Re: [EM] Intermediate RV rating is never optimal

2007-07-22 Thread Chris Benham



Abd ul-Rahman Lomax wrote:


bits and pieces

At 05:33 AM 7/21/2007, Michael Ossipoff wrote:
 

That's incorrect. It's exactly the same in RV as in Approval. In 
your example, with B at your Approval cutoff, it doesn't matter how you rate B.
   



In what I wrote, B was not at the voters approval cutoff. I didn't 
give an approval cutoff. Approval cutoff is an artificial insertion; 
it's a device for converting range ratings to approval votes.


This is the situation described:

The voter prefers ABC, with the preference strength between A and B 
being the same as the strength between B and C.


There is nothing here about Approval cutoff, there is nothing that 
says that the voter does or does not approve of *any* candidate.




I think we safely say that max-rating a candidate is equivalent to 
approving that candidate.


Ossipoff confused the fact that the candidate was intermediate 
between A and C in sincere rating, i.e., being midrange, with being 
at your Approval cutoff.


If the preference strength between A and B is  weaker than that between 
B and C then with
the winning probabilities being equal (or unknown) then the voter's best 
strategy is to max-rate
A and B. If instead the preference strength between B and C is weaker, 
the voter does best to

min-rate B and C (and of course max-rate A).

Since the situation you describe is at the border of these two (max-rate 
B or min-rate B), we can

say that B is at your approval cutoff.

And, quite clearly, it *does* matter how 
you rate B in some scenarios; for example, if the real pairwise 
election is between A and B, then the optimum vote is to rate B at 
minimum. And if it is between B and C, then the optimum vote is to 
rate B at maximum.




Of  course it can matter after the fact, but with both possible real 
pairwise elections being
equally likely at the time of voting, in Abd's scenario it 
probabilistically makes no difference what

rating the voter gives B.

Chris Benham



election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] RV comments

2007-07-20 Thread Chris Benham



Abd ul-Rahman Lomax wrote:


At 07:20 AM 7/20/2007, Michael Ossipoff wrote:


Say, for the moment, we disregard the fact that the SU claims 
depend on sincere voting, and that sincere voting is nearly always 
suboptimal in RV.



Ossipoff continually makes this claim. It's false. Suboptimal is 
the trick. It is suboptimal, true, from the point of view of the 
individual voter maximizing his or her own personal utility, *in some 
scenarios.* In others, it is clearly optimal to vote sincerely.




Can we please have an example of one of these other scenarios that 
shows that Mike Ossipoff's

claim  is false?

I think Warren Schudy put it well in a  July 2007 draft paper:

Range voting is a generalisation of approval voting where you can give 
each candidate any score
between 0 and 1. Optimal strategies never vote anything other than 0 or 
1, so range voting

complicates ballots and confuses voters for little or no gain.

If I prefer ABC, and those are the only options, it's 
clear that I optimize my expectation by voting A max, B min, but 
where do I rate B? ...


Where do I rate B? Well, if the B utility is midway between A and C, 
we can define a sincere rating of B as 50%. If we have rated A max 
and C min. However, that max and min rating is itself a full 
disclosure of the utilities, the ratings have been normalized to the 
election candidate set, causing loss of absolute utilities.


It never hurts the voter personally to normalize in that way.



That is only true (probabilistically) if  both the B utility is 
*exactly* midway between A and C
and  also  (as far as  the  voter  knows)  both   A  and   C   are  
equally  likely   to  win.


It  is obvious that in practice the voter in Abd's example could be  
hurt personally by not voting
B max if  that causes C to win instead of B, or by not voting B min if  
that causes B to win instead

of  A.

Chris Benham







election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Conditional Approval (was Does this method have a name?)

2007-05-29 Thread Chris Benham

Forest,
I had a quick look at this. It seems that when there are just three 
candidates and they are in

a  cycle it elects the Approval winner. Is that right?

In that situation I prefer ASM. I think my favourite method that uses 
the same type of  ballots
as your Conditional Approval  would be a version of  ASM Elimination 
that uses the voters'
original approval cutoffs while they make some distinction among 
remaining candidates and
thereafter interprets the voters' ballots as approving all  but the 
lowest ranked of the remaining

candidates.

