Hello Jon, Ben, Lists,

Does phenomenology need hypotheses?  Let's take one of Peirce's many 
formulations of what we are doing when we engage in the kind of 
phenomenological inquiry that he is recommending to us.  Here is a description 
of this science:  "Phenomenology ascertains and studies the kinds of elements 
universally present in the phenomenon; meaning by the phenomenon, whatever is 
present at any time to the mind in any way."  So, in doing phenomenology, we 
are asking the following kind of question:  are there some elements that are 
universally present in the phenomena?  Here are a series of hypotheses:

1) Yes, there are such universal elements.
2) There are three fundamental elements that are universal and necessary for 
all possible experience.
3) The matter of these elements can be understood to consist in three 
categories:  quality, brute fact, thought (pick your favorite term for the last 
of the three)
4) The form of these elements can be understood to consists in three basic 
kinds of relationships:  monadic, dyadic and triadic; or firstness, secondness 
and thirdness (pick your favorite list)
5) The material categories correspond, in some sense, to the formal categories.

What is the purpose of examining these elements more carefully and trying to 
generate a theory about the character of each and how experience might be 
composed of relations between these formal relationships?  Well, there are 
several related purposes.  Let me point to a few that are prominent in my mind. 
 In a long discussion of the character of the observations we should use for 
the sake of engaging in philosophical inquiry, where Peirce is trying to 
explain how we should go about analyzing the phenomena that we need to draw on 
for the sake of developing better explanations in the normative science of 
logic, he makes the following point about the method he is using:

Our object is to formulate the law of mind. We have to consider all mental 
action whatsoever and, generalizing it, to say not what all the elements of it 
are, but what that element of it is which is legislative. "Generalization," is 
the old answer.... A feeling is an element of consciousness just as it 
immediately is in the moment when it is there for itself and not as delegate of 
some other feeling not present. Such a feeling is not a psychological datum. 
The data are highly complex. That there is a cream colored surface with black 
characters on it is as near as I can readily describe the datum of my 
consciousness at this minute, -- but in truth the moment I pick it to pieces, 
as I must do to describe it, it ceases to be a datum.  CP 7.464-5. 

Let me now emphasize the following points that he makes:  "As for the pure 
feeling, that is a hypothetical entity, and is as completely veiled from me by 
its own immediacy as a material particle, as it exists in itself, is veiled by 
the somewhat absurd requirement that it shall be considered in itself. The 
truth is there are no data. We have a lot of inferences from data, liable to 
error, and these we have to correct as best we can by putting them together."  
Having made this point, Peirce draws an analogy between inquiry in the 
cenoscopic sciences and inquiry in the indioscopic sciencs:  "The state of the 
case is quite similar to that of a physical science, say astronomy. All we have 
to go upon in astronomy is observations, and all those observations are 
erroneous. But we collect them and take their means and find a general 
description of the path of the observed object; and from this we can calculate 
an ephemeris, and finally, if there is any interest in doing so, ascertain what 
those observations ought to have been. We can no more start with immediate 
feelings in psychology than we can start with accurate places of the planets, 
as affected by parallax, aberration, refraction, etc. in astronomy. We start 
with mediate data, subject to error, and requiring correction."

This is think, articulates some of the main purposes of phenomenology.  The 
data we are working with in philosophy are mediate and highly subject to error. 
 Our aim is to build a theory of the phenomena we observe in common experience 
for the sake of learning to: 1) analyze the data more carefully, 2) identify 
possible sources of error, and then 3) correct for the observational errors we 
might have made.

Does phenomenology need hypotheses?  Yes.  The point of the hypotheses is to 
show us how to do 1-3 above better.  If you have time, I recommend taking a 
look at what Peirce says next about how he is refining the logical account of 
the law of mind.  Starting from the old answer, which is that the fundamental 
law is one of generalization, Peirce goes on to analyze the experience of how 
something, such as a line that is being drawn on a piece of paper, is 
experienced as something that changes in a continuous manner over time.  
Without going into the details of the analysis, I think that Peirce is really 
onto to something about how we might build explanations in the normative 
science of logic in a better manner than it has been done by the likes of 
Descartes, Hume, Kant and Mill—and the other philosophers who have tried to 
answer the same question.  One key part of the strategy, I take it, is to 
develop the logical theory with an improved understanding of how we should work 
with the data (i.e., the observations) that we're trying to explain.

--Jeff

Here is what Peirce says next, in case anyone who does not have volume 7 of the 
CP handy would like to take a look.


466. The mind pronounces that what I see now resembles something I saw 
yesterday. The whole aspect of things as flowing in time is, it is plain, 
virtually a theory of the mind's creation. But, for the present, we take that 
theory as true, that is, as a stable one. Taking it as true, it seems to 
provide no possible means by which the mind could compare what is present to it 
now with what is past and gone and done with. This compels us to say that the 
time idea, -- at least, in its first crude shape, -- needs correction, like an 
erroneous observation in astronomy. Examining it more carefully, we observe 
that the idea is that the series of instants of time is continuous.  Analyzing 
this idea of continuity, as we shall do in a future chapter with the most 
minute accuracy which an improved art of logic puts at our disposition,†30 we 
find that it implies that there are instants infinitesimally close together; 
that is that there are durations of time so short, that every one such starting 
with a given date has a character exactly like the one before it in some 
respect, without any limitation to this rule, while yet a time a little later 
does not possess that character. This enables us to suppose that the 
consciousness is not limited to a single instant but that it immediately and 
objectively extends over a lapse of time, without thereby extending over any 
sensible lapse of time. We are thus able to suppose that consciousness is 
carried along from one time to another, and is able to compare what is present 
to it at different times. Such we may suppose to be the process of memory; and 
this is the account of it which best squares with those natural beliefs which 
are all the data the psychologist can possibly have upon which to found his 
science, corresponding, as they do, to the observations of the astronomer.

