RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I actually agree with Greg on much here:  The reason that we
allow people to inflict various harms on others via their speech has a
lot to do with *the way* the harm is inflicted:  When harm is inflicted
by persuading, informing, or offending people with the content of
speech, we treat that infliction of harm as privileged.

And that's the reason that I think it's a mistake to say (and
Greg hasn't said it, but I think others have), "The Free Speech Clause
caselaw gives people the constitutional right to harm others through
speech, so the Free Exercise Clause should be interpreted as giving
people the constitutional right to harm others through religiously
motivated conduct."  The Free Speech Clause caselaw lets people harm
others through some specific speech-related ways.  It doesn't follow
that the Free Exercise Clause lets people harm others in other ways --
whether through discriminating against them, trespassing on their
property, breaching contracts, and so on, even if the harms are
comparatively minor.

Eugene

> -Original Message-
> From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
> [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
> Sisk, Gregory C.
> Sent: Monday, March 14, 2005 5:15 PM
> To: 'Law & Religion issues for Law Academics'
> Subject: RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others
> 
> 
> I accept Eugene's observation that my comparison cases suffer 
> from inadequate similarity comparison purposes.  Perhaps at 
> some point I'll try harder to develop less inferior paired 
> hypotheticals to better express my point (perhaps that task 
> will seem more appealing in a few weeks when I'm grading blue books).
> 
> But I still am not convinced either (1) that a greater degree 
> of burden from speech is acceptable because freedom of speech 
> is a more robust constitutional right than free exercise, or 
> (2) that the harms identified in the Flynt/Glynt 
> hypotheticals are truly comparable and thus illustrate the 
> point.  Indeed, in the Glynt hypothetical, if Mary Glynt 
> engaged in the same expression by bull-horn at the house 
> window but offered a free speech rather than free exercise 
> justification, the result would be the same -- she still 
> would lose.  Thus, it isn't the nature of the right that 
> explains the differing results but something about the nature 
> of the intrusion or the harm or the presence or absence of an 
> attenuated link between them.
> 
> Along these same lines, I'm persuaded that Eugene has a point 
> that we permit a larger range of expression under freedom of 
> speech than conduct under free exercise.  But isn't that in 
> part because speech is different from conduct (as Jim Maule 
> suggested) rather than because the constitutional rights 
> underlying one or the other are at different points in the 
> hierarchy of constitutional values?  While speech may and 
> sometimes does cause harm, it almost always does so 
> indirectly, as it depends for efficacy upon persuading 
> someone else that the message is credible or that a response 
> should be made. Thus, speech that is harmful depends upon a 
> chain from the speaker through the medium to a recipient who 
> in turn chooses to respond in a manner that induces harm to 
> the recipient or someone else.  Even speech that is intended 
> to cause harm may prove ineffective due to breaks in the 
> chain, especially if the recipient finds it uninteresting or 
> unpersuasive. By contrast, conduct -- whether expressive in 
> nature or not -- is immediate and if that conduct is harmful, 
> the harm is rather directly realized.
> 
> And related to that, I still think -- although my clumsy 
> hypotheticals may not have illustrated it well -- that the 
> harms involved may be different in nature or degree.  While 
> one subjectively and understandably might regard being 
> slandered before millions of readers as a greater source of 
> distress than being momentarily accosted at one's home by a 
> loud protester, the law always has treated a physical 
> invasion as different from an emotional response, even an 
> induced emotional response.  Indeed, some strains of law even 
> today still preclude recovery in tort for emotional distress 
> that is unaccompanied by physical injury.  If there is 
> anything to what I'm trying to say here, would it not follow 
> that different treatment of the trespasser who asserts a free 
> exercise defense from the magazine writer who claims freedom 
> of speech turns not upon which actor invokes which 
> constitutional protection but rather upon the nature of the 
> impact caused by the underlying conduct/expression?
> 
> Greg Sisk
> 
> 
> 
> -Original Message-
> From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
> Sent: Monday, March 14, 2005 3:57 PM
> To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics
> Subject: RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others
> 
>   I appreciate Greg's thoughtful analysis, but I think 
> that ultimately the magnitude of the burden on t

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
My analysis:  Warning of bad behavior by others, who are
genuinely unrelated to the speaker, and who are understood by listeners
to be unrelated to the speaker is protected.  Warning of retribution by
God is thus not a threat -- but neither is warning of retribution by
religious zealots, if it's clear from context that the zealots aren't
the speaker or his confederates.

Warning of bad behavior by yourself or by your confederates is
unprotected.  Warning of retribution is thus a threat, if it's intended
to and reasonably likely to lead the listener to think that you or your
confederates will act as God's agents in this.

This may well leave lots of questions about when ambiguous
warnings are really warnings of future misconduct by the speaker or his
confederates.  But that's true whether you're warning of retaliation by
God or by others.

A closing set of examples:
1.  "Don't have promiscuous sex, or else God will strike you
dead."
2.  "Don't have promiscuous sex, or else you'll die of AIDS."
3.  "Don't have promiscuous sex, or else your crazy cousin will
kill you."  (Assume that the speaker is unconnected to the cousin.)
4.  "Don't have promiscuous sex, cousin, because I'll kill you
to wipe off the stain from our family honor."
5.  "Don't have promiscuous sex, cousin, because God will strike
you dead."  (Assume that other people the listeners know have been
killed under mysterious circumstances, and it's assumed that these were
"honor killings" by family.)

Seems to me that #1-3 are protected and #4-5 are unprotected;
the relevant distinction isn't the religiosity of the motivation or the
statement, but the items I mention above.

Eugene

> -Original Message-
> From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
> [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of James Maule
> Sent: Monday, March 14, 2005 7:52 PM
> To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
> Subject: RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others
> 
> 
> Suppose the statement was a wee bit different: "This is a
> really nice restaurant you have here, except for those 
> blasphemous pictures on the walls.  It would be a shame if 
> God caused it to burn down, for example, by causing lightning 
> to strike or a meteor fragment to hit, which I pray every day 
> God will do if you don't let God answer my other prayer that 
> you see the light and take down those pictures." And assume 
> there hasn't been a previous history of restaurants burning 
> down. Much preaching contains the not-so-veiled threat of 
> divine retribution. So in this case the speech has to be protected.
> 
> Now suppose a few days later an unexplained fire destroys the
> restaurant. Shortly before a thunderstorm. Speaker argues her 
> prayers were answered. Case probably dismissed on basis of 
> failure of proof.
> 
> Then it happens again. And again. At some point the
> coincidences become too much. So does protected speech lose 
> its protection based on the "track record" of previous 
> speech? By the same person? By confederates? By proselytizers 
> of another denomination or sect? 
> 
> Jim Maule
> 
> >>> [EMAIL PROTECTED] 3/14/2005 10:33:25 PM >>>
>   I think the question in either case would be (1)
> whether the listener would reasonably understand this as a 
> threat of attack by the speaker or the speaker's confederates 
> and (2) whether the speaker intended to put the listener in 
> fear of such attack (see Virginia v. Black).  So it's 
> possible that #2 would indeed be a threat, and that #1 would 
> not be, depending on what else the listener knows about the 
> speaker.  If the speaker or his buddies are suspected of 
> killing other annoying people, for instance, statement #2 
> might well be punishable.
> 
>   Consider this statement:  "This is a really nice
> restaurant you have here, except for those blasphemous 
> pictures on the walls.  It would be a shame if God caused it 
> to burn down."  Other neighboring restaurants have in fact 
> burned down after they refused to take down blasphemous 
> pictures.  The speaker is religiously motivated (which I take 
> it is the test for a Sherbert/Yoder-era free exercise claim), 
> and as it happens the underlying dispute, as well as the 
> language of the statement, are religious.  If the speaker 
> intends to make the listener afraid of burning by the speaker 
> or his confederates, and a reasonable listener would have 
> this fear, then it seems to me that this is a punishable threat.
> 
> > -Original Message-
> > From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
> > [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of James Maule
> > Sent: Monday, March 14, 2005 5:38 PM
> > To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
> > Subject: RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others
> > 
> > 
> > OK, I see your point and it helps me refine the hypo:
> > 
> > 1. "I pray I can find someone to put an end to your annoying 
> > existence on this planet."
> > 
> > 2. "I pray to God every night that someh

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread James Maule
Suppose the statement was a wee bit different: "This is a really nice
restaurant you have here, except for those blasphemous pictures on the
walls.  It would be a shame if God caused it to burn down, for example,
by causing lightning to strike or a meteor fragment to hit, which I pray
every day God will do if you don't let God answer my other prayer that
you see the light and take down those pictures." And assume there hasn't
been a previous history of restaurants burning down. Much preaching
contains the not-so-veiled threat of divine retribution. So in this case
the speech has to be protected.

Now suppose a few days later an unexplained fire destroys the
restaurant. Shortly before a thunderstorm. Speaker argues her prayers
were answered. Case probably dismissed on basis of failure of proof.

Then it happens again. And again. At some point the coincidences become
too much. So does protected speech lose its protection based on the
"track record" of previous speech? By the same person? By confederates?
By proselytizers of another denomination or sect? 

Jim Maule

>>> [EMAIL PROTECTED] 3/14/2005 10:33:25 PM >>>
I think the question in either case would be (1) whether the
listener would reasonably understand this as a threat of attack by the
speaker or the speaker's confederates and (2) whether the speaker
intended to put the listener in fear of such attack (see Virginia v.
Black).  So it's possible that #2 would indeed be a threat, and that
#1
would not be, depending on what else the listener knows about the
speaker.  If the speaker or his buddies are suspected of killing other
annoying people, for instance, statement #2 might well be punishable.

Consider this statement:  "This is a really nice restaurant you
have here, except for those blasphemous pictures on the walls.  It
would
be a shame if God caused it to burn down."  Other neighboring
restaurants have in fact burned down after they refused to take down
blasphemous pictures.  The speaker is religiously motivated (which I
take it is the test for a Sherbert/Yoder-era free exercise claim), and
as it happens the underlying dispute, as well as the language of the
statement, are religious.  If the speaker intends to make the listener
afraid of burning by the speaker or his confederates, and a reasonable
listener would have this fear, then it seems to me that this is a
punishable threat.

> -Original Message-
> From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
> [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of James Maule
> Sent: Monday, March 14, 2005 5:38 PM
> To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu 
> Subject: RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others
> 
> 
> OK, I see your point and it helps me refine the hypo:
> 
> 1. "I pray I can find someone to put an end to your annoying 
> existence on this planet."
> 
> 2. "I pray to God every night that somehow the angel of death 
> visits you and puts an end to your annoying existence on this
planet."
> 
> Assuming that the recipient of the words doesn't treat #2 as 
> a silliness (e.g. reaction of an athiest) but has a 
> theological perspective that makes it upsetting and 
> emotionally distressful, ought not #2 be protected and #1 
> actionable (assuming a showing of damage or injury, etc.)? Is 
> it because the second is unprovable to a purely rational 
> mind? Would it be on account of #2 being religiously 
> motivated? (By religiously motivated, do you mean the 
> motivation for the belief that the threat can be made, or the 
> underlying dispute that generates the felt need to make the 
> threat? I'm assuming the first, but perhaps I'm misreading 
> your explanation.)
> 
> Jim Maule
> 
> >>> [EMAIL PROTECTED] 3/14/2005 7:08:23 PM >>>
>   I suspect that the distinction here isn't religious 
> speech vs. secular speech and more (1) speech that sounds 
> like warning of action by others who are unrelated to the 
> speakers vs. (2) speech that sounds like warning of action by 
> the speaker or his confederates.  If a mother is really angry 
> at a child and says "You're going to get killed if you use 
> drugs / run around with bad kids / do other dangerous stuff," 
> we wouldn't treat that as a threat, because it's clearly a 
> warning of what others might do.  Conversely, "God is going 
> to call you to judgment soon" might well be a threat if in 
> context it's pretty clear that the person is conveying a 
> message that he or his confederates might be the tools that 
> God uses for this call.  More broadly, there surely shouldn't 
> be unqualified Free Exercise Clause protection for all 
> threats that are religiously motivated, no?
> 
>   Eugene
> 
> Jim Maule writes:
> 
> > Compare "You're going to get yours some day, and it could be
> > within the next minute" (shouted, eyes bulging, face red, 
> > fists clenched, during law conerence disputing whether a 
> > state should permit same-gender
> > marriages) with "You're going to burn in hell and swim with 
> > the demons some day, and it could be within the

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I think the question in either case would be (1) whether the
listener would reasonably understand this as a threat of attack by the
speaker or the speaker's confederates and (2) whether the speaker
intended to put the listener in fear of such attack (see Virginia v.
Black).  So it's possible that #2 would indeed be a threat, and that #1
would not be, depending on what else the listener knows about the
speaker.  If the speaker or his buddies are suspected of killing other
annoying people, for instance, statement #2 might well be punishable.

Consider this statement:  "This is a really nice restaurant you
have here, except for those blasphemous pictures on the walls.  It would
be a shame if God caused it to burn down."  Other neighboring
restaurants have in fact burned down after they refused to take down
blasphemous pictures.  The speaker is religiously motivated (which I
take it is the test for a Sherbert/Yoder-era free exercise claim), and
as it happens the underlying dispute, as well as the language of the
statement, are religious.  If the speaker intends to make the listener
afraid of burning by the speaker or his confederates, and a reasonable
listener would have this fear, then it seems to me that this is a
punishable threat.

> -Original Message-
> From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
> [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of James Maule
> Sent: Monday, March 14, 2005 5:38 PM
> To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
> Subject: RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others
> 
> 
> OK, I see your point and it helps me refine the hypo:
> 
> 1. "I pray I can find someone to put an end to your annoying 
> existence on this planet."
> 
> 2. "I pray to God every night that somehow the angel of death 
> visits you and puts an end to your annoying existence on this planet."
> 
> Assuming that the recipient of the words doesn't treat #2 as 
> a silliness (e.g. reaction of an athiest) but has a 
> theological perspective that makes it upsetting and 
> emotionally distressful, ought not #2 be protected and #1 
> actionable (assuming a showing of damage or injury, etc.)? Is 
> it because the second is unprovable to a purely rational 
> mind? Would it be on account of #2 being religiously 
> motivated? (By religiously motivated, do you mean the 
> motivation for the belief that the threat can be made, or the 
> underlying dispute that generates the felt need to make the 
> threat? I'm assuming the first, but perhaps I'm misreading 
> your explanation.)
> 
> Jim Maule
> 
> >>> [EMAIL PROTECTED] 3/14/2005 7:08:23 PM >>>
>   I suspect that the distinction here isn't religious 
> speech vs. secular speech and more (1) speech that sounds 
> like warning of action by others who are unrelated to the 
> speakers vs. (2) speech that sounds like warning of action by 
> the speaker or his confederates.  If a mother is really angry 
> at a child and says "You're going to get killed if you use 
> drugs / run around with bad kids / do other dangerous stuff," 
> we wouldn't treat that as a threat, because it's clearly a 
> warning of what others might do.  Conversely, "God is going 
> to call you to judgment soon" might well be a threat if in 
> context it's pretty clear that the person is conveying a 
> message that he or his confederates might be the tools that 
> God uses for this call.  More broadly, there surely shouldn't 
> be unqualified Free Exercise Clause protection for all 
> threats that are religiously motivated, no?
> 
>   Eugene
> 
> Jim Maule writes:
> 
> > Compare "You're going to get yours some day, and it could be
> > within the next minute" (shouted, eyes bulging, face red, 
> > fists clenched, during law conerence disputing whether a 
> > state should permit same-gender
> > marriages) with "You're going to burn in hell and swim with 
> > the demons some day, and it could be within the next minute 
> > because you never know when God's going to call you to 
> > judgment" (shouted, eyes bulging, face red, fists clenched, 
> > during theological convention disputing whether a 
> > denomination should sanctify same-gender marriages).
> > 
> > Recipient of speech in both instances sues, alleging
> > emotional distress, fear of harm, and physical manifestations 
> > thereof. Recipient in both instances is a person who believes 
> > in the existence of hell and for whom an eternal placement 
> > therein is a horrifying thought. Recipient is also a person 
> > who dreads physical pain. If the first tirade is construed as 
> > fighting words, is the second necessarily treated the same 
> > way? I can see the same jury finding for the plaintiff in the 
> > first but not in the second. Why? Because the second involves 
> > speech the meaning of which is immersed in theological 
> > mystery (after all, who really knows for sure?) whereas the 
> > first involves speeach the meaning of which is immersed in a 
> > not so mysterious message of imminent physical threat. Note 
> > that the conduct and principa

Re: ministerial exception

2005-03-14 Thread Hamilton02




Chip-- How does this principle play out in the Petruska case now heading to 
the 3d Cir?  The district court threw out a woman's claim against the 
Catholic Church on the theory of the "ministerial exception."  She was a 
Catholic chaplain who was fired after being a whistleblower on clergy abuse 
in the church.  She claimed gender issues were involved.  District 
court held that her claim was barred by the ministerial exception.
 
