RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-28 Thread Newsom Michael
Eugene's analogies in defense of not requiring an exemption for the
religious use of wine don't hold up.  None of them implicates the
difficult history involving evangelical Protestants and liturgical
Protestants, Roman Catholics, Jews, and Eastern Orthodox.  His analogies
require that we ignore history, a dangerous thing for the law to do.  We
have had some experience with attempts to impose prohibition without
exempting the religious use of wine.  None of those experiences could be
called happy or constructive.  In one case the Arizona AG stipulated, in
four lawsuits brought to challenge a prohibition amendment that
contained no exemption for the religious use of wine, that he would not
enforce the ban against clergymen.  Two years later, the Arizona voters
approved a prohibition amendment with an exemption for at least the
*Christian* religious use of wine.  In Oklahoma, the state Supreme Court
read an exemption into the bone dry prohibition law in an 1918 case.
(The Oklahoma Supreme Court reaffirmed this decision 40 or 50 years
ago.)

The reasons why the first Arizona prohibition amendment failed to exempt
the religious use of wine had nothing to do with the difficulties of
prohibition enforcement.  The Drys backed off largely because of
pressure from Episcopalians.  The ostensible reason was that the Drys
didn't want to be seen as religious bigots.  In Oklahoma, it is clear
that an anti-Catholic (not to mention anti-Episcopalian) bias had
everything to do with the failure to include the exemption.  Enforcement
of a prohibition regime was a non-issue because the leader of the Dry
forces candidly admitted that he would have cut a deal with Catholics
and Episcopalians if they had been willing to play along.

The experience during National Prohibition is mixed on the point of
enforcement.  Many Drys believe that large amounts of wine would up
being consumed outside of religious ceremonies.  But I don't think that
the evidence is clear cut on this point.  But no one could plausibly
argue that the enforcement difficulties that the country faced in the
1920s had anything to do with the exemption for the use of wine by
Christians and Jews.  Among the disastrous consequences of National
Prohibition (leaving to one side the draconian developments in criminal
procedure and the growth of the mob) was the conversion of a nation of
beer and wine-drinkers into a nation of distilled spirits drinkers.  The
truth was that it made economic sense to bootleg distilled spirits
rather than beer or wine because there was more alcohol per volumetric
measure in the case of whiskey and the like than there was with beer or
wine.  It made economic sense to manufacture and smuggle distilled
spirits, and thirsty Americans in the 1920s accommodated themselves to
the liquor that was available.  (A famous song of the times went Gin,
gin, gin, gin, my God how the money rolls in.  It didn't go wine,
wine, wine, wine, etc.)

There simply is no rational basis for thinking or believing that carving
out the exemption would make enforcement impossibly difficult or even
marginally more difficult.  Our history and experience teach us
otherwise.  The liquor that we are likely to see in a prohibition regime
is the distilled stuff, not beer and wine, for, as I have indicated, the
obvious economic reasons.

Legislative discretion, it seems to me, has its limits.  With all due
respect, Holmes was right on the matter of experience and logic.  And he
was certainly right when it comes to history and experience that go to
the heart and center of what this country is.

The Drys in Arizona (on the second try) and the Oklahoma Supreme Court
got it right.  Appeal to abstractions and unsound analogies only become
a cover for indefensible results on the merits, results that we avoided,
even in a time when religious bias was stronger than it is now.  Why, on
earth, in the name of some abstraction, would we ever want to do worse
than the Drys of the early 20th century did?   

 

-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Thursday, March 24, 2005 7:43 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

I appreciate Tom's remarks, but I'm a bit skeptical on both
counts.  As to item (2), I would think that in the wake of Thomas v.
Review Bd. people could claim an exemption even if they aren't members
of an identifiable religious group, so long as they're sincere.  Perhaps
courts would be likely to question the sincerity of a would-be alcohol
user's religious beliefs if he doesn't belong to a well-known religious
group that has well-known religious uses for alcohol.  But I don't think
they'd just be able to categorically avoid the possibility that many
people would claim that God calls on them to consume the sacred
beverage.

As to item (1), though, why should we necessarily assume that
other jurisdictions' exemptions shows that there's not much cost

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-28 Thread Volokh, Eugene
There surely are good political and practical reasons to exempt
sacramental wines from a prohibition of alcohol, despite the burden this
may put on law enforcement.  This doesn't mean that a sacramental wine
exemption doesn't undermine the government's compelling interest -- only
that legislatures may conclude that they're willing to sacrifice some
measure of the compelling interest in order to ease the burden on
religious objectors (or to get a political consensus to enact or to
enforce the law).

The question is whether the same reasons justify courts doing
the same, as a matter of constitutional obligation under a strict
scrutiny regime.  I don't see how this is so, notwithstanding the
history of legislative accommodations (or even judicial accommodations
as a matter of statutory construction).  When a legislature concludes
that it really does want to try to accomplish the compelling interest to
the extent possible, I don't see why a more half-measures approach by
other legislatures -- which simply reflects the legislature's different
weighing of the admittedly compelling interest and the concerns of
religious objectors -- should foreclose this full-bore legislature from
trying to achieve its goals.

Now one possible argument, which Michael's post suggests, is
that the marginal enforcement burdens created by the exemption are small
compared to the overall enforcement burden created by widespread
flouting of the law by others.  Can that, however, be enough to show
that a total ban can't pass strict scrutiny?  If it is, then courts
would have to accept religious objections to marijuana bans, LSD bans,
and so on -- after all, there too our best guess is that the enforcement
headaches created by the religious objections would be very small
compared to the enforcement headache created by massive nonreligious
violations, no?

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Newsom Michael
 Sent: Monday, March 28, 2005 3:53 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others
 
 
 Eugene's analogies in defense of not requiring an exemption 
 for the religious use of wine don't hold up.  None of them 
 implicates the difficult history involving evangelical 
 Protestants and liturgical Protestants, Roman Catholics, 
 Jews, and Eastern Orthodox.  His analogies require that we 
 ignore history, a dangerous thing for the law to do.  We have 
 had some experience with attempts to impose prohibition 
 without exempting the religious use of wine.  None of those 
 experiences could be called happy or constructive.  In one 
 case the Arizona AG stipulated, in four lawsuits brought to 
 challenge a prohibition amendment that contained no exemption 
 for the religious use of wine, that he would not enforce the 
 ban against clergymen.  Two years later, the Arizona voters 
 approved a prohibition amendment with an exemption for at least the
 *Christian* religious use of wine.  In Oklahoma, the state 
 Supreme Court read an exemption into the bone dry 
 prohibition law in an 1918 case. (The Oklahoma Supreme Court 
 reaffirmed this decision 40 or 50 years
 ago.)
 
 The reasons why the first Arizona prohibition amendment 
 failed to exempt the religious use of wine had nothing to do 
 with the difficulties of prohibition enforcement.  The Drys 
 backed off largely because of pressure from Episcopalians.  
 The ostensible reason was that the Drys didn't want to be 
 seen as religious bigots.  In Oklahoma, it is clear that an 
 anti-Catholic (not to mention anti-Episcopalian) bias had 
 everything to do with the failure to include the exemption.  
 Enforcement of a prohibition regime was a non-issue because 
 the leader of the Dry forces candidly admitted that he would 
 have cut a deal with Catholics and Episcopalians if they had 
 been willing to play along.
 
 The experience during National Prohibition is mixed on the 
 point of enforcement.  Many Drys believe that large amounts 
 of wine would up being consumed outside of religious 
 ceremonies.  But I don't think that the evidence is clear cut 
 on this point.  But no one could plausibly argue that the 
 enforcement difficulties that the country faced in the 1920s 
 had anything to do with the exemption for the use of wine by 
 Christians and Jews.  Among the disastrous consequences of 
 National Prohibition (leaving to one side the draconian 
 developments in criminal procedure and the growth of the mob) 
 was the conversion of a nation of beer and wine-drinkers into 
 a nation of distilled spirits drinkers.  The truth was that 
 it made economic sense to bootleg distilled spirits rather 
 than beer or wine because there was more alcohol per 
 volumetric measure in the case of whiskey and the like than 
 there was with beer or wine.  It made economic sense to 
 manufacture and smuggle distilled spirits, and thirsty 
 Americans

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-28 Thread Newsom Michael
See my interlineations.

-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Monday, March 28, 2005 7:16 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

There surely are good political and practical reasons to exempt
sacramental wines from a prohibition of alcohol, despite the burden this
may put on law enforcement.  This doesn't mean that a sacramental wine
exemption doesn't undermine the government's compelling interest -- only
that legislatures may conclude that they're willing to sacrifice some
measure of the compelling interest in order to ease the burden on
religious objectors (or to get a political consensus to enact or to
enforce the law).

MDN: I don't think that our history permits us to say that the
government's interest in not granting an exemption for the religious use
of wine is compelling.

The question is whether the same reasons justify courts doing
the same, as a matter of constitutional obligation under a strict
scrutiny regime.  I don't see how this is so, notwithstanding the
history of legislative accommodations (or even judicial accommodations
as a matter of statutory construction).  When a legislature concludes
that it really does want to try to accomplish the compelling interest to
the extent possible, I don't see why a more half-measures approach by
other legislatures -- which simply reflects the legislature's different
weighing of the admittedly compelling interest and the concerns of
religious objectors -- should foreclose this full-bore legislature from
trying to achieve its goals.

MDN: Again, prohibiting the religious use of wine is not a compelling
state interest.  That, rather than prohibiting the use of wine becomes
the question, given the facts regarding exemptions of the religious use
of wine in the period 1840-1920.  See my remarks below.  

Now one possible argument, which Michael's post suggests, is
that the marginal enforcement burdens created by the exemption are small
compared to the overall enforcement burden created by widespread
flouting of the law by others.  Can that, however, be enough to show
that a total ban can't pass strict scrutiny?  If it is, then courts
would have to accept religious objections to marijuana bans, LSD bans,
and so on -- after all, there too our best guess is that the enforcement
headaches created by the religious objections would be very small
compared to the enforcement headache created by massive nonreligious
violations, no?

MDN:  (1) The analogy to marijuana or LSD is unsound.  We don't have the
same fundamental core set of concerns about them that we do about the
religious use of wine, especially by Catholics and liturgical
Protestants.  Wine has, for better or worse, a different history than
the other substances.  I might grant that the marijuana and LSD cases
might be difficult to decide, but I don't think that they control the
wine case or vice versa for entirely practical -- and rational --
reasons.

(2) We cannot look at marginal and core or overall enforcement issues
out of context.  Failure to exempt the religious use of wine probably
leads to contempt for the basic prohibition regime, thus making
enforcement, as a general proposition, all the more difficult.  Consider
the 1920s.  The *cultural* bias of National Prohibition was bad enough.
Matters would have been even worse if Drys had destroyed the Catholic
Mass, the Orthodox Divine Liturgy, the Anglican Holy Communion, the
(German-American) Lutheran Eucharistic service, and the Jewish Seder.
Fear of the probable backlash to such religious destruction offers up
one possible explanation for the presence of the exemption in a very
liberal form in section 6 of Title II of the Volstead Act.

(3) The exemption for the religious use of wine first appeared in the
early 19th century, at a time when evangelical Protestants had not yet
abandoned wine for grape juice.  Welch's pasteurized grape juice showed
up some time after the Civil War.  (Welch, or his wife, was a devout
Methodist.)  It was only then that evangelical Protestants, in large
numbers, egged on by the WCTU and others, abandoned wine.  By 1900,
therefore, the question was starkly posed: whether to continue to grant
the exemption even though evangelicals no longer needed it to protect
their religious practices.  A refusal to continue extend protection to
others, under the circumstances, looks very much like bias and bigotry.
(Although it is true that the wording of the exemptions adopted in some
of the states, particularly two or three Southern states, makes it
unlikely that these exemptions protected any group other than
evangelical Protestants.  The Volstead Act section 6 form, by contrast,
specifically protects Catholics and Jews, as well as Eastern Orthodox
and liturgical Protestants.) 

(4) Eugene has not offered up a plausible reason (other than, by
implication, Smith) for ignoring all of the lessons

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-24 Thread Berg, Thomas C.
(Apologies for delay in posting ...)
 
I haven't considered the assisted-suicide free exercise claim fully, but
there are some considerations that seem relevant to me.  I think that free
exercise law should start off with the principle that causing harm simply to
yourself because of your sincere religious conscience is prima facie
protected by the basic logic of religious freedom (you have a right to
practice your faith as long as it doesn't harm others).  I would be
inclined, for example, to allow people to handle poisonous snakes in worship
services as long as there were strong safety precautions to avoid
endangering others.
 
However, that's not the end of the matter, because I agree that there can be
complicated questions about whether harms to nonconsenting persons or to
society will accompany or follow an exemption.  In the assisted-suicide
case, those harms include, as Eugene notes, the pressure in the future on
terminal patients who do not fully desire to end their lives.  At least a
couple of factors about the assisted-suicide case make me extremely leery
about having judges recognize any free exercise claim.
 
(1) Only one state allows assisted suicide, and to my knowledge no state
with a law against it makes any exception for claims of religious or other
conscience.  The legal practice of other jurisdictions is at least somewhat
objective evidence of the strength of the government's concerns -- i.e., of
the threat to public peace and safety that would follow from an exemption.
When virtually every state bars a practice and gives no conscience
exemptions, a court would have to be very aggressive to conclude that this
pattern doesn't reflect strong societal concerns.  Compare that with, at the
other extreme, the fact that virtually no jurisdiction in the nation bars
the serving of small amounts of alcohol in a worship service.  In that
instance, it would seem almost impossible for one county to show that its
circumstances are so special as to necessitate prohibiting the activity.
(There are of course intermediate issues where the practice of jurisdictions
varies -- and as Eugene has noted before, different states may have
different circumstances bearing on the particular question involved.  But in
these two cases the evidence of other jurisdiction's legal rules seems
clear, and it would be hard to show that circumstances are so different in
any one given state than everywhere else.)
 
(2) A free exercise claim concerning assisted suicide is, by its nature, not
limited to the particular  practice of an identifiable religious group or
subgroup.  It is, instead, the kind of claim that most any individual in a
terminal situation can assert.  Indeed, there have been significant
arguments that the decision to end one's life is inherently religious (I
think that this argument appeared in some of the briefs in Glucksberg and in
Vacco v. Quill; it also appears in Ronald Dworkin's book and elsewhere).
This does not mean that the claim falls outside free exercise review -- free
exercise protects individual conscience as well as communally formed
practices.  But it does greatly increase the consequences to public peace
and safety or the lives of others from granting an exemption; no longer can
one say (as with the snake handlers, or Jehovah's Witnesses refusing
transfusions) that only this predictable group and a few others will claim
the exemption.  Rather, as the Dworkin argument suggests, recognizing an
exemption here comes close to striking down the assisted-suicide law in
total; or at least it goes a long way down that road.  With such a broad
effect come all of the reasons to be leery about assisted suicide in
general.  The common-sense argument for exemption is that it allows the
government to act in the majority of cases while avoiding suppressing
religious exercise in a minority of cases.  If the exemption can't be
confined somehow -- if the exception swallows the rule -- then that
common-sense argument goes away, and courts should be much more leery about
the consequences of exemption to public peace and safety.
 
Tom Berg 

  _  

From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Tue 3/15/2005 6:47 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others



I agree that it was only one of the problems -- but I think it 
was an important one.  I've argued that elsewhere extensively, and don't 
want to rehash it here.  But consider another unhypothetical scenario. 

