On Sat, 29 Dec 2007 20:31:13 -0800 CLAY SHENTRUP wrote: > On Dec 29, 2007 7:03 PM, Dave Ketchum <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> wrote: > >>Somehow we are not talking the same language. >> >>An example that could be executed, with voters each splitting candidates >>into two groups (as many as they choose into each) and voting via: >> Approval, using its full capability of approving vs not approving. >> Condorcet, with voters restricting themselves to rank 1 vs not ranked. >> Range, with voters restricting themselves to max rating vs not rated. >> >>Approval's full capability is used here. >> >>Condorcet and Range each have other abilities not used in this demo. > > > yes, but condorcet (and many other methods) allow voters to employ > strategies that can actually diminish the extent to which the election > satisfies "my" preferences, even if they give "me" more apparent > expressiveness on my ballot. ("me", meaning "joe blow") > > as for range voting, you are correct, but as i recall, i was promoting > approval in contrast to rank-order methods. > My point is that, whatever Approval can do, the other methods are also capable of doing.
Certainly the other methods have abilities not used in this demo. > >>BUT, Approval has no way to express intensity. > > > of course it does. if you and i both prefer X>Y>Z, but i like Y more > than the average of X and Z, and you like Y less than the average of X > and Z, then i'll vote for both X and Y, and you'll just vote for X. > it's what is called "revealed preference" in ecenomics - we are forced > to say something about the relative intensity of our support for Y, > even though we have the same ordered preferences. > That might reveal a bit, though even that not clearly. BUT, assuming I want to indicate preference of X and Y over Z, Approval can show my less liking for Z, but cannot, in the same vote, indicate my relative preference as to X vs Y. > >>Where does Approval have a limit on quantity of comparisons? > > > if we have n candidates, a ranked method allows n(n-1) head-to-head > comparisons to be expressed. approval allows, at most, (n^2)/4 > > so with 4 candidates, for example, a ranked method allows the > expression of 12 comparisons, whereas approval allows a maximum of 4. > I am getting dizzy. With 4 candidates, how do you come up with more than 6 pairs to even consider comparing? > >>How does Approval qualify as having ratings vs ranks? It is too simple to >>reasonably care. > > > this is a non-controversial fact of election theory. approval voting > is cardinal. it only allows us to classify each candidate into a > predefined set of (2) categories, but does not restrict how many > candidates may go into any of those categories. if we look at > plurality, for instance, there are two categories, "voted for" and > "not voted for", but you may place only one candidate in the "voted > for" category. with RCV (with 3 candidates allowed) you have 4 > "categories", first, second, third, and non-ranked. again, you can > only place 1 candidate in 3 of those categories. of course, we might > then ask if equal rankings would make RCV a cardinal method. it gets > fuzzier. maybe a concrete definition is this. a voting method is > cardinal if it complies with iia, as the votes are cast. i could be > totally wrong, and maybe there's a simple strict definition. > REALLY dizzy now. "RCV (with 3 candidates allowed)"? Is this from some definition I have not seen, or something that seemed to make sense in the above statement? > >>Costs deserve more attention than some offer. Still, voters being able to >>express their desires, and be understood, is a non-trivial topic. > > > that is measured by social utility efficiency, and approval is better > in that regard than ranked methods. there are some ranked methods > that can apparently satisfy expressed preferences better than > approval, but they have externalities (what rob brown likes to talk > about) that cause problems - if we're talking about public adoption at > least. > > >> > rank-order voting methods are chaff. >>How and why? > > > utility efficiency and complexity/adoptibility. to quote from william > poundstone's forthcoming booking _gaming the vote_ > > "The profession dealing with collective choice is just about > completely dysfunctional," Hillinger said, "from the point of view of > dealing with the social problem that they are ostensibly dealing > with." That "social problem" is of course making our elections > fairer. To have any chance of solving the problem it is necessary to > recognize the gaping chasm between what Arrow's theorem says and what > people thought it meant. The impossibility theorem is poised on the > knife's edge of truth. Frame the problem exactly the way Arrow did, > and rational democracy is "impossible". Drop the obsession with > ranking, and life becomes a lot easier. > > So what does the impossibility theorem mean? Smith's and Hillinger's > answer could hardly be more different from the pessimistic > interpretations that have prevailed. The message of the impossibility > theorem is: don't use ranked voting systems. > > "There is an open door to social choice," Hillinger says, "and another > one...that is closed. One would have expected choice theorists to > pass through the open door; they chose instead to bang their heads > against the closed one." -- [EMAIL PROTECTED] people.clarityconnect.com/webpages3/davek Dave Ketchum 108 Halstead Ave, Owego, NY 13827-1708 607-687-5026 Do to no one what you would not want done to you. If you want peace, work for justice. ---- Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info