Marci
 
 
In a message dated 3/14/2005 4:44:13 P.M. Eastern Standard Time, 
[EMAIL PROTECTED] writes:
for now 
  the ministerial exception doctrine has held firm in every non-harassment case 
  of discrimination brought by a member of the clergy against his or her 
  denomination.

 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-14 Thread Hamilton02




As I have said repeatedly, plenty of legislative accommodations are 
constitutional and legitimate.  Blind accommodation, though, (RFRA/RLUIPA) 
in particular, presents legislators at their worst-- deferential to the point of 
being brain-dead, when there are obvious harms to others in the process.  
It's not that legislators have to come out on the side of the third-party 
victims every time.  Rather, a legislator that does not question  the 
religious entity's request for exemption has sold out.
 
Marci
 
 
In a message dated 3/14/2005 4:54:30 P.M. Eastern Standard Time, 
[EMAIL PROTECTED] writes:

  In other words, the unifying theme in this 
  position is not deference to legislative acts, but hostility to legislative 
  acts and judicial rules alike if they help religious litigants.
   

 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread James Maule
OK, I see your point and it helps me refine the hypo:

1. "I pray I can find someone to put an end to your annoying existence
on this planet."

2. "I pray to God every night that somehow the angel of death visits
you and puts an end to your annoying existence on this planet."

Assuming that the recipient of the words doesn't treat #2 as a
silliness (e.g. reaction of an athiest) but has a theological
perspective that makes it upsetting and emotionally distressful, ought
not #2 be protected and #1 actionable (assuming a showing of damage or
injury, etc.)? Is it because the second is unprovable to a purely
rational mind? Would it be on account of #2 being religiously motivated?
(By religiously motivated, do you mean the motivation for the belief
that the threat can be made, or the underlying dispute that generates
the felt need to make the threat? I'm assuming the first, but perhaps
I'm misreading your explanation.)

Jim Maule

>>> [EMAIL PROTECTED] 3/14/2005 7:08:23 PM >>>
I suspect that the distinction here isn't religious speech vs.
secular speech and more (1) speech that sounds like warning of action
by
others who are unrelated to the speakers vs. (2) speech that sounds
like
warning of action by the speaker or his confederates.  If a mother is
really angry at a child and says "You're going to get killed if you
use
drugs / run around with bad kids / do other dangerous stuff," we
wouldn't treat that as a threat, because it's clearly a warning of
what
others might do.  Conversely, "God is going to call you to judgment
soon" might well be a threat if in context it's pretty clear that the
person is conveying a message that he or his confederates might be the
tools that God uses for this call.  More broadly, there surely
shouldn't
be unqualified Free Exercise Clause protection for all threats that
are
religiously motivated, no?

Eugene

Jim Maule writes:

> Compare "You're going to get yours some day, and it could be 
> within the next minute" (shouted, eyes bulging, face red, 
> fists clenched, during law conerence disputing whether a 
> state should permit same-gender
> marriages) with "You're going to burn in hell and swim with 
> the demons some day, and it could be within the next minute 
> because you never know when God's going to call you to 
> judgment" (shouted, eyes bulging, face red, fists clenched, 
> during theological convention disputing whether a 
> denomination should sanctify same-gender marriages).
> 
> Recipient of speech in both instances sues, alleging 
> emotional distress, fear of harm, and physical manifestations 
> thereof. Recipient in both instances is a person who believes 
> in the existence of hell and for whom an eternal placement 
> therein is a horrifying thought. Recipient is also a person 
> who dreads physical pain. If the first tirade is construed as 
> fighting words, is the second necessarily treated the same 
> way? I can see the same jury finding for the plaintiff in the 
> first but not in the second. Why? Because the second involves 
> speech the meaning of which is immersed in theological 
> mystery (after all, who really knows for sure?) whereas the 
> first involves speeach the meaning of which is immersed in a 
> not so mysterious message of imminent physical threat. Note 
> that the conduct and principal issue are identical, but the 
> location, context, and participants differ (secular v. theological).

> 
> Would you protect the speech in both cases? Not protect it in 
> both cases? Or leave open the possibility of different outcomes?
> 
> Jim Maule
> Villanova University School of Law
> 
> >>> [EMAIL PROTECTED] 3/14/2005 6:23:40 PM >>>
>   I'm not sure why "it makes a lot of sense to severely 
> limit the extent to which courts measure the emotional 
> distress caused by religious expression (in contrast to other 
> speech)" -- why not severely limit the extent to which courts 
> impose liability on emotional distress caused by speech, 
> period?  If Senator Llynt gives a speech decrying the 
> political positions taken by Falwell, denouncing the alleged 
> intrusion of Falwell's theology into politics, and 
> characterizing Falwell as a generally bad person, it seems to 
> me that he should be categorically immune from IIED liability 
> even if his speech is purely nonreligious. If I'm right, then 
> why is there any need for extra protection for religious speech?
> 
>   (I realize that there might be some situations where 
> religious speech is immune from liability because it's 
> incapable of secular proof; but generally the remedy there is 
> to treat is the same as secular opinions that are incapable 
> of proof, which are constitutionally
> protected,)
> 
>   Eugene
> 
> Jim Maule writes:
> 
> > Suppose instead of Flynt satirizing Falwell, the Rev. Llynt
> > preaches a sermon in his progressive church decrying the 
> > theological positions taken by Falwell, denouncing the 
> > alleged intrusion of Falwell's theology into po

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread Sisk, Gregory C.
I accept Eugene's observation that my comparison cases suffer from
inadequate similarity comparison purposes.  Perhaps at some point I'll try
harder to develop less inferior paired hypotheticals to better express my
point (perhaps that task will seem more appealing in a few weeks when I'm
grading blue books).

But I still am not convinced either (1) that a greater degree of burden from
speech is acceptable because freedom of speech is a more robust
constitutional right than free exercise, or (2) that the harms identified in
the Flynt/Glynt hypotheticals are truly comparable and thus illustrate the
point.  Indeed, in the Glynt hypothetical, if Mary Glynt engaged in the same
expression by bull-horn at the house window but offered a free speech rather
than free exercise justification, the result would be the same -- she still
would lose.  Thus, it isn't the nature of the right that explains the
differing results but something about the nature of the intrusion or the
harm or the presence or absence of an attenuated link between them.

Along these same lines, I'm persuaded that Eugene has a point that we permit
a larger range of expression under freedom of speech than conduct under free
exercise.  But isn't that in part because speech is different from conduct
(as Jim Maule suggested) rather than because the constitutional rights
underlying one or the other are at different points in the hierarchy of
constitutional values?  While speech may and sometimes does cause harm, it
almost always does so indirectly, as it depends for efficacy upon persuading
someone else that the message is credible or that a response should be made.
Thus, speech that is harmful depends upon a chain from the speaker through
the medium to a recipient who in turn chooses to respond in a manner that
induces harm to the recipient or someone else.  Even speech that is intended
to cause harm may prove ineffective due to breaks in the chain, especially
if the recipient finds it uninteresting or unpersuasive. By contrast,
conduct -- whether expressive in nature or not -- is immediate and if that
conduct is harmful, the harm is rather directly realized.

And related to that, I still think -- although my clumsy hypotheticals may
not have illustrated it well -- that the harms involved may be different in
nature or degree.  While one subjectively and understandably might regard
being slandered before millions of readers as a greater source of distress
than being momentarily accosted at one's home by a loud protester, the law
always has treated a physical invasion as different from an emotional
response, even an induced emotional response.  Indeed, some strains of law
even today still preclude recovery in tort for emotional distress that is
unaccompanied by physical injury.  If there is anything to what I'm trying
to say here, would it not follow that different treatment of the trespasser
who asserts a free exercise defense from the magazine writer who claims
freedom of speech turns not upon which actor invokes which constitutional
protection but rather upon the nature of the impact caused by the underlying
conduct/expression?

Greg Sisk



-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Monday, March 14, 2005 3:57 PM
To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

I appreciate Greg's thoughtful analysis, but I think that
ultimately the magnitude of the burden on the nonspeaker's/nonclaimant's
rights doesn't resolve the problems.  I would feel *much* more
distressed by knowing that millions (?) of people are reading about how
I supposedly had sex with my mother in an outhouse (even if they know
it's a gag) than by a few nights of loud noise outside my house.

Likewise, I suspect that the more-or-less three-year-long
boycott in Claiborne Hardware affected local businesses more than the
occasional blockage would affect the business of an abortion clinic.
It's true that this may be so because the boycott went on for a long
time, while the blockage in my hypothetical wouldn't.  But under free
speech law, even speech urging a long boycott can't be punished -- and
even one instance of entrance blockage, which would cause vastly less
damage than the boycott, would be punishable, whether or not it's
religiously based.  So people are constitutionally entitled to inflict
considerably greater harms through the communicative impact of their
speech than through the religiously motivated conduct.  Or am I mistaken
here?

As to the housing discrimination scenario, I just think Greg's
comparison cases are actually not terribly similar.  The gay couple's
claim isn't necessarily that they're deeply emotionally distressed --
rather, it is that they have a legal right to equal treatment,
regardless of whether the unequal treatment is terribly distressing.
Maybe this right flows from a general sense that the unequal treatment
is usually distressing, but it d

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Title: Message



    (1)  I don't think anything I've said 
suggests that displays of the Ten Commandments by nongovernmental actors could 
be restrictable.  They are just as protected by the freedom of speech as 
displays of any other sentiments.  (Whether governmental actors may display 
the Ten Commandments is of course a matter of the Establishment Clause 
constraints on the government.)
 
    (2)  I think that the Free Speech Clause protects Mormons' 
and Jehovah's Witnesses' ability to express their views precisely to the same 
extent that it protects Greenpeace's or the Libertarians' ability.  Given 
Martin v. Struthers, both are protected if the householder hasn't put up a No 
Soliciting sign, and both are unprotected if the householder has put up a No 
Soliciting sign.  See also Heffron v. ISKCON, holding, even during the 
Sherbert/Yoder era, that the Free Exercise Clause gave no more protection to 
religious speech than the Free Speech Clause gives to speech generally (and thus 
applying intermediate scrutiny rather than strict scrutiny to a Free Exercise 
Clause challenge to a content-neutral speech restriction).
 
    (3)  A simple and plausible example:  Operation Rescue 
decides, because of their religious beliefs, to picket an abortion 
provider's home.  A pro-choice group decides, because of their nonreligious 
political beliefs, to picket the Operation Rescue leader's home.  
Could Operation Rescue really have broader speech rights than the pro-choice 
group -- with the Operation Rescue claim being subject to strict scrutiny, and 
the pro-choice group's being subject only to intermediate scrutiny (see Frisby 
v. Schultz) -- because Operation Rescue has a religious motivation for its 
speech?  I would think the answer is no.
 
    Eugene
 
Steve Jamar 
writes:

  
  -Original Message-From: 
  [EMAIL PROTECTED] [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
  On Behalf Of Steven JamarSent: Monday, March 14, 2005 3:52 
  PMTo: Law & Religion issues for Law 
  AcademicsSubject: Re: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to 
  others
  On Monday, March 14, 2005, at 06:20 PM, Volokh, Eugene wrote: 
  
Rather, my argument is 
that the Free Exercise Clause ought not be read as allowing people to 
do 
things that harm others simply because they feel a religious obligation 

to do those things. 
  So you would be against displays of the 10 commandments on free exercise 
  grounds because of the of the psychic harm caused by them to others even 
  though they are displayed as a result of a religious obligation? And you would 
  ban Mormons and JWs from stopping at my door just like all other peddlars -- 
  if I could show psychic harm? I guess I don't see where this leads us out of 
  the wilderness any better than the current mish mash of principles, policies, 
  and adjustments. 
   
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I suspect that the distinction here isn't religious speech vs.
secular speech and more (1) speech that sounds like warning of action by
others who are unrelated to the speakers vs. (2) speech that sounds like
warning of action by the speaker or his confederates.  If a mother is
really angry at a child and says "You're going to get killed if you use
drugs / run around with bad kids / do other dangerous stuff," we
wouldn't treat that as a threat, because it's clearly a warning of what
others might do.  Conversely, "God is going to call you to judgment
soon" might well be a threat if in context it's pretty clear that the
person is conveying a message that he or his confederates might be the
tools that God uses for this call.  More broadly, there surely shouldn't
be unqualified Free Exercise Clause protection for all threats that are
religiously motivated, no?