In Washington v. Glucksberg, the Court concluded that bans on 
assisted suicide didn't have to be judged under strict scrutiny.  In 
doing so, the Court managed to avoid having to decide the moral question 
of whether there's a compelling interest in prolonging people's lives 
when they don't want them prolonged.  It also managed to avoid having to 
decide the empirical question of whether allowing such assisted suicide 
would end up letting relatives or doctors

Re: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-24 Thread Brad Pardee
Eugene,
You wrote, I'm not sure that the Free Exercise Clause should be read as 
requiring the government to bear such harms; I think the Court is right to 
basically treat it as an antidiscrimination rule, in which case evenhanded 
restrictions are permissible.  But perhaps that's not right: Maybe just like 
the Free Speech Clause is read as providing modest protection against 
content-neutral restrictions and extremely strong protection against 
content-based restrictions, the Free Exercise Clause should be read 
likewise. But that, I think, is an argument for a modest sort of 
intermediate scrutiny (if such a thing as possible), and not for full-on 
strict scrutiny (or more) that we have for content-based speech 
restrictions.  Maybe it's ultimately a good argument -- but if it prevails, 
it would be (and should be) precisely because it's much less ambitious than 
the strict scrutiny advocates by defenders of Sherbert and Yoder.

My own layman's view is that the Free Exercise clause should actually 
provide more protection than the Free Speech clause, simply due to the 
nature of the activity in question.  In my own observations, when a person 
speaks, invoking the Free Speech clause, it is generally because they feel a 
desire to speak or a need to speak.  Rarely, though, is it because they are 
under an external obligation to speak.  In contrast, the adherents of any 
religion that is founded upon an understanding of a divine being (for lack 
of a broader term) who requires obedience are going to be compelled 
externally to do certain things, some of which the person might prefer not 
to do but does nonetheless because they understand themselves to be under an 
external obligation to do so.  The vast majority of these requirements, such 
as meatless Fridays during Lent for Roman Catholics, abstaining from 
premarital and extramarital sexual activity for Roman Catholics, evangelical 
protestants, and others as well (these are simply the two communities which 
I have firsthand knowledge of), and so forth, are not likely to cause a 
conflict with neutral, generally applicable law.

When there is a conflict, however, then the adherent is placed in a position 
of having to choose between faithfulness to their God and obedience to the 
laws of man.  There will be times when it is necessary to compel the latter 
(for example, to use an extreme case, somebody whose faith involves human 
sacrifice).  However, if you look at the conscientious objector status, you 
see an example where a person, on the basis of conscience, is exempted from 
military duty they would otherwise be obligated to serve.  We rightly 
understand that, even in a matter as compelling as our national security, we 
must tread very lightly when we consider forcing somebody to do something 
which they understand to be morally incompatible with their perception of 
right and wrong.  When you look at a religious adherent, you take a step 
further to whether we can or should force a person to do something which is 
not merely incompatible with their own understanding of right and wrong but 
is in fact prohibited by their God.

This is why I believe that the Free Exercise clause is vastly more than an 
antidiscrimination measure.  The use of the word Exercise infers activity 
that is protected.  It's not merely the belief in a religion or the status 
of being an adherent to a religion.  It is the free exercise of religion. 
This the essence of religious freedom: That a person will not be required, 
barring some substantive kind of proven necessity, to act contrary to the 
demands placed on them by their God.  If we reduce it to antidiscrimination 
protection, then we give legislators and judges free reign to run roughshod 
over people whose faith they either don't like or simply don't care about 
one way or another, as long as everybody is required to do the same things. 
Stephen Carter's Culture of Disbelief gives clear examples that we can't 
simply assume that legislators (or judges, for that matter) are going to 
protect free exercise without being compelled to do so by strong 
Constitutional protection that goes beyond simply not singling people out 
for discrimination.

Brad Pardee 

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the messages to others.


Re: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-15 Thread Richard Dougherty
Eugene:
You suggested that we don't know the meaning of the free speech clause, and the 
result is that we should read it very broadly, to protect even speech-related 
harm to others.  (And would that judgment ultimately be made by...judges?)  But 
because we think we
know more about the meaning of free exercise, it should be read much more 
narrowly, to protect no harm, even when it might be an incident of true 
exercise of religion?  Do I have that right?

Richard Dougherty

Volokh, Eugene wrote:

 I actually agree with Greg on much here:  The reason that we
 allow people to inflict various harms on others via their speech has a
 lot to do with *the way* the harm is inflicted:  When harm is inflicted
 by persuading, informing, or offending people with the content of
 speech, we treat that infliction of harm as privileged.

 And that's the reason that I think it's a mistake to say (and
 Greg hasn't said it, but I think others have), The Free Speech Clause
 caselaw gives people the constitutional right to harm others through
 speech, so the Free Exercise Clause should be interpreted as giving
 people the constitutional right to harm others through religiously
 motivated conduct.  The Free Speech Clause caselaw lets people harm
 others through some specific speech-related ways.  It doesn't follow
 that the Free Exercise Clause lets people harm others in other ways --
 whether through discriminating against them, trespassing on their
 property, breaching contracts, and so on, even if the harms are
 comparatively minor.

 Eugene

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-15 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I'm not saying that this is because of the original meaning,
though I think the original meaning as to the Free Exercise Clause
supports my position.  I think that a reading of the Free Exercise
Clause that gives me the right to inflict harms on you, for no other
reason than that I think my God requires (or motivates) me to do this,
would be a pretty bad reading.  If the original meaning commanded this
rule, then I'd conclude that we ought to follow it.  But if it doesn't
command it -- and neither does the precedent, or anything else -- then I
don't see why such a rule should be adopted.  Religious freedom defenses
resting on the arguments that say[ing] there are twenty gods, or no God
. . . neither picks my pocket nor breaks my leg, that religion should
be immun[e] . . . from civil jurisdiction, in every case where it does
not trespass on private rights or the public peace, and that we should
be free to practice our religions so long as we do not injure others
(Jefferson, Madison, McConnell) are appealing.  Arguments that others'
religious conduct picks my pocket and breaks my leg, but it should still
be constitutionally protected, that religion should be immune from
civil jurisdiction, even in cases where it does trespass on private
rights, and that we should be free to practice our religions even when
we injure others are not.

But if you think otherwise, what do you think of the three hypos
that I pointed to (and which I repeat below)?  Do you think that
scenarios A and B in the hypos should be treated the same?  And if not,
doesn't it suggest that harms caused through the communicative impact of
speech ought to be treated differently than harms caused by the
noncommunicative impact of conduct, even when the speaker has a
religious motivation for the conduct?

Eugene

1.  (A)  Larry Flynt inflicts emotional distress on Jerry
Falwell by publishing his vitriolic ad parody in Hustler Magazine;
when sued under the IIED tort, Flynt raises his free speech rights as a
defense.  (B)  Mary Glynt inflicts emotional distress on Jerry Falwell
by standing outside his window at night with a bullhorn; when sued under
the IIED tort, Glynt raises her free exercise rights as a defense -- she
claims (assume that the claim is sincere) that she feels a religious
obligation to remonstrate this way with heretics (and she considers
Falwell to be one).

2.  (A)  The NAACP interferes with Claiborne Hardware's business
relations by publicizing the names of its visitors, and urging people to
boycott Claiborne; when sued under the interference with business
advantage tort, it raises its free speech rights as a defense.  (B)
Operation Rescue interferes with an abortion clinic's business relations
by blocking the entrance to the clinic; when sued under the same tort,
it raises its (or its members') free exercise rights as a defense -- it
claims (assume that the claim is sincere) that its members feel a
religious obligation to protect fetuses this way.

3.  (A)  A modern-day Schenck tries to interfere with the war
effort by publishing books, leaflets, and Web sites urging people to
vandalize munitions manufacturers; when prosecuted for counseling
illegal conduct, he raises his free speech rights as a defense.  (B)
His religiously pacifist cousin Penck tries to interfere with the war
effort by blocking the entrance to a military contractor's building;
when prosecuted for trepassing, he claims (assume that the claim is
sincere) that he feels a religious obligation to fight the war this way.

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Richard Dougherty
 Sent: Tuesday, March 15, 2005 10:31 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others
 
 
 Eugene:
 You suggested that we don't know the meaning of the free 
 speech clause, and the result is that we should read it very 
 broadly, to protect even speech-related harm to others.  
 (And would that judgment ultimately be made by...judges?)  
 But because we think we know more about the meaning of free 
 exercise, it should be read much more narrowly, to protect no 
 harm, even when it might be an incident of true exercise of 
 religion?  Do I have that right?
 
 Richard Dougherty
 
 Volokh, Eugene wrote:
 
  I actually agree with Greg on much here:  The 
 reason that we 
  allow people to inflict various harms on others via their 
 speech has a 
  lot to do with *the way* the harm is inflicted:  When harm is 
  inflicted by persuading, informing, or offending people with the 
  content of speech, we treat that infliction of harm as privileged.
 
  And that's the reason that I think it's a mistake 
 to say (and 
  Greg hasn't said it, but I think others have), The Free 
 Speech Clause 
  caselaw gives people the constitutional right to harm 
 others through 
  speech, so the Free Exercise Clause should be interpreted as giving

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-15 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I again appreciate Alan's remarks, but I'm not sure that they
fully deal with the argument.

(1)  I assume Alan would conclude that there's no free exercise
clause right to block even the entrance to a hardware store.  (Imagine
that someone believes the store sells some environmentally unsound or
otherwise immoral product, and feels a religious motivation to block
such sales.)  So it's not really abortion rights that are doing the
work, or even the medical procedures vs. mere hardware distinction.
What's doing the work, I think, is that my religion doesn't give me the
right to block entrances to your property.

(2)  Alan's next argument is that the harm of blocking entrances
is greater than merely the harm of a boycott or of advocacy.  But I'm
not sure that this is so.  The economic harm of blocking an entrance for
a few days, or even for a few hours in a day, is probably much less than
the economic harm caused by a more-or-less three-year-long boycott.  Yet
presumably the religious blockers could be arrested and taken away 15
minutes after they start blocking the entrance (even if they announce
that they'll only do it for a day, so as to minimize the harm).  They
don't have the right to inflict even modest economic harm on me through
their religious conduct.  Yet they have the right to inflict much
greater economic harm on me by organizing a political boycott.

(3)  As to Mary Glynt, say that she's not using a bullhorn but
some noise but noncommunicative device (say just banging pots and pans,
and say her intent and effect is not convey a message but just to make
noise).  Allowing such noncommunicative banging for religious reasons
but not nonreligious reasons wouldn't violate the rule against content-
or viewpoint-based speech restrictions -- there'd be no speech
restriction involved here.  Yet I take it the result is the same; again,
what's doing the work is not the content-neutrality rule, but the
principle that my religion doesn't give me the right to interfere with
your sleep through my noncommunicative behavior.

Alan, am I mistaken on these points?  If I'm right, then it
seems to me that we do have the very situation I described:  The Free
Speech Clause quite properly gives people the right to inflict certain
harms on others through the communicative impact of speech.  But the
Free Exercise Clause does not give people the right to inflict
comparable harms on others through their noncommunicative conduct, even
if the conduct is religious motivated or compelled.

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of A.E. 
 Brownstein
 Sent: Tuesday, March 15, 2005 10:40 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others
 
 
 Eugene, let me respond to your three examples in this post. Then I'll 
 continue discussing the issues I raised in a second post.
 
 I would allow the abridgement of free exercise rights in all three of 
 Eugene's examples -- for the reasons described below.
 
1.  (A)  Larry Flynt inflicts emotional distress on Jerry 
 Falwell by publishing his vitriolic ad parody in Hustler 
 Magazine; when sued under the IIED tort, Flynt raises his 
 free speech rights as a defense.  (B)  Mary Glynt inflicts 
 emotional distress on Jerry Falwell by standing outside his 
 window at night with a bullhorn; when sued under the IIED 
 tort, Glynt raises her free exercise rights as a defense -- 
 she claims (assume that the claim is sincere) that she feels 
 a religious obligation to remonstrate this way with heretics 
 (and she considers Falwell to be one).
 
  Mary engages in expressive activities (using a bullhorn to 
 communicate a message.) She does so in a context which is typically 
 prohibited (using a bullhorn in a residential neighborhood at 
 night) and 
 the prohibition of such expressive activities is upheld 
 against free speech 
 review. I don't believe that religiously motivated speech or 
 speech with 
 religious content is exempt from speech regulations that non 
 religious 
 speakers or speech is subject to. The free speech clause prohibition 
 against content and viewpoint discrimination trumps free 
 exercise rights.
 
  Alternatively, Mary's speech activities might be viewed as 
 intentional infliction of emotional distress and subject to 
 sanction on 
 that ground. I assume she could be liable for her actions 
 under free speech 
 doctrine. Again, I do not think that religiously motivated 
 speech or speech 
 with religious content that causes emotional distress can be 
 treated more 
 favorably than non religious speakers or speech that causes 
 emotional distress.
 
  2.  (A)  The NAACP interferes with Claiborne 
 Hardware's business relations by publicizing the names of its 
 visitors, and urging people to boycott Claiborne; when sued 
 under the interference with business advantage tort

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-15 Thread Berg, Thomas C.
But Eugene's position is also unattractive, I would suggest, because it
asserts that we should be free to practice our religion as long as it does
not harm others, and the government determines what is a harm to others,
without any constitutional review of that determination by the courts.  I
think that when you add that second assertion, his reading of the Free
Exercise Clause becomes unattractive, and in many cases just as out of line
with common intuitions about the scope of religious freedom as protecting
the religious conduct arguably would be in his hypotheticals.
 
Under Eugene's position, if the county board decides that this shall be a
dry county -- say, no serving of alcohol to any group of persons -- then the
serving of wine at a Catholic mass or the Jewish seder is barred with no
constitutional objection.  Under Eugene's view, the county board can say
all citizens of this county have a 'private right' not to have anyone in
the county drinking alcohol, or it can say even the smallest serving of
alcohol in a communion or seder cup threatens the public peace or harms
others.  This is because under Eugene's view, the legislature can define
anything as a private right or a harm or a threat to public peace.
(Even if the court can first declare the mass or seder protected under
Eugene's common law religious freedom approach, his position, as I
understand it, is that if the county board comes back and explicitly
declares the religious conduct illegal, the courts then may not question
that.)  The central worship service of Catholicism and other faiths can be
barred or drastically altered by the coercive force of law even though the
activity goes on regularly elsewhere across the nation without significant
real-world harm.
 
Perhaps Eugene would respond, This seems a perfectly attractive implication
of religious liberty to me.  But I doubt he'd say that, and if he did, I
think he would be out of line with most common intuitions about the scope of
religious freedom.  Or he might say, Yes, this is an unattractive result --
it would be great to protect the mass or other serving of small amounts of
sacramental alcohol -- but we have to accept this unattractive result
because it follows from the best theory of religious freedom.  But in that
case, I would make two responses:  (1) his theory no longer can lay claim to
be obviously the one whose applications accord with common intuitions; and
(2) his theory is a good deal more about institutional competence to measure
things like private rights and public peace than it is about the
normative principle of religious freedom.
 
I don't think it's obvious that these concepts are undefinable by courts and
therefore we have to defer to whatever the political branches say.  The
example of Jefferson's neither breaks my leg nor picks my pocket is
revealing because it invokes rights in one's physical integrity and one's
property that are individualized (rather than diffuse social effects) and
are part of the basic common-law framework that the Framers would have
assumed.  I don't think it follows from the Jefferson quote that the
legislature can define whatever it wants as a private right or as an
injury to another, without any further questions.
 