Chris Benham




Forest W Simmons wrote:

In probability theory when partial info about a random variable is 
given, the resulting updated expections and probabilities are called 
conditional expectations and probabilities.


In that spirit, instead of calling the updated approvals based on 
partial info reactive, from now on I'm going to call them 
conditional.


So the (i,j) element of the conditional approval matrix approximates 
the approval that candidate i would get, given only that candidate j is 
the poll front runner.


Now for an update on how to use this conditional approval matrix to 
choose an election winner.


Previously, I suggested circling the highest number in each column, 
removing each row not having a circled number as well as the 
corresponding column, repeating the process until every row has exactly 
one circled number (not worrying about ties for now), and finally 
electing the candidate with the largest row minimum in the remaining 
matrix.


For this update I would like to change the final step.

By the time each row has exactly one circled number the set of 
candidates is partitioned into cycles of one or more candidates each of 
the type


x0, x1, x2, ... x0

where candidate i follows candidate j in the cycle if and only if 
element i of column j is circled.


Let's use X~Y to denote that X and Y are members of the same cycle.

In the revised final step, elect the candidate X with the largest 
minimum conditional approval given Y over all candidates Y such that 
Y~X.


In other words X maximizes

Min over Y~X of CA(X,Y)

where CA(X,Y) is the (X,Y) entry of the remaining conditional approval 
matrix.


Ideally, each of the remaining candidates (after iteratively crossing 
out the rows and columnns of the conditional approval losers) would be 
a conditional approval equilibrium candidate, which would make each 
cycle consist of exactly one candidate.  In that ideal case, the 
equilibrium candidate with the greatest approval would be the winner.


But since the ideal case is too much to expect, we think of equilibrium 
cycles instead of equilibrium candidates, and go with the winner of the 
cycle that maximizes the min conditional approval of its cycle winner.


Forest

 


From: Forest W Simmons [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Subject: Re: [EM] Does this method have a name?


The reactive approval of candidate X relative to Y as defined below 
is supposed to approximate the approval that X would get given only 
that Y was ahead of all the other candidates in the polls.


In other words, if there were zero info up until someone reveals that Y 
is the front runner, would you approve X or not?


Suppose that under zero info your approval cutoff was below Y.  Given 
the information that Y is the frontrunner, wouldn't it make sense to 
move your cutoff up to just below Y?


On the other hand, suppose that under zero info you disapprove Y.  
Given the info that Y is the frontrunner wouldn't it make sense to move 
your cutoff down to just above Y? 

The move would be in reaction to the given information, hence the term 
reactive.


So we define the reactive approval of X relative to Y as the number of 
ballots on which X would be approved if the voted approval cutoff were 
moved adjacent to (but not past) Y on each and every ballot.


Let RA be the matrix whose entry in row i and column j is the reactive 
approval of candidate i relative to candidate j.


Let's call this matrix the reactive approval matrix.

Below I suggested one way of using this matrix to determine a winner.  
Here's a more interesting one:


1. Circle the largest number in each column of the RA matrix.

2. Cross out each row that has no circled element.

3. Cross out the columns that correspond to the rows that were crossed 
out. [These rows and columns represent straw men or false alarms, so to 
speak, since any poll indicating that they were ahead would be 
misleading.]


4. Repeat steps 2 and 3 until each remaining row has exactly one 
remaining circled element.


5. The winner is the candidate who has the largest row minimum in the 
remaining matrix.


What do you think?

Forest



   


Here's an example that might clear up some questions:

Suppose that the original ballot is

A=BC=DE=F|G=HI=JK=L

where | is the voter's marked approval cutoff.

Then in calculating reactive approvals relative to C we move the 
approval cutoff adjacent to but not past the position shared by C

Re: [EM] Does this method already have a name?

2007-05-09 Thread Chris Benham

Forest W Simmons wrote:

Ballots are ordinal with approval cutoffs.

Forest,
I gather from your description of the method that the voters don't/can't 
give explicit
approval cutoffs that allow them to rank among unapproved candidates. I 
say this because
in the algorithm these cuttoffs are moved about with their 'original 
position' having no effect.
Is that right?

If so, it seems to me that they way you define the ballots somewhat 
mixes up the concepts of
input and algorithm and maybe even strategy.