Eugene

Jim Maule writes:

> Compare "You're going to get yours some day, and it could be 
> within the next minute" (shouted, eyes bulging, face red, 
> fists clenched, during law conerence disputing whether a 
> state should permit same-gender
> marriages) with "You're going to burn in hell and swim with 
> the demons some day, and it could be within the next minute 
> because you never know when God's going to call you to 
> judgment" (shouted, eyes bulging, face red, fists clenched, 
> during theological convention disputing whether a 
> denomination should sanctify same-gender marriages).
> 
> Recipient of speech in both instances sues, alleging 
> emotional distress, fear of harm, and physical manifestations 
> thereof. Recipient in both instances is a person who believes 
> in the existence of hell and for whom an eternal placement 
> therein is a horrifying thought. Recipient is also a person 
> who dreads physical pain. If the first tirade is construed as 
> fighting words, is the second necessarily treated the same 
> way? I can see the same jury finding for the plaintiff in the 
> first but not in the second. Why? Because the second involves 
> speech the meaning of which is immersed in theological 
> mystery (after all, who really knows for sure?) whereas the 
> first involves speeach the meaning of which is immersed in a 
> not so mysterious message of imminent physical threat. Note 
> that the conduct and principal issue are identical, but the 
> location, context, and participants differ (secular v. theological). 
> 
> Would you protect the speech in both cases? Not protect it in 
> both cases? Or leave open the possibility of different outcomes?
> 
> Jim Maule
> Villanova University School of Law
> 
> >>> [EMAIL PROTECTED] 3/14/2005 6:23:40 PM >>>
>   I'm not sure why "it makes a lot of sense to severely 
> limit the extent to which courts measure the emotional 
> distress caused by religious expression (in contrast to other 
> speech)" -- why not severely limit the extent to which courts 
> impose liability on emotional distress caused by speech, 
> period?  If Senator Llynt gives a speech decrying the 
> political positions taken by Falwell, denouncing the alleged 
> intrusion of Falwell's theology into politics, and 
> characterizing Falwell as a generally bad person, it seems to 
> me that he should be categorically immune from IIED liability 
> even if his speech is purely nonreligious. If I'm right, then 
> why is there any need for extra protection for religious speech?
> 
>   (I realize that there might be some situations where 
> religious speech is immune from liability because it's 
> incapable of secular proof; but generally the remedy there is 
> to treat is the same as secular opinions that are incapable 
> of proof, which are constitutionally
> protected,)
> 
>   Eugene
> 
> Jim Maule writes:
> 
> > Suppose instead of Flynt satirizing Falwell, the Rev. Llynt
> > preaches a sermon in his progressive church decrying the 
> > theological positions taken by Falwell, denouncing the 
> > alleged intrusion of Falwell's theology into politics, and 
> > characterizing Falwell as a modern-day Pharisee. The sermon 
> > concludes that it is behavior and proselytization such as 
> > that in which Falwell engages that continues to contribute to 
> > the agony of Jesus on the Cross. The sermon is broadcast on 
> > tv, radio, and/or the web (to get roughly the same 
> > dissemination as Flynt managed with Hustler). Falwell is 
> > understandably upset and emotionally distressed (assume that 
> > it's just as distressing to him as were the comments about 
> > his mother).
> > 
> > Must Falwell meet a higher burden because the offending
> > speech is a religious sermon rather than a parody in a 
> > secular publication? Should the courts get involved in the 
> > modern equivalent of the 17th century "pamphlet wars" if one 
> > or both of the parties alleges some sort of emotional 
> > distress or other damage? Or should the courts do as 
> > suggested the jury in Thomas Maule's trial: "This is a matter 
> > for a

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread James Maule
Compare "You're going to get yours some day, and it could be within the
next minute" (shouted, eyes bulging, face red, fists clenched, during
law conerence disputing whether a state should permit same-gender
marriages) with "You're going to burn in hell and swim with the demons
some day, and it could be within the next minute because you never know
when God's going to call you to judgment" (shouted, eyes bulging, face
red, fists clenched, during theological convention disputing whether a
denomination should sanctify same-gender marriages).

Recipient of speech in both instances sues, alleging emotional
distress, fear of harm, and physical manifestations thereof. Recipient
in both instances is a person who believes in the existence of hell and
for whom an eternal placement therein is a horrifying thought. Recipient
is also a person who dreads physical pain. If the first tirade is
construed as fighting words, is the second necessarily treated the same
way? I can see the same jury finding for the plaintiff in the first but
not in the second. Why? Because the second involves speech the meaning
of which is immersed in theological mystery (after all, who really knows
for sure?) whereas the first involves speeach the meaning of which is
immersed in a not so mysterious message of imminent physical threat.
Note that the conduct and principal issue are identical, but the
location, context, and participants differ (secular v. theological). 

Would you protect the speech in both cases? Not protect it in both
cases? Or leave open the possibility of different outcomes?

Jim Maule
Villanova University School of Law

>>> [EMAIL PROTECTED] 3/14/2005 6:23:40 PM >>>
I'm not sure why "it makes a lot of sense to severely limit the
extent to which courts measure the emotional distress caused by
religious expression (in contrast to other speech)" -- why not
severely
limit the extent to which courts impose liability on emotional
distress
caused by speech, period?  If Senator Llynt gives a speech decrying
the
political positions taken by Falwell, denouncing the alleged intrusion
of Falwell's theology into politics, and characterizing Falwell as a
generally bad person, it seems to me that he should be categorically
immune from IIED liability even if his speech is purely nonreligious.
If I'm right, then why is there any need for extra protection for
religious speech?

(I realize that there might be some situations where religious
speech is immune from liability because it's incapable of secular
proof;
but generally the remedy there is to treat is the same as secular
opinions that are incapable of proof, which are constitutionally
protected,)

Eugene

Jim Maule writes:

> Suppose instead of Flynt satirizing Falwell, the Rev. Llynt 
> preaches a sermon in his progressive church decrying the 
> theological positions taken by Falwell, denouncing the 
> alleged intrusion of Falwell's theology into politics, and 
> characterizing Falwell as a modern-day Pharisee. The sermon 
> concludes that it is behavior and proselytization such as 
> that in which Falwell engages that continues to contribute to 
> the agony of Jesus on the Cross. The sermon is broadcast on 
> tv, radio, and/or the web (to get roughly the same 
> dissemination as Flynt managed with Hustler). Falwell is 
> understandably upset and emotionally distressed (assume that 
> it's just as distressing to him as were the comments about 
> his mother).
> 
> Must Falwell meet a higher burden because the offending 
> speech is a religious sermon rather than a parody in a 
> secular publication? Should the courts get involved in the 
> modern equivalent of the 17th century "pamphlet wars" if one 
> or both of the parties alleges some sort of emotional 
> distress or other damage? Or should the courts do as 
> suggested the jury in Thomas Maule's trial: "This is a matter 
> for a jury of divines."?
> 
> I think it makes a lot of sense to severely limit the extent 
> to which courts measure the emotional distress caused by 
> religious expression (in contrast to other speech). 
> Otherwise, because religious expression also is a form of 
> free exercise, a back door is open to curtail the free 
> exercise rights of the speaker.
> 
> Jim Maule
> Villanova University School of Law
> 
> >>> [EMAIL PROTECTED] 3/14/2005 4:36:01 PM >>>
> While free exercise and free speech may be different in many 
> respects, and indeed most constitutional rights differ from 
> all other rights, as they are not merely fungible from one to 
> another, I don't think Eugene Volokh's thoughtful 
> hypotheticals satisfactorily dispose of the argument that 
> free exercise and free speech ought not be treated 
> differently in the amount of burden that we accept (or the 
> courts ought to accept) upon the public or others.  The 
> problem with Eugene's hypotheticals, as I see it, is that the 
> burdens outlined are not comparable, in part because one 
> involves non-physical speech and the

Re: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread Steven Jamar

On Monday, March 14, 2005, at 06:20  PM, Volokh, Eugene wrote:

Rather, my argument is
that the Free Exercise Clause ought not be read as allowing people to do
things that harm others simply because they feel a religious obligation
to do those things.

So you would be against displays of the 10 commandments on free exercise grounds because of the of the psychic harm caused by them to others even though they are displayed as a result of a religious obligation?  And you would ban Mormons and JWs from stopping at my door just like all other peddlars -- if I could show psychic harm?  I guess I don't see where this leads us out of the wilderness any better than the current mish mash of principles, policies, and adjustments.

-- 
Prof. Steven D. Jamar   vox:  202-806-8017
Howard University School of Law fax:  202-806-8567
2900 Van Ness Street NW   mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Washington, DC  20008   http://www.law.howard.edu/faculty/pages/jamar/

"Whenever you find yourself on the side of the majority, it is time to pause and reflect."

Mark Twain
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I'm not sure why "it makes a lot of sense to severely limit the
extent to which courts measure the emotional distress caused by
religious expression (in contrast to other speech)" -- why not severely
limit the extent to which courts impose liability on emotional distress
caused by speech, period?  If Senator Llynt gives a speech decrying the
political positions taken by Falwell, denouncing the alleged intrusion
of Falwell's theology into politics, and characterizing Falwell as a
generally bad person, it seems to me that he should be categorically
immune from IIED liability even if his speech is purely nonreligious.
If I'm right, then why is there any need for extra protection for
religious speech?

(I realize that there might be some situations where religious
speech is immune from liability because it's incapable of secular proof;
but generally the remedy there is to treat is the same as secular
opinions that are incapable of proof, which are constitutionally
protected,)

Eugene

Jim Maule writes:

> Suppose instead of Flynt satirizing Falwell, the Rev. Llynt 
> preaches a sermon in his progressive church decrying the 
> theological positions taken by Falwell, denouncing the 
> alleged intrusion of Falwell's theology into politics, and 
> characterizing Falwell as a modern-day Pharisee. The sermon 
> concludes that it is behavior and proselytization such as 
> that in which Falwell engages that continues to contribute to 
> the agony of Jesus on the Cross. The sermon is broadcast on 
> tv, radio, and/or the web (to get roughly the same 
> dissemination as Flynt managed with Hustler). Falwell is 
> understandably upset and emotionally distressed (assume that 
> it's just as distressing to him as were the comments about 
> his mother).
> 
> Must Falwell meet a higher burden because the offending 
> speech is a religious sermon rather than a parody in a 
> secular publication? Should the courts get involved in the 
> modern equivalent of the 17th century "pamphlet wars" if one 
> or both of the parties alleges some sort of emotional 
> distress or other damage? Or should the courts do as 
> suggested the jury in Thomas Maule's trial: "This is a matter 
> for a jury of divines."?
> 
> I think it makes a lot of sense to severely limit the extent 
> to which courts measure the emotional distress caused by 
> religious expression (in contrast to other speech). 
> Otherwise, because religious expression also is a form of 
> free exercise, a back door is open to curtail the free 
> exercise rights of the speaker.
> 
> Jim Maule
> Villanova University School of Law
> 
> >>> [EMAIL PROTECTED] 3/14/2005 4:36:01 PM >>>
> While free exercise and free speech may be different in many 
> respects, and indeed most constitutional rights differ from 
> all other rights, as they are not merely fungible from one to 
> another, I don't think Eugene Volokh's thoughtful 
> hypotheticals satisfactorily dispose of the argument that 
> free exercise and free speech ought not be treated 
> differently in the amount of burden that we accept (or the 
> courts ought to accept) upon the public or others.  The 
> problem with Eugene's hypotheticals, as I see it, is that the 
> burdens outlined are not comparable, in part because one 
> involves non-physical speech and the other involves conduct 
> (as Jim Maule observes), but also simply because of the 
> anticipated degree of negative impact upon persons other than 
> the one exercising the right.
> 
> Just to look at the first pair of hypotheticals:  While Jerry 
> Falwell is postulated to have experienced emotional distress 
> as a result of both incidents, I submit that we intuitively 
> would recognize that the immediacy and intrusiveness of the 
> harm differs greatly when we compare reading a scurrilous 
> reference to one's self in a periodical with experiencing an 
> almost physical trespass accompanied by the use of loud 
> sounds that cannot easily be escaped and, perhaps most 
> importantly, that occurs at one's place of sanctuary, the 
> home.  Thus, while I agree that the free speech claim in that 
> pair of hypotheticals is stronger than the free exercise 
> claim, I don't see the two cases as truly comparable in terms 
> of the degree and perhaps the nature of the harm, even if 
> both forms of harm are generally categorized as emotional distress.
> 
> Thus, for a set of hypotheticals comparing the strength of 
> free speech and free exercise claims to be truly comparable, 
> the nature or at least the degree of harm must also be 
> comparable.  While not neatly involving parallel factual 
> settings or messages, consider these two scenarios:  First, 
> we again have the offensive parody of Jerry Falwell in Larry 
> Flynt's Hustler magazine, in which Flynt invokes freedom of 
> speech as a defense against a claim for emotional distress.  
> Second, we have a homosexual couple that is rejected as 
> tenants by a homeowner of traditional religious val

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I'm not grounding it on the text, which gets us fairly little
here.  I'm generally persuaded by Justice Scalia's original meaning
argument in City of Boerne v. Flores as to free exercise; as to the
original meaning of free speech, I think that's basically unknown and
likely unknowable.

I should say, by the way, that my argument is *not* that
religiously motivated conduct or speech should be treated worse than the
nonreligiously motivated conduct or speech; I think the Free Exercise
Clause bars such discrimination against religious motivation.  I think
Lukumi is right, and Locke v. Davey is wrong.  Rather, my argument is
that the Free Exercise Clause ought not be read as allowing people to do
things that harm others simply because they feel a religious obligation
to do those things.

> -Original Message-
> From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
> [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
> Richard Dougherty
> Sent: Monday, March 14, 2005 2:35 PM
> To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics
> Subject: Re: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others
> 
> 
> Eugene:
> Are you grounding your analysis here of speech and religion 
> in the text of the First Amendment?  It seems to my untutored 
> eye that it is precisely "exercise" of religion that is 
> protected, no?  Is there any reason to think that exercise of 
> religion might not be harmful?  I guess my question is 
> whether you see the harm done by religion as unprotected 
> because of  some constitutional reason (such as, it amounts 
> to establishment)?  Why would the religious motivation be 
> treated any differently than an anti-religious motivation, or 
> a commitment to Millian liberalism, or the will to power?  If 
> the protection for speech's harm, is that speech is good for 
> democracy, cannot one make the same argument about much, if 
> not all, religious exercise?
> 
> (I'm not defending the principle that there is a right to 
> harm, only looking for consistency.)
> 
> Thanks,
> Richard Dougherty
> 
> 
> "Volokh, Eugene" wrote (in part):
> 
> > The Free Speech Clause and other rights *are* rights to 
> > inflict certain kinds of harm on others in certain ways 
> (for instance, 
> > through the communicative impact of speech); we think that 
> for various 
> > reasons, the government ought not be allowed to interfere with this 
> > harm, perhaps because speech is so valuable to democratic 
> > self-government, or because we suspect the government will 
> abuse its 
> > regulatory powers.  Likewise, as I argue at 
> > 
> http://www1.law.ucla.edu/>
~volokh/relfree.htm#Several%20Specific%20Proh
> > ib
> > itions%20on%20Government, in a few contexts (for instance,
> > discrimination in hiring clergy, or religious frauds), the 
> Free Exercise
> > Clause also allows religious people or institutions to 
> inflict what the
> > law might otherwise treat as harm to others.
> >
> > But we ought not read the Free Exercise Clause as generally 
> > licensing religious objectors to inflict harm on others (or 
> even to do 
> > so subject to a possible strict scrutiny trump).  As I argue, my 
> > relationship with my God may be important to me, but it can't by 
> > itself be a constitutionally sufficient justification for 
> my harming 
> > you, even slightly (for instance, by intentionally inflicting 
> > emotional distress on you in secular ways, blocking access 
> to your property, or slightly
> > vandalizing your commercial building).   From your 
> perspective and the
> > legal system's perspective (even if not from my own), my God is my 
> > God, not yours, and the Constitution doesn't give those 
> acting in His 
> > name sovereignty over your legally recognized rights and interests.
> >
> 
> ___
> To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
> To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, 
> see http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
> 
> Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be 
> viewed as private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read 
> messages that are posted; people can read the Web archives; 
> and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
> messages to others.
> 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread James Maule
Suppose instead of Flynt satirizing Falwell, the Rev. Llynt preaches a
sermon in his progressive church decrying the theological positions
taken by Falwell, denouncing the alleged intrusion of Falwell's theology
into politics, and characterizing Falwell as a modern-day Pharisee. The
sermon concludes that it is behavior and proselytization such as that in
which Falwell engages that continues to contribute to the agony of Jesus
on the Cross. The sermon is broadcast on tv, radio, and/or the web (to
get roughly the same dissemination as Flynt managed with Hustler).
Falwell is understandably upset and emotionally distressed (assume that
it's just as distressing to him as were the comments about his mother).