Tom Berg, University of St. Thomas (Minnesota)
 

  _  

From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Tue 3/15/2005 12:42 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others



I'm not saying that this is because of the original meaning, 
though I think the original meaning as to the Free Exercise Clause 
supports my position.  I think that a reading of the Free Exercise 
Clause that gives me the right to inflict harms on you, for no other 
reason than that I think my God requires (or motivates) me to do this, 
would be a pretty bad reading.  If the original meaning commanded this 
rule, then I'd conclude that we ought to follow it.  But if it doesn't 
command it -- and neither does the precedent, or anything else -- then I 
don't see why such a rule should be adopted.  Religious freedom defenses 
resting on the arguments that say[ing] there are twenty gods, or no God 
. . . neither picks my pocket nor breaks my leg, that religion should 
be immun[e] . . . from civil jurisdiction, in every case where it does 
not trespass on private rights or the public peace, and that we should 
be free to practice our religions so long as we do not injure others 
(Jefferson, Madison, McConnell) are appealing.  Arguments that others' 
religious conduct picks my pocket and breaks my leg, but it should still 
be constitutionally protected, that religion should be immune from 
civil jurisdiction, even in cases where it does trespass on private 
rights, and that we should be free to practice our religions even when 
we injure others are not. 

But if you think otherwise, what do you think of the three hypos 
that I pointed to (and which I repeat below)?  Do you

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-15 Thread Berg, Thomas C.
Eugene, you took the route I didn't expect, which is to say that the
suppression of the mass by a no-alcohol law would not be constitutionally
troubling under our most common intuitions about religious freedom.  I
strongly suspect that most courts following the Sherbert/Yoder approach
would disagree and would mandate an exemption.
 
Indeed, I think that courts following Sherbert/Yoder would be more likely to
mandate alcohol exemptions than peyote exemptions -- which themselves have
been quite common under the Sherbert/Yoder approach (see, e.g., three USSCT
dissenting justices in Smith finding no compelling interest, versus O'Connor
concurring alone finding a compelling interest; see also Smith v. Employment
Division, 763 P.2d 146 (Or. 1988); Whitehorn v. State, 561 P.2d 539 (Okla.
Crim. App. 1977); State v. Whittingham, 504 P.2d 950 (Ariz. App. 1973);
People v. Woody, 394 P.2d 813 (Cal. 1964); Peyote Way Church of God v.
Smith, 742 F.2d 193 (5th Cir. 1984)).  It is true that alcohol causes more
deaths and injuries than peyote, but alcohol is also far more widespread and
permitted in many jurisdictions, and for most people small amounts of wine
are harmless (or even of some medicinal value).  Moreover, and importantly,
some of the peyote-exemption cases noted that there were statutory
exemptions for sacramental peyote in other jurisdictions, and that this
undermined the assertion of a compelling interest under Sherbert/Yoder;
indeed, exemptions or an absence of regulation have regularly been cited in
free exercise cases generally as evidence that a state's interest is not
compelling.  This argument would be many, many orders of magnitude stronger
in the case of an alcohol ban in a dry county (and that was my hypothetical,
not National Prohibition).  A dry county would be almost alone among
thousands of governmental units in prohibiting all public serving of alcohol
including in sacramental settings.  The Catholic church would convincingly
say, Look at the hundreds or thousands of jurisdictions where sacramental
wine is permitted either by exemption or because there is no ban in the
first place; and there's no evidence that the sacramental use has increased
deaths or injuries in any significant amount.  In that light, how can you,
dry county, claim that prohibiting our use is a compelling necessity?
 
I'm quite confident that most courts applying Sherbert/Yoder to a dry county
would mandate the wine exemption, and even more readily than the peyote
exemption.  But I too would be interested in what others on the list think.
 
Tom Berg 




  _  

From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Tue 3/15/2005 4:32 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others



I support sacramental wine exemptions as a policy matter, but I don't
think they'd be constitutionally mandated even under strict scrutiny.
Alcohol contributes to the deaths of 100,000 people a year, including about
15,000 innocent bystanders.  I'm not an expert on Prohibition history, but
my guess is that a sacramental wine exemption -- unless it's accompanied
with some very intrusive policing -- would allow a considerable amount of
leakage into the black market, and would more broadly interfere with
enforcement.  (A minister who gets a shipment of sacramental wine for mass
can easily get drunk, and then drive drunk; people who get wine for Passover
seders can do the same; and it's much easier to smuggle alcohol if you can
claim Oh, officer, this batch is for sacramental use -- here are some
papers that say so.)
 
In practice, an alcohol prohibition is likely to be so underenforced
that this leakage doesn't matter much -- but I quite doubt that a court
applying the Sherbert/Yoder-era regime would find as a matter of
constitutional fact that the sacramental exemption is likely to be harmless
enough that the government won't satisfy strict scrutiny.  Instead, a court
would likely reason the way O'Connor did in Smith, especially since alcohol
seems to be much more deadly than peyote.  Am I mistaken?  Do people think
that even if Sherbert/Yoder-era strict scrutiny had been applied to an
alcohol ban, an exemption would have been or should have been carved out,
despite how deadly alcohol can be?
 
More broadly, I do ultimately support the Smith regime, which keeps the
courts out of the business of deciding as a *constitutional* matter which
harms to others are real harms and which aren't.  As I argue in my
Common-Law Model paper, that business was one of the problems of the Lochner
era cases, where some of the decisions (see, e.g., Adair) were indeed based
on a court's judgment that discrimination isn't a real harm that the
legislature can try to avoid.  At the same time, for reasons I explain
there, I think the state RFRA model, where courts are given the power to
carve out exemptions in the first instance, subject to legislative override,
is better than either pure Smith

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-15 Thread Berg, Thomas C.
I'd say that the problem of deciding as a constitutional matter which harms
to others are real harms was only one problem of the Lochner cases.  At
least two other problems were present there that are not present for free
exercise exemption cases:
 
(1) The asserted constitutional right in the Lochner cases rested on a
dubious or at least uncertain ground, substantive due process, versus an
explicit textual provision like free exercise, which has an extensive
background and history tied to the decision to enact it.  That background
and history includes the use of terms like private rights and public
peace, which it seems doubtful Madison and others would have meant to
collapse into whatever any legislature or political body says is a harm. 
 
(2) Challenges under Lochner logically aimed to strike down the entire law
as an interference with economic liberty in all its applications, whereas a
free exercise challenge to a generally applicable law seeks only an
exemption for the claimant and others similarly situated.  It is indeed more
difficult and complicated, and more a sortie into basic policy questions, to
say that a law as whole does not prevent real harms than to say that an
exemption for a particular claimant will not cause real harms.  In the
latter kind of analysis, judges can look at the facts and record adduced as
to this litigant and others like him; they are engaged in large part in the
fitting of particular facts into broader principles, which is what judges
commonly do.
 
Tom Berg
 

  _  

From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Tue 3/15/2005 4:32 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others


. . .
More broadly, I do ultimately support the Smith regime, which keeps the
courts out of the business of deciding as a *constitutional* matter which
harms to others are real harms and which aren't.  As I argue in my
Common-Law Model paper, that business was one of the problems of the Lochner
era cases, where some of the decisions (see, e.g., Adair) were indeed based
on a court's judgment that discrimination isn't a real harm that the
legislature can try to avoid.  At the same time, for reasons I explain
there, I think the state RFRA model, where courts are given the power to
carve out exemptions in the first instance, subject to legislative override,
is better than either pure Smith or pure Sherbert.  In any event, I realize
the Smith regime reaches some unappealing results -- but I don't think that
as to sacramental wines, Sherbert or Yoder would likely reach any different
results.
 
-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Berg, Thomas C.
Sent: Tuesday, March 15, 2005 1:34 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others



But Eugene's position is also unattractive, I would suggest, because it
asserts that we should be free to practice our religion as long as it does
not harm others, and the government determines what is a harm to others,
without any constitutional review of that determination by the courts.  I
think that when you add that second assertion, his reading of the Free
Exercise Clause becomes unattractive, and in many cases just as out of line
with common intuitions about the scope of religious freedom as protecting
the religious conduct arguably would be in his hypotheticals.
 
Under Eugene's position, if the county board decides that this shall be a
dry county -- say, no serving of alcohol to any group of persons -- then the
serving of wine at a Catholic mass or the Jewish seder is barred with no
constitutional objection.  Under Eugene's view, the county board can say
all citizens of this county have a 'private right' not to have anyone in
the county drinking alcohol, or it can say even the smallest serving of
alcohol in a communion or seder cup threatens the public peace or harms
others.  This is because under Eugene's view, the legislature can define
anything as a private right or a harm or a threat to public peace.
(Even if the court can first declare the mass or seder protected under
Eugene's common law religious freedom approach, his position, as I
understand it, is that if the county board comes back and explicitly
declares the religious conduct illegal, the courts then may not question
that.)  The central worship service of Catholicism and other faiths can be
barred or drastically altered by the coercive force of law even though the
activity goes on regularly elsewhere across the nation without significant
real-world harm.
 
Perhaps Eugene would respond, This seems a perfectly attractive implication
of religious liberty to me.  But I doubt he'd say that, and if he did, I
think he would be out of line with most common intuitions about the scope of
religious freedom.  Or he might say, Yes, this is an unattractive result --
it would be great to protect the mass or other serving of small

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-15 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I agree that it was only one of the problems -- but I think it
was an important one.  I've argued that elsewhere extensively, and don't
want to rehash it here.  But consider another unhypothetical scenario.

In Washington v. Glucksberg, the Court concluded that bans on
assisted suicide didn't have to be judged under strict scrutiny.  In
doing so, the Court managed to avoid having to decide the moral question
of whether there's a compelling interest in prolonging people's lives
when they don't want them prolonged.  It also managed to avoid having to
decide the empirical question of whether allowing such assisted suicide
would end up letting relatives or doctors pressure patients to choose
assisted suicide, even when the patients would rather not have chosen
that (much as allowing dueling might pressure people into dueling even
if they'd have preferred not to do so)

Now let's say that a patient claims a Free Exercise Clause right
to have assistance in his suicide (because he believes that God is
calling him home), or a patient's spouse claims a Free Exercise Clause
right to be the Good Samaritan who helps the patient out of his misery.

See Sanderson v. People, 12 P.3d 851 (Colo.App.2000); see also, e.g.,
Winthrop Drake Thies, Shall the Dying Be Denied Their Religious
Freedom?, Newark Star-Ledger, Feb. 6, 1997, at 26; Brief of 36 Religious
Organizations, Leaders, and Scholars as Amici Curiae in Support of
Respondents, Vacco v. Quill, 521 U.S. 793 (1997) (No. 95-1858), and
Washington v. Glucksberg, 521 U.S. 702 (1997) (No. 96-110) (making this
argument).  Under the Sherbert/Yoder regime, the Court would be right
back in the strict scrutiny inquiry that Glucksberg avoided:  The Court
would have to make those moral and empirical judgments that I described.
Tom, do you think it would be good for these judgments to be made as a
matter of constitutional law by the judiciary?

Eugene

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Berg, Thomas C.
Sent: Tuesday, March 15, 2005 4:14 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others


I'd say that the problem of deciding as a constitutional matter which
harms to others are real harms was only one problem of the Lochner
cases.  At least two other problems were present there that are not
present for free exercise exemption cases:

(1) The asserted constitutional right in the Lochner cases rested on a
dubious or at least uncertain ground, substantive due process, versus an
explicit textual provision like free exercise, which has an extensive
background and history tied to the decision to enact it.  That
background and history includes the use of terms like private rights
and public peace, which it seems doubtful Madison and others would
have meant to collapse into whatever any legislature or political body
says is a harm. 

(2) Challenges under Lochner logically aimed to strike down the entire
law as an interference with economic liberty in all its applications,
whereas a free exercise challenge to a generally applicable law seeks
only an exemption for the claimant and others similarly situated.  It is
indeed more difficult and complicated, and more a sortie into basic
policy questions, to say that a law as whole does not prevent real
harms than to say that an exemption for a particular claimant will not
cause real harms.  In the latter kind of analysis, judges can look at
the facts and record adduced as to this litigant and others like him;
they are engaged in large part in the fitting of particular facts into
broader principles, which is what judges commonly do.

Tom Berg




From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Tue 3/15/2005 4:32 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others


. . .
More broadly, I do ultimately support the Smith regime, which keeps
the courts out of the business of deciding as a *constitutional* matter
which harms to others are real harms and which aren't.  As I argue in
my Common-Law Model paper, that business was one of the problems of the
Lochner era cases, where some of the decisions (see, e.g., Adair) were
indeed based on a court's judgment that discrimination isn't a real
harm that the legislature can try to avoid.  At the same time, for
reasons I explain there, I think the state RFRA model, where courts are
given the power to carve out exemptions in the first instance, subject
to legislative override, is better than either pure Smith or pure
Sherbert.  In any event, I realize the Smith regime reaches some
unappealing results -- but I don't think that as to sacramental wines,
Sherbert or Yoder would likely reach any different results.

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Berg, Thomas C.
Sent: Tuesday, March 15, 2005 1:34 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-15 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Title: Message



 Well, I'd love to hear what others would 
think. Peyote has been the outlier in the drug cases -- as I understand 
it, as to marijuana and other drugs the overwhelming judgment of the lower 
courts has been that denying an exemption would pass strict scrutiny. (A 
few courts in marijuana cases, if I recall, have taken the opposite view, but 
that's a minority view.) Part of the dissenters' arguments in Smith had to 
do with peyote's relative lack of broad public appeal; that wouldn't apply to 
alcohol.

 As to the merits of the alcohol exemption claim, I'm not at all 
convinced by the hypothetical Catholic argument before. There may in fact 
be no criminological studies showing that the sacramental use exception has 
increased deaths or injuries -- but how could we have an effectivestudy on 
such a question? Criminologists will tell you that measuring criminal 
behavior is notoriously difficult. Criminal law judgments such as this one 
therefore necessarily operate -- whether the subject is drugs, guns, or anything 
else -- based on intuitive judgments about human nature, not about 
studies.

 Let me offer an analogy. Imagine we had no Second Amendment 
or state right to bear arms provisions, just to set aside that possible issue; 
and imagine that a state law banned the carrying of guns. A Neo-Sikh, who 
believes that the requirement that Sikhs carry a kirpan should be updated to 
reflect modern weaponry, and who thinks that symbolic weaponry isn't 
enough,sincerely believes that he has a duty to carry a gun in order to 
help protect those in peril from criminal attack. Or someone believes God 
has given him the obligation to effectively protect his wife and children were 
on the street; imagine this is sincere. Should courts really have to 
figure out whether gun control is necessary to fight crime, and sort through all 
the contradictory and often inadequate studies? Also, I believe that now 
36 of the 50 states let any law-abiding adult get a license to carry concealed 
-- does it follow that the other 14 states would have to give religious 
objectors similiar licenses, at least so long as a judge concludes that Lott's 
research that suggests that such laws slightly decrease crime is persuasive, and 
contrary research that suggests that such laws slightly increase violent crime 
is unpersuasive?

 Eugene


-Original Message-From: 
[EMAIL PROTECTED] [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
On Behalf Of Berg, Thomas C.Sent: Tuesday, March 15, 2005 3:57 
PMTo: Law  Religion issues for Law AcademicsSubject: 
RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

  
  Eugene, you took the route 
  I didn't expect, which is to say that the suppression of the mass by a 
  no-alcohol law would not be constitutionally troubling under our most common 
  intuitions about religious freedom. I strongly suspect that most courts 
  following the Sherbert/Yoder approach would disagree and 
  would mandate an exemption.
  