467. But granting that memory is thus justified, -- while errors may, of 
course, creep in during the process, -- it still remains that when the mind 
declares that what it sees now, or remembers to have seen yesterday, I seen 
last week, the likeness, which though accompanied like all mental processess 
like what it remembers to have with a peculiar and characteristic sensation, is 
mainly a fact, a mental fact, and the sensation of it is of no consequence 
except as an advertisement of that fact. That fact is that by virtue of the 
occult working of the depths within us, those two feelings coalesce into one 
notion. For the sake of calling this by a familiar name, I call this 
association by similarity. But the ideas united by virtue of an occult inward 
power, are not always regarded as similar. Contraries are also so joined. Ideas 
and feelings are so joined which are neither merely declared by the mind to be 
similar nor to be contrary. Such, for instance, are length, breadth, and 
thickness. The mind delights in triads. In general, what the mind pronounces is 
that the feeling or idea of yesterday and that of today belong to one system, 
of which it forms a conception. A concept is not a mere jumble of particulars, 
-- that is only its crudest species. A concept is the living influence upon us 
of a diagram, or icon, with whose several parts are connected in thought an 
equal number of feelings or ideas. The law of mind is that feelings and ideas 
attach themselves in thought so as to form systems. But the icon is not always 
clearly apprehended. We may not know at all what it is; or we may have learned 
it by the observation of nature.


Jeff Downard
Associate Professor
Department of Philosophy
NAU
(o) 523-8354
________________________________________
From: Jon Awbrey [jawb...@att.net]
Sent: Saturday, October 31, 2015 7:36 AM
To: Jeffrey Brian Downard; biosemiot...@lists.ut.ee; PEIRCE-L
Subject: Re: Peirce's Categories

Jeff, List,

It seems to me there is something slightly off about looking for
the hypotheses that underlie phenomenology. I do not think any
number of verbal evasions will fix the problem. The whole point
of anyone's version of phenomenology is to “bracket away” all such
hypotheses and to “cleanse the doors of perception”, etc. We may
be convinced by subsequent reflections: “the myth of the given”,
“data are really capta”, all of Peirce's many analyses, and the
results of experimental cognitive psychology, to name just a few,
that such levels of purity are not really possible for the complex,
concrete creatures we appear to be, but that is the project anyway.

On the other hand, as far as Peirce's distinctive perspective
on mathematics ‘per se’ goes, there is a tempting but unhappy
tendency to adulterate it with all the notions of logicism,
syntacticism, and other species of nominalism that I think
we really ought to try and cleanse from the pons thereto.

Regards,

Jon

On 10/31/2015 4:52 AM, Jeffrey Brian Downard wrote:
 > Hello Ben, List,
 >
 > I was particularly interested in the prospect of making a comparison between 
 > the hypotheses that we are working with
in mathematics and the hypotheses that we are working with phenomenology.  
There are good reasons to point out, as you
have, that the hypotheses in phenomenology are based on something that is, in 
some sense prior.  Call them, if you will,
particular discernments.
 >
 > Having searched around a bit, I don't see a large number of places where 
 > Peirce uses this kind of language when
talking about phenomenology.  Having said that, here is one:  "Philosophy has 
three grand divisions. The first is
Phenomenology, which simply contemplates the Universal Phenomenon and discerns 
its ubiquitous elements...." (CP 5.121)
 >
 > There are interesting differences between the ways that we arrive at the 
 > hypotheses that serve as "starting points"
for mathematical deduction, and ways that we arrive at the hypotheses that are 
being formulated in phenomenology.  One
reason I retained the language of "starting points" that was in the original 
questions that Peirce asked about
mathematics is that hypotheses are, at heart, quite closely related to the 
questions that are guiding inquiry.  We
normally think of hypotheses as explanations that can serve as possible answers 
to some questions.  In some cases, I
think it might be better to think of the formulation of the questions were 
trying to answer as itself a kind of hypotheses..
 >
 > We can ask the following kinds of questions about hypotheses in math, 
 > phenomenology, normative science and the like.
  What are we drawing on when we formulate these hypotheses?  How should we 
develop the hypotheses from the "stuff" that
we are drawing on so that the hypotheses we form will offer the greatest 
promise as we proceed in our inquiries.
 >
 > With these kinds of issues in mind, let me rephrase the questions about 
 > phenomenology so as to respond to the concern
you've raised:
 >
 > 1. What are the different kinds of hypotheses that might be fruitful for 
 > phenomenological inquiry?
 > 2. What are the general characters of these phenomenological hypotheses?
 > 3. Why are not other phenomenological hypotheses possible, and the like?
 >
 > --Jeff
 >
 > Jeff Downard
 > Associate Professor
 > Department of Philosophy
 > NAU
 > (o) 523-8354

--

academia: http://independent.academia.edu/JonAwbrey
my word press blog: http://inquiryintoinquiry.com/
inquiry list: http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/
isw: http://intersci.ss.uci.edu/wiki/index.php/JLA
oeiswiki: http://www.oeis.org/wiki/User:Jon_Awbrey
facebook page: https://www.facebook.com/JonnyCache
-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .




Reply via email to