The candidate with Maximum Minimal Reactionary Approval wins.

A candidate's reactionary approval relative to another candidate is 
the approval she would get if the approval cutoff were moved adjacent 
to (but not past) the other candidate's position in the ballot order on 
every ballot.
  


Am I correct in taking it that (a) sometimes the approval cutoff is 
moved so that some ballots
'approve' none of the candidates, and (b) the cutoff is never moved to a 
position where it distinguishes
between candidates given the same rank?


Chris  Benham



Forest W Simmons wrote:

Ballots are ordinal with approval cutoffs.

The candidate with Maximum Minimal Reactionary Approval wins.

A candidate's reactionary approval relative to another candidate is 
the approval she would get if the approval cutoff were moved adjacent 
to (but not past) the other candidate's position in the ballot order on 
every ballot.

So each candidate's score is her minimum reactionary approval relative 
to the other candidates.  The candidate with the highest score wins.

It turns out that when rankings are complete this method is equivalent 
to the common versions of MinMax.

It doesn't get tripped up on Kevin's standard example against pure MMPO:

49 A
1 A=B
1 B=C
49 C

Does it satisfy the FBC?

Forest

election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info

  


election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Student government - what voting system to recommend?

2007-04-25 Thread Chris Benham



Howard Swerdfeger wrote:


Tim Hull wrote:
 


 Condorcet, on the other hand, does not suffer
from the center squeeze.  However, it suffers from the opposite problem -
the so-called Pro Wrestler or Loony syndrome in an election with a
couple polarized candidates and a weak centrist or joke candidate.  In my
student government elections, I picture this being a candidate walking
around campus in a clown suit and winning based on becoming everybody's #2.
Also, Condorcet's later-no-harm failure may mean people give a less sincere
ranking than in IRV, though this failure is far less so than in range.
   



This is a potential problem with all pure Condorcet methods.
It might be able to be overcome with some restrictions
Candidate must have 5% first preference votes or be one of the top 5 
candidates in number of first preference votes.

Or some other restriction might help.
 



I can see why this is a marketing/propaganda problem, but not why it is 
a *real* problem.
One reason why not is that Condorcet gives serious candidates incentive 
to contest the centre so if the
election is serious then at least one serious centrist will run and one 
will win. If the election isn't serious then
why is polarised candidate necessarily a better winner than a weak 
centrist or even a joke candidate?



While I agree party lists are rotten.

there are lots of other multi winner PR systems, that don't require a 
party list

MMP where the top-up comes from the best of the losers.



How exactly does this version of  MMP work?


Chris Benham




election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Student government - what voting system to recommend?

2007-04-25 Thread Chris Benham



Tim Hull wrote:

Regarding IRV, I do know it isn't ideal.  In fact, if someone can show 
me it's necessarily worse than plurality, I'd just stick

with plurality in single-winner and use STV in multi-winner.


Plurality's only advantages over IRV are just a lot of monotonicty and 
mathematical elegance properties.

IRV's advantages over Plurality:
meets Majority for Solid Coalitions, Dominant Mutual Third, Condorcet 
Loser, Clone-Winner.


The incentive for the voter to use the Compromise strategy is much much 
weaker than in Plurality.


On this topic, does anyone know of a modified, 
kind-of-Condorcet-but-not-quite method which preserves later-no-harm? 


A method that would well handle all the 3-candidate examples you (Tim) 
and Juho have been trading is one where the voters
can give an approval cutoff in their rankings. Rankings below the 
'approval' cutoff cannot harm candidates ranked above it.


1. Voters rank candidates, truncation allowed but otherwise 
equal-preferences not, and voters give an 'approval' cutoff.

Default placement is  just above strict bottom or truncated candidates.

2. If one (remaining) candidate X is top-ranked (among remaining 
candidates) on more than half the (unexhausted)  ballots,

then elect X.

3. If not eliminate and drop from the ballots the least approved 
candidate. Then ignore ballots that make no preference distinction
among remaining candidates (as 'exhausted') in resetting the majority 
threshold.  Ballots that no longer make any explicit approval
distinction among remaining candidates are now given the default 
placement as if though the eliminated candidate/s had never

existed.