  Indeed, I think that courts following 
  Sherbert/Yoder would be more likely to mandate alcohol 
  exemptions than peyote exemptions -- which themselves have been quite common 
  under the Sherbert/Yoder approach (see, e.g., three 
  USSCT dissenting justices in Smith finding no compelling 
  interest,versus O'Connor concurringalone finding a 
  compelling interest; see alsoSmith v. Employment Division,763 
  P.2d 146 (Or. 1988);Whitehorn v. State, 561 P.2d 539 (Okla. Crim. App. 
  1977); State v. Whittingham,504 P.2d 950 (Ariz. App. 1973); People v. 
  Woody, 394 P.2d 813 (Cal. 1964); Peyote Way Church of God v. Smith, 742 F.2d 
  193 (5th Cir. 1984)). It is true that alcohol causes more 
  deaths and injuries than peyote, but alcohol is also far more widespread and 
  permitted in many jurisdictions, and for most people small amounts of wine are 
  harmless (or even of some medicinal value). Moreover, and importantly, 
  some of the peyote-exemption cases noted that there were statutory exemptions 
  for sacramental peyote in other jurisdictions, and that this undermined the 
  assertion of a compelling interest under 
  Sherbert/Yoder;indeed, exemptions or an absence of 
  regulation have regularly been cited in free exercise cases generally as 
  evidence that a state's interest is not compelling. This argument would 
  be many, manyorders of magnitude stronger in the case of an alcohol ban 
  in a dry county (and that was my hypothetical, not National 
  Prohibition). A dry county would be almost alone among thousands of 
  governmental units inprohibiting all public serving of alcohol including 
  in sacramental settings. The Catholic church would convincingly say, 
  "Look at the hundreds or thousands of jurisdictions where sacramental wine is 
  permittedeither by exemption or because there is no ban in the first 
  place; and there's no evidence that the sacramental usehas increased 
  deaths or injuries in any significant amount. In that light, how can 
  you, dry county, 

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-15 Thread A.E. Brownstein
I know I'm falling behind in this thread, but let me do my best to catch up.
I think these are better examples than your first group, Eugene. I could 
probably distinguish some of them  -- but let me see if I can jump over the 
trees and look at the forest instead.

I think there are at least two arguments that explain why we might protect 
free speech that harms others, but not the exercise of religion when it 
harms others. I think you have mentioned both of them in this thread. 
First, the instrumental goals and functions of free speech may be so 
important to the effective functioning of democratic self government and 
other paramount public interests related to the reasons why we protect free 
speech that they justify protecting speech that causes private harms. 
Second, the kind of harm that speech causes is often different in nature 
than the kind of harm that the exercise of religion may cause because the 
latter is so much more conduct intensive than the former. When expressive 
activities are very conduct intensive and the conduct aspect of the 
activity causes harm to third parties, we often do not protect the activity 
as free speech -- and therefore, we should not protect the conduct 
intensive exercise of religion when it causes similar harms.

I don't think these are bad arguments, as far as they go. What I don't 
think they do is to explain why we should never protect the free exercise 
of religion when it causes harm to third parties.

I think the key difference between our positions may be this: I think we 
determine the scope of what the free speech clause protects in terms of two 
constitutional concerns. One concern is that we want to protect speech 
sufficiently to avoid undermining the reasons why we protect freedom of 
speech. For example, we protect speech enough to maintain the effective 
functioning of democratic self government. The second concern is that we do 
not protect speech so much that doing so causes unacceptable harm to third 
parties or the public good. The scope of the right is worked out by taking 
both of these variables into account. Thus, speech that undermines the war 
effort may be quite costly to society, but we lose too much of the value of 
free speech if we allow government to suppress speech that is critical of 
its war policies.

Basically, I think we determine the scope of most rights this way -- by 
looking at these two concerns.

When we define the scope of what the free exercise clause protects solely 
in terms of the harm caused by the exercise of religion, we are leaving out 
an essential part of the constitution equation. We are not asking whether 
defining the right in this way undermines the reasons why we protect the 
exercise of religion.

I recognize that identifying the purpose of protecting the exercise of 
religion is more open and controversial a question than is explaining why 
we protect freedom of speech. But that does not mean that the question can 
be avoided. It seems to me that one core purpose of the free exercise 
clause is that government should act in a way that recognizes how serious 
and important religious beliefs and practices are to religious people.  I 
think the idea of harm to others is so indeterminate and so malleable that 
a principle limiting the protection of free exercise rights to those 
practices that cause no harm to anyone and impose no cost on the public 
undermines the goal of government treating an individual's religious 
identity as something that deserves respect. Indeed, I think any purpose 
served by protecting the exercise of religion as a liberty right (as 
opposed to an equality right) is undermined by the principle that holds 
that the exercise of religion is unprotected whenever it causes harm.

This analysis leaves a lot of issues open to debate and discussion. It says 
nothing about the standard of review to be applied in free exercise cases. 
It says nothing about what kind of harms justify abridging free exercise 
rights. As I have written elsewhere, I think a meaningful free exercise 
jurisprudence should be more complex and nuanced than any unitary formula 
or standard of review -- something more akin to free speech or equal 
protection doctrine.

But a principle that simply rejects any and all protection of religious 
exercise that burdens anyone seems inconsistent with the idea that the 
exercise of religion is a right worthy of protection. It suggests (at least 
to me) that we don't ask whether limiting the scope of right in this way 
undermines the reasons why we protect religious liberty -- because we do 
not think there are any reasons to protect religious liberty.

I respectfully disagree.
Alan Brownstein
UC Davis



(1)  I assume Alan would conclude that there's no free exercise
clause right to block even the entrance to a hardware store.  (Imagine
that someone believes the store sells some environmentally unsound or
otherwise immoral product, and feels a religious motivation 

Re: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread James Maule
Eugene,

Is the distinction between your hypothetical pairings one of free
speech versus free exercise or one of words versus conduct? (Flynt
writes, Glynt yells; the NAACP publishes, Operation Rescue blocks;
Schenck writes/publishes, Penck blocks).

If Glynt, Operation Rescue or Penck were to write/publish would there
be a difference in the analysis? Assume that the writing was based on,
and reflected, sincerely held religious beliefs. Does free speech
subsume free exercise if the exercise is that of
writing/speaking/publishing? Does free exercise not include free speech
with respect to religious beliefs? Are the two concomitant with respect
to religious expression? I'm not convinced that the overlap is
symmetrical or concomitant, and I wonder if concluding that the overlap
IS concomitant effectively makes one of the freedoms subservient to the
other.

Nor do I think that a blanket conclusion requiring a higher level of
proof of harm for free exercise than for free speech is necessary or
wise. I also think that there is a freedom of religious expression that
draws on both freedoms and that may need to be tested differently than
either free speech or free exercise.

Jim Maule
Villanova University School of Law

 [EMAIL PROTECTED] 3/14/2005 12:59:04 PM 
Brad's and Marc's posts raise an excellent question:  If free
speech means that people have the constitutional right to impose
burdens
on others, why shouldn't free exercise operate the same way?  The same
can be said of other rights, incidentally:  For instance, the
Compulsory
Process Clause right gives criminal defendants very substantial powers
to constrain others' liberty.  (I set aside here the permissible scope
of legislative accommodations, and focusing on what's constitutionally
compelled.)

I think that free speech and free exercise *are* different this
way, and let me briefly try to explain why.  I'll begin with some
hypotheticals that I think help illustrate this, and then offer a
broader theoretical explanation.  (The following is borrowed from my A
Common-Law Model for Religious Exemptions, 46 UCLA L. Rev. 1465
(1999),
http://www1.law.ucla.edu/~volokh/relfree.htm.)  Here are the hypos,
which consist of pairs of claims, one free speech and one religious
freedom:

1.  (A)  Larry Flynt inflicts emotional distress on Jerry
Falwell by publishing his vitriolic ad parody in Hustler Magazine;
when sued under the IIED tort, Flynt raises his free speech rights as
a
defense.  (B)  Mary Glynt inflicts emotional distress on Jerry Falwell
by standing outside his window at night with a bullhorn; when sued
under
the IIED tort, Glynt raises her free exercise rights as a defense --
she
claims (assume that the claim is sincere) that she feels a religious
obligation to remonstrate this way with heretics (and she considers
Falwell to be one).

2.  (A)  The NAACP interferes with Claiborne Hardware's
business
relations by publicizing the names of its visitors, and urging people
to
boycott Claiborne; when sued under the interference with business
advantage tort, it raises its free speech rights as a defense.  (B)
Operation Rescue interferes with an abortion clinic's business
relations
by blocking the entrance to the clinic; when sued under the same tort,
it raises its (or its members') free exercise rights as a defense --
it
claims (assume that the claim is sincere) that its members feel a
religious obligation to protect fetuses this way.

3.  (A)  A modern-day Schenck tries to interfere with the war
effort by publishing books, leaflets, and Web sites urging people to
vandalize munitions manufacturers; when prosecuted for counseling
illegal conduct, he raises his free speech rights as a defense.  (B)
His religiously pacifist cousin Penck tries to interfere with the war
effort by blocking the entrance to a military contractor's building;
when prosecuted for trepassing, he claims (assume that the claim is
sincere) that he feels a religious obligation to fight the war this
way.

Under standard free speech doctrine, the free speech claimants
in each of these cases would have a good Free Speech Clause defense,
*even though* their speech causes harm to others.  But do people on
this
list think that the religious freedom claimants in each of these cases
should likewise prevail with their Free Exercise Clause defenses?

The government interests -- and the private interests that the
government is protecting -- in all the cases, it seems to me, are
quite
similar.  The speech and the religious conduct jeopardizes those
interests (perhaps not identically, but to similar degrees).  But
while
the government is barred from restricting the speech when the content
of
the speech causes harm to others, the government may (and I think
should) restrict the religious conduct when that causes harm to
others.

If I'm right, then this suggests that we can't just casually
equate free speech and free exercise claims (perhaps, for 

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Religious speech, it seems to me, should be no more and no less
protected by the Free Speech Clause than other speech.  Thus, the
interesting questions (including the ones we've been discussing on
related threads) arise when there's a claim of religious accommodation
for conduct, or for speech that causes harm through its noncommunicative
components.

So my pairs of examples do compare the Free Speech Clause
treatment of speech (speech that causes harm through what it
communicates) against the Free Exercise Clause treatment of conduct (or
speech that causes harm through its noncommunicative impact).  But
that's the comparison, I take it, that Brad and Marc were urging; if
they had simply been demanding protection for religious speech, they
would be getting it, see Widmar, Lamb's Chapel, etc.

Jim Maule writes:

 Is the distinction between your hypothetical pairings one of 
 free speech versus free exercise or one of words versus 
 conduct? (Flynt writes, Glynt yells; the NAACP publishes, 
 Operation Rescue blocks; Schenck writes/publishes, Penck blocks).
 
 If Glynt, Operation Rescue or Penck were to write/publish 
 would there be a difference in the analysis? Assume that the 
 writing was based on, and reflected, sincerely held religious 
 beliefs. Does free speech subsume free exercise if the 
 exercise is that of writing/speaking/publishing? Does free 
 exercise not include free speech with respect to religious 
 beliefs? Are the two concomitant with respect to religious 
 expression? I'm not convinced that the overlap is symmetrical 
 or concomitant, and I wonder if concluding that the overlap 
 IS concomitant effectively makes one of the freedoms 
 subservient to the other.
 
 Nor do I think that a blanket conclusion requiring a higher 
 level of proof of harm for free exercise than for free speech 
 is necessary or wise. I also think that there is a freedom of 
 religious expression that draws on both freedoms and that may 
 need to be tested differently than either free speech or free 
 exercise.
 
 Jim Maule
 Villanova University School of Law
 
  [EMAIL PROTECTED] 3/14/2005 12:59:04 PM 
   Brad's and Marc's posts raise an excellent question:  
 If free speech means that people have the constitutional 
 right to impose burdens on others, why shouldn't free 
 exercise operate the same way?  The same can be said of other 
 rights, incidentally:  For instance, the Compulsory Process 
 Clause right gives criminal defendants very substantial 
 powers to constrain others' liberty.  (I set aside here the 
 permissible scope of legislative accommodations, and focusing 
 on what's constitutionally
 compelled.)
 
   I think that free speech and free exercise *are* 
 different this way, and let me briefly try to explain why.  
 I'll begin with some hypotheticals that I think help 
 illustrate this, and then offer a broader theoretical 
 explanation.  (The following is borrowed from my A Common-Law 
 Model for Religious Exemptions, 46 UCLA L. Rev. 1465 (1999),
 http://www1.law.ucla.edu/~volokh/relfree.htm.)  Here are the 
 hypos, which consist of pairs of claims, one free speech and 
 one religious
 freedom:
 
   1.  (A)  Larry Flynt inflicts emotional distress on 
 Jerry Falwell by publishing his vitriolic ad parody in 
 Hustler Magazine; when sued under the IIED tort, Flynt raises 
 his free speech rights as a defense.  (B)  Mary Glynt 
 inflicts emotional distress on Jerry Falwell by standing 
 outside his window at night with a bullhorn; when sued under 
 the IIED tort, Glynt raises her free exercise rights as a 
 defense -- she claims (assume that the claim is sincere) that 
 she feels a religious obligation to remonstrate this way with 
 heretics (and she considers Falwell to be one).
 
   2.  (A)  The NAACP interferes with Claiborne Hardware's 
 business relations by publicizing the names of its visitors, 
 and urging people to boycott Claiborne; when sued under the 
 interference with business advantage tort, it raises its free 
 speech rights as a defense.  (B) Operation Rescue interferes 
 with an abortion clinic's business relations by blocking the 
 entrance to the clinic; when sued under the same tort, it 
 raises its (or its members') free exercise rights as a 
 defense -- it claims (assume that the claim is sincere) that 
 its members feel a religious obligation to protect fetuses this way.
 
   3.  (A)  A modern-day Schenck tries to interfere with 
 the war effort by publishing books, leaflets, and Web sites 
 urging people to vandalize munitions manufacturers; when 
 prosecuted for counseling illegal conduct, he raises his free 
 speech rights as a defense.  (B) His religiously pacifist 
 cousin Penck tries to interfere with the war effort by 
 blocking the entrance to a military contractor's building; 
 when prosecuted for trepassing, he claims (assume that the claim is
 sincere) that he feels a religious obligation to fight the 
 war this way.
 
   

Re: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread A.E. Brownstein
I tend to agree with Eugene that free speech and free exercise rights do 
not parallel each other -- so that it does not necessarily follow that 
because freedom of speech is protected even when the speech causes harm to 
third parties, free exercise rights must receive similar protection. But I 
have several problems with other parts of Eugene's analysis.

1. As I tried to argue in an earlier post, harm to others can be an 
ambiguous term. If it includes financial costs and emotional distress, most 
rights are protected at least to some extent, even if doing so imposes such 
consequences on third parties or the general public. Maybe free exercise 
rights are different than other rights in this regard -- but that 
difference needs to be explained and justified. And with due respect, 
Eugene, I don't think you have done that. I understand that my G-d may not 
a deity to you. But it is also true for most self realizing rights or 
autonomy or dignitary rights that what is important and meaningful to me 
may be meaningless and irrelevant to you. This is even true for the 
non-instrumental value of freedom of speech. Maybe X needs to express 
racially derogatory comments to individuals of a different race to be self 
-fulfilled. But I don't. And I see virtually no instrumental value in 
permitting targeted racist invective. But I accept that some such 
expression is constitutionally protected, notwithstanding the emotional 
harm that it causes. Why is that different than protecting free exercise 
rights that harm others of a faith committed to tenets that I do not accept.