Must Falwell meet a higher burden because the offending speech is a
religious sermon rather than a parody in a secular publication? Should
the courts get involved in the modern equivalent of the 17th century
"pamphlet wars" if one or both of the parties alleges some sort of
emotional distress or other damage? Or should the courts do as suggested
the jury in Thomas Maule's trial: "This is a matter for a jury of
divines."?

I think it makes a lot of sense to severely limit the extent to which
courts measure the emotional distress caused by religious expression (in
contrast to other speech). Otherwise, because religious expression also
is a form of free exercise, a back door is open to curtail the free
exercise rights of the speaker.

Jim Maule
Villanova University School of Law

>>> [EMAIL PROTECTED] 3/14/2005 4:36:01 PM >>>
While free exercise and free speech may be different in many respects,
and
indeed most constitutional rights differ from all other rights, as they
are
not merely fungible from one to another, I don't think Eugene Volokh's
thoughtful hypotheticals satisfactorily dispose of the argument that
free
exercise and free speech ought not be treated differently in the amount
of
burden that we accept (or the courts ought to accept) upon the public
or
others.  The problem with Eugene's hypotheticals, as I see it, is that
the
burdens outlined are not comparable, in part because one involves
non-physical speech and the other involves conduct (as Jim Maule
observes),
but also simply because of the anticipated degree of negative impact
upon
persons other than the one exercising the right.

Just to look at the first pair of hypotheticals:  While Jerry Falwell
is
postulated to have experienced emotional distress as a result of both
incidents, I submit that we intuitively would recognize that the
immediacy
and intrusiveness of the harm differs greatly when we compare reading
a
scurrilous reference to one's self in a periodical with experiencing
an
almost physical trespass accompanied by the use of loud sounds that
cannot
easily be escaped and, perhaps most importantly, that occurs at one's
place
of sanctuary, the home.  Thus, while I agree that the free speech claim
in
that pair of hypotheticals is stronger than the free exercise claim, I
don't
see the two cases as truly comparable in terms of the degree and
perhaps the
nature of the harm, even if both forms of harm are generally
categorized as
emotional distress.

Thus, for a set of hypotheticals comparing the strength of free speech
and
free exercise claims to be truly comparable, the nature or at least
the
degree of harm must also be comparable.  While not neatly involving
parallel
factual settings or messages, consider these two scenarios:  First, we
again
have the offensive parody of Jerry Falwell in Larry Flynt's Hustler
magazine, in which Flynt invokes freedom of speech as a defense against
a
claim for emotional distress.  Second, we have a homosexual couple that
is
rejected as tenants by a homeowner of traditional religious values for
the
spare room in her house, in which the homeowner invokes free exercise
as a
defense as a claim for discrimination by the homosexual couple under a
municipal gay rights ordinance.  Assume for the sake of argument that
other
rental opportunities for homosexual couples are available in that
community
(a reasonable assumption, as a municipality in which political support
exists for enactment of a gay rights law involving housing is unlikely
to
one in which such discrimination is omnipresent across the community,
but
even if you find the assumption more debatable, I ask you to accept it
for
this hypothetical).

Under that hypothetical, then, the claim of the homosexual couple,
although
framed as housing discrimination and seeking the remedy of an
injunction, in
practical terms is about the emotional distress of having experienced
discrimination by being rejected as a tenant on the basis of sexual
orientation.  Isn't that experience of emotional distress comparable to
that
of Jerry Falwell who was targeted for sexualized slurs based upon his
religious and political views?  In both instances, the complaining
party
understandably and sincerely has suffered an emotional injury (as I'll
assume for this hypothetical, as I doub

Re: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread Richard Dougherty
Eugene:
Are you grounding your analysis here of speech and religion in the text of the 
First Amendment?  It seems to my untutored eye that it is precisely "exercise" 
of religion that is protected, no?  Is there any reason to think that exercise 
of religion might not
be harmful?  I guess my question is whether you see the harm done by religion 
as unprotected because of  some constitutional reason (such as, it amounts to 
establishment)?  Why would the religious motivation be treated any differently 
than an anti-religious
motivation, or a commitment to Millian liberalism, or the will to power?  If 
the protection for speech's harm, is that speech is good for democracy, cannot 
one make the same argument about much, if not all, religious exercise?

(I'm not defending the principle that there is a right to harm, only looking 
for consistency.)

Thanks,
Richard Dougherty


"Volokh, Eugene" wrote (in part):

> The Free Speech Clause and other rights *are* rights to inflict
> certain kinds of harm on others in certain ways (for instance, through
> the communicative impact of speech); we think that for various reasons,
> the government ought not be allowed to interfere with this harm, perhaps
> because speech is so valuable to democratic self-government, or because
> we suspect the government will abuse its regulatory powers.  Likewise,
> as I argue at
> http://www1.law.ucla.edu/~volokh/relfree.htm#Several%20Specific%20Prohib
> itions%20on%20Government, in a few contexts (for instance,
> discrimination in hiring clergy, or religious frauds), the Free Exercise
> Clause also allows religious people or institutions to inflict what the
> law might otherwise treat as harm to others.
>
> But we ought not read the Free Exercise Clause as generally
> licensing religious objectors to inflict harm on others (or even to do
> so subject to a possible strict scrutiny trump).  As I argue, my
> relationship with my God may be important to me, but it can't by itself
> be a constitutionally sufficient justification for my harming you, even
> slightly (for instance, by intentionally inflicting emotional distress
> on you in secular ways, blocking access to your property, or slightly
> vandalizing your commercial building).   From your perspective and the
> legal system's perspective (even if not from my own), my God is my God,
> not yours, and the Constitution doesn't give those acting in His name
> sovereignty over your legally recognized rights and interests.
>

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


Re: Wash. Post article on churches and land use regulation

2005-03-14 Thread Steven Jamar
 Yes, let's adopt a position of neutrality -- and tax churches 
and church lands just like other businesses and their land.  Why 
accommodate religion anyway?  Give them equal treatment on taxation. 


Eugene, how do you square the neutrality principle you advocate for 
benefits but not burdens?

On Monday, March 14, 2005, at 04:31  PM, Scarberry, Mark wrote:
http://www.washingtonpost.com/wp-dyn/articles/A32382-2005Mar13.html
Mark S. Scarberry
Pepperdine Univ. School of Law
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are 
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can 
(rightly or wrongly) forward the messages to others.


--
Prof. Steven D. Jamar vox:  202-806-8017
Howard University School of Law   fax:  202-806-8428
2900 Van Ness Street NW mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Washington, DC  20008  http://www.law.howard.edu/faculty/pages/jamar
"Nothing that is worth anything can be achieved in a lifetime; 
therefore we must be saved by hope."

Reinhold Neibuhr
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the messages to others.


Re: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-14 Thread Steven Jamar
I take it that challenges are improper even if well grounded?  Not all challenges, of course, prevail (Rosenberger).

On Monday, March 14, 2005, at 04:53  PM, Anthony Picarello wrote:

Then, with the sole exception of federal constitutional amendments, religious groups can expect Establishment Clause challenges to their hard-won legislative accommodations:  as "blind giveaways" if they are too broad (Cutter), as "denominational preferences" if too tailored (Kiryas Joel).  They may also face separation of powers challenges on the (ironic) theory that in providing accommodations, the legislature is usurping the role of judiciary.
 
In other words, the unifying theme in this position is not deference to legislative acts, but hostility to legislative acts and judicial rules alike if they help religious litigants.

Hostility by whom toward whom?  The ACLU and other groups defend religious people's rights as well as the rights of others, including in schools when teachers, principals or school boards utterly ban religious expression

-- 
Prof. Steven D. Jamar vox:  202-806-8017
Howard University School of Law   fax:  202-806-8428
2900 Van Ness Street NW	mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Washington, DC  20008  http://www.law.howard.edu/faculty/pages/jamar

"Nothing that is worth anything can be achieved in a lifetime; therefore we must be saved by hope."

Reinhold Neibuhr

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I was glad to see Alan's response, and I'll try to respond
myself below.  But Alan, what do you think of the three examples I give?

Alan Brownstein writes:

> 1. As I tried to argue in an earlier post, "harm to others" can be an
ambiguous term. If it includes financial costs and emotional 
> distress, most rights are protected at least to some extent, even if
doing so imposes such 
> consequences on third parties or the general public. Maybe free
exercise rights are different than other rights in this regard -- but
that 
> difference needs to be explained and justified. And with due respect,
Eugene, I don't think you have done that. I understand that 
> my G-d may not a deity to you. But it is also true for most self
realizing rights or autonomy or dignitary rights that what is important
and 
> meaningful to me may be meaningless and irrelevant to you. This is
even true for the non-instrumental value of freedom of speech.
> Maybe X needs to express racially derogatory comments to individuals
of a different race to be self 
> -fulfilled. But I don't. And I see virtually no instrumental value in
permitting targeted racist invective. But I accept that some such 
> expression is constitutionally protected, notwithstanding the
emotional harm that it causes. Why is that different than protecting 
> free exercise rights that "harm" others of a faith committed to tenets
that I do not accept.

I think this is a great explanation for why pure self-expression
isn't an adequate defense for free speech claims, and it's one reason
that the Court has accepted some exceptions from free speech protection
even when the speaker is deriving self-expression benefits from the
speech (e.g., lies, threats, and -- most relevant for Alan's example --
fighting words).  But the chief reason the Court has given for
protecting free speech is the social benefits of speech, and the social
harms of giving the government broad power to restrict speech.  So I do
think there's substantial social benefit in protecting racist speech
broadly (though not necessarily fighting words, whether racist or not).
 
> 2. Also, Eugene, for the purpose of your argument, does harm to the
general community have the same analytic consequence as harm to 
> specific third  parties. The burden of granting some free exercise
exemptions is  essentially financial -- it imposes costs on the public
fisc. 
> For example,  exempting a church from land use regulations limiting
development in a  commercial zone has financial consequences for a
> community --  since the  church does not pay taxes and does not engage
in activities  that provide sales tax revenue to the city. But the costs
> of protecting freedom of speech can also be quite high. For example,
large political demonstrations do not police themselves. Is their a
> reason why we should accept the  financial costs of exercising free
speech rights, but not  those associated 
> with exercising free exercise rights? (I recognize that  political
rallies  have instrumental value, but certainly, one can argue that 
> society benefits in a variety of intangible and tangible ways from the
houses of worship in our communities)

I think that harm to the general community at least often does
qualify as harm -- and that includes financial harm.  For instance,
criticism of the draft (short of Brandenburg incitement) is protected,
even when that is likely to lead some people to disobey the draft law;
religious refusal to obey the draft is not protected, see Gillette.
Criticism of the tax system (again, short of incitement) is protected,
even when that is likely to lead to less tax revenue; religious refusal
to pay taxes is not, see Bob Jones.  Alan, do you think these results
are wrong?  

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I appreciate Greg's thoughtful analysis, but I think that
ultimately the magnitude of the burden on the nonspeaker's/nonclaimant's
rights doesn't resolve the problems.  I would feel *much* more
distressed by knowing that millions (?) of people are reading about how
I supposedly had sex with my mother in an outhouse (even if they know
it's a gag) than by a few nights of loud noise outside my house.

Likewise, I suspect that the more-or-less three-year-long
boycott in Claiborne Hardware affected local businesses more than the
occasional blockage would affect the business of an abortion clinic.
It's true that this may be so because the boycott went on for a long
time, while the blockage in my hypothetical wouldn't.  But under free
speech law, even speech urging a long boycott can't be punished -- and
even one instance of entrance blockage, which would cause vastly less
damage than the boycott, would be punishable, whether or not it's
religiously based.  So people are constitutionally entitled to inflict
considerably greater harms through the communicative impact of their
speech than through the religiously motivated conduct.  Or am I mistaken
here?

As to the housing discrimination scenario, I just think Greg's
comparison cases are actually not terribly similar.  The gay couple's
claim isn't necessarily that they're deeply emotionally distressed --
rather, it is that they have a legal right to equal treatment,
regardless of whether the unequal treatment is terribly distressing.
Maybe this right flows from a general sense that the unequal treatment
is usually distressing, but it doesn't, I think, require a case-by-case
analysis here.  I have a right to be free even from minor trespasses on
my land, or minor batteries (consider someone popping me in the face
with a cream pie, probably not tremendously insulting as batteries go).
People aren't free to engage in this conduct even if they feel a
religious obligation to do so (say, for instance, that they want to
engage in a pilgrimage to what they think is a newly discovered holy
site on my land, or that they feel they need to pie me as a statement
about my blasphemy).  Likewise, I take it that many supporters of
antidiscrimination law believe that a right to be free from certain
kinds of discrimination in certain transactions is a comparable private
entitlement.  I don't see how a court can, as a constitutional matter,
conclude that this form of infringement of one's rights just isn't that
emotionally distressing, while other forms are.

Eugene

Greg Sisk writes:

> While free exercise and free speech may be different in many 
> respects, and indeed most constitutional rights differ from 
> all other rights, as they are not merely fungible from one to 
> another, I don't think Eugene Volokh's thoughtful 
> hypotheticals satisfactorily dispose of the argument that 
> free exercise and free speech ought not be treated 
> differently in the amount of burden that we accept (or the 
> courts ought to accept) upon the public or others.  The 
> problem with Eugene's hypotheticals, as I see it, is that the 
> burdens outlined are not comparable, in part because one 
> involves non-physical speech and the other involves conduct 
> (as Jim Maule observes), but also simply because of the 
> anticipated degree of negative impact upon persons other than 
> the one exercising the right.
> 
> Just to look at the first pair of hypotheticals:  While Jerry 
> Falwell is postulated to have experienced emotional distress 
> as a result of both incidents, I submit that we intuitively 
> would recognize that the immediacy and intrusiveness of the 
> harm differs greatly when we compare reading a scurrilous 
> reference to one's self in a periodical with experiencing an 
> almost physical trespass accompanied by the use of loud 
> sounds that cannot easily be escaped and, perhaps most 
> importantly, that occurs at one's place of sanctuary, the 
> home.  Thus, while I agree that the free speech claim in that 
> pair of hypotheticals is stronger than the free exercise 
> claim, I don't see the two cases as truly comparable in terms 
> of the degree and perhaps the nature of the harm, even if 
> both forms of harm are generally categorized as emotional distress.
> 
> Thus, for a set of hypotheticals comparing the strength of 
> free speech and free exercise claims to be truly comparable, 
> the nature or at least the degree of harm must also be 
> comparable.  While not neatly involving parallel factual 
> settings or messages, consider these two scenarios:  First, 
> we again have the offensive parody of Jerry Falwell in Larry 
> Flynt's Hustler magazine, in which Flynt invokes freedom of 
> speech as a defense against a claim for emotional distress.  
> Second, we have a homosexual couple that is rejected as 
> tenants by a homeowner of traditional religious values for 
> the spare room in her house, in which the homeowner invokes 
> free exercise as a d

RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-14 Thread Anthony Picarello



Then, with the sole exception of federal 
constitutional amendments, religious groups can expect Establishment Clause 
challenges to their hard-won legislative accommodations:  as "blind 
giveaways" if they are too broad (Cutter), as "denominational preferences" if 
too tailored (Kiryas Joel).  They may also face separation of powers 
challenges on the (ironic) theory that in providing accommodations, the 
legislature is usurping the role of judiciary.
 