4. Repeat until there is winning X..

To answer your question more specifically, you might find CDTT methods 
interesting.


http://nodesiege.tripod.com/elections/#methcdtt

The CDTT is a set of candidates defined by Woodall to include every 
candidate A such that, for any other candidate B, if B has a 
majority-strength beatpath to A, then A also has a majority-strength 
beatpath back to B. (See Schulze #methsch for a definition of a 
beatpath.) Another definition (actually, the one Woodall chooses to 
use) of the CDTT is that it is the union of all minimal sets such that 
no candidate in each set has a majority-strength loss to any candidate 
outside this set. (Candidate A has a majority-strength loss to 
candidate B if v[b,a] is greater than 50% of the number of cast votes.)


Markus Schulze proposed this set earlier, in 1997. His wording was to 
take the /Schwartz/ set resulting from replacing with pairwise ties, 
all pairwise wins with under a majority of the votes on the winning side.



http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/CDTT

Limiting an election method's selection to the CDTT members can permit 
it to satisfy the Minimal Defense criterion 
/wiki/Minimal_Defense_criterion (and thus the Strong Defensive 
Strategy criterion /wiki/Strong_Defensive_Strategy_criterion) and 
the Majority criterion for solid coalitions 
/wiki/Mutual_majority_criterion, while coming close to satisfying 
the Later-no-harm criterion /wiki/Later-no-harm_criterion. 
Specifically, the CDTT completely satisfies Later-no-harm 
/wiki/Later-no-harm_criterion in the three-candidate case, and 
failures can only occur in the general case when there are 
majority-strength cycles.



Chris Benham



election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] maybe a new variant of Condorcet

2007-04-18 Thread Chris Benham

peter barath wrote (18/04/2007):

I call a subset of candidates a quasi-clone set, if:

1. they don't make up the whole set of candidates
2. for every candidate out of the set they are in
the same winning relation with (all beat / all tie /
all lose)

(You can ask why to make the subsets at all, but I think
this Rubicon is already crossed with the Smith-set,
which is a special kind of quasi-clone sets.)
  


This is similar to Forest Simmons'  beat clone sets he uses in his 
Dec. 2004
sprucing up process idea.

http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2004-December/014325.html

http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2004-December/014326.html

http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2004-December/014328.html

http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2004-December/014330.html

http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2004-December/014331.html

http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2004-December/014354.html

http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2004-December/014337.html

Chris Benham


Markus Schulze wrote:

Dear Peter Barath,

your proposal is very similar to Mike Ossipoff's subcycle rule.
Please read:

http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/1996-June/000494.html
http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/1996-June/000532.html
http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/1996-July/000572.html
http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/1997-September/001532.html
http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/1998-June/001721.html
http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2005-February/014707.html

Markus Schulze
  


election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Approval-Sorted Margins(Ranking) Elimination

2007-04-17 Thread Chris Benham



Brian Olson wrote:


I'm trying to understand the details of this procedure.

On Apr 16, 2007, at 12:03 PM, Chris Benham wrote:

 

My current favourite plain ranked-ballot method is  Approval- 
Sorted Margins(Ranking) Elimination:


1. Voters rank candidates, truncation and equal-ranking allowed.

2. Interpreting ranking above bottom or equal-bottom as 'approval',  
initially order the candidates
according to their approval scores from the most approved (highest  
ordered) to the least approved

(lowest ordered).
   



I'm a little fuzzy on this step, it sounds like that reverse-IRV  
method of disqualifying the most-last-placed choice.

Does ABCD mean I approve of all but D?



If there are no other candidates then for the initial ordering  (or 
seeding as the electowiki

ASM entry puts it)  yes.


And I'd think ABC=D would mean I approve of A and B,..

Same answer. If there are no other candidates then C and D are ranked 
equal-bottom.

The above in step 2 applies to both bottom and equal-bottom.

...but this  
statement seems to imply approval for all of A-D, unless perhaps  
there's E and F left unranked then it would approve A-D and not E,F




Brian, is this exactly what you meant to write?


3. If any candidate Y pairwise beats the candidate next highest in  
the order (X) , then modify the order
by switching  the order of the XY  pair  (to YX) that are closest  
in approval score.
Repeat until all the candidates not ordered top are pairwise beaten  
by the next highest-ordered candidate.
   



