the
 words mean, we can keep 'at the back of our heads' the necessary reserves
 and qualifications and the adjustments which we shall have to make later
 on, in a way in which we cannot keep complicated partial differentials 'at
 the back' of several pages of algebra which assume that they all vanish.
 Too large a proportion of recent 'mathematical' economics are mere
 concoctions, as imprecise as the initial assumptions they rest on, which
 allow the author to lose4 sight of the complexities and interdependencies
 of the real world in a maze of pretentious and unhelpful symbols."
 
 In 1940 Keynes was greatly worried that his American disciplices "were more
 orthodox than the master," in the sense that they failed to keep the
 necessary reservations "at the back of their head."






[PEN-L:11381] Re: Intuition in Math Reasoning

1997-07-22 Thread Laurence Shute

Does this help any?  From the General Theory (pp 297-98):

"It is a great fault of symbolic pseudo-mathematical methods of formalising
a system of economic analysis, such as we shall set down in section VI of
this chapter, that they expressly assume strict independence between the
factors involved and lose all their cogency and authority if this
hypothesis is disallowed; whereas, in ordinary discourse, where we are not
blindly manipulating but know all the time what we are doing and what the
words mean, we can keep 'at the back of our heads' the necessary reserves
and qualifications and the adjustments which we shall have to make later
on, in a way in which we cannot keep complicated partial differentials 'at
the back' of several pages of algebra which assume that they all vanish.
Too large a proportion of recent 'mathematical' economics are mere
concoctions, as imprecise as the initial assumptions they rest on, which
allow the author to lose4 sight of the complexities and interdependencies
of the real world in a maze of pretentious and unhelpful symbols."

In 1940 Keynes was greatly worried that his American disciplices "were more
orthodox than the master," in the sense that they failed to keep the
necessary reservations "at the back of their head."  

Larry Shute

Thanks for your message at 07:06 AM 7/22/97 -0700, [EMAIL PROTECTED]  Your
message was:
In a message dated 97-07-21 10:04:11 EDT, Anders writes:

At 07:35 PM 7/20/97 -0700, Maggie wrote:
Nope. This is why ( as I pointed out) other types of debate are more
It may not have been phrased exactly this way, but what I say in the rest
of
my initial message is that one of the primary feminist critiques is that
econometrics (models) are almost by definition inaccurate.  In other words,
they are parsimonious to the point where they can not possibly reflect
social
issues (power, gender, race, sexual preference, etc.).  So even when power
is
added to a model, the model inaccurately portrays the exercise of power
because the one dimensional nature of mathematics does not allow for the
variable degrees of the exercise of power.  

Is that really the result of mathematics, or is it the result of a model
that starts with the assumption that we don't have to worry about power (or
attempts to change the rules of the game)?  If you had a model that did
start by putting power at the center, why couldn't you use math to talk
about variable degrees of power?
Wl, part of it is the assumptions on which the model is based--so,
frinstance, Posner's recent work which "proves" that white men should receive
a larger part of the medical research dollar because the loss of white men to
ill health or death costs more is an excellent example of assumptions
determining outcome.  As long as we measure the value of life in terms of
documented income from the market place, and do not place a monetary value on
household labor, mainstream economists will always reach this conclusion.
 ***However even if one incorporates truly progressive values into
econometric work--and I think that there is some really good work out there
(frinstance, Australlian economist Gillian Hewitson did an excellent rational
choice model for surrogate mothers) I question the ability of mathematics to
portray the complexities of social interactions.  Does racism or sexism or
power vary with mathematical certitude even in exactly the same situations
over time?  I really don't think so.


Further, econometrics is only one
form of logic, generally associated with men, and its use as a legitimizing
force to the exclusion of all other types of logic (artistic, intuitive) is
in and of itself a form of bigotry.

Two questions:

-- Suppose econometrics gave us the answers we wanted.  Would it be bigotry
to say, that's what we're going to use to the exclusion of, say, artistic
logic?
I'm not sure I understand the question--but--I wrote in answer to Jim Devine
that I am not completely convinced by this portion of the feminist argument.
 I don't think there has been enough of a separation between econometrics as
a tool and the USE of that tool by the mainstream as a way of promoting all
forms of bigotry.