In 
other words, the unifying theme in this position is not deference to legislative 
acts, but hostility to legislative acts and judicial rules alike if they help 
religious litigants.
 

  -Original Message-From: 
  [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
  [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]On Behalf Of 
  [EMAIL PROTECTED]Sent: Monday, March 14, 2005 4:15 
  PMTo: religionlaw@lists.ucla.eduSubject: Re: 
  Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions
  
  As Justice Scalia notes in Smith, the likelihood in this society that 
  such an exemption would not go forward is highly unlikely.  It is 
  harmless to others, and the religious entities had ready access to the 
  governing powers that be.  That is how the system works -- entities who 
  want to amend the law or to force it to accommodate them before it is enacted, 
  lobby their representatives and every other power center they can.  There 
  has never been an era in the United States when religious entities felt shy 
  about such political pressure.  
   
  Marci
   
   
  In a message dated 3/14/2005 2:05:54 P.M. Eastern Standard Time, 
  [EMAIL PROTECTED] writes:
  
Would it have been 
acceptable during National Prohibition to force Episcopalians, Eastern 
Orthodox and Catholics to âassimilateâ by giving up wine and using grape 
juice instead in celebrating the Eucharist?  Is the use of wine no 
different than the religiously motivated practices that you described below? 
  
  
   
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: ministerial exception

2005-03-14 Thread Lupu
Marci:

I know of no cases challenging the exclusion of women from the  
Catholic priesthood.  But if denominations that purport to treat 
women and men equally for clergy positions get the benefit of the 
ministerial exception, as they do, it would seem to follow a fortiori 
that the Catholic Church, Orthodox Jewish congregations, and 
others that exclude women from the clergy as a matter of religious 
doctrine would get the exception as well.   

As for whether the sexual harassment cases represent, as I say, an 
"exception to the ministerial exception," or, as you say, "are part of
> the evolving law being applied to religious entity's employment
> practices and point the way to the future," only time will tell.  But for now 
> the ministerial exception doctrine has held firm in every non-harassment case 
> of discrimination brought by a member of the clergy against his or her 
> denomination.

By the way -- you alluded earlier to cases about race discrimination 
and the ministerial exception.  Are you aware of any case in which 
the clergy-plaintiff alleged race discrimination, the religious entity  
defendant pleaded the ministerial exception, and the court rejected 
the defense and let the case go forward?  I know of no such cases 
(or of cases that go the other way, where the defense is accepted), 
and I would like to learn of any cases about race discrimination and 
the ministerial exception.  

Chip

On 14 Mar 2005 at 16:19, [EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:

> Chip-- I never said that the Catholic Church had experienced such
> litigation; we were talking about hypotheticals. 
> 
> Isthe absence of Catholic Church gender litigationbecause these cases
> have never been brought, or because the claimis not cognizable
> underthe ministerial exception?  With respect to Bollard and Elvig,
> they are not simply exceptions to the general rule, but are part of
> the evolving law being applied to religious entity's employment
> practices and point the way to the future.
> 
> Marci
> 
> In a message dated 3/14/2005 2:35:47 P.M. Eastern Standard Time,
> [EMAIL PROTECTED] writes:
> The ministerial exception cases have never involved the Catholic
> priesthood or any denomination which claims a sincere religious
> belief in favor of gender exclusion from the clergy.
> 
> 
> 



Ira C. ("Chip") Lupu
F. Elwood & Eleanor Davis Professor of Law 
The George Washington University Law School 
2000 H St., NW
Washington D.C 20052

(202) 994-7053

[EMAIL PROTECTED]
[EMAIL PROTECTED]

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread Sisk, Gregory C.
While free exercise and free speech may be different in many respects, and
indeed most constitutional rights differ from all other rights, as they are
not merely fungible from one to another, I don't think Eugene Volokh's
thoughtful hypotheticals satisfactorily dispose of the argument that free
exercise and free speech ought not be treated differently in the amount of
burden that we accept (or the courts ought to accept) upon the public or
others.  The problem with Eugene's hypotheticals, as I see it, is that the
burdens outlined are not comparable, in part because one involves
non-physical speech and the other involves conduct (as Jim Maule observes),
but also simply because of the anticipated degree of negative impact upon
persons other than the one exercising the right.

Just to look at the first pair of hypotheticals:  While Jerry Falwell is
postulated to have experienced emotional distress as a result of both
incidents, I submit that we intuitively would recognize that the immediacy
and intrusiveness of the harm differs greatly when we compare reading a
scurrilous reference to one's self in a periodical with experiencing an
almost physical trespass accompanied by the use of loud sounds that cannot
easily be escaped and, perhaps most importantly, that occurs at one's place
of sanctuary, the home.  Thus, while I agree that the free speech claim in
that pair of hypotheticals is stronger than the free exercise claim, I don't
see the two cases as truly comparable in terms of the degree and perhaps the
nature of the harm, even if both forms of harm are generally categorized as
emotional distress.

Thus, for a set of hypotheticals comparing the strength of free speech and
free exercise claims to be truly comparable, the nature or at least the
degree of harm must also be comparable.  While not neatly involving parallel
factual settings or messages, consider these two scenarios:  First, we again
have the offensive parody of Jerry Falwell in Larry Flynt's Hustler
magazine, in which Flynt invokes freedom of speech as a defense against a
claim for emotional distress.  Second, we have a homosexual couple that is
rejected as tenants by a homeowner of traditional religious values for the
spare room in her house, in which the homeowner invokes free exercise as a
defense as a claim for discrimination by the homosexual couple under a
municipal gay rights ordinance.  Assume for the sake of argument that other
rental opportunities for homosexual couples are available in that community
(a reasonable assumption, as a municipality in which political support
exists for enactment of a gay rights law involving housing is unlikely to
one in which such discrimination is omnipresent across the community, but
even if you find the assumption more debatable, I ask you to accept it for
this hypothetical).

Under that hypothetical, then, the claim of the homosexual couple, although
framed as housing discrimination and seeking the remedy of an injunction, in
practical terms is about the emotional distress of having experienced
discrimination by being rejected as a tenant on the basis of sexual
orientation.  Isn't that experience of emotional distress comparable to that
of Jerry Falwell who was targeted for sexualized slurs based upon his
religious and political views?  In both instances, the complaining party
understandably and sincerely has suffered an emotional injury (as I'll
assume for this hypothetical, as I doubt that Jerry Falwell truly was that
distressed).  But both emotional injuries are unaccompanied by any physical
component and both involve primarily upset feelings.  By that analysis,
shouldn't the free exercise claim of the homeowner be regarded as equally
viable as the free speech claim of Larry Flynt?

(And if you don't like my hypotheticals, feel free to formulate your own, in
which the comparability of harm is the pivot point rather than comparable
factual settings.)

Greg Sisk


Gregory Sisk
Professor of Law
University of St. Thomas School of Law (Minneapolis)
MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue
Minneapolis, MN  55403-2005
651-962-4923
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
http://personal2.stthomas.edu/GCSISK/sisk.html




-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Monday, March 14, 2005 11:59 AM
To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

Brad's and Marc's posts raise an excellent question:  If free
speech means that people have the constitutional right to impose burdens
on others, why shouldn't free exercise operate the same way?  The same
can be said of other rights, incidentally:  For instance, the Compulsory
Process Clause right gives criminal defendants very substantial powers
to constrain others' liberty.  (I set aside here the permissible scope
of legislative accommodations, and focusing on what's constitutionally
compelled.)

I think that free speech and free exercise *are* different this
way, and let me briefly try to explai

Wash. Post article on churches and land use regulation

2005-03-14 Thread Scarberry, Mark
http://www.washingtonpost.com/wp-dyn/articles/A32382-2005Mar13.html 

Mark S. Scarberry
Pepperdine Univ. School of Law

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


Re: ministerial exception

2005-03-14 Thread Hamilton02




Chip-- I never said that the Catholic Church had experienced such 
litigation; we were talking about hypotheticals.  
 
Is the absence of Catholic Church gender litigation because these 
cases have never been brought, or because the claim is not cognizable 
under the ministerial exception?     With respect to Bollard 
and Elvig, they are not simply exceptions to the general rule, but are part of 
the evolving law being applied to religious entity's employment practices and 
point the way to the future.
 
Marci
 
In a message dated 3/14/2005 2:35:47 P.M. Eastern Standard Time, 
[EMAIL PROTECTED] writes:
The 
  ministerial exception cases have never involved the Catholic priesthood or 
  any denomination which claims a sincere religious belief in favor of 
  gender exclusion from the clergy. 

 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-14 Thread Hamilton02




As Justice Scalia notes in Smith, the likelihood in this society that such 
an exemption would not go forward is highly unlikely.  It is harmless to 
others, and the religious entities had ready access to the governing powers that 
be.  That is how the system works -- entities who want to amend the law or 
to force it to accommodate them before it is enacted, lobby their 
representatives and every other power center they can.  There has never 
been an era in the United States when religious entities felt shy about such 
political pressure.  
 
Marci
 
 
In a message dated 3/14/2005 2:05:54 P.M. Eastern Standard Time, 
[EMAIL PROTECTED] writes:

  Would it have been 
  acceptable during National Prohibition to force Episcopalians, Eastern 
  Orthodox and Catholics to âassimilateâ by giving up wine and using grape juice 
  instead in celebrating the Eucharist?  Is the use of wine no different 
  than the religiously motivated practices that you described below? 
    

 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread A.E. Brownstein
I tend to agree with Eugene that free speech and free exercise rights do 
not parallel each other -- so that it does not necessarily follow that 
because freedom of speech is protected even when the speech causes harm to 
third parties, free exercise rights must receive similar protection. But I 
have several problems with other parts of Eugene's analysis.

1. As I tried to argue in an earlier post, "harm to others" can be an 
ambiguous term. If it includes financial costs and emotional distress, most 
rights are protected at least to some extent, even if doing so imposes such 
consequences on third parties or the general public. Maybe free exercise 
rights are different than other rights in this regard -- but that 
difference needs to be explained and justified. And with due respect, 
Eugene, I don't think you have done that. I understand that my G-d may not 
a deity to you. But it is also true for most self realizing rights or 
autonomy or dignitary rights that what is important and meaningful to me 
may be meaningless and irrelevant to you. This is even true for the 
non-instrumental value of freedom of speech. Maybe X needs to express 
racially derogatory comments to individuals of a different race to be self 
-fulfilled. But I don't. And I see virtually no instrumental value in 
permitting targeted racist invective. But I accept that some such 
expression is constitutionally protected, notwithstanding the emotional 
harm that it causes. Why is that different than protecting free exercise 
rights that "harm" others of a faith committed to tenets that I do not accept.

2. Also, Eugene, for the purpose of your argument, does harm to the general 
community have the same analytic consequence as harm to specific third 
parties. The burden of granting some free exercise exemptions is 
essentially financial -- it imposes costs on the public fisc. For example, 
exempting a church from land use regulations limiting development in a 
commercial zone has financial consequences for a community -- since the 
church does not pay taxes and does not engage in activities that provide 
sales tax revenue to the city. But the costs of protecting freedom of 
speech can also be quite high. For example, large political demonstrations 
do not police themselves. Is their a reason why we should accept the 
financial costs of exercising free speech rights, but not those associated 
with exercising free exercise rights? (I recognize that political rallies 
have instrumental value, but certainly, one can argue that society benefits 
in a variety of intangible and tangible ways from the houses of worship in 
our communities)

Again, I am not suggesting that all rights are analogous to each other with 
regard to whether they include the freedom to inflict harm on others -- or 
with regard to other attributes. But if free exercise rights are to be 
defined more narrowly than many if not most other rights, I think the 
proponents of doing so need to persuasively explain why this is so.

Alan Brownstein
UC Davis
Eugene writes,
  But we ought not read the Free Exercise Clause as generally
licensing religious objectors to inflict harm on others (or even to do
so subject to a possible strict scrutiny trump).  As I argue, my
relationship with my God may be important to me, but it can't by itself
be a constitutionally sufficient justification for my harming you, even
slightly (for instance, by intentionally inflicting emotional distress
on you in secular ways, blocking access to your property, or slightly
vandalizing your commercial building).   From your perspective and the
legal system's perspective (even if not from my own), my God is my God,
not yours, and the Constitution doesn't give those acting in His name
sovereignty over your legally recognized rights and interests.
The trouble with such a broad religious freedom claim to do
whatever you please so long as you don't harm others is not that private
contract, property, and tort law rights, or private interests in being
free from criminal vandalism (consider the rights and interests
implicated in the three examples I note above) somehow outweigh
religious freedom rights:  How could we justify such a conclusion?  Even
if one somehow determines that such private rights are as important as
religious freedom rights, I see no way to explain why they are more
important, which would be required to show such an outweighing.
Rather, the reason why a general exemption regime can't override
these rights must be that any religious freedom right that's solely
grounded in the religious motivation for one's actions simply can't
extend to actions that impair others' rights or impose improper
externalities on others.  Whether your countervailing right is a right
to life, to bodily integrity, or to something perhaps somewhat less
important, such as property or freedom from emotional distress, if it is
indeed a right then the religiosity of my motivation can't justify
violating it.
_

RLUIPA Reply Briefs

2005-03-14 Thread Marty Lederman
RLUIPA Reply Briefs
03:01 PM | Marty Lederman | Comments (0) | TrackBack (0)
Both the private Petitioners and the Acting SG have filed their reply briefs 
in No. 03-9877, Cutter v. Wilkinson. The respondents'-side briefs can be 
found here; the top-side briefs will be available here (when the link is 
fixed). Argument is next Monday.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the messages to others.


Re: ministerial exception

2005-03-14 Thread Lupu
Marci is correct that " the ministerial
 exception is not some blanket protection for anything that happens  
between clergy and religious institution," because courts have 
tended not to permit religious entities to rely on it to get rid of claims 
of negligent supervision in cases of harm to third party victims of 
clergy (e.g,. sexual abuse victims.)

But she is wrong when she asserts that, under the ministerial 
exception, "if an abusive or discriminatory practice is not motivated 
by a sincere religious belief, the claim can go forward in the courts."  
The ministerial exception cases have never involved the Catholic 
priesthood or any denomination which claims a sincere religious 
belief in favor of gender exclusion from the clergy.  All of the 
ministerial exception cases (and there are many) involve 
denominations that DO ordain female clergy, but assert that courts 
cannot adjudicate claims of pretext when the dismissed 
clergywoman asserts gender discrimination, and the religious 
employer might be obliged to show that it had a non-gendered 
reason for the dismissal.  Such inquiries into the possibility of 
pretext in the employment relation with clergy, the cases uniformly 
hold, is constitutionally impermissible.  The harassment cases like 
Bollard and Elvig are thus exceptions to the ministerial exception 
(justified, it is said, because they can be adjudicated without a court 
second-guessing a religious entity's evaluation of a member of the 
clergy), with the remedial limitiations that Mark and Doug have 
noted.

Chip Lupu  


On 14 Mar 2005 at 14:01, [EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:

> Mark-- Elvig does not gainsay my point that . So > 
> Marci
> 
> 
> In a message dated 3/14/2005 12:00:00 P.M. Eastern Standard Time,
> [EMAIL PROTECTED] writes:
> With regard to Marci's point on the ministerial exception having
> no bite in the Ninth Circuit where the claim is for sexual
> harassment, I think she overstates the case. The most recent Ninth
> Circuit case on the issue (Elvig) severely limits the remedies
> that an allegedly sexually harassed minister can seek
> 
> 
> 



Ira C. ("Chip") Lupu
F. Elwood & Eleanor Davis Professor of Law 
The George Washington University Law School 
2000 H St., NW
Washington D.C 20052

(202) 994-7053

[EMAIL PROTECTED]
[EMAIL PROTECTED]

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-14 Thread Newsom Michael
Title: Message









I don’t understand the distinction
between across the board and ad hoc exemptions, particularly as applied to
something like National Prohibition and the exemption for the religious use of
wine.