2. Also, Eugene, for the purpose of your argument, does harm to the general 
community have the same analytic consequence as harm to specific third 
parties. The burden of granting some free exercise exemptions is 
essentially financial -- it imposes costs on the public fisc. For example, 
exempting a church from land use regulations limiting development in a 
commercial zone has financial consequences for a community -- since the 
church does not pay taxes and does not engage in activities that provide 
sales tax revenue to the city. But the costs of protecting freedom of 
speech can also be quite high. For example, large political demonstrations 
do not police themselves. Is their a reason why we should accept the 
financial costs of exercising free speech rights, but not those associated 
with exercising free exercise rights? (I recognize that political rallies 
have instrumental value, but certainly, one can argue that society benefits 
in a variety of intangible and tangible ways from the houses of worship in 
our communities)

Again, I am not suggesting that all rights are analogous to each other with 
regard to whether they include the freedom to inflict harm on others -- or 
with regard to other attributes. But if free exercise rights are to be 
defined more narrowly than many if not most other rights, I think the 
proponents of doing so need to persuasively explain why this is so.

Alan Brownstein
UC Davis
Eugene writes,
  But we ought not read the Free Exercise Clause as generally
licensing religious objectors to inflict harm on others (or even to do
so subject to a possible strict scrutiny trump).  As I argue, my
relationship with my God may be important to me, but it can't by itself
be a constitutionally sufficient justification for my harming you, even
slightly (for instance, by intentionally inflicting emotional distress
on you in secular ways, blocking access to your property, or slightly
vandalizing your commercial building).   From your perspective and the
legal system's perspective (even if not from my own), my God is my God,
not yours, and the Constitution doesn't give those acting in His name
sovereignty over your legally recognized rights and interests.
The trouble with such a broad religious freedom claim to do
whatever you please so long as you don't harm others is not that private
contract, property, and tort law rights, or private interests in being
free from criminal vandalism (consider the rights and interests
implicated in the three examples I note above) somehow outweigh
religious freedom rights:  How could we justify such a conclusion?  Even
if one somehow determines that such private rights are as important as
religious freedom rights, I see no way to explain why they are more
important, which would be required to show such an outweighing.
Rather, the reason why a general exemption regime can't override
these rights must be that any religious freedom right that's solely
grounded in the religious motivation for one's actions simply can't
extend to actions that impair others' rights or impose improper
externalities on others.  Whether your countervailing right is a right
to life, to bodily integrity, or to something perhaps somewhat less
important, such as property or freedom from emotional distress, if it is
indeed a right then the religiosity of my motivation can't justify
violating it.

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread Sisk, Gregory C.
While free exercise and free speech may be different in many respects, and
indeed most constitutional rights differ from all other rights, as they are
not merely fungible from one to another, I don't think Eugene Volokh's
thoughtful hypotheticals satisfactorily dispose of the argument that free
exercise and free speech ought not be treated differently in the amount of
burden that we accept (or the courts ought to accept) upon the public or
others.  The problem with Eugene's hypotheticals, as I see it, is that the
burdens outlined are not comparable, in part because one involves
non-physical speech and the other involves conduct (as Jim Maule observes),
but also simply because of the anticipated degree of negative impact upon
persons other than the one exercising the right.

Just to look at the first pair of hypotheticals:  While Jerry Falwell is
postulated to have experienced emotional distress as a result of both
incidents, I submit that we intuitively would recognize that the immediacy
and intrusiveness of the harm differs greatly when we compare reading a
scurrilous reference to one's self in a periodical with experiencing an
almost physical trespass accompanied by the use of loud sounds that cannot
easily be escaped and, perhaps most importantly, that occurs at one's place
of sanctuary, the home.  Thus, while I agree that the free speech claim in
that pair of hypotheticals is stronger than the free exercise claim, I don't
see the two cases as truly comparable in terms of the degree and perhaps the
nature of the harm, even if both forms of harm are generally categorized as
emotional distress.

Thus, for a set of hypotheticals comparing the strength of free speech and
free exercise claims to be truly comparable, the nature or at least the
degree of harm must also be comparable.  While not neatly involving parallel
factual settings or messages, consider these two scenarios:  First, we again
have the offensive parody of Jerry Falwell in Larry Flynt's Hustler
magazine, in which Flynt invokes freedom of speech as a defense against a
claim for emotional distress.  Second, we have a homosexual couple that is
rejected as tenants by a homeowner of traditional religious values for the
spare room in her house, in which the homeowner invokes free exercise as a
defense as a claim for discrimination by the homosexual couple under a
municipal gay rights ordinance.  Assume for the sake of argument that other
rental opportunities for homosexual couples are available in that community
(a reasonable assumption, as a municipality in which political support
exists for enactment of a gay rights law involving housing is unlikely to
one in which such discrimination is omnipresent across the community, but
even if you find the assumption more debatable, I ask you to accept it for
this hypothetical).

Under that hypothetical, then, the claim of the homosexual couple, although
framed as housing discrimination and seeking the remedy of an injunction, in
practical terms is about the emotional distress of having experienced
discrimination by being rejected as a tenant on the basis of sexual
orientation.  Isn't that experience of emotional distress comparable to that
of Jerry Falwell who was targeted for sexualized slurs based upon his
religious and political views?  In both instances, the complaining party
understandably and sincerely has suffered an emotional injury (as I'll
assume for this hypothetical, as I doubt that Jerry Falwell truly was that
distressed).  But both emotional injuries are unaccompanied by any physical
component and both involve primarily upset feelings.  By that analysis,
shouldn't the free exercise claim of the homeowner be regarded as equally
viable as the free speech claim of Larry Flynt?

(And if you don't like my hypotheticals, feel free to formulate your own, in
which the comparability of harm is the pivot point rather than comparable
factual settings.)

Greg Sisk


Gregory Sisk
Professor of Law
University of St. Thomas School of Law (Minneapolis)
MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue
Minneapolis, MN  55403-2005
651-962-4923
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
http://personal2.stthomas.edu/GCSISK/sisk.html




-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Monday, March 14, 2005 11:59 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

Brad's and Marc's posts raise an excellent question:  If free
speech means that people have the constitutional right to impose burdens
on others, why shouldn't free exercise operate the same way?  The same
can be said of other rights, incidentally:  For instance, the Compulsory
Process Clause right gives criminal defendants very substantial powers
to constrain others' liberty.  (I set aside here the permissible scope
of legislative accommodations, and focusing on what's constitutionally
compelled.)

I think that free speech and free exercise *are* different this
way, and let me briefly try to 

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I appreciate Greg's thoughtful analysis, but I think that
ultimately the magnitude of the burden on the nonspeaker's/nonclaimant's
rights doesn't resolve the problems.  I would feel *much* more
distressed by knowing that millions (?) of people are reading about how
I supposedly had sex with my mother in an outhouse (even if they know
it's a gag) than by a few nights of loud noise outside my house.

Likewise, I suspect that the more-or-less three-year-long
boycott in Claiborne Hardware affected local businesses more than the
occasional blockage would affect the business of an abortion clinic.
It's true that this may be so because the boycott went on for a long
time, while the blockage in my hypothetical wouldn't.  But under free
speech law, even speech urging a long boycott can't be punished -- and
even one instance of entrance blockage, which would cause vastly less
damage than the boycott, would be punishable, whether or not it's
religiously based.  So people are constitutionally entitled to inflict
considerably greater harms through the communicative impact of their
speech than through the religiously motivated conduct.  Or am I mistaken
here?

As to the housing discrimination scenario, I just think Greg's
comparison cases are actually not terribly similar.  The gay couple's
claim isn't necessarily that they're deeply emotionally distressed --
rather, it is that they have a legal right to equal treatment,
regardless of whether the unequal treatment is terribly distressing.
Maybe this right flows from a general sense that the unequal treatment
is usually distressing, but it doesn't, I think, require a case-by-case
analysis here.  I have a right to be free even from minor trespasses on
my land, or minor batteries (consider someone popping me in the face
with a cream pie, probably not tremendously insulting as batteries go).
People aren't free to engage in this conduct even if they feel a
religious obligation to do so (say, for instance, that they want to
engage in a pilgrimage to what they think is a newly discovered holy
site on my land, or that they feel they need to pie me as a statement
about my blasphemy).  Likewise, I take it that many supporters of
antidiscrimination law believe that a right to be free from certain
kinds of discrimination in certain transactions is a comparable private
entitlement.  I don't see how a court can, as a constitutional matter,
conclude that this form of infringement of one's rights just isn't that
emotionally distressing, while other forms are.

Eugene

Greg Sisk writes:

 While free exercise and free speech may be different in many 
 respects, and indeed most constitutional rights differ from 
 all other rights, as they are not merely fungible from one to 
 another, I don't think Eugene Volokh's thoughtful 
 hypotheticals satisfactorily dispose of the argument that 
 free exercise and free speech ought not be treated 
 differently in the amount of burden that we accept (or the 
 courts ought to accept) upon the public or others.  The 
 problem with Eugene's hypotheticals, as I see it, is that the 
 burdens outlined are not comparable, in part because one 
 involves non-physical speech and the other involves conduct 
 (as Jim Maule observes), but also simply because of the 
 anticipated degree of negative impact upon persons other than 
 the one exercising the right.
 
 Just to look at the first pair of hypotheticals:  While Jerry 
 Falwell is postulated to have experienced emotional distress 
 as a result of both incidents, I submit that we intuitively 
 would recognize that the immediacy and intrusiveness of the 
 harm differs greatly when we compare reading a scurrilous 
 reference to one's self in a periodical with experiencing an 
 almost physical trespass accompanied by the use of loud 
 sounds that cannot easily be escaped and, perhaps most 
 importantly, that occurs at one's place of sanctuary, the 
 home.  Thus, while I agree that the free speech claim in that 
 pair of hypotheticals is stronger than the free exercise 
 claim, I don't see the two cases as truly comparable in terms 
 of the degree and perhaps the nature of the harm, even if 
 both forms of harm are generally categorized as emotional distress.
 
 Thus, for a set of hypotheticals comparing the strength of 
 free speech and free exercise claims to be truly comparable, 
 the nature or at least the degree of harm must also be 
 comparable.  While not neatly involving parallel factual 
 settings or messages, consider these two scenarios:  First, 
 we again have the offensive parody of Jerry Falwell in Larry 
 Flynt's Hustler magazine, in which Flynt invokes freedom of 
 speech as a defense against a claim for emotional distress.  
 Second, we have a homosexual couple that is rejected as 
 tenants by a homeowner of traditional religious values for 
 the spare room in her house, in which the homeowner invokes 
 free exercise as a defense as a claim for discrimination by 
 

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I was glad to see Alan's response, and I'll try to respond
myself below.  But Alan, what do you think of the three examples I give?

Alan Brownstein writes:

 1. As I tried to argue in an earlier post, harm to others can be an
ambiguous term. If it includes financial costs and emotional 
 distress, most rights are protected at least to some extent, even if
doing so imposes such 
 consequences on third parties or the general public. Maybe free
exercise rights are different than other rights in this regard -- but
that 
 difference needs to be explained and justified. And with due respect,
Eugene, I don't think you have done that. I understand that 
 my G-d may not a deity to you. But it is also true for most self
realizing rights or autonomy or dignitary rights that what is important
and 
 meaningful to me may be meaningless and irrelevant to you. This is
even true for the non-instrumental value of freedom of speech.
 Maybe X needs to express racially derogatory comments to individuals
of a different race to be self 
 -fulfilled. But I don't. And I see virtually no instrumental value in
permitting targeted racist invective. But I accept that some such 
 expression is constitutionally protected, notwithstanding the
emotional harm that it causes. Why is that different than protecting 
 free exercise rights that harm others of a faith committed to tenets
that I do not accept.

I think this is a great explanation for why pure self-expression
isn't an adequate defense for free speech claims, and it's one reason
that the Court has accepted some exceptions from free speech protection
even when the speaker is deriving self-expression benefits from the
speech (e.g., lies, threats, and -- most relevant for Alan's example --
fighting words).  But the chief reason the Court has given for
protecting free speech is the social benefits of speech, and the social
harms of giving the government broad power to restrict speech.  So I do
think there's substantial social benefit in protecting racist speech
broadly (though not necessarily fighting words, whether racist or not).
 
 2. Also, Eugene, for the purpose of your argument, does harm to the
general community have the same analytic consequence as harm to 
 specific third  parties. The burden of granting some free exercise
exemptions is  essentially financial -- it imposes costs on the public
fisc. 
 For example,  exempting a church from land use regulations limiting
development in a  commercial zone has financial consequences for a
 community --  since the  church does not pay taxes and does not engage
in activities  that provide sales tax revenue to the city. But the costs
 of protecting freedom of speech can also be quite high. For example,
large political demonstrations do not police themselves. Is their a
 reason why we should accept the  financial costs of exercising free
speech rights, but not  those associated 
 with exercising free exercise rights? (I recognize that  political
rallies  have instrumental value, but certainly, one can argue that 
 society benefits in a variety of intangible and tangible ways from the
houses of worship in our communities)

I think that harm to the general community at least often does
qualify as harm -- and that includes financial harm.  For instance,
criticism of the draft (short of Brandenburg incitement) is protected,
even when that is likely to lead some people to disobey the draft law;
religious refusal to obey the draft is not protected, see Gillette.
Criticism of the tax system (again, short of incitement) is protected,
even when that is likely to lead to less tax revenue; religious refusal
to pay taxes is not, see Bob Jones.  Alan, do you think these results
are wrong?  

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


Re: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread Richard Dougherty
Eugene:
Are you grounding your analysis here of speech and religion in the text of the 
First Amendment?  It seems to my untutored eye that it is precisely exercise 
of religion that is protected, no?  Is there any reason to think that exercise 
of religion might not
be harmful?  I guess my question is whether you see the harm done by religion 
as unprotected because of  some constitutional reason (such as, it amounts to 
establishment)?  Why would the religious motivation be treated any differently 
than an anti-religious
motivation, or a commitment to Millian liberalism, or the will to power?  If 
the protection for speech's harm, is that speech is good for democracy, cannot 
one make the same argument about much, if not all, religious exercise?

(I'm not defending the principle that there is a right to harm, only looking 
for consistency.)

Thanks,
Richard Dougherty


Volokh, Eugene wrote (in part):

 The Free Speech Clause and other rights *are* rights to inflict
 certain kinds of harm on others in certain ways (for instance, through
 the communicative impact of speech); we think that for various reasons,
 the government ought not be allowed to interfere with this harm, perhaps
 because speech is so valuable to democratic self-government, or because
 we suspect the government will abuse its regulatory powers.  Likewise,
 as I argue at
 http://www1.law.ucla.edu/~volokh/relfree.htm#Several%20Specific%20Prohib
 itions%20on%20Government, in a few contexts (for instance,
 discrimination in hiring clergy, or religious frauds), the Free Exercise
 Clause also allows religious people or institutions to inflict what the
 law might otherwise treat as harm to others.

 But we ought not read the Free Exercise Clause as generally
 licensing religious objectors to inflict harm on others (or even to do
 so subject to a possible strict scrutiny trump).  As I argue, my
 relationship with my God may be important to me, but it can't by itself
 be a constitutionally sufficient justification for my harming you, even
 slightly (for instance, by intentionally inflicting emotional distress
 on you in secular ways, blocking access to your property, or slightly
 vandalizing your commercial building).   From your perspective and the
 legal system's perspective (even if not from my own), my God is my God,
 not yours, and the Constitution doesn't give those acting in His name
 sovereignty over your legally recognized rights and interests.


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread James Maule
Suppose instead of Flynt satirizing Falwell, the Rev. Llynt preaches a
sermon in his progressive church decrying the theological positions
taken by Falwell, denouncing the alleged intrusion of Falwell's theology
into politics, and characterizing Falwell as a modern-day Pharisee. The
sermon concludes that it is behavior and proselytization such as that in
which Falwell engages that continues to contribute to the agony of Jesus
on the Cross. The sermon is broadcast on tv, radio, and/or the web (to
get roughly the same dissemination as Flynt managed with Hustler).
Falwell is understandably upset and emotionally distressed (assume that
it's just as distressing to him as were the comments about his mother).