-- Are you arguing that econometrics doesn't involve intuitive and other
forms of logic, or are you saying that when it's used as a legitimating
force, it pretends that it doesn't involve intuition, etc.?  The reason I
ask is that I remember reading articles about the history of econometrics
many moons ago that analyzed the shift in rhetoric, and they all argued
that econometrics was an attempt to appopriate the images of "hardness" and
"rigor" from physics while denying the role of intuition, etc. that physics
takes for granted.
All science begins with intuition.  However, econometrics simplifies this
intuition to a parsimonious skeleton and--at best--is useful as a compliment
to intuitive explanations.  Further, I question the definition of

[PEN-L:5635] Re: language math

1995-06-22 Thread John R. Ernst

On Tue, 20 Jun 95 [EMAIL PROTECTED] (Paul Cockshott) said: 
 
 
John asks 
 
All of the above is true but seems to miss the point of the Okishio
Theorem.
That is, Okishio points out that rattional capitalists make investments to
 
increase their rates of profit or, at least, to keep them at 
their current level.  Thus,  why would a capitalist invest to bring about
a 
fall in the rate of profit?  This question was first raised by
Tugan-Baranowsky  
 using a one commodity model as Van Parijs pointed out. 
 
Paul 
 
The point is that in the real world, as opposed to equilibrium models,  
capitalists do not know what their profits are going to be this year let
alone  
next. They do not know what the level of effective demand will be nor next
 
years price level. 
 
I think that it is unrealistic to expect to be able to construct a theory
of  
the rate of accumulation at this kind of micro level, since it is
inherently a  
dynamic macroeconomic phenomenon, affected by interest rates, existing  
accumulation levels, changes in wages etc. The point about the declining  
tendancy of the rate of profit is that over long periods, the fall in
profit  
rates relative to interest rates tends to act as a limiting factor on the
rate  
of accumulation. It is this macroscopic limitation that is the interesting
 
factor. 
 
John says 
 
Ok.  Let me see if this question clarifies matters.  Do capitalists invest
in ne techniques which, using current prices, will reduce their rates of
profit?  
-- 
John R. Ernst 



[PEN-L:5626] Tendency of falling profit rate - was: language math

1995-06-21 Thread Trond Andresen

Tavis Barr says:

 ..if there is no tendency of the profit rate to fall, why 
 has it been on a downward trend for the last 25 years or so?

First: Are economists in agreement on this?  I have economist
acquaintances who say otherwise. Just asking.

Secondly: If this rate really has been falling, it could perfectly well
do so without being caused by mechanization/automation. Even a
static economy (static in the sense of negligible technical change and
productivity growth in the period considered) will experience long run
financial crisis symptoms simply due to accumulation of assets. As long
as all sorts of returns (from loans, bonds, stocks) are re-invested,
aggregate net assets (mirrored by net debts) will grow, regardless of
productivity growth and technical change. Sooner or later the net
assets holders (and I am not only talking of the financial sector here,
also any economic agent who holds dividend-giving assets - including
firm owners who behave as rentiers towards their own firms) will have
trouble upholding a return flow that is proportional to net assets.

Thirdly: Imagine a future class society with 5% of the workforce in
manufacturing, and where physical production is undertaken 90% by
robots and automated processes with the workers as overseers and
maintenance personnel. Since this is a class society the workforce will
be dependent on selling their labour power to capitalists on the
market. This extremely productive society will therefore employ the
majority of workers in a huge service sector, which to a great degree
is employed with catering to the needs of the capitalist class. This
service sector will - being a service sector - have a lower organic
composition of capital than industry, and therefore give good
possibilities for exploitiation of employees.  The capitalists will
exploit those service workers as hard as possible, and accumulate as
today.  If returns to capitalists in the automated industrial sector
are lower than in the service sector, the industrial sector will
shrink. But this will increase prices for products from this sector
until profitability there is comparable to that of the service sector.