 

How are you going to know whether a practice
of a religion about which you know, hypothetically speaking, little or nothing,
was significant enough to warrant an exemption?

 

I don’t understand how the
indeterminacy of text renders any reliance on it unprincipled.  If that were
true then none of the Religion Clause cases (or Equal Protection or Due Process
cases) could be said to have been principled.  Is that your position?

 

I might agree with you that the ”founders”
would have thought that at least *some*
religious exemptions were not guaranteed.  But of course the question that
matters is which ones were and which ones were not, and whether or not the
topography of the domain of freedom from and freedom of religion might have
changed over time.

 

-Original Message-
From: West, Ellis
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Sunday, March 13, 2005 2:43 PM
To: Law & Religion issues for
Law Academics
Subject: FW: Institutional
Capacity to Manage Exemptions

 



 





In response to Prof.
Newsome's questions below, I would, first, simply repeat that my original
question was whether an across-the-board exemption from valid, secular
laws given, by either a legislature or the Supreme Court, to religious
persons/groups, and them alone, can be justified on the basis of
some  theory or principle (other than that the majority has
a right to pass whatever laws it wants to pass).  Second, as explained in
an earlier message, by an across-the-board exemption, I mean an exemption
from all laws or a large category of laws that is given unconditionally or
given unless the government, on the basis of some test like the strict scrutiny
test, can convince a judge that in any given situation an exemption  should
not be given.  Third, I am not opposed in principle to legislatures'
granting ad hoc exemptions, i.e., exemptions from particular laws granted to
certain categories of persons/groups, religious or otherwise, who
would be significantly harmed by the application of those laws to them. 
Therefore, and fourth, I would not be opposed in principle to churches' being
given an exemption from a prohibition law so that they could use wine in their
rituals.  Moreover, although I am not familiar with how essential the use
of wine is in various churches, if I were a legislator being asked to include
such an exemption in a prohibition law, I would certainly be open to being
shown that the harm caused the churches by the law was significant enough
to warrant their being given an exemption.  Finally, I am not
sure how to respond to your second question because I do not understand its
import.  My initial question, stated above, was predicated on the
assumption that there was such disagreement about the meaning of the free exercise
clause that one could not simply cite the free exercise clause as a principled
reason for across-the-board religion-based exemptions.  Although I
personally believe, having researched and written on this matter for some years
now, that the free exercise clause as originally understood does not guarantee
a right to religion-based exemptions, if I could be shown otherwise, then,
given my own theory of constitutional adjudication, I would not object to the
courts' granting religion-based exemptions on the basis of the free exercise
clause.





 





Ellis M. West 
Political
Science Department 
University
of Richmond, VA 23173 
804-289-8536

[EMAIL PROTECTED]






-Original
Message-
From:
[EMAIL PROTECTED] [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Newsom Michael
Sent: Friday, March 11, 2005 6:40
PM
To: Law & Religion issues for
Law Academics
Subject: RE: Institutional
Capacity to Manage Exemptions

I have to ask Professor
West whether it would have been OK with him if during National Prohibition no
exemption had been allowed for the religious use of wine.  His answer to *that* question will be most
revealing.  A second question deserving a response is what conclusions
should one draw if it turns out that the meaning(s) of the Religion Clauses are
contestable or contingent.  (His answer to the first question should have
some bearing on his answer to the second question.)  A third question is
when did I say that I favored “across the board” exemptions. 
I still don’t know, however, what that term means, as Professor West uses
it.  As I said before the exemption in the Volstead Act is probably not
“across the board.”) 

 

 








___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messa

RE: Harm to Others as a Factor in Accommodation Doctrine

2005-03-14 Thread Douglas Laycock
What Elvig appears to hold is that if the remedy does not interfere with the 
church's selection of its own clergy, the ministerial exception is not 
implicated.  It certainly does not hold that a pastor can be reinstated if she 
was discharged because of her sex, or her complaints about sexual harassment, 
and not because of some religious belief on the part of the church.
 
Douglas Laycock
University of Texas Law School
727 E. Dean Keeton St.
Austin, TX  78705
512-232-1341
512-471-6988 (fax)



From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] on behalf of [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Mon 3/14/2005 1:01 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Harm to Others as a Factor in Accommodation Doctrine


Mark-- Elvig does not gainsay my point that if an abusive or discriminatory 
practice is not motivated by a sincere religious belief, the claim can go 
forward in the courts.  So the ministerial exception is not some blanket 
protection for anything that happens between clergy and religious institution.
 
Marci
 
 
In a message dated 3/14/2005 12:00:00 P.M. Eastern Standard Time, [EMAIL 
PROTECTED] writes:

With regard to Marci's point on the ministerial exception having no 
bite in
the Ninth Circuit where the claim is for sexual harassment, I think she
overstates the case. The most recent Ninth Circuit case on the issue 
(Elvig)
severely limits the remedies that an allegedly sexually harassed 
minister
can seek

 
<>___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Institutional Capacity to Manage Exemptions

2005-03-14 Thread Newsom Michael









Would it have been
acceptable during National Prohibition to force Episcopalians, Eastern Orthodox
and Catholics to “assimilate” by giving up wine and using grape
juice instead in celebrating the Eucharist?  Is the use of wine no different
than the religiously motivated practices that you described below?   

 

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Friday, March 11, 2005 7:02
AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Institutional
Capacity to Manage Exemptions

 



It is
lamentable when an  accommodation that makes good sense is turned
down by a legislature.   But I see no reason to think that forcing
assimilation of many behaviors is lamentable.  Only the most rose-colored
vision of religion that can think that it should not assimilate in
many circumstances.  Religiously motivated practices have included
slavery, the oppression of women, and polygamy.   The oppression of
children for religious purposes continues to this day, putting them at risk of
sex abuse, physical abuse, and the suffering and death associated with medical
neglect.





 





Marci





 





It's
just unavoidable that the Smith rule, without 
> strong and frequent legislative protection for religious 
> exemptions, will force religious observers to convert 
> outright, to minimize their own religiosity, or to change it 
> to fit the government regulation -- religious people will 
> have "to convert, to pass and to cover."  I find that
lamentable. 
>     
>     Chris Lund





 








___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Harm to Others as a Factor in Accommodation Doctrine

2005-03-14 Thread Hamilton02




Mark-- Elvig does not gainsay my point that if an abusive or discriminatory 
practice is not motivated by a sincere religious belief, the claim can go 
forward in the courts.  So the ministerial exception is not some blanket 
protection for anything that happens between clergy and religious 
institution.
 
Marci
 
 
In a message dated 3/14/2005 12:00:00 P.M. Eastern Standard Time, 
[EMAIL PROTECTED] writes:
With 
  regard to Marci's point on the ministerial exception having no bite inthe 
  Ninth Circuit where the claim is for sexual harassment, I think 
  sheoverstates the case. The most recent Ninth Circuit case on the issue 
  (Elvig)severely limits the remedies that an allegedly sexually harassed 
  ministercan seek

 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Religious speech, it seems to me, should be no more and no less
protected by the Free Speech Clause than other speech.  Thus, the
interesting questions (including the ones we've been discussing on
related threads) arise when there's a claim of religious accommodation
for conduct, or for speech that causes harm through its noncommunicative
components.

So my pairs of examples do compare the Free Speech Clause
treatment of speech (speech that causes harm through what it
communicates) against the Free Exercise Clause treatment of conduct (or
speech that causes harm through its noncommunicative impact).  But
that's the comparison, I take it, that Brad and Marc were urging; if
they had simply been demanding protection for religious speech, they
would be getting it, see Widmar, Lamb's Chapel, etc.

Jim Maule writes:

> Is the distinction between your hypothetical pairings one of 
> free speech versus free exercise or one of words versus 
> conduct? (Flynt writes, Glynt yells; the NAACP publishes, 
> Operation Rescue blocks; Schenck writes/publishes, Penck blocks).
> 
> If Glynt, Operation Rescue or Penck were to write/publish 
> would there be a difference in the analysis? Assume that the 
> writing was based on, and reflected, sincerely held religious 
> beliefs. Does free speech subsume free exercise if the 
> exercise is that of writing/speaking/publishing? Does free 
> exercise not include free speech with respect to religious 
> beliefs? Are the two concomitant with respect to religious 
> expression? I'm not convinced that the overlap is symmetrical 
> or concomitant, and I wonder if concluding that the overlap 
> IS concomitant effectively makes one of the freedoms 
> subservient to the other.
> 
> Nor do I think that a blanket conclusion requiring a higher 
> level of proof of harm for free exercise than for free speech 
> is necessary or wise. I also think that there is a freedom of 
> religious expression that draws on both freedoms and that may 
> need to be tested differently than either free speech or free 
> exercise.
> 
> Jim Maule
> Villanova University School of Law
> 
> >>> [EMAIL PROTECTED] 3/14/2005 12:59:04 PM >>>
>   Brad's and Marc's posts raise an excellent question:  
> If free speech means that people have the constitutional 
> right to impose burdens on others, why shouldn't free 
> exercise operate the same way?  The same can be said of other 
> rights, incidentally:  For instance, the Compulsory Process 
> Clause right gives criminal defendants very substantial 
> powers to constrain others' liberty.  (I set aside here the 
> permissible scope of legislative accommodations, and focusing 
> on what's constitutionally
> compelled.)
> 
>   I think that free speech and free exercise *are* 
> different this way, and let me briefly try to explain why.  
> I'll begin with some hypotheticals that I think help 
> illustrate this, and then offer a broader theoretical 
> explanation.  (The following is borrowed from my A Common-Law 
> Model for Religious Exemptions, 46 UCLA L. Rev. 1465 (1999),
> http://www1.law.ucla.edu/~volokh/relfree.htm.)  Here are the 
> hypos, which consist of pairs of claims, one free speech and 
> one religious
> freedom:
> 
>   1.  (A)  Larry Flynt inflicts emotional distress on 
> Jerry Falwell by publishing his vitriolic "ad parody" in 
> Hustler Magazine; when sued under the IIED tort, Flynt raises 
> his free speech rights as a defense.  (B)  Mary Glynt 
> inflicts emotional distress on Jerry Falwell by standing 
> outside his window at night with a bullhorn; when sued under 
> the IIED tort, Glynt raises her free exercise rights as a 
> defense -- she claims (assume that the claim is sincere) that 
> she feels a religious obligation to remonstrate this way with 
> heretics (and she considers Falwell to be one).
> 
>   2.  (A)  The NAACP interferes with Claiborne Hardware's 
> business relations by publicizing the names of its visitors, 
> and urging people to boycott Claiborne; when sued under the 
> interference with business advantage tort, it raises its free 
> speech rights as a defense.  (B) Operation Rescue interferes 
> with an abortion clinic's business relations by blocking the 
> entrance to the clinic; when sued under the same tort, it 
> raises its (or its members') free exercise rights as a 
> defense -- it claims (assume that the claim is sincere) that 
> its members feel a religious obligation to protect fetuses this way.
> 
>   3.  (A)  A modern-day Schenck tries to interfere with 
> the war effort by publishing books, leaflets, and Web sites 
> urging people to vandalize munitions manufacturers; when 
> prosecuted for counseling illegal conduct, he raises his free 
> speech rights as a defense.  (B) His religiously pacifist 
> cousin Penck tries to interfere with the war effort by 
> blocking the entrance to a military contractor's building; 
> when prosecuted for trepassing, he claims (assume that the claim is

Re: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread James Maule
Eugene,

Is the distinction between your hypothetical pairings one of free
speech versus free exercise or one of words versus conduct? (Flynt
writes, Glynt yells; the NAACP publishes, Operation Rescue blocks;
Schenck writes/publishes, Penck blocks).

If Glynt, Operation Rescue or Penck were to write/publish would there
be a difference in the analysis? Assume that the writing was based on,
and reflected, sincerely held religious beliefs. Does free speech
subsume free exercise if the exercise is that of
writing/speaking/publishing? Does free exercise not include free speech
with respect to religious beliefs? Are the two concomitant with respect
to religious expression? I'm not convinced that the overlap is
symmetrical or concomitant, and I wonder if concluding that the overlap
IS concomitant effectively makes one of the freedoms subservient to the
other.

Nor do I think that a blanket conclusion requiring a higher level of
proof of harm for free exercise than for free speech is necessary or
wise. I also think that there is a freedom of religious expression that
draws on both freedoms and that may need to be tested differently than
either free speech or free exercise.

Jim Maule
Villanova University School of Law

>>> [EMAIL PROTECTED] 3/14/2005 12:59:04 PM >>>
Brad's and Marc's posts raise an excellent question:  If free
speech means that people have the constitutional right to impose
burdens
on others, why shouldn't free exercise operate the same way?  The same
can be said of other rights, incidentally:  For instance, the
Compulsory
Process Clause right gives criminal defendants very substantial powers
to constrain others' liberty.  (I set aside here the permissible scope
of legislative accommodations, and focusing on what's constitutionally
compelled.)

I think that free speech and free exercise *are* different this
way, and let me briefly try to explain why.  I'll begin with some
hypotheticals that I think help illustrate this, and then offer a
broader theoretical explanation.  (The following is borrowed from my A
Common-Law Model for Religious Exemptions, 46 UCLA L. Rev. 1465
(1999),
http://www1.law.ucla.edu/~volokh/relfree.htm.)  Here are the hypos,
which consist of pairs of claims, one free speech and one religious
freedom:

1.  (A)  Larry Flynt inflicts emotional distress on Jerry
Falwell by publishing his vitriolic "ad parody" in Hustler Magazine;
when sued under the IIED tort, Flynt raises his free speech rights as
a
defense.  (B)  Mary Glynt inflicts emotional distress on Jerry Falwell
by standing outside his window at night with a bullhorn; when sued
under
the IIED tort, Glynt raises her free exercise rights as a defense --
she
claims (assume that the claim is sincere) that she feels a religious
obligation to remonstrate this way with heretics (and she considers
Falwell to be one).

2.  (A)  The NAACP interferes with Claiborne Hardware's
business
relations by publicizing the names of its visitors, and urging people
to
boycott Claiborne; when sued under the interference with business
advantage tort, it raises its free speech rights as a defense.  (B)
Operation Rescue interferes with an abortion clinic's business
relations
by blocking the entrance to the clinic; when sued under the same tort,
it raises its (or its members') free exercise rights as a defense --
it
claims (assume that the claim is sincere) that its members feel a
religious obligation to protect fetuses this way.

3.  (A)  A modern-day Schenck tries to interfere with the war
effort by publishing books, leaflets, and Web sites urging people to
vandalize munitions manufacturers; when prosecuted for counseling
illegal conduct, he raises his free speech rights as a defense.  (B)
His religiously pacifist cousin Penck tries to interfere with the war
effort by blocking the entrance to a military contractor's building;
when prosecuted for trepassing, he claims (assume that the claim is
sincere) that he feels a religious obligation to fight the war this
way.