Must Falwell meet a higher burden because the offending speech is a
religious sermon rather than a parody in a secular publication? Should
the courts get involved in the modern equivalent of the 17th century
pamphlet wars if one or both of the parties alleges some sort of
emotional distress or other damage? Or should the courts do as suggested
the jury in Thomas Maule's trial: This is a matter for a jury of
divines.?

I think it makes a lot of sense to severely limit the extent to which
courts measure the emotional distress caused by religious expression (in
contrast to other speech). Otherwise, because religious expression also
is a form of free exercise, a back door is open to curtail the free
exercise rights of the speaker.

Jim Maule
Villanova University School of Law

 [EMAIL PROTECTED] 3/14/2005 4:36:01 PM 
While free exercise and free speech may be different in many respects,
and
indeed most constitutional rights differ from all other rights, as they
are
not merely fungible from one to another, I don't think Eugene Volokh's
thoughtful hypotheticals satisfactorily dispose of the argument that
free
exercise and free speech ought not be treated differently in the amount
of
burden that we accept (or the courts ought to accept) upon the public
or
others.  The problem with Eugene's hypotheticals, as I see it, is that
the
burdens outlined are not comparable, in part because one involves
non-physical speech and the other involves conduct (as Jim Maule
observes),
but also simply because of the anticipated degree of negative impact
upon
persons other than the one exercising the right.

Just to look at the first pair of hypotheticals:  While Jerry Falwell
is
postulated to have experienced emotional distress as a result of both
incidents, I submit that we intuitively would recognize that the
immediacy
and intrusiveness of the harm differs greatly when we compare reading
a
scurrilous reference to one's self in a periodical with experiencing
an
almost physical trespass accompanied by the use of loud sounds that
cannot
easily be escaped and, perhaps most importantly, that occurs at one's
place
of sanctuary, the home.  Thus, while I agree that the free speech claim
in
that pair of hypotheticals is stronger than the free exercise claim, I
don't
see the two cases as truly comparable in terms of the degree and
perhaps the
nature of the harm, even if both forms of harm are generally
categorized as
emotional distress.

Thus, for a set of hypotheticals comparing the strength of free speech
and
free exercise claims to be truly comparable, the nature or at least
the
degree of harm must also be comparable.  While not neatly involving
parallel
factual settings or messages, consider these two scenarios:  First, we
again
have the offensive parody of Jerry Falwell in Larry Flynt's Hustler
magazine, in which Flynt invokes freedom of speech as a defense against
a
claim for emotional distress.  Second, we have a homosexual couple that
is
rejected as tenants by a homeowner of traditional religious values for
the
spare room in her house, in which the homeowner invokes free exercise
as a
defense as a claim for discrimination by the homosexual couple under a
municipal gay rights ordinance.  Assume for the sake of argument that
other
rental opportunities for homosexual couples are available in that
community
(a reasonable assumption, as a municipality in which political support
exists for enactment of a gay rights law involving housing is unlikely
to
one in which such discrimination is omnipresent across the community,
but
even if you find the assumption more debatable, I ask you to accept it
for
this hypothetical).

Under that hypothetical, then, the claim of the homosexual couple,
although
framed as housing discrimination and seeking the remedy of an
injunction, in
practical terms is about the emotional distress of having experienced
discrimination by being rejected as a tenant on the basis of sexual
orientation.  Isn't that experience of emotional distress comparable to
that
of Jerry Falwell who was targeted for sexualized slurs based upon his
religious and political views?  In both instances, the complaining
party
understandably and sincerely has suffered an emotional injury (as I'll
assume for this hypothetical, as I doubt that 

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I'm not grounding it on the text, which gets us fairly little
here.  I'm generally persuaded by Justice Scalia's original meaning
argument in City of Boerne v. Flores as to free exercise; as to the
original meaning of free speech, I think that's basically unknown and
likely unknowable.

I should say, by the way, that my argument is *not* that
religiously motivated conduct or speech should be treated worse than the
nonreligiously motivated conduct or speech; I think the Free Exercise
Clause bars such discrimination against religious motivation.  I think
Lukumi is right, and Locke v. Davey is wrong.  Rather, my argument is
that the Free Exercise Clause ought not be read as allowing people to do
things that harm others simply because they feel a religious obligation
to do those things.

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Richard Dougherty
 Sent: Monday, March 14, 2005 2:35 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others
 
 
 Eugene:
 Are you grounding your analysis here of speech and religion 
 in the text of the First Amendment?  It seems to my untutored 
 eye that it is precisely exercise of religion that is 
 protected, no?  Is there any reason to think that exercise of 
 religion might not be harmful?  I guess my question is 
 whether you see the harm done by religion as unprotected 
 because of  some constitutional reason (such as, it amounts 
 to establishment)?  Why would the religious motivation be 
 treated any differently than an anti-religious motivation, or 
 a commitment to Millian liberalism, or the will to power?  If 
 the protection for speech's harm, is that speech is good for 
 democracy, cannot one make the same argument about much, if 
 not all, religious exercise?
 
 (I'm not defending the principle that there is a right to 
 harm, only looking for consistency.)
 
 Thanks,
 Richard Dougherty
 
 
 Volokh, Eugene wrote (in part):
 
  The Free Speech Clause and other rights *are* rights to 
  inflict certain kinds of harm on others in certain ways 
 (for instance, 
  through the communicative impact of speech); we think that 
 for various 
  reasons, the government ought not be allowed to interfere with this 
  harm, perhaps because speech is so valuable to democratic 
  self-government, or because we suspect the government will 
 abuse its 
  regulatory powers.  Likewise, as I argue at 
  
 http://www1.law.ucla.edu/
~volokh/relfree.htm#Several%20Specific%20Proh
  ib
  itions%20on%20Government, in a few contexts (for instance,
  discrimination in hiring clergy, or religious frauds), the 
 Free Exercise
  Clause also allows religious people or institutions to 
 inflict what the
  law might otherwise treat as harm to others.
 
  But we ought not read the Free Exercise Clause as generally 
  licensing religious objectors to inflict harm on others (or 
 even to do 
  so subject to a possible strict scrutiny trump).  As I argue, my 
  relationship with my God may be important to me, but it can't by 
  itself be a constitutionally sufficient justification for 
 my harming 
  you, even slightly (for instance, by intentionally inflicting 
  emotional distress on you in secular ways, blocking access 
 to your property, or slightly
  vandalizing your commercial building).   From your 
 perspective and the
  legal system's perspective (even if not from my own), my God is my 
  God, not yours, and the Constitution doesn't give those 
 acting in His 
  name sovereignty over your legally recognized rights and interests.
 
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, 
 see http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be 
 viewed as private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read 
 messages that are posted; people can read the Web archives; 
 and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
 messages to others.
 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I'm not sure why it makes a lot of sense to severely limit the
extent to which courts measure the emotional distress caused by
religious expression (in contrast to other speech) -- why not severely
limit the extent to which courts impose liability on emotional distress
caused by speech, period?  If Senator Llynt gives a speech decrying the
political positions taken by Falwell, denouncing the alleged intrusion
of Falwell's theology into politics, and characterizing Falwell as a
generally bad person, it seems to me that he should be categorically
immune from IIED liability even if his speech is purely nonreligious.
If I'm right, then why is there any need for extra protection for
religious speech?

(I realize that there might be some situations where religious
speech is immune from liability because it's incapable of secular proof;
but generally the remedy there is to treat is the same as secular
opinions that are incapable of proof, which are constitutionally
protected,)

Eugene

Jim Maule writes:

 Suppose instead of Flynt satirizing Falwell, the Rev. Llynt 
 preaches a sermon in his progressive church decrying the 
 theological positions taken by Falwell, denouncing the 
 alleged intrusion of Falwell's theology into politics, and 
 characterizing Falwell as a modern-day Pharisee. The sermon 
 concludes that it is behavior and proselytization such as 
 that in which Falwell engages that continues to contribute to 
 the agony of Jesus on the Cross. The sermon is broadcast on 
 tv, radio, and/or the web (to get roughly the same 
 dissemination as Flynt managed with Hustler). Falwell is 
 understandably upset and emotionally distressed (assume that 
 it's just as distressing to him as were the comments about 
 his mother).
 
 Must Falwell meet a higher burden because the offending 
 speech is a religious sermon rather than a parody in a 
 secular publication? Should the courts get involved in the 
 modern equivalent of the 17th century pamphlet wars if one 
 or both of the parties alleges some sort of emotional 
 distress or other damage? Or should the courts do as 
 suggested the jury in Thomas Maule's trial: This is a matter 
 for a jury of divines.?
 
 I think it makes a lot of sense to severely limit the extent 
 to which courts measure the emotional distress caused by 
 religious expression (in contrast to other speech). 
 Otherwise, because religious expression also is a form of 
 free exercise, a back door is open to curtail the free 
 exercise rights of the speaker.
 
 Jim Maule
 Villanova University School of Law
 
  [EMAIL PROTECTED] 3/14/2005 4:36:01 PM 
 While free exercise and free speech may be different in many 
 respects, and indeed most constitutional rights differ from 
 all other rights, as they are not merely fungible from one to 
 another, I don't think Eugene Volokh's thoughtful 
 hypotheticals satisfactorily dispose of the argument that 
 free exercise and free speech ought not be treated 
 differently in the amount of burden that we accept (or the 
 courts ought to accept) upon the public or others.  The 
 problem with Eugene's hypotheticals, as I see it, is that the 
 burdens outlined are not comparable, in part because one 
 involves non-physical speech and the other involves conduct 
 (as Jim Maule observes), but also simply because of the 
 anticipated degree of negative impact upon persons other than 
 the one exercising the right.
 
 Just to look at the first pair of hypotheticals:  While Jerry 
 Falwell is postulated to have experienced emotional distress 
 as a result of both incidents, I submit that we intuitively 
 would recognize that the immediacy and intrusiveness of the 
 harm differs greatly when we compare reading a scurrilous 
 reference to one's self in a periodical with experiencing an 
 almost physical trespass accompanied by the use of loud 
 sounds that cannot easily be escaped and, perhaps most 
 importantly, that occurs at one's place of sanctuary, the 
 home.  Thus, while I agree that the free speech claim in that 
 pair of hypotheticals is stronger than the free exercise 
 claim, I don't see the two cases as truly comparable in terms 
 of the degree and perhaps the nature of the harm, even if 
 both forms of harm are generally categorized as emotional distress.
 
 Thus, for a set of hypotheticals comparing the strength of 
 free speech and free exercise claims to be truly comparable, 
 the nature or at least the degree of harm must also be 
 comparable.  While not neatly involving parallel factual 
 settings or messages, consider these two scenarios:  First, 
 we again have the offensive parody of Jerry Falwell in Larry 
 Flynt's Hustler magazine, in which Flynt invokes freedom of 
 speech as a defense against a claim for emotional distress.  
 Second, we have a homosexual couple that is rejected as 
 tenants by a homeowner of traditional religious values for 
 the spare room in her house, in which the homeowner invokes 
 free exercise 

Re: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread Steven Jamar

On Monday, March 14, 2005, at 06:20  PM, Volokh, Eugene wrote:

Rather, my argument is
that the Free Exercise Clause ought not be read as allowing people to do
things that harm others simply because they feel a religious obligation
to do those things.

So you would be against displays of the 10 commandments on free exercise grounds because of the of the psychic harm caused by them to others even though they are displayed as a result of a religious obligation?  And you would ban Mormons and JWs from stopping at my door just like all other peddlars -- if I could show psychic harm?  I guess I don't see where this leads us out of the wilderness any better than the current mish mash of principles, policies, and adjustments.

-- 
Prof. Steven D. Jamar   vox:  202-806-8017
Howard University School of Law fax:  202-806-8567
2900 Van Ness Street NW   mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Washington, DC  20008   http://www.law.howard.edu/faculty/pages/jamar/

Whenever you find yourself on the side of the majority, it is time to pause and reflect.

Mark Twain
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread James Maule
Compare You're going to get yours some day, and it could be within the
next minute (shouted, eyes bulging, face red, fists clenched, during
law conerence disputing whether a state should permit same-gender
marriages) with You're going to burn in hell and swim with the demons
some day, and it could be within the next minute because you never know
when God's going to call you to judgment (shouted, eyes bulging, face
red, fists clenched, during theological convention disputing whether a
denomination should sanctify same-gender marriages).

Recipient of speech in both instances sues, alleging emotional
distress, fear of harm, and physical manifestations thereof. Recipient
in both instances is a person who believes in the existence of hell and
for whom an eternal placement therein is a horrifying thought. Recipient
is also a person who dreads physical pain. If the first tirade is
construed as fighting words, is the second necessarily treated the same
way? I can see the same jury finding for the plaintiff in the first but
not in the second. Why? Because the second involves speech the meaning
of which is immersed in theological mystery (after all, who really knows
for sure?) whereas the first involves speeach the meaning of which is
immersed in a not so mysterious message of imminent physical threat.
Note that the conduct and principal issue are identical, but the
location, context, and participants differ (secular v. theological). 

Would you protect the speech in both cases? Not protect it in both
cases? Or leave open the possibility of different outcomes?

Jim Maule
Villanova University School of Law

 [EMAIL PROTECTED] 3/14/2005 6:23:40 PM 
I'm not sure why it makes a lot of sense to severely limit the
extent to which courts measure the emotional distress caused by
religious expression (in contrast to other speech) -- why not
severely
limit the extent to which courts impose liability on emotional
distress
caused by speech, period?  If Senator Llynt gives a speech decrying
the
political positions taken by Falwell, denouncing the alleged intrusion
of Falwell's theology into politics, and characterizing Falwell as a
generally bad person, it seems to me that he should be categorically
immune from IIED liability even if his speech is purely nonreligious.
If I'm right, then why is there any need for extra protection for
religious speech?

(I realize that there might be some situations where religious
speech is immune from liability because it's incapable of secular
proof;
but generally the remedy there is to treat is the same as secular
opinions that are incapable of proof, which are constitutionally
protected,)

Eugene

Jim Maule writes:

 Suppose instead of Flynt satirizing Falwell, the Rev. Llynt 
 preaches a sermon in his progressive church decrying the 
 theological positions taken by Falwell, denouncing the 
 alleged intrusion of Falwell's theology into politics, and 
 characterizing Falwell as a modern-day Pharisee. The sermon 
 concludes that it is behavior and proselytization such as 
 that in which Falwell engages that continues to contribute to 
 the agony of Jesus on the Cross. The sermon is broadcast on 
 tv, radio, and/or the web (to get roughly the same 
 dissemination as Flynt managed with Hustler). Falwell is 
 understandably upset and emotionally distressed (assume that 
 it's just as distressing to him as were the comments about 
 his mother).
 
 Must Falwell meet a higher burden because the offending 
 speech is a religious sermon rather than a parody in a 
 secular publication? Should the courts get involved in the 
 modern equivalent of the 17th century pamphlet wars if one 
 or both of the parties alleges some sort of emotional 
 distress or other damage? Or should the courts do as 
 suggested the jury in Thomas Maule's trial: This is a matter 
 for a jury of divines.?
 
 I think it makes a lot of sense to severely limit the extent 
 to which courts measure the emotional distress caused by 
 religious expression (in contrast to other speech). 
 Otherwise, because religious expression also is a form of 
 free exercise, a back door is open to curtail the free 
 exercise rights of the speaker.
 