So, said another way, if the intermediate total order is
ABCDEF as ordered by approval counts, but more ballots rank CB than BC,  
and more ballots rank ED than DE, then if the approval count [difference] of B-C  
is less than D-E, then flop B and C in the intermediate order.
Repeat fixing up the intermediate order, always with the closest  
approval count difference, until no neighbors in the intermediate  
order violate pairwise ranking winner. (This seems to be very much  
like a condorcet process, actually, is it ever different unless  
there's a tie?)


Yes, ASM is a Condorcet method.  And so of course is ASM(R)E. As I put 
it in my Apr.16 post:


At some point in the process all except the candidates in the 
top-cycle will be eliminated,..


The top-cycle is the Smith set.

4. Eliminate and drop from the ballots the (now) lowest ordered  
candidate.


5. Repeat steps 2-4 until one candidate (the winner) remains.



Thanks for taking an interest,

Chris Benham



election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Approval-Sorted Margins(Ranking) Elimination

2007-04-16 Thread Chris Benham

Hello,
My current favourite plain ranked-ballot method is  Approval-Sorted 
Margins(Ranking) Elimination:


1. Voters rank candidates, truncation and equal-ranking allowed.

2. Interpreting ranking above bottom or equal-bottom as 'approval', 
initially order the candidates
according to their approval scores from the most approved (highest 
ordered) to the least approved

(lowest ordered).

3. If any candidate Y pairwise beats the candidate next highest in the 
order (X) , then modify the order
by switching  the order of the XY  pair  (to YX) that are closest in 
approval score.
Repeat until all the candidates not ordered top are pairwise beaten by 
the next highest-ordered candidate.


4. Eliminate and drop from the ballots the (now) lowest ordered candidate.

5. Repeat steps 2-4 until one candidate (the winner) remains.


Simply electing the highest ordered candidate after step3 is ASM(Ranking):

http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/Approval_Sorted_Margins

First seed the list in approval order. Then while any alternative X 
pairwise defeats the alternative Y
 immediately above it in the list, find the X and Y of this type that 
have the least difference D in approval,

and modify the list by swapping X and Y.


It is equivalent to ASM(R) in the situation where there are three 
candidates in the top cycle with no voter
ranking all three above bottom  (and in any election with just three 
candidates).


The advantage of this over ASM(R) is that there is less truncation 
incentive and voters who rank all the
viable candidates plus one or more others will normally face little or 
no disadvantage compared to informed
strategists. At some point in the process all except the candidates in 
the top-cycle will be eliminated, and
assuming three remain then from that point it will proceed like an 
ASM(R) election as though the over-rankers

'approve'  their two most preferred candidates (of the 3 in the top cycle).

An advantage it has over  Winning Votes (BP, RP,River) is that it 
doesn't have a 0-info. random-fill incentive.
Also unlike both WV and Margins it meets the  Possible Approval Winner 
(PAW) criterion.


35: A
10: A=B
30: BC
25: C

CA 55-45,   AB 35-30,   BC 40-25.

In this Kevin Venzke example, if we assume that voters rank all approved 
candidates strictly above all others
then it isn't possible for B to be approved on more ballots than A.  WV 
and Margins elect B.


ASM(R)E, like ASM(R) and DMC(R), elects C.

It seems obvious that ASM(R)E meets Minimal Defense.
http://nodesiege.tripod.com/elections/#critmd
//
If more than half of the voters rank candidate A above candidate B, and 
don't rank candidate B above

anyone, then candidate B must be elected with 0% probability.//

Referring to this definition, while A and B remain uneliminated A will 
always be considered to be more 'approved'
than B and of course A pairwise beats B, so B will always be ordered 
below A and so must at some point be

eliminated.

Chris  Benham

//




election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] final support

2007-04-03 Thread Chris Benham


Forest W Simmons wrote (31/03/2007):

So far, the three most promising measures of defeat strength for 
Beatpath and the other immune methods are ...

1. Winning Votes: the number of ballots in favor of the pairwise win.

2. Total Approval: the number of ballots on which the pairwise winner 
is approved.  The Beatpath, Ranked Pairs, and River formulations of DMC 
make use of this measure of defeat strength.

3. Approval Against: the number of ballots on which the pairwise winner 
is approved but the defeated alternative is not approved.