Under standard free speech doctrine, the free speech claimants
in each of these cases would have a good Free Speech Clause defense,
*even though* their speech causes harm to others.  But do people on
this
list think that the religious freedom claimants in each of these cases
should likewise prevail with their Free Exercise Clause defenses?

The government interests -- and the private interests that the
government is protecting -- in all the cases, it seems to me, are
quite
similar.  The speech and the religious conduct jeopardizes those
interests (perhaps not identically, but to similar degrees).  But
while
the government is barred from restricting the speech when the content
of
the speech causes harm to others, the government may (and I think
should) restrict the religious conduct when that causes harm to
others.

If I'm right, then this suggests that we can't just casually
equate free speech and free exercise claims (perhaps

Re: Harm to Others as a Factor in Accommodation Doctrine

2005-03-14 Thread Hamilton02



This is rather far afield, actually.  These are questions of what 
evidence can be adduced in court.  Penitent-minister communications are 
generally not fair game and have been excluded, unless the penitent waives the 
privilege.  Patient-doctor privileges essentially get the same 
treatment.
 
if the first 
  is fair game (penitent-minister), why not the second (patient-doctor), if in 
  both cases the goal is to prosecute child abusers? 
 

 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Harm to Others as a Factor in Accommodation Doctrine

2005-03-14 Thread Hamilton02




With respect to religious speech, there is no difference.  When it 
comes to conduct, though, it is fairly obvious that conduct must be capable of 
greater regulation than speech, because of its greater potential for harm.  
This is a principle that has a distinguished pedigree, Locke, Jefferson, Mill, 
etc. etc.
 
Marci
 
In a message dated 3/14/2005 10:22:00 A.M. Eastern Standard Time, 
[EMAIL PROTECTED] writes:
Why 
  would the Free Exercise clause have less weight and power to protect than the 
  Free Speech clause?  

 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Brad's and Marc's posts raise an excellent question:  If free
speech means that people have the constitutional right to impose burdens
on others, why shouldn't free exercise operate the same way?  The same
can be said of other rights, incidentally:  For instance, the Compulsory
Process Clause right gives criminal defendants very substantial powers
to constrain others' liberty.  (I set aside here the permissible scope
of legislative accommodations, and focusing on what's constitutionally
compelled.)

I think that free speech and free exercise *are* different this
way, and let me briefly try to explain why.  I'll begin with some
hypotheticals that I think help illustrate this, and then offer a
broader theoretical explanation.  (The following is borrowed from my A
Common-Law Model for Religious Exemptions, 46 UCLA L. Rev. 1465 (1999),
http://www1.law.ucla.edu/~volokh/relfree.htm.)  Here are the hypos,
which consist of pairs of claims, one free speech and one religious
freedom:

1.  (A)  Larry Flynt inflicts emotional distress on Jerry
Falwell by publishing his vitriolic "ad parody" in Hustler Magazine;
when sued under the IIED tort, Flynt raises his free speech rights as a
defense.  (B)  Mary Glynt inflicts emotional distress on Jerry Falwell
by standing outside his window at night with a bullhorn; when sued under
the IIED tort, Glynt raises her free exercise rights as a defense -- she
claims (assume that the claim is sincere) that she feels a religious
obligation to remonstrate this way with heretics (and she considers
Falwell to be one).

2.  (A)  The NAACP interferes with Claiborne Hardware's business
relations by publicizing the names of its visitors, and urging people to
boycott Claiborne; when sued under the interference with business
advantage tort, it raises its free speech rights as a defense.  (B)
Operation Rescue interferes with an abortion clinic's business relations
by blocking the entrance to the clinic; when sued under the same tort,
it raises its (or its members') free exercise rights as a defense -- it
claims (assume that the claim is sincere) that its members feel a
religious obligation to protect fetuses this way.

3.  (A)  A modern-day Schenck tries to interfere with the war
effort by publishing books, leaflets, and Web sites urging people to
vandalize munitions manufacturers; when prosecuted for counseling
illegal conduct, he raises his free speech rights as a defense.  (B)
His religiously pacifist cousin Penck tries to interfere with the war
effort by blocking the entrance to a military contractor's building;
when prosecuted for trepassing, he claims (assume that the claim is
sincere) that he feels a religious obligation to fight the war this way.

Under standard free speech doctrine, the free speech claimants
in each of these cases would have a good Free Speech Clause defense,
*even though* their speech causes harm to others.  But do people on this
list think that the religious freedom claimants in each of these cases
should likewise prevail with their Free Exercise Clause defenses?

The government interests -- and the private interests that the
government is protecting -- in all the cases, it seems to me, are quite
similar.  The speech and the religious conduct jeopardizes those
interests (perhaps not identically, but to similar degrees).  But while
the government is barred from restricting the speech when the content of
the speech causes harm to others, the government may (and I think
should) restrict the religious conduct when that causes harm to others.

If I'm right, then this suggests that we can't just casually
equate free speech and free exercise claims (perhaps, for instance,
because the Court was correct to conclude in Smith that the Free
Exercise Clause right is a nondiscrimination right, or perhaps because
both Smith and Sherbert were wrong and the proper test for exemptions
from generally applicable laws is less than strict scrutiny though not
rational basis).  And here's my thinking as to why this is so:

The Free Speech Clause and other rights *are* rights to inflict
certain kinds of harm on others in certain ways (for instance, through
the communicative impact of speech); we think that for various reasons,
the government ought not be allowed to interfere with this harm, perhaps
because speech is so valuable to democratic self-government, or because
we suspect the government will abuse its regulatory powers.  Likewise,
as I argue at
http://www1.law.ucla.edu/~volokh/relfree.htm#Several%20Specific%20Prohib
itions%20on%20Government, in a few contexts (for instance,
discrimination in hiring clergy, or religious frauds), the Free Exercise
Clause also allows religious people or institutions to inflict what the
law might otherwise treat as harm to others.

But we ought not read the Free Exercise Clause as generally
licensing religious objectors to inflict harm on others (or even to do
so subject to a

RE: Harm to Others as a Factor in Accommodation Doctrine

2005-03-14 Thread Scarberry, Mark
I see a larger role than Marci does for constitutionally mandated and
judicially enforced free exercise exemptions, but there is a problem with
Brad's argument. A law that prohibited a certain kind of speech *as speech*
would not be neutral and generally applicable; it would target speech the
same way the City of Hialea targeted the Santeria religious ritual in the
Lukumi case. Cf. O'Brien and other symbolic speech cases in which regulation
of conduct is usually upheld despite the effect on the symbolic speech.

With regard to Marci's point on the ministerial exception having no bite in
the Ninth Circuit where the claim is for sexual harassment, I think she
overstates the case. The most recent Ninth Circuit case on the issue (Elvig)
severely limits the remedies that an allegedly sexually harassed minister
can seek. In a suit for sexual harassment and for retaliation for making a
claim of sexual harassment, the plaintiff's recovery cannot include
reinstatement, lost wages, recovery for damage to reputation caused by an
allegedly retaliatory firing, or an order requiring the church to give the
plaintiff access to its process by which ministers find new positions. The
court also held that retaliatory employment decisions (e.g., firing,
demotion, change in duties) were not actionable, though retaliatory "verbal
abuse and intimidation" would be (if such speech were not religiously
mandated), with possible recovery for emotional distress and damage to
reputation. (I think the court had in mind a situation in which verbal abuse
and intimidation might happen in front of others in the church, with
resulting possible damage to the plaintiff's reputation.) I think the
plaintiff is left with the possibility of recovering only for emotional
distress associated with the alleged harassment, and for emotional distress
(and possible damage to reputation) associated with the alleged retaliation.

Mark S. Scarberry
Pepperdine Univ. School of Law


-Original Message-
From: Brad Pardee
To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics
Sent: 3/14/2005 7:18 AM
Subject: Re: Harm to Others as a Factor in Accommodation Doctrine

Doesn't that render the Free Exercise clause powerless as a guarantor of
religious freedom?  Suppose, for instance, we were talking about freedom
of speech instead of the free exercise of religion.  I can't imagine
that the legislature would be able to outlaw any type of speech they
wanted to as long as it was in a neutral and generally applicable law,
and that people would have to lobby the legislature for an accomodation
to be able to have the freedom of speech they thought the Constitution
already provided.  Rather, the legislature would need to be able to
justify to the court why the outlawing of a type of speech was not an
unconstitutional infringement on an explicitly Constitutionally
protected freedom.  Why would the Free Exercise clause have less weight
and power to protect than the Free Speech clause?  Tell me what I'm
missing in your understanding of what the Free Exercise clause actually
protects.
 
Brad
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


gender as bfoq

2005-03-14 Thread Steven Jamar
Assume there was no exemption for religious organizations per se under Title VII.  But assume there was a BFOQ exemption for any employer, including religious organizations.  Can there be any doubt that the free exercise clause would be applied to permit Catholics to ordain only men into the priesthood as a religious BFOQ?  

So there must be some content in the FE clause that would be in some cases narrower and in some cases broader than legislative accommodations.  And should this not be the case?  That there is a core set of rules built around the Constitution directly that cannot be constricted or perhaps even touched by legislative/majoritarian/money-powered interests?

The free exercise clause is to protect the minorities against the majorities, and to protect even the majority religion -- Christianity -- from governmental aggrandizement of power.  This latter aspect has been played to great effect of late by Christians asserting victimhood at the hands of the government -- exactly who this "evil government" foisting victimhood on downtrodden Christian may be a bit hard to determine, given the huge predominance of Christians in all positions of power in our society -- even a greater level of control than the Republicans currently possess.  Sometimes one might think we are back in pre-Constantinian Rome.

But the FE clause is there to protect the people against the government and the minorities against the majorities.  And legislative action will not always work out for the minorities. 

Steve


-- 
Prof. Steven D. Jamar vox:  202-806-8017
Howard University School of Law   fax:  202-806-8428
2900 Van Ness Street NW	mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Washington, DC  20008   http://www.law.howard.edu/faculty/pages/jamar

"Rarely do we find men who willingly engage in hard, solid thinking. There is an almost universal quest for easy answers and half-baked solutions. Nothing pains some people more than having to think."

- Martin Luther King Jr., "Strength to Love", 1963


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Harm to Others as a Factor in Accommodation Doctrine

2005-03-14 Thread Francis Beckwith
Title: Re: Harm to Others as a Factor in Accommodation Doctrine



Although Marci’s point is well-taken, I think another way to understand Marc’s (BTW, how cute is that, “Marci and Marc”?) point is to change Marci’s counter-example from church’s protecting pedophiles under the free exercise clause to abortion clinics protecting pedophiles under the right to privacy.  Recently, an attorney general (I forgot what state) tried to acquire the medical records of underage girls who underwent abortions in order to try to investigate whether their pregnancies were the result of relations with adult men.  Many folks opposed this acquisition on the grounds that it violated the girls’ right to privacy.  Imagine, however, if the teenage boys molested by priests were seeing them under the cloak of penitent-minister confidentiality.  So, we have a pretty good analogy here: penitent-minister, patient-doctor.  Here’s what Marc may be suggesting (if I am wrong, Marc, please correct me): if the first is fair game (penitent-minister), why not the second (patient-doctor), if in both cases the goal is to prosecute child abusers?  

Frank


On 3/14/05 8:52 AM, "[EMAIL PROTECTED]" <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> wrote:

 
Just for the record-- I never said never can there be any burden on third parties, rather that that burden should be assessed by the legislature.  There are arenas where the burden may never be tolerable, though, e.g., there are few burdens on children's health or safety that can be justified.
 
There is a broad sprectrum, of course.  Exemptions for peyote and religious headgear in the military create de minimis burdens on third parties.  Exemptions that permit churches to hide pedophiles from unsuspecting parents and children are enormous burdens.
 
Marci
 
For those who believe accommodation can never entail any burdens on third parties, I wonder if they could explain why the constitutional right (or interest) is in free exercise of religion qualitatively different than these other examples.
 

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the messages to others.





___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Harm to Others as a Factor in Accommodation Doctrine

2005-03-14 Thread Brad Pardee



Doesn't that render the Free Exercise clause powerless as a guarantor 
of religious freedom?  Suppose, for instance, we were talking about freedom 
of speech instead of the free exercise of religion.  I can't 
imagine that the legislature would be able to outlaw any type of speech 
they wanted to as long as it was in a neutral and generally applicable law, and 
that people would have to lobby the legislature for an accomodation to be able 
to have the freedom of speech they thought the Constitution already 
provided.  Rather, the legislature would need to be able to justify to the 
court why the outlawing of a type of speech was not an unconstitutional 
infringement on an explicitly Constitutionally protected freedom.  Why 
would the Free Exercise clause have less weight and power to protect than the 
Free Speech clause?  Tell me what I'm missing in your understanding of what 
the Free Exercise clause actually protects.
 
Brad

  The answer would be that those religious groups would lobby and obtain 
  what they want.  Just because the courts don't provide something does not 
  mean religious entities throw up their hands and quit.  Quite to the 
  contrary. 
   
  Marci
   
  So my 
question would be, if Title VII had not included the exemption, what 
would prevent the Church from being required to comply with 
anti-discrimination laws in the employment of priests if her position 
prevailed?  It seems like the logical conclusion would be that 
women wishing to serve as priests would be harmed, so the Church would 
be required to assimilate, regardless of its understanding of God's 
requirements.Brad
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Harm to Others as a Factor in Accommodation Doctrine

2005-03-14 Thread Hamilton02



 
Just for the record-- I never said never can there be any burden on third 
parties, rather that that burden should be assessed by the legislature.  
There are arenas where the burden may never be tolerable, though, 
e.g., there are few burdens on children's health or safety that can be 
justified.
 
There is a broad sprectrum, of course.  Exemptions for peyote 
and religious headgear in the military create de minimis burdens on third 
parties.  Exemptions that permit churches to hide pedophiles from 
unsuspecting parents and children are enormous burdens.
 
Marci
 
For those who believe accommodation can never entail any burdens 
  on third parties, I wonder if they could explain why the constitutional right 
  (or interest) is in free exercise of religion qualitatively different than 
  these other examples.

 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Harm to Others as a Factor in Accommodation Doctrine

2005-03-14 Thread Marc Stern








Vindication of constitutional rights often
entails shifting burdens form one party to another. A public figure defamed
without malice has to suffer damage to reputation in the furtherance of
creating a vigorous marketplace of ideas. The interests of a fetus‘father
in the birth of his child yield to the superior right of a mother not to be compelled
to carry to term. One could multiply still further such examples. For those who
believe accommodation can never entail any burdens on third parties, I wonder
if they could explain why the constitutional right (or interest) is in free
exercise of religion qualitatively different than these other examples.

Marc Stern

 









From:
[EMAIL PROTECTED] [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Monday, March 14, 2005 9:39
AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Harm to Others as a
Factor in Accommodation Doctrine



 



The state courts are actually not uniform
on this -- except for race.  I could not find a church that was permitted
to discriminate according to race, even if the discrimination was religiously
motivated.  The ministerial exception is being argued in many clergy abuse
cases as a general right to control all aspects of the clergy-religious
institution employment relationship.





 





Marci





 





The general right of churches to insist
that their employees share the church's religious beliefs cannot be used to
circumvent the other prohibitions of title VII.  





 








___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Harm to Others as a Factor in Accommodation Doctrine

2005-03-14 Thread Hamilton02



The state courts are actually not uniform on this -- except for race.  
I could not find a church that was permitted to discriminate according to race, 
even if the discrimination was religiously motivated.  The ministerial 
exception is being argued in many clergy abuse cases as a general right to 
control all aspects of the clergy-religious institution employment 
relationship.
 