So my conclusion is that as long as a society is divided into two main
classes: Capitalists and wage labourers, there will be the same
possibilities for harvesting profits as today, or for that sake 50
years ago. The average rate of profit doesn't depend on level of
automation/mechanization, but on the power balance between exploiters
and the exploited.

And back to my second point: To the degree one observes a some-decades 
long path towards stagnation and crisis in capitalism (a "long
wave"), this is explained by accumulation due to compound returns, not
by increased organic composition.

Futhermore to the third point above: If I am right here, any marxist
who believes that socialism  and then communism is inevitable in the
long run because capitalism is doomed due to a profit rate tending
towards zero because of automation/mechanization, must be in error.
Capitalism can continue indefinitely as long as one class has the power
to coerce the majority to work for them by control over their means of
living.

Incidently I _do_ believe that socialism and some sort of "asymptote"
towards communism is bound to come in the long run. But this belief is
based on the relentless and gradual increase in average workforce
education level and the communication technologies that the capitalists
themselves need in the global competitiveness rat race. In this sense
they are themselves bringing forth the tools that will mean their
future demise.  But this is another discussion.

All this, IMHO, of course. I may be wrong.

cheers,


Trond
-
| Trond Andresen  ([EMAIL PROTECTED])  |
| Department of Engineering Cybernetics |
| The Norwegian Institute of Technology |
| N-7034 Trondheim, NORWAY  |
|   |
| phone (work)  +47 73 59 43 58 |
| fax   (work)  +47 73 59 43 99 |
| private phone +47 73 53 08 23 |
| private mobile phone +47 90 16 69 30  |
|   |
| http://www.itk.unit.no/ansatte/Andresen,Trond |
-



[PEN-L:5608] Re: language math

1995-06-20 Thread Tavis Barr
On the other hand, looking at interactive behavior, things could go 
either way depending on expectations (i.e., dynamic strategies), for 
which the Folk Theorem says pretty much anything interesting goes.  
Successfully choosing not to make an innovation might happen in more 
mature markets where entrepreneurs are more sure of their competitors' 
profits versus newer markets (e.g., computers) where somebody is bound to 
enter the market with the new technology fairly soon.

In any event, in the latter case (which I would argue is probably more 
the norm; few markets are entirely fixed from entry) I think it's pretty 
straight forward to illustrate Shaikh's response to Okishio with a 
Cournot example (for which Shaikh with his aversion to anything vaguely 
neoclassical would be none too happy).  I'm trying to use "reasonable" 
numbers here.

Suppose two firms face a demand function p = 10 - q and two possible 
technologies with constant marginal costs 5 and 2.5.  Ignore sunk costs 
for a second.  The Cournot equilibrium for the first technology is q = 
5/3 for each firm, p = 6 2/3, and each firm has profits 2 7/9.  In the 
second case, q = 2 1/2, p = 5, and each firm has profits 6 1/4.

(the "reasonableness" so far is that the price elasticity of demand at 
the relevant point is just over 1, which is a little high but actually then 
only underscores the point since a lower elasticity would strengthen
the effect.  The thing I like about the two-player Cournot example is 
that it puts the individual firm's elasticity at about twice that of the 
aggregate elasticity, which seems ballpark right to me though I don't 
know of studies of this kind of stuff).

Now, back to the sunk costs: Suppose all marginal costs are labor and all 
sunk costs are capital (it doesn't really matter for the Marxian 
questions since they are, by definition, variable and constant capital).
Each firm would be willing to just over double its capital costs in order 
to maintain the same profit rate.  Given that each firm raises its output 
by fifty percent, this seems excessive but not too excessive.  I'm sure 
moving the elasticity up would create a 1-1 increase or even less in the 
break-even case. 

I do think this kind of game is a lot more reasonable than the typical 
neoclassical functions that Okishio considers for a couple of reasons: 
(1) innovations more typically involve larger sunk costs and smaller 
marginal costs and (2) firms have a bit of room to manoever their prices 
as well as get into price wars or not get into them.  The point is not 
that changes under these conditions _always_ lower the profit rate, but 
that under very reasonable specifications they may.