I suggest that we combine these three measures, and call the resulting 
measure Final Support, because it is an indication of the 
ratification support that the victor of a pairwise contest would 
receive, given that the defeated alternative is out of the picture.

4. Final Support: the number of ballots on which the victor of a 
pairwise contest is either approved or ranked above the defeated 
alternative (or both).

I suggest that River(fs) would be worth looking into, starting with all 
of the troublesome three candidate scenarios.
  


Forest,

Why isn't  

Approval Margins: the number of ballots on which the pairwise winner is 
approved minus the
number of ballots on which the pairwise defeated alternative is approved

on your list of  most promising measures of defeat strength..?

Chris Benham



  


election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] One example of a wording problem

2007-03-25 Thread Chris Benham

Michael Ossipoff wrote:

Chris wrote:

  

If the balloting rules don't allow the voters to fully express their 
intended ranking, then we assume that the voters
vote to express as much of it as the balloting rules allow, giving 
priority to expressing as many of their intended
strict pairwise preferences as possible
  


I reply:

If we take that literally, then, if the actual method is Approval, then the 
actual ballot has to approve half of the candidates in the intended ranking, 
because that's the way to expressing as many of that ranking's pairwise 
preferences as possible. But that isn't what you intend.


Mike,
Yes you are right, thanks. If there are 4 candidates A,B,C,D, I want 
both A and ABC to be both allowable
interpretations on an Approval ballot of the 'intended ranking' ABC.

But A only expresses 3 pairwise preferences (AB, AC, AD) whereas  
AB expresses 4 (AC,AD, BC,
BD). Also ABC only expresses 3 (AD, BD,CD).

In a way what I said maybe wasn't ridiculous, but it wasn't and isn't 
what I intend/ed. I'll re-think it.

Chris Benham


  

  


election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Venzke system for applying criteria, FARCS

2007-03-24 Thread Chris Benham

This current discussion was sparked by my remark (March 17, 2007):

I share the Venke (similar to Woodall's) approach that the criteria
should assume that the voters intend to submit a ranked ballot (maybe 
truncated, maybe with some equal-ranking) and that voters fill out 
their actual (maybe restricted) ballots in a way that is consistent 
with their intended ballots, and when ballot restrictions prevent
voters from fully voting their intended ranked ballots the criteria are 
based on the intended ballots.


Mike Ossipoff responded (March 20, 2007):

 What an elaborate counterfactual story. It’s amazing what lengths to 
 which some people will go, to make Plurality fail Condorcet’s 
 Criterion without mentioning preference.

 I've already answered about that. It's based on a privileged balloting 
 system. My criteria make no mention of any balloting system.

 Though you go to great lengths to avoid mentioning preferences, you 
 don't mind saying that the voter intends to vote a ranking, when s/he 
 votes in Plurality. I've talked to voters, and many of them are 
 adamantly opposed to any voting system other than Plurality. They 
 don't intend to vote a ranking when they vote Plurality. And that's 
 only part of the counterfactual nature of your fictitious-rankings 
 system of criteria.


Mike, notice that I specified that the voters' intended ranking is 
maybe truncated. It doesn't matter if the voters subjectively
don't have rank in their vocabulary: those that plan to cast a valid 
Plurality vote intend to rank a single candidate above all others.

Whatever balloting system is used all votes (that make any distinction 
among the candidates) contain some (logically implicit)
ranking data and there is no other type of data that they all contain, 
so I can't see that your reference to a privileged balloting
system is a meaningful criticism.

Mike apparently didn't think that I or Kevin had properly defined 
Kevin's way of applying criteria, so he came up with
a definition of what he called Fictitiously Assumed Rankings Criteria 
System (FARCS).

Here is my attempt at a definition of the Venzke approach to applying 
criteria with Mike-satisfying precision:

 Venzke rules for demonstrating a voting method's failure of criterion X:

 Criteria are written in the form of if A, then B where A refers to 
 some stipulation about the votes and B refers to
 something about the election result that must happen.

 It is assumed that the voters have an 'intended ranking' of the 
 candidates that may be truncated and/or include some
 above-bottom equal ranking. By definition, if the balloting rules 
 allow the voters to fully express this ranking then
 that is what the voters will do.

 The A part of a criterion refers to this intended ranking.