 Jim Maule
 Villanova University School of Law
 
  [EMAIL PROTECTED] 3/14/2005 4:36:01 PM 
 While free exercise and free speech may be different in many 
 respects, and indeed most constitutional rights differ from 
 all other rights, as they are not merely fungible from one to 
 another, I don't think Eugene Volokh's thoughtful 
 hypotheticals satisfactorily dispose of the argument that 
 free exercise and free speech ought not be treated 
 differently in the amount of burden that we accept (or the 
 courts ought to accept) upon the public or others.  The 
 problem with Eugene's hypotheticals, as I see it, is that the 
 burdens outlined are not comparable, in part because one 
 involves non-physical speech and the other involves conduct 
 (as Jim Maule observes), but also simply 

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I suspect that the distinction here isn't religious speech vs.
secular speech and more (1) speech that sounds like warning of action by
others who are unrelated to the speakers vs. (2) speech that sounds like
warning of action by the speaker or his confederates.  If a mother is
really angry at a child and says You're going to get killed if you use
drugs / run around with bad kids / do other dangerous stuff, we
wouldn't treat that as a threat, because it's clearly a warning of what
others might do.  Conversely, God is going to call you to judgment
soon might well be a threat if in context it's pretty clear that the
person is conveying a message that he or his confederates might be the
tools that God uses for this call.  More broadly, there surely shouldn't
be unqualified Free Exercise Clause protection for all threats that are
religiously motivated, no?

Eugene

Jim Maule writes:

 Compare You're going to get yours some day, and it could be 
 within the next minute (shouted, eyes bulging, face red, 
 fists clenched, during law conerence disputing whether a 
 state should permit same-gender
 marriages) with You're going to burn in hell and swim with 
 the demons some day, and it could be within the next minute 
 because you never know when God's going to call you to 
 judgment (shouted, eyes bulging, face red, fists clenched, 
 during theological convention disputing whether a 
 denomination should sanctify same-gender marriages).
 
 Recipient of speech in both instances sues, alleging 
 emotional distress, fear of harm, and physical manifestations 
 thereof. Recipient in both instances is a person who believes 
 in the existence of hell and for whom an eternal placement 
 therein is a horrifying thought. Recipient is also a person 
 who dreads physical pain. If the first tirade is construed as 
 fighting words, is the second necessarily treated the same 
 way? I can see the same jury finding for the plaintiff in the 
 first but not in the second. Why? Because the second involves 
 speech the meaning of which is immersed in theological 
 mystery (after all, who really knows for sure?) whereas the 
 first involves speeach the meaning of which is immersed in a 
 not so mysterious message of imminent physical threat. Note 
 that the conduct and principal issue are identical, but the 
 location, context, and participants differ (secular v. theological). 
 
 Would you protect the speech in both cases? Not protect it in 
 both cases? Or leave open the possibility of different outcomes?
 
 Jim Maule
 Villanova University School of Law
 
  [EMAIL PROTECTED] 3/14/2005 6:23:40 PM 
   I'm not sure why it makes a lot of sense to severely 
 limit the extent to which courts measure the emotional 
 distress caused by religious expression (in contrast to other 
 speech) -- why not severely limit the extent to which courts 
 impose liability on emotional distress caused by speech, 
 period?  If Senator Llynt gives a speech decrying the 
 political positions taken by Falwell, denouncing the alleged 
 intrusion of Falwell's theology into politics, and 
 characterizing Falwell as a generally bad person, it seems to 
 me that he should be categorically immune from IIED liability 
 even if his speech is purely nonreligious. If I'm right, then 
 why is there any need for extra protection for religious speech?
 
   (I realize that there might be some situations where 
 religious speech is immune from liability because it's 
 incapable of secular proof; but generally the remedy there is 
 to treat is the same as secular opinions that are incapable 
 of proof, which are constitutionally
 protected,)
 
   Eugene
 
 Jim Maule writes:
 
  Suppose instead of Flynt satirizing Falwell, the Rev. Llynt
  preaches a sermon in his progressive church decrying the 
  theological positions taken by Falwell, denouncing the 
  alleged intrusion of Falwell's theology into politics, and 
  characterizing Falwell as a modern-day Pharisee. The sermon 
  concludes that it is behavior and proselytization such as 
  that in which Falwell engages that continues to contribute to 
  the agony of Jesus on the Cross. The sermon is broadcast on 
  tv, radio, and/or the web (to get roughly the same 
  dissemination as Flynt managed with Hustler). Falwell is 
  understandably upset and emotionally distressed (assume that 
  it's just as distressing to him as were the comments about 
  his mother).
  
  Must Falwell meet a higher burden because the offending
  speech is a religious sermon rather than a parody in a 
  secular publication? Should the courts get involved in the 
  modern equivalent of the 17th century pamphlet wars if one 
  or both of the parties alleges some sort of emotional 
  distress or other damage? Or should the courts do as 
  suggested the jury in Thomas Maule's trial: This is a matter 
  for a jury of divines.?
  
  I think it makes a lot of sense to severely limit the extent
  to which courts measure the 

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Title: Message



 (1) I don't think anything I've said 
suggests that displays of the Ten Commandments by nongovernmental actors could 
be restrictable. They are just as protected by the freedom of speech as 
displays of any other sentiments. (Whether governmental actors may display 
the Ten Commandments is of course a matter of the Establishment Clause 
constraints on the government.)

 (2) I think that the Free Speech Clause protects Mormons' 
and Jehovah's Witnesses' ability to express their views precisely to the same 
extent that it protects Greenpeace's or the Libertarians' ability. Given 
Martin v. Struthers, both are protected if the householder hasn't put up a No 
Soliciting sign, and both are unprotected if the householder has put up a No 
Soliciting sign. See also Heffron v. ISKCON, holding, even during the 
Sherbert/Yoder era, that the Free Exercise Clause gave no more protection to 
religious speech than the Free Speech Clause gives to speech generally (and thus 
applying intermediate scrutiny rather than strict scrutiny to a Free Exercise 
Clause challenge to a content-neutral speech restriction).

 (3) A simple and plausible example: Operation Rescue 
decides, because of their religious beliefs,to picket an abortion 
provider's home. A pro-choice group decides, because of their nonreligious 
political beliefs,to picket the Operation Rescue leader's home. 
Could Operation Rescue really have broader speech rights than the pro-choice 
group -- with the Operation Rescue claim being subject to strict scrutiny, and 
the pro-choice group's being subject only to intermediate scrutiny (see Frisby 
v. Schultz) -- because Operation Rescue has a religious motivation for its 
speech? I would think the answer is no.

 Eugene

Steve Jamar 
writes:

  
  -Original Message-From: 
  [EMAIL PROTECTED] [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
  On Behalf Of Steven JamarSent: Monday, March 14, 2005 3:52 
  PMTo: Law  Religion issues for Law 
  AcademicsSubject: Re: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to 
  others
  On Monday, March 14, 2005, at 06:20 PM, Volokh, Eugene wrote: 
  
Rather, my argument is 
that the Free Exercise Clause ought not be read as allowing people to 
do 
things that harm others simply because they feel a religious obligation 

to do those things. 
  So you would be against displays of the 10 commandments on free exercise 
  grounds because of the of the psychic harm caused by them to others even 
  though they are displayed as a result of a religious obligation? And you would 
  ban Mormons and JWs from stopping at my door just like all other peddlars -- 
  if I could show psychic harm? I guess I don't see where this leads us out of 
  the wilderness any better than the current mish mash of principles, policies, 
  and adjustments. 
  
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread Sisk, Gregory C.
I accept Eugene's observation that my comparison cases suffer from
inadequate similarity comparison purposes.  Perhaps at some point I'll try
harder to develop less inferior paired hypotheticals to better express my
point (perhaps that task will seem more appealing in a few weeks when I'm
grading blue books).

But I still am not convinced either (1) that a greater degree of burden from
speech is acceptable because freedom of speech is a more robust
constitutional right than free exercise, or (2) that the harms identified in
the Flynt/Glynt hypotheticals are truly comparable and thus illustrate the
point.  Indeed, in the Glynt hypothetical, if Mary Glynt engaged in the same
expression by bull-horn at the house window but offered a free speech rather
than free exercise justification, the result would be the same -- she still
would lose.  Thus, it isn't the nature of the right that explains the
differing results but something about the nature of the intrusion or the
harm or the presence or absence of an attenuated link between them.

Along these same lines, I'm persuaded that Eugene has a point that we permit
a larger range of expression under freedom of speech than conduct under free
exercise.  But isn't that in part because speech is different from conduct
(as Jim Maule suggested) rather than because the constitutional rights
underlying one or the other are at different points in the hierarchy of
constitutional values?  While speech may and sometimes does cause harm, it
almost always does so indirectly, as it depends for efficacy upon persuading
someone else that the message is credible or that a response should be made.
Thus, speech that is harmful depends upon a chain from the speaker through
the medium to a recipient who in turn chooses to respond in a manner that
induces harm to the recipient or someone else.  Even speech that is intended
to cause harm may prove ineffective due to breaks in the chain, especially
if the recipient finds it uninteresting or unpersuasive. By contrast,
conduct -- whether expressive in nature or not -- is immediate and if that
conduct is harmful, the harm is rather directly realized.

And related to that, I still think -- although my clumsy hypotheticals may
not have illustrated it well -- that the harms involved may be different in
nature or degree.  While one subjectively and understandably might regard
being slandered before millions of readers as a greater source of distress
than being momentarily accosted at one's home by a loud protester, the law
always has treated a physical invasion as different from an emotional
response, even an induced emotional response.  Indeed, some strains of law
even today still preclude recovery in tort for emotional distress that is
unaccompanied by physical injury.  If there is anything to what I'm trying
to say here, would it not follow that different treatment of the trespasser
who asserts a free exercise defense from the magazine writer who claims
freedom of speech turns not upon which actor invokes which constitutional
protection but rather upon the nature of the impact caused by the underlying
conduct/expression?

Greg Sisk



-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Monday, March 14, 2005 3:57 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

I appreciate Greg's thoughtful analysis, but I think that
ultimately the magnitude of the burden on the nonspeaker's/nonclaimant's
rights doesn't resolve the problems.  I would feel *much* more
distressed by knowing that millions (?) of people are reading about how
I supposedly had sex with my mother in an outhouse (even if they know
it's a gag) than by a few nights of loud noise outside my house.

Likewise, I suspect that the more-or-less three-year-long
boycott in Claiborne Hardware affected local businesses more than the
occasional blockage would affect the business of an abortion clinic.
It's true that this may be so because the boycott went on for a long
time, while the blockage in my hypothetical wouldn't.  But under free
speech law, even speech urging a long boycott can't be punished -- and
even one instance of entrance blockage, which would cause vastly less
damage than the boycott, would be punishable, whether or not it's
religiously based.  So people are constitutionally entitled to inflict
considerably greater harms through the communicative impact of their
speech than through the religiously motivated conduct.  Or am I mistaken
here?

As to the housing discrimination scenario, I just think Greg's
comparison cases are actually not terribly similar.  The gay couple's
claim isn't necessarily that they're deeply emotionally distressed --
rather, it is that they have a legal right to equal treatment,
regardless of whether the unequal treatment is terribly distressing.
Maybe this right flows from a general sense that the unequal treatment
is usually distressing

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread James Maule
OK, I see your point and it helps me refine the hypo:

1. I pray I can find someone to put an end to your annoying existence
on this planet.

2. I pray to God every night that somehow the angel of death visits
you and puts an end to your annoying existence on this planet.

Assuming that the recipient of the words doesn't treat #2 as a
silliness (e.g. reaction of an athiest) but has a theological
perspective that makes it upsetting and emotionally distressful, ought
not #2 be protected and #1 actionable (assuming a showing of damage or
injury, etc.)? Is it because the second is unprovable to a purely
rational mind? Would it be on account of #2 being religiously motivated?
(By religiously motivated, do you mean the motivation for the belief
that the threat can be made, or the underlying dispute that generates
the felt need to make the threat? I'm assuming the first, but perhaps
I'm misreading your explanation.)

Jim Maule

 [EMAIL PROTECTED] 3/14/2005 7:08:23 PM 
I suspect that the distinction here isn't religious speech vs.
secular speech and more (1) speech that sounds like warning of action
by
others who are unrelated to the speakers vs. (2) speech that sounds
like
warning of action by the speaker or his confederates.  If a mother is
really angry at a child and says You're going to get killed if you
use
drugs / run around with bad kids / do other dangerous stuff, we
wouldn't treat that as a threat, because it's clearly a warning of
what
others might do.  Conversely, God is going to call you to judgment
soon might well be a threat if in context it's pretty clear that the
person is conveying a message that he or his confederates might be the
tools that God uses for this call.  More broadly, there surely
shouldn't
be unqualified Free Exercise Clause protection for all threats that
are
religiously motivated, no?

Eugene

Jim Maule writes:

 Compare You're going to get yours some day, and it could be 
 within the next minute (shouted, eyes bulging, face red, 
 fists clenched, during law conerence disputing whether a 
 state should permit same-gender
 marriages) with You're going to burn in hell and swim with 
 the demons some day, and it could be within the next minute 
 because you never know when God's going to call you to 
 judgment (shouted, eyes bulging, face red, fists clenched, 
 during theological convention disputing whether a 
 denomination should sanctify same-gender marriages).
 
 Recipient of speech in both instances sues, alleging 
 emotional distress, fear of harm, and physical manifestations 
 thereof. Recipient in both instances is a person who believes 
 in the existence of hell and for whom an eternal placement 
 therein is a horrifying thought. Recipient is also a person 
 who dreads physical pain. If the first tirade is construed as 
 fighting words, is the second necessarily treated the same 
 way? I can see the same jury finding for the plaintiff in the 
 first but not in the second. Why? Because the second involves 
 speech the meaning of which is immersed in theological 
 mystery (after all, who really knows for sure?) whereas the 
 first involves speeach the meaning of which is immersed in a 
 not so mysterious message of imminent physical threat. Note 
 that the conduct and principal issue are identical, but the 
 location, context, and participants differ (secular v. theological).

 
 Would you protect the speech in both cases? Not protect it in 
 both cases? Or leave open the possibility of different outcomes?
 
 Jim Maule
 Villanova University School of Law
 
  [EMAIL PROTECTED] 3/14/2005 6:23:40 PM 
   I'm not sure why it makes a lot of sense to severely 
 limit the extent to which courts measure the emotional 
 distress caused by religious expression (in contrast to other 
 speech) -- why not severely limit the extent to which courts 
 impose liability on emotional distress caused by speech, 
 period?  If Senator Llynt gives a speech decrying the 
 political positions taken by Falwell, denouncing the alleged 
 intrusion of Falwell's theology into politics, and 
 characterizing Falwell as a generally bad person, it seems to 
 me that he should be categorically immune from IIED liability 
 even if his speech is purely nonreligious. If I'm right, then 
 why is there any need for extra protection for religious speech?
 
   (I realize that there might be some situations where 
 religious speech is immune from liability because it's 
 incapable of secular proof; but generally the remedy there is 
 to treat is the same as secular opinions that are incapable 
 of proof, which are constitutionally
 protected,)
 
   Eugene
 
 Jim Maule writes:
 
  Suppose instead of Flynt satirizing Falwell, the Rev. Llynt
  preaches a sermon in his progressive church decrying the 
  theological positions taken by Falwell, denouncing the 
  alleged intrusion of Falwell's theology into politics, and 
  characterizing Falwell as a modern-day Pharisee. The sermon 
  concludes 

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I think the question in either case would be (1) whether the
listener would reasonably understand this as a threat of attack by the
speaker or the speaker's confederates and (2) whether the speaker
intended to put the listener in fear of such attack (see Virginia v.
Black).  So it's possible that #2 would indeed be a threat, and that #1
would not be, depending on what else the listener knows about the
speaker.  If the speaker or his buddies are suspected of killing other
annoying people, for instance, statement #2 might well be punishable.