Either way, it illustrates Marx's point pretty well: I leave it to the 
reader :) :) to show that in the break-even case (i.e., the same profit 
rate in the two scenarios), the firm that stays with the higher-MC 
technology while the other one switches will get really screwed.  I 
haven't done the math but it seems pretty intuitive and not hard to 
compute just annoying.  If a firm believes that it can switch 
technologies a "period" before its competitors do anyway, then the 
incentives will be that much greater.  So expectational considerations 
can go a long way toward lowering the profit rate.

In any event, I don't think this is the main justification for falling 
profits.  Technical change seems to be correlated with higher profits, 
though I don't know of studies of this on a firm-level basis, with 3-5 
year lags and using more "Marxian" estimates of these variables.  But 
it does raise serious questions about the relevance of Okishio's theorem,
even within the one side of the story of accumulation that it does address.

Added to this, Gil, if there is no tendency of the profit rate to fall, why 
has it been on a downward trend for the last 25 years or so?


Yours for the squabble after the revolution,
Tavis




[PEN-L:5619] Re: language and math

1995-06-20 Thread Roderick Hay

This was Ricardo's argument for a declining rate of profit. Marx wanted 
to develop an argument that was internal to his theory of capitalist 
dynamics, i.e., not imposed outside the system. Not that Ricardo was 
wrong just that his argument was endogenous. David Levine discusses this 
in one of his early books.


On Tue, 20 Jun 1995, John L Gulick wrote:

 Can't the rate of profit also fall when technical and organizational
 changes which increase surplus value extraction meet various "natural
 limits to growth" ? I adamantly am not talking a Club of Rome discourse
 here, merely referring to the conditioning of "revolutions in value
 production" by the uneven and unpredictable process of rationalizing
 and taming (an already socially modified) "nature". 
 
 For example, socio-technical change in intermodal shipping -- containerization,
 concentration of capital, rationalization of routes, the building of huge
 supertankers and cargo ships -- has played a major role in the multinational-
 ization, transnationalization, and globalization of production. Given the
 high organic composition of capital in this sector, continued price reductions
 in ocean-going shipping services has depended a lot on reducing turnover
 times. But this is coming up against all sort of (socially modified) "natural
 limits" -- increased harbor traffic leads to congestion, channels must be
 dredged to accomodate the giant new-generation liners, increased speed of
 vessels leads to accidents, etc. Shippers internalize these costs and the
 price of shipping services rise. Rising prices for shipping services take
 a cut out of the aggregate social surplus created.
 
 (I recognize the limitations of the example, since it
 entails only a singular sector and kind of ignores the fluidity of
 investment across sectors).
 
 Any comments for this argument by a non-economist ?
 
 John Gulick
 UC-Santa Cruz
 Sociology Graduate Program
 research interest: eco-Marxist theory of the built environment
 
 



[PEN-L:5571] Re: language math

1995-06-19 Thread Paul Cockshott

The discussion of whether the falling rate of profit is true
under different assumptions of wage rates seems to me beside
the point. What one should be looking at is not micro
phenomena like that but macro dynamics. A sufficient condition
for the rate of profit to have a declining upper bound, is
that capital accumulates faster than the growth of the 
pool of exploitable labour.

When this occurs the rate of profit does decline, and in
periods of stagnation - when capital accumulation is often
negative - it does not.

The maths required to demonstrate this do not go beyond 
elementary differential calculus - but one does not even
need this to see the argument.



[PEN-L:5600] Math 2

1995-06-19 Thread Curtis Moore

Math  Language 2.

 The controversy between Newton and Leibniz over the
"invention" of the calculus is interesting in this regard and
sheds some light on the subject.  The three greatest mathe-
maticians of all time are generally considered to be Archimedes,
Newton and Gauss.  The crown probably belongs to Newton although
he insisted that he "stood on the shoulders of giants" -- which
is correct.  It is said that Newton worked out his proofs using
his newly invented?/discovered? calculus, but then restated or
translated these proofs into the language of Euclidean geometry. 
Thus the great treatise called _... Principia Mathematica_(1687)
is incredibly obscure because calculus is carried out in the
language of Euclidean geometry.  Why did Newton do such a thing? 
He said he wanted to make it difficult in order to avoid
intellectual squabbling.  However, I suspect that another more
important reason is that he was first and foremost concerned to
demonstrate without question the truth of his theorems.  He
couldn't do this at that time with "calculus" because arithmetic
and calculus were not axiomatized  until after centuries more
work (eventually in axiomatic set theory this century).  However,
Euclidean geometry had been axiomatized by Euclid, was based on
five "transparent" axioms (except the fifth wasn't so trans-
parent) and hence Newton could demonstrate the truth of his
theorems by "translating" calculus into Euclidean geometry,
thereby creating an incredibly exact but obscure treatise.