 If the balloting rules don't allow the voters to fully express their 
 intended ranking, then we assume that the voters
 vote to express as much of it as the balloting rules allow, giving 
 priority to expressing as many of their intended
 strict pairwise preferences as possible followed by expressing as many 
 of their intended pairwise equal-preferenes
 (indifferences) as possible.

 If the voters can only express some or all of their intended ranking 
 by giving preference data that isn't on their
 intended ranking, then we assume that they do so in a way that 
 contradicts their intended ranking as little as
 possible.

 If in testing for a method's compliance with criterion X, we can 
 follow the above rules/assumptions and show
 an example of A and not B, then we have proved that the method fails 
 criterion X.


Chris Benham















election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] A definition for your criteria system

2007-03-21 Thread Chris Benham


Michael Ossipoff wrote:

 FARCS stands for Fictitiously Assumed Rankings Criteria System.

 Because no FARCS advocate on EM has defined FARCS, I’m going to define 
 it in this posting.

 Definition of FARCS, consisting of instructions for writing a 
 criterion failure example in the FARCS system:

 1. Specify a set of voter rankings that complies with the criterion’s 
 premise’s stipulations about rankings.

 2. Specify each voter’s actual vote (using the actual balloting system 
 of the method being tested) in such a way that s/he doesn’t vote X 
 over Y when your ranking for that voter ranks Y over X.

 3. If you can thereby specify actual votes that give a result that 
 doesn’t comply with the criterion’s requirement, then you have written 
 a successful failure example.

 [end of FARCS definition]


Regarding (1), I'm not sure exactly what the criterion’s premise’s 
stipulations about rankings means.

Your point (2) is inadequate, because it could be that the voter intends 
to strictly rank some candidates while the actual
used method allows but not compels the voter to equal-rank them. By this 
definition it could be possible to create a
criterion failure example by having actual votes with equal-ranking 
where the voter intended strict ranking, even though
the the used method would have allowed the intended strict ranking.

Chris Benham



  


election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] More FARCS problems

2007-03-21 Thread Chris Benham



Michael Ossipoff wrote:

Chris said that people arrive at the polls intending to vote a certain way 
in a rank method, and then find out that it's (say) Plurality or Approval. 
Say it's Plurality. Their ranking that they arrive with would reasonably 
have their favorite in 1st place (Yes, I know it's a no-no to speak of 
preference).
Now, upon finding out that it's Plurality, they have strategic reason to 
give their one vote to a lower choice compromise. But FARCS has them voting 
consistent with their rankings, so that their 1st ranked candidate must be 
the one they vote for in Plurality.




Yes. All the strategising (if any) is supposed to only happen between 
their sincere preferences and their

'intended ranking'.

Or, if it's known to be a Plurality election, do they come to the polls 
intending to vote a ranking that has their Plurality compromise at the top 
of the ranking? 


Yes.

What about FBC? One must not get a better result by burying one's favorite. 
But FARCS and votes-only doesn't allow speaking of favorites. So, what is it 
then, does top-ranked replace favorite?
But then, if the actual ballot has to be consistent with the ranking, the 
top ranked candidate can't be buried.  So how could there be an FBC test?




Kevin's Sincere Favourite criterion seems fine to me. If  the voter's 
intended ranking is A=BC and
this results in neither of  A or B winning, but some other intended 
ranking with one or both of A and B not

given top preference results in one of them winning, then SF is failed.



  *Sincere Favorite*.

/Suppose a subset of the ballots, all identical, rank every candidate 
in S (where S contains at least two candidates) equal to each other, 
and above every other candidate. Then, arbitrarily lowering some 
candidate X from S on these ballots must not increase the probability 
that the winner comes from S./


A simpler way to word this would be: /You should never be able to help 
your favorites by lowering one of them./



http://nodesiege.tripod.com/elections/

Chris Benham


election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] RE : Chris: Approval

2007-03-19 Thread Chris Benham



Kevin Venzke wrote:


Aside from that, why is it ok to speak of intent, but not preference?
   