Consider this statement:  This is a really nice restaurant you
have here, except for those blasphemous pictures on the walls.  It would
be a shame if God caused it to burn down.  Other neighboring
restaurants have in fact burned down after they refused to take down
blasphemous pictures.  The speaker is religiously motivated (which I
take it is the test for a Sherbert/Yoder-era free exercise claim), and
as it happens the underlying dispute, as well as the language of the
statement, are religious.  If the speaker intends to make the listener
afraid of burning by the speaker or his confederates, and a reasonable
listener would have this fear, then it seems to me that this is a
punishable threat.

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of James Maule
 Sent: Monday, March 14, 2005 5:38 PM
 To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Subject: RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others
 
 
 OK, I see your point and it helps me refine the hypo:
 
 1. I pray I can find someone to put an end to your annoying 
 existence on this planet.
 
 2. I pray to God every night that somehow the angel of death 
 visits you and puts an end to your annoying existence on this planet.
 
 Assuming that the recipient of the words doesn't treat #2 as 
 a silliness (e.g. reaction of an athiest) but has a 
 theological perspective that makes it upsetting and 
 emotionally distressful, ought not #2 be protected and #1 
 actionable (assuming a showing of damage or injury, etc.)? Is 
 it because the second is unprovable to a purely rational 
 mind? Would it be on account of #2 being religiously 
 motivated? (By religiously motivated, do you mean the 
 motivation for the belief that the threat can be made, or the 
 underlying dispute that generates the felt need to make the 
 threat? I'm assuming the first, but perhaps I'm misreading 
 your explanation.)
 
 Jim Maule
 
  [EMAIL PROTECTED] 3/14/2005 7:08:23 PM 
   I suspect that the distinction here isn't religious 
 speech vs. secular speech and more (1) speech that sounds 
 like warning of action by others who are unrelated to the 
 speakers vs. (2) speech that sounds like warning of action by 
 the speaker or his confederates.  If a mother is really angry 
 at a child and says You're going to get killed if you use 
 drugs / run around with bad kids / do other dangerous stuff, 
 we wouldn't treat that as a threat, because it's clearly a 
 warning of what others might do.  Conversely, God is going 
 to call you to judgment soon might well be a threat if in 
 context it's pretty clear that the person is conveying a 
 message that he or his confederates might be the tools that 
 God uses for this call.  More broadly, there surely shouldn't 
 be unqualified Free Exercise Clause protection for all 
 threats that are religiously motivated, no?
 
   Eugene
 
 Jim Maule writes:
 
  Compare You're going to get yours some day, and it could be
  within the next minute (shouted, eyes bulging, face red, 
  fists clenched, during law conerence disputing whether a 
  state should permit same-gender
  marriages) with You're going to burn in hell and swim with 
  the demons some day, and it could be within the next minute 
  because you never know when God's going to call you to 
  judgment (shouted, eyes bulging, face red, fists clenched, 
  during theological convention disputing whether a 
  denomination should sanctify same-gender marriages).
  
  Recipient of speech in both instances sues, alleging
  emotional distress, fear of harm, and physical manifestations 
  thereof. Recipient in both instances is a person who believes 
  in the existence of hell and for whom an eternal placement 
  therein is a horrifying thought. Recipient is also a person 
  who dreads physical pain. If the first tirade is construed as 
  fighting words, is the second necessarily treated the same 
  way? I can see the same jury finding for the plaintiff in the 
  first but not in the second. Why? Because the second involves 
  speech the meaning of which is immersed in theological 
  mystery (after all, who really knows for sure?) whereas the 
  first involves speeach the meaning of which is immersed in a 
  not so mysterious message of imminent physical threat. Note 
  that the conduct and principal issue are identical, but the 
  location, context, and participants differ (secular v. theological).
 
  
  Would you

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread James Maule
Suppose the statement was a wee bit different: This is a really nice
restaurant you have here, except for those blasphemous pictures on the
walls.  It would be a shame if God caused it to burn down, for example,
by causing lightning to strike or a meteor fragment to hit, which I pray
every day God will do if you don't let God answer my other prayer that
you see the light and take down those pictures. And assume there hasn't
been a previous history of restaurants burning down. Much preaching
contains the not-so-veiled threat of divine retribution. So in this case
the speech has to be protected.

Now suppose a few days later an unexplained fire destroys the
restaurant. Shortly before a thunderstorm. Speaker argues her prayers
were answered. Case probably dismissed on basis of failure of proof.

Then it happens again. And again. At some point the coincidences become
too much. So does protected speech lose its protection based on the
track record of previous speech? By the same person? By confederates?
By proselytizers of another denomination or sect? 

Jim Maule

 [EMAIL PROTECTED] 3/14/2005 10:33:25 PM 
I think the question in either case would be (1) whether the
listener would reasonably understand this as a threat of attack by the
speaker or the speaker's confederates and (2) whether the speaker
intended to put the listener in fear of such attack (see Virginia v.
Black).  So it's possible that #2 would indeed be a threat, and that
#1
would not be, depending on what else the listener knows about the
speaker.  If the speaker or his buddies are suspected of killing other
annoying people, for instance, statement #2 might well be punishable.

Consider this statement:  This is a really nice restaurant you
have here, except for those blasphemous pictures on the walls.  It
would
be a shame if God caused it to burn down.  Other neighboring
restaurants have in fact burned down after they refused to take down
blasphemous pictures.  The speaker is religiously motivated (which I
take it is the test for a Sherbert/Yoder-era free exercise claim), and
as it happens the underlying dispute, as well as the language of the
statement, are religious.  If the speaker intends to make the listener
afraid of burning by the speaker or his confederates, and a reasonable
listener would have this fear, then it seems to me that this is a
punishable threat.

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of James Maule
 Sent: Monday, March 14, 2005 5:38 PM
 To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu 
 Subject: RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others
 
 
 OK, I see your point and it helps me refine the hypo:
 
 1. I pray I can find someone to put an end to your annoying 
 existence on this planet.
 
 2. I pray to God every night that somehow the angel of death 
 visits you and puts an end to your annoying existence on this
planet.
 
 Assuming that the recipient of the words doesn't treat #2 as 
 a silliness (e.g. reaction of an athiest) but has a 
 theological perspective that makes it upsetting and 
 emotionally distressful, ought not #2 be protected and #1 
 actionable (assuming a showing of damage or injury, etc.)? Is 
 it because the second is unprovable to a purely rational 
 mind? Would it be on account of #2 being religiously 
 motivated? (By religiously motivated, do you mean the 
 motivation for the belief that the threat can be made, or the 
 underlying dispute that generates the felt need to make the 
 threat? I'm assuming the first, but perhaps I'm misreading 
 your explanation.)
 
 Jim Maule
 
  [EMAIL PROTECTED] 3/14/2005 7:08:23 PM 
   I suspect that the distinction here isn't religious 
 speech vs. secular speech and more (1) speech that sounds 
 like warning of action by others who are unrelated to the 
 speakers vs. (2) speech that sounds like warning of action by 
 the speaker or his confederates.  If a mother is really angry 
 at a child and says You're going to get killed if you use 
 drugs / run around with bad kids / do other dangerous stuff, 
 we wouldn't treat that as a threat, because it's clearly a 
 warning of what others might do.  Conversely, God is going 
 to call you to judgment soon might well be a threat if in 
 context it's pretty clear that the person is conveying a 
 message that he or his confederates might be the tools that 
 God uses for this call.  More broadly, there surely shouldn't 
 be unqualified Free Exercise Clause protection for all 
 threats that are religiously motivated, no?
 
   Eugene
 
 Jim Maule writes:
 
  Compare You're going to get yours some day, and it could be
  within the next minute (shouted, eyes bulging, face red, 
  fists clenched, during law conerence disputing whether a 
  state should permit same-gender
  marriages) with You're going to burn in hell and swim with 
  the demons some day, and it could be within the next minute 
  because you never know when God's going to call you to 
  judgment (shouted

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
My analysis:  Warning of bad behavior by others, who are
genuinely unrelated to the speaker, and who are understood by listeners
to be unrelated to the speaker is protected.  Warning of retribution by
God is thus not a threat -- but neither is warning of retribution by
religious zealots, if it's clear from context that the zealots aren't
the speaker or his confederates.

Warning of bad behavior by yourself or by your confederates is
unprotected.  Warning of retribution is thus a threat, if it's intended
to and reasonably likely to lead the listener to think that you or your
confederates will act as God's agents in this.

This may well leave lots of questions about when ambiguous
warnings are really warnings of future misconduct by the speaker or his
confederates.  But that's true whether you're warning of retaliation by
God or by others.

A closing set of examples:
1.  Don't have promiscuous sex, or else God will strike you
dead.
2.  Don't have promiscuous sex, or else you'll die of AIDS.
3.  Don't have promiscuous sex, or else your crazy cousin will
kill you.  (Assume that the speaker is unconnected to the cousin.)
4.  Don't have promiscuous sex, cousin, because I'll kill you
to wipe off the stain from our family honor.
5.  Don't have promiscuous sex, cousin, because God will strike
you dead.  (Assume that other people the listeners know have been
killed under mysterious circumstances, and it's assumed that these were
honor killings by family.)

Seems to me that #1-3 are protected and #4-5 are unprotected;
the relevant distinction isn't the religiosity of the motivation or the
statement, but the items I mention above.

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of James Maule
 Sent: Monday, March 14, 2005 7:52 PM
 To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Subject: RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others
 
 
 Suppose the statement was a wee bit different: This is a
 really nice restaurant you have here, except for those 
 blasphemous pictures on the walls.  It would be a shame if 
 God caused it to burn down, for example, by causing lightning 
 to strike or a meteor fragment to hit, which I pray every day 
 God will do if you don't let God answer my other prayer that 
 you see the light and take down those pictures. And assume 
 there hasn't been a previous history of restaurants burning 
 down. Much preaching contains the not-so-veiled threat of 
 divine retribution. So in this case the speech has to be protected.
 
 Now suppose a few days later an unexplained fire destroys the
 restaurant. Shortly before a thunderstorm. Speaker argues her 
 prayers were answered. Case probably dismissed on basis of 
 failure of proof.
 
 Then it happens again. And again. At some point the
 coincidences become too much. So does protected speech lose 
 its protection based on the track record of previous 
 speech? By the same person? By confederates? By proselytizers 
 of another denomination or sect? 
 
 Jim Maule
 
  [EMAIL PROTECTED] 3/14/2005 10:33:25 PM 
   I think the question in either case would be (1)
 whether the listener would reasonably understand this as a 
 threat of attack by the speaker or the speaker's confederates 
 and (2) whether the speaker intended to put the listener in 
 fear of such attack (see Virginia v. Black).  So it's 
 possible that #2 would indeed be a threat, and that #1 would 
 not be, depending on what else the listener knows about the 
 speaker.  If the speaker or his buddies are suspected of 
 killing other annoying people, for instance, statement #2 
 might well be punishable.
 
   Consider this statement:  This is a really nice
 restaurant you have here, except for those blasphemous 
 pictures on the walls.  It would be a shame if God caused it 
 to burn down.  Other neighboring restaurants have in fact 
 burned down after they refused to take down blasphemous 
 pictures.  The speaker is religiously motivated (which I take 
 it is the test for a Sherbert/Yoder-era free exercise claim), 
 and as it happens the underlying dispute, as well as the 
 language of the statement, are religious.  If the speaker 
 intends to make the listener afraid of burning by the speaker 
 or his confederates, and a reasonable listener would have 
 this fear, then it seems to me that this is a punishable threat.
 
  -Original Message-
  From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
  [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of James Maule
  Sent: Monday, March 14, 2005 5:38 PM
  To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
  Subject: RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others
  
  
  OK, I see your point and it helps me refine the hypo:
  
  1. I pray I can find someone to put an end to your annoying 
  existence on this planet.
  
  2. I pray to God every night that somehow the angel of death visits

  you and puts an end to your annoying existence on this
 planet.
  
  Assuming

RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others

2005-03-14 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I actually agree with Greg on much here:  The reason that we
allow people to inflict various harms on others via their speech has a
lot to do with *the way* the harm is inflicted:  When harm is inflicted
by persuading, informing, or offending people with the content of
speech, we treat that infliction of harm as privileged.

And that's the reason that I think it's a mistake to say (and
Greg hasn't said it, but I think others have), The Free Speech Clause
caselaw gives people the constitutional right to harm others through
speech, so the Free Exercise Clause should be interpreted as giving
people the constitutional right to harm others through religiously
motivated conduct.  The Free Speech Clause caselaw lets people harm
others through some specific speech-related ways.  It doesn't follow
that the Free Exercise Clause lets people harm others in other ways --
whether through discriminating against them, trespassing on their
property, breaching contracts, and so on, even if the harms are
comparatively minor.

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Sisk, Gregory C.
 Sent: Monday, March 14, 2005 5:15 PM
 To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
 Subject: RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others
 
 
 I accept Eugene's observation that my comparison cases suffer 
 from inadequate similarity comparison purposes.  Perhaps at 
 some point I'll try harder to develop less inferior paired 
 hypotheticals to better express my point (perhaps that task 
 will seem more appealing in a few weeks when I'm grading blue books).
 
 But I still am not convinced either (1) that a greater degree 
 of burden from speech is acceptable because freedom of speech 
 is a more robust constitutional right than free exercise, or 
 (2) that the harms identified in the Flynt/Glynt 
 hypotheticals are truly comparable and thus illustrate the 
 point.  Indeed, in the Glynt hypothetical, if Mary Glynt 
 engaged in the same expression by bull-horn at the house 
 window but offered a free speech rather than free exercise 
 justification, the result would be the same -- she still 
 would lose.  Thus, it isn't the nature of the right that 
 explains the differing results but something about the nature 
 of the intrusion or the harm or the presence or absence of an 
 attenuated link between them.
 
 Along these same lines, I'm persuaded that Eugene has a point 
 that we permit a larger range of expression under freedom of 
 speech than conduct under free exercise.  But isn't that in 
 part because speech is different from conduct (as Jim Maule 
 suggested) rather than because the constitutional rights 
 underlying one or the other are at different points in the 
 hierarchy of constitutional values?  While speech may and 
 sometimes does cause harm, it almost always does so 
 indirectly, as it depends for efficacy upon persuading 
 someone else that the message is credible or that a response 
 should be made. Thus, speech that is harmful depends upon a 
 chain from the speaker through the medium to a recipient who 
 in turn chooses to respond in a manner that induces harm to 
 the recipient or someone else.  Even speech that is intended 
 to cause harm may prove ineffective due to breaks in the 
 chain, especially if the recipient finds it uninteresting or 
 unpersuasive. By contrast, conduct -- whether expressive in 
 nature or not -- is immediate and if that conduct is harmful, 
 the harm is rather directly realized.
 
 And related to that, I still think -- although my clumsy 
 hypotheticals may not have illustrated it well -- that the 
 harms involved may be different in nature or degree.  While 
 one subjectively and understandably might regard being 
 slandered before millions of readers as a greater source of 
 distress than being momentarily accosted at one's home by a 
 loud protester, the law always has treated a physical 
 invasion as different from an emotional response, even an 
 induced emotional response.  Indeed, some strains of law even 
 today still preclude recovery in tort for emotional distress 
 that is unaccompanied by physical injury.  If there is 
 anything to what I'm trying to say here, would it not follow 
 that different treatment of the trespasser who asserts a free 
 exercise defense from the magazine writer who claims freedom 
 of speech turns not upon which actor invokes which 
 constitutional protection but rather upon the nature of the 
 impact caused by the underlying conduct/expression?
 
 Greg Sisk
 
 
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 Sent: Monday, March 14, 2005 3:57 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Free Exercise, Free Speech, and harm to others
 
   I appreciate Greg's thoughtful analysis, but I think 
 that ultimately the magnitude of the burden on the 
 nonspeaker's/nonclaimant's rights doesn't resolve the 
 problems.  I would