 Later on there was a huge intellectual dispute over who
"invented" the calculus, Newton or Leibniz.  Leibniz was the one
who invented the language of the caluclus that we use today.  He
took great pains in crafting the language.  For the next hundred
years English mathematicians, out of loyalty to Newton (English
nationalism) attempted to develop the calculus along Newton's
lines and failed.  Rather, further development of the calculus
was carried out on the continent because Leibniz had forged the
superior mathematical symbolism.

 Point -- mathematical languages themselves undergo develop-
ment.  What motivates this development?  The ease in carrying out
proofs and performing calculations.  However, such ease in one
direction (proofs and calculations) does not make for an easy
language to understand.  Rather it makes for a new language to
learn.  On the other hand, the deepest mathematical results are
very often most lucidly explained in ordinary language.  

 There was a linguistic progression in the development of the
symbolism (language) of mathematical logic also.  The first work
on this subject by G. Frege came out in 1879.  The symbolism was
hopelessly obscure. Thus Frege is obscure.  Bertrand Russell
studied under  the Italian mathematician G. Peano for a few years
and adopted Peano's symbolism as the symbolism of his _Principia
Mathematica_ -- like Newton's tome, another obscure work that had
to be gone over by scores of mathematicians and subsequent
generations thereof.  Gerhard Gentzen reformulated Russell's
awkward "symbolic logic" into a system of "natural deduction,"
the way we (i.e., mathematicians) "naturally" reason, the mature
form of mathematical logic today.  

 However, this reasoning is not that "natural" to most of the
species, but must be learned, just  as you have to learn French
if you're an English speaker.  Math majors seem to be so natural-
ly adept at this language that they don't need or bother to study
it formally.  It's sort of a sixth sense for them, even though it
took Bertrand Russell his entire early career to codify the
grammar.  (Should this grammar be taught to everyone, like
English grammar in grade school?  Is this possible or is the
subject too difficult?)  But I have to get on to mathematics in
economics.  I am hardly an expert on this subject, but I did take
a look at mathematical economics once in the 60s and formed an
opinion on it.  Which may be of interest.

Curtis Moore [EMAIL PROTECTED]



[PEN-L:5549] Re: language math

1995-06-15 Thread James Devine

In the midst of his very interesting and useful thoughts on math, 
Gil writes that "even if one doesn't agree with the premises of 
Okishio's theorem, who would have known that Marx's claim was 
inconsistent with those premises before Okishio's proof?"

I think this example shows up some of the limitations of 
mathematics as often applied to economics, though they do not 
apply to math _per se_.  The fact is that Okishio's premise 
(constant real wages) is _not_ the same as Marx's (constant rate 
of surplus-value), so that Okishio's theorem is not really a 
critique of Marx. Pen-l will be glad to hear that I am not 
criticizing Gil here, since I think he is familiar with the 
problems arising from the conflation of the two assumptions (with 
Marx's, real wages rise with productivity). What I'm commenting 
on is the fact that many or even most of the writings since 
Okishio ignored this confusion and even ignored John Roemer's 
generalization of Okishio to a case that approximates the 
constant rate of surplus-value assumption. The authors wanted to 
talk about, apply, and extend Okishio's math and how it "proved" 
Marx wrong. I hope that authors such as Dave Laibman (and Gil 
himself  Frank Thompson) have gotten us away from the 
constant-real-wage assumption. 