Marci
 
The general 
  right of churches to insist that their employees share the church's religious 
  beliefs cannot be used to circumvent the other prohibitions of title 
  VII.  

 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Harm to Others as a Factor in Accommodation Doctrine

2005-03-14 Thread Marty Lederman



The caselaw and legislative history are fairly clear -- and uniform, as far 
as I know -- in holding to the contrary.  The general right of 
churches to insist that their employees share the church's religious beliefs 
cannot be used to circumvent the other prohibitions of title VII.  For 
example, if the church has a tenet prohibiting pre-marital pregnancy, or 
prohibiting lawsuits against the church, such a tenet will not excuse the church 
from engaging in discrimination based on pregnancy, and will not justify 
employment sanctions against those who sue the church.  In our October 12, 
2000 OLC Opinion on religious discrimination by recipients of "charitable 
choice" funds, we included a fairly extensive discussion of the cases up through 
2000 (pages 30-32).  The authorities include, e.g., Senator Williams's 
statement at 118 Cong. Rec. 7167 (1972); and the following cases:
 
Cline, 206 F3d at 658; Bollard, 196 F.3d at 945; 
Boyd, 88 F3d at 413-14; Demarco, 4 F3d at 173; Freemont 
Christian Sch., 781 F2d at 1364-67; Rayburn, 772 F2d at 1166-67; 
Pacific Press, 676 F2d at 1276-77; Mississippi College, 626 
F2d at 484; McClure, 460 F2d at 558; Ganzy, 995 F. Supp. at 
348-49, 359-60; Vigars, 805 F. Supp. at 806-08; and Dolter, 
483 F. Supp. at 269-70.

  - Original Message - 
  From: 
  [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
  To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu 
  Sent: Monday, March 14, 2005 8:09 
AM
  Subject: Re: Harm to Others as a Factor 
  in Accommodation Doctrine
  
  
\
  I would disagree, because any woman who wants to be a priest is clearly 
  at odds with heavily document ecclesiology in the Church that forbids them 
  becoming a priest.  Their views, therefore, cut them out of the picture 
  before you even get to gender.
   
  Marci
  
Actually, as to the Catholic Church and women (priests), the title 
VII exemption does not address the problem at all, as I tried to 
explain in a post yesterday.  In order to permit the Church 
to limit the priesthood to men, it's necessary to turn to the First 
Amendment.

  - Original Message - 

  
   
  
  

  ___To post, send 
  message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.eduTo subscribe, unsubscribe, change 
  options, or get password, see 
  http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlawPlease note 
  that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
  read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
  messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Harm to Others as a Factor in Accommodation Doctrine

2005-03-14 Thread Hamilton02




  \
I would disagree, because any woman who wants to be a priest is clearly at 
odds with heavily document ecclesiology in the Church that forbids them becoming 
a priest.  Their views, therefore, cut them out of the picture before you 
even get to gender.
 
Marci

  Actually, as to the Catholic Church and women (priests), the title VII 
  exemption does not address the problem at all, as I tried to 
  explain in a post yesterday.  In order to permit the Church to 
  limit the priesthood to men, it's necessary to turn to the First 
  Amendment.
  
- Original Message - 
  

 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Harm to Others as a Factor in Accommodation Doctrine

2005-03-14 Thread Hamilton02



My view of accommodation arises from the institutional competencies of the 
legislative and judicial branches.  This is not a pragmatic view, but 
rather one based on the enumerated powers and constitutional limitations on 
each branch. The judicial branch lacks the power and investigatory 
powers to determine whether a law that is neutral and generally applicable 
is consistent with the public good.  For such laws, strict scrutiny places 
the court in a position of free-wheeling power to assess public interest 
according to the court's view of the world (which can hardly be reliable if she 
is an honorable judge, because she is not in contact with constituents, not 
working through public positions on issues that may well appear before the 
court, and only considering those laws and issues coming to the court at the 
parties' behest, not hers).  So any doctrine that makes a court into a 
mini-legislature is at cross-purposes with the enumerated powers.
 
I would measure the harm that a court can discern according to how well the 
accommodation fits the practice (not according to agreement on public policy 
goals).  If the accommodation fits the practice perfectly, then 
the accommodation is legitimate (even if wrongheaded).  If there are 
unacceptable levels of harm, the victims need to go to the legislature to 
educate the legislators.  That is what is happening all over the country 
with clergy abuse survivors.  It is extremely difficult to get legislators 
to listen to any entity that is arguing against religious entities, because the 
religious entities have such entree to the legislators, but they are slowly 
making progress a legislators are becoming educated about the intense harm 
done by religious entities to them. 
 
That does not mean I would never invoke strict scrutiny of legislation by a 
court.  When the law is such that it appears to have discriminatory 
purpose, because it is not neutral and generally applicable, strict scrutiny is 
completely appropriate.  The legislature has lost the justification for 
deference by working outside the neutral and generally applicable rubric, and 
the court must determine whether the discrimination exists.  (Note 
that the Court is not determining whether the public policy is good, but rather 
whether the legislature has enacted a law that exceeds constitutional 
purposes.)  This is how strict scrutiny works in other rights arenas, 
including the Equal Protection Clause and the Free Speech Clause.  In 
neither of those arenas do the courts get the power to prowl around neutral, 
generally applicable legislative determinations to see if the policy enacted 
fits their view of proper policy (best example again is Yoder).  Rather, 
the courts are deferential until the legislature acts in a way that demands 
closer scrutiny of the purposes behind the law.  (by purposes, I don't mean 
motivation).  If they don't get that power in the speech context, they 
should not get that power in the religious conduct context, because it 
is manifest that religious conduct can cause much more harm than religious 
speech in the vast majority of circumstances.
 
 
Marci
 
 
Marci,my 
  comment was responding to Marty's and Tom Berg's earlier post, about harm 
  to third parties being part of the criteria courts employ in determing 
  whether an accommodation the legislature has granted should be struck down 
  on Establishment Clause grounds. Several federal and state court decisions 
  suggest this, but they are typically unclear about what constitutes 
  suffcient harm or the kind of harm that violates the Establishment Clause. 
  I don't know if you have a position on this, but I would be curious to 
  know your thoughts. As your earlier response to Tom's post suggested, I 
  don't think you are arguing that legislative discretion should control 
  this Establishment Clause question -- but that means that we need to 
  address the amount and kind of harm caused by an accommodation that would 
  render it invalid.Also, I understand that you believe as a matter of 
  constitutional principle that determining whether religious exemptions or 
  accommodations should be granted is exclusively the province of the 
  legislature. I don't know whether you believe that principle is supported 
  by a pragmatic evaluation of how legislatures deal with these issues in 
  fact. But it would seem to me that it would be useful to know the cost or 
  burden on religious liberty that your position entails. If legislatures do 
  grant accommodations when third parties are not being harmed, that cost is 
  lower than it would be if legislatures often deny exemptions even when 
  relatively trivial state interests are at issue. That kind of pragmatic 
  analysis, however, requires some understanding of what kinds of harms to 
  third parties justify abridging religious liberty.Similarly, 
  although I recognize that the normative or political question of whether 
  an accommodation is jus

Re: Harm to Others as a Factor in Accommodation Doctrine

2005-03-14 Thread Steven Jamar
Not exactly, I think.  The law allows sex to be BFOQ.  Of course the BFOQ comes from the religious beliefs which in turn are what is protected by the First Amendment.  Other BFOQs based on sex include things like restroom attendants and roles in operas and plays and movies -- though Elizabethan theatre could, I suppose, be used to call the arts into question.

Steve

On Monday, March 14, 2005, at 07:49  AM, Marty Lederman wrote:

Actually, as to the Catholic Church and women (priests), the title VII exemption does not address the problem at all, as I tried to explain in a post yesterday.  In order to permit the Church to limit the priesthood to men, it's necessary to turn to the First Amendment.

-- 
Prof. Steven D. Jamar   vox:  202-806-8017
Howard University School of Law fax:  202-806-8567
2900 Van Ness Street NW   mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Washington, DC  20008   http://www.law.howard.edu/faculty/pages/jamar/

"Whenever you find yourself on the side of the majority, it is time to pause and reflect."

Mark Twain
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Harm to Others as a Factor in Accommodation Doctrine

2005-03-14 Thread Hamilton02



The answer would be that those religious groups would lobby and obtain what 
they want.  Just because the courts don't provide something does not mean 
religious entities throw up their hands and quit.  Quite to the contrary. 

 
Marci
 
So my question 
  would be, if Title VII had not included the exemption, what would prevent 
  the Church from being required to comply with anti-discrimination laws in 
  the employment of priests if her position prevailed?  It seems like 
  the logical conclusion would be that women wishing to serve as priests 
  would be harmed, so the Church would be required to assimilate, regardless 
  of its understanding of God's 
requirements.Brad

 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Harm to Others as a Factor in Accommodation Doctrine

2005-03-14 Thread Marty Lederman



Actually, as to the Catholic Church and women (priests), the title VII 
exemption does not address the problem at all, as I tried to 
explain in a post yesterday.  In order to permit the Church to 
limit the priesthood to men, it's necessary to turn to the First 
Amendment.

  - Original Message - 
  From: 
  [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
  To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu 
  Sent: Monday, March 14, 2005 7:45 
AM
  Subject: Re: Harm to Others as a Factor 
  in Accommodation Doctrine
  
  There is a structural check on discrimination in the neutral, generally 
  applicable rule.  If the law is tailored to only burden a religious 
  entity's religious practices and not other identical secular practices, it is 
  unconstitutional per Lukumi.  If the legislature, though, is willing to 
  burden everyone who engages in the conduct with the law, they are in all 
  likelihood are regulating the conduct as harmful conduct, not religious 
  conduct in particular.
   
  This makes sense of the Sherbert and unemployment cases as Smith 
  explained them.  They are problematic, because govt was willing to make 
  an exception to its rule (meaning that the rule against conduct did not need 
  to be absolute) and therefore when the state refused the same exemption for 
  religious reasons, the state has triggered concern about discriminatory 
  conduct and deserves to be subjected to strict scrutiny.
   
  On the same reasoning, Yoder was wrongly decided, which is my view.  
  
   
  By the way, in this era, in my experience, you will have to look long and 
  hard for a legislator that is not eager to grant even the most troubling 
  exemptions, e.g., exemptions for clergy from having to report known child 
  abuse.  The balance at rest at this point in history is not on the side 
  of the public good, but rather the religious entity.
   
  As to the Catholic Church and women, the Title VII exemption for 
  religious belief goes a long way to take care of that problem.  Where the 
  church is not choosing clergy, though, I think it is perfectly legitimate for 
  the govt to decide whether to permit discrimination or not.
   
  Marci
  
As 
I read this, I found myself wondering what the point is of having 
constitutionally protected free exercise if the exercise is only free when 
the legislature decides it is.  The scenario you describe seems to be 
one where the legislature is free to demand or prohibit any conduct they 
like, and to the religious adherent who is unable to comply without 
violating the tenets of their faith is simply out of luck unless they can 
get the legislature to exempt them.  The legislature can then, out of 
either hostility or indifference, simply say, "We're not singling you 
out.  Everybody has to do it."
 
Using your theory as I am understanding it, would you say that the 
Catholic Church is required, by anti-discrimination laws, to hire women 
as priests unless the anti-discrimination law was to specifically exempt the 
Church?  That certainly is a neutral, generally applicable law, and 
women who want to be priests could certainly claim that they would be 
harmed by an accomodation to allow the Church to only have men as 
priests.  And yet, if the Church is required by law to violate what it 
understands to be the constraints placed upon it by God, how does that 
equate with the free exercise of religion?
 
  
   
  
  

  ___To post, send 
  message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.eduTo subscribe, unsubscribe, change 
  options, or get password, see 
  http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlawPlease note 
  that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
  read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
  messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Harm to Others as a Factor in Accommodation Doctrine

2005-03-14 Thread Hamilton02



In some jurisdictions, the ministerial exemption is not quite as broad as 
Marty describes it.  It has been held that when the religious entity's 
conduct is not religiously motivated, e.g., sexual harrassment of a seminarian 
(Bollard, 9th Cir), the ministerial exception has no bite.
 
Marci
 
The exemption that permits the Church to ignore all of the 
  limitations of title VII for the priesthood is, instead, the so-called 
  "ministerial" exemption.  That exemption differs from the statutory 
  exemption in at least three ways:  (1)  Notwithstanding some early 
  judicial language to the contrary, it is a constitutional exemption, 
  not a statutory exemption.  (That is to say, Jean Dudley's question about 
  the need for constitutional exemptions in this context remains relevant 
  to this thread.)   (2) It's broader than the statutory 
  exemption in one important sense -- namely, that it applies to each 
  type of proscribed discrimination in title VII.  (3)  On the other 
  hand, it's narrower than the statutory exemption in another sense -- namely, 
  that it applies only to a limited number of positions that are "ministerial" 
  in nature (and thus probably does not at all protect some organizations that 
  do make some use of the statutory exemption).

 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Harm to Others as a Factor in Accommodation Doctrine

2005-03-14 Thread Hamilton02



There is a structural check on discrimination in the neutral, generally 
applicable rule.  If the law is tailored to only burden a religious 
entity's religious practices and not other identical secular practices, it is 
unconstitutional per Lukumi.  If the legislature, though, is willing to 
burden everyone who engages in the conduct with the law, they are in all 
likelihood are regulating the conduct as harmful conduct, not religious conduct 
in particular.
 
This makes sense of the Sherbert and unemployment cases as Smith explained 
them.  They are problematic, because govt was willing to make an exception 
to its rule (meaning that the rule against conduct did not need to be absolute) 
and therefore when the state refused the same exemption for religious reasons, 
the state has triggered concern about discriminatory conduct and deserves to be 
subjected to strict scrutiny.
 
On the same reasoning, Yoder was wrongly decided, which is my view.  

 
By the way, in this era, in my experience, you will have to look long and 
hard for a legislator that is not eager to grant even the most troubling 
exemptions, e.g., exemptions for clergy from having to report known child 
abuse.  The balance at rest at this point in history is not on the side of 
the public good, but rather the religious entity.
 
As to the Catholic Church and women, the Title VII exemption for religious 
belief goes a long way to take care of that problem.  Where the church is 
not choosing clergy, though, I think it is perfectly legitimate for the govt to 
decide whether to permit discrimination or not.
 
Marci

  As I 
  read this, I found myself wondering what the point is of having 
  constitutionally protected free exercise if the exercise is only free when the 
  legislature decides it is.  The scenario you describe seems to be one 
  where the legislature is free to demand or prohibit any conduct they like, and 
  to the religious adherent who is unable to comply without violating the tenets 
  of their faith is simply out of luck unless they can get the legislature to 
  exempt them.  The legislature can then, out of either hostility or 
  indifference, simply say, "We're not singling you out.  Everybody has to 
  do it."
   
  Using your theory as I am understanding it, would you say that the 
  Catholic Church is required, by anti-discrimination laws, to hire women 
  as priests unless the anti-discrimination law was to specifically exempt the 
  Church?  That certainly is a neutral, generally applicable law, and women 
  who want to be priests could certainly claim that they would be harmed by 
  an accomodation to allow the Church to only have men as priests.  
  And yet, if the Church is required by law to violate what it understands to be 
  the constraints placed upon it by God, how does that equate with the free 
  exercise of religion?
   

 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.