The moral of the story is that one has to remember that math is a 
_means to an end_ (it's formalized logic) and should not become 
an end in itself, replacing scholarly discussion of the subject 
matter (such as actual reading of Marx) or other methods (such as 
dialectics). 

in pen-l solidarity,

Jim Devine   [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Econ. Dept., Loyola Marymount Univ., Los Angeles, CA 90045-2699 USA
310/338-2948 (daytime, during workweek); FAX: 310/338-1950
"Segui il tuo corso, e lascia dir le genti." (Go your own way
and let people talk.) -- K. Marx, paraphrasing Dante A.



[PEN-L:5551] Re: language math

1995-06-15 Thread GSKILLMAN

Jim writes:

 In the midst of his very interesting and useful thoughts on math, 
 Gil writes that "even if one doesn't agree with the premises of 
 Okishio's theorem, who would have known that Marx's claim was 
 inconsistent with those premises before Okishio's proof?"
 
 I think this example shows up some of the limitations of 
 mathematics as often applied to economics, though they do not 
 apply to math _per se_.  The fact is that Okishio's premise 
 (constant real wages) is _not_ the same as Marx's (constant rate 
 of surplus-value), so that Okishio's theorem is not really a 
 critique of Marx. Pen-l will be glad to hear that I am not 
 criticizing Gil here, since I think he is familiar with the 
 problems arising from the conflation of the two assumptions (with 
 Marx's, real wages rise with productivity). What I'm commenting 
 on is the fact that many or even most of the writings since 
 Okishio ignored this confusion and even ignored John Roemer's 
 generalization of Okishio to a case that approximates the 
 constant rate of surplus-value assumption. The authors wanted to 
 talk about, apply, and extend Okishio's math and how it "proved" 
 Marx wrong. I hope that authors such as Dave Laibman (and Gil 
 himself  Frank Thompson) have gotten us away from the 
 constant-real-wage assumption. 
 
 The moral of the story is that one has to remember that math is a 
 _means to an end_ (it's formalized logic) and should not become 
 an end in itself, replacing scholarly discussion of the subject 
 matter (such as actual reading of Marx) or other methods (such as 
 dialectics). 
 
Right on!

One minor comment:  Marx phrased his argument under the assumption 
that the rate of surplus value is held constant, but I don't read him 
positing this as the economically relevant condition--rather it's a 
simplifying assumption stipulated as a point of departure.  The 
economically relevant condition on wages would have to be supplied by 
a separate story about the impact of technical changes on labor 
market outcomes.  Roemer's argument is that there is (to him) an 
economically plausible story which supports the Okishio assumption, 
and he doesn't know of one which supports the constant-rate-of-
surplus-condition.  In a recent paper to which Jim refers (still in 
submission limbo), I establish market conditions --something like a 
stationary-state competitive equilibrium in a dynamic market--which 
support this assumption.

But the point still holds: if one replaces Marx's simplifying 
assumption with a demonstrably market-relevant condition (long-run 
wages constant at the subsistence level), there is no "tendency" for 
the rate of profit to fall--and this is a useful result. Gil



[PEN-L:5554] Re: language math

1995-06-15 Thread John R. Ernst

Gil, 
 
 
Other than as an exercise in gaining clarification concerning Marx's
terminology and thus in extending his efforts, how is the Okishio Theorem
relevant or "useful."  Note that for Okishio not only is the real wage
constant but all prices used in determining whether or not the rate of
profit fall are "equilibrium" prices determined with the assumption that
all capitals earn the same rate of profit.   I find this result not only of
 little use but also one absent in Marx's CAPITAL.  Note that the concepts
of "market value" and of "market price"  are both introduced  prior to the
discussion of "the law of the tendency of the rate of profit to fall." 
Thus, the question concerning the fall in the rate of profit should, at
least, consider an "equilibrium" condition in which the rates of profit are
not equal.  In an earlier plan for the third book o CAPITAL, Marx actually
planned to discuss the concept of rent prior to introducing the concept of
the falling rate of profit.   I realize that this may make mathematical
exercises concerning the falling rate of profit somewhat more complex,  but
they may yield something that relates to Marx's work.
 
Marx himself makes a slightly different point in Part III of Book III when
he notes that if price reductions due to  increases in productivity are
uniform, the rate of profit will not fall.   
 
 
   
   John