Intent is post-strategy. Here's an example of the process:

1. Say my sincere preferences are ABCDE.
2. Then I apply whatever reasoning and decide that I will be voting DAB
and truncate the rest. Then that DAB is my intended vote.
3. At this point I the voter do not make any more decisions. Suppose the
ballot format is such that I can only vote for two candidates equally
and nobody else. Then my cast ballot is either D=A or D=B, according
to arbitrary resolution.



Kevin,

Is this exactly what you meant to write? The way it is written, I don't 
see how D=B is a possible
choice of cast ballot for the voter whose intended ranking is DAB. If 
D=B is possible, why not

A=B?

I would rather say (in your point 3) that if the method is approval the 
voter with an intended ranking
of  DAB  (in this field of more than 3 candidates) makes an arbitrary 
choice  between D or DA or

DAB for his 'cast ballot'.

Chris Benham



Mike,

--- Michael Ossipoff [EMAIL PROTECTED] a écrit :
 


I share the Venke (similar to Woodall's) approach that the criteria
should assume that the voters intend to submit a ranked ballot (maybe 
truncated, maybe with some equal-ranking) and that voters
fill out their actual (maybe restricted) ballots in a way that is 
consistent with their intended ballots, and when ballot restrictions 
prevent
voters from fully voting their intended ranked ballots the criteria are 
based on the intended ballots.
 

I've already answered about that. It's based on a privileged balloting 
system. My criteria make no mention of any balloting system.
   



But you also can't demonstrate that they are unambiguous for any possible
election method.

 


Though you go to great lengths to avoid mentioning preferences, you don't
mind saying that the voter intends to vote a ranking, when s/he votes in 
Plurality. I've talked to voters, and many of them are adamantly opposed
to 
any voting system other than Plurality. They don't intend to vote a
ranking 
when they vote Plurality.
   



Doesn't matter. That's not the point of speaking of intent.

 


Could you demonstrate why Approval and 0-10 CR fail Condorcet's
Criterion, 
in your system?
   



Personally I don't have anything to add on these topics. I gave an
example of dealing with CR, and acknowledged that Approval is a weak
point.

 


Aside from that, why is it ok to speak of intent, but not preference?
   



Intent is post-strategy. Here's an example of the process:

1. Say my sincere preferences are ABCDE.
2. Then I apply whatever reasoning and decide that I will be voting DAB
and truncate the rest. Then that DAB is my intended vote.
3. At this point I the voter do not make any more decisions. Suppose the
ballot format is such that I can only vote for two candidates equally
and nobody else. Then my cast ballot is either D=A or D=B, according
to arbitrary resolution.

So an advantage of using intent over preference is that the voter only
has input at one stage. That's exactly as if you were only considering
cast ballots, except that you don't have to worry that perhaps the voter
was not allowed by the ballot to cast his preferred vote.

Preference and intent really take the same approach to not having to
worry about ballot restrictions, in that they both try to regard voter
input before it hits the paper.

Kevin Venzke








 


election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Chris: Approval

2007-03-19 Thread Chris Benham



Michael Ossipoff wrote:

Your definition of your criteria system sounds conversational and 
inexact. Could you demonstrate why Approval and 0-10 CR fail 
Condorcet's Criterion, in your system?


Aside from that, why is it ok to speak of intent, but not preference?


Speaking of preference is an ok alternative, but we don't necessarily 
want to worry about what might be 'sincere preferences'

that are voluntarily not voted.


Chris continues:

[after naming a long list of criteria met by Approval]


But it fails Majority Favourite and Majority Loser



Do you mean those criteria with your fictitious rankings? 


Yes.

I've never denied that rank methods can add advantages not available 
in Approval. I've even said that I myself would prefer a good rank 
method for our public elections, though I myself, as a voter, would be 
content with Approval. It would be a nice luxury to rank the best 
candidates, but I don't really care which one of the best candidates 
wins.


That is your individual inclination, one which is very convenient for an 
Approval advocate.



I'd said:

Obviously majority rule is violated by an outcome that is contrary 
to what a majority have voted that they want. For instance, if a 
majority vote B over A, then we can assume that, if A or B wins, 
they vote that it be B.




Chris says:

That is reasonable, and granted for the sake of argument. That 
implies that you agree with Kevin Venzke that Minimal Defense(MD) 
must be met



It does?? I don't agree with Keviln Venzke that Minimal Defense (MD) 
must be met. 


From Levin's page:



  *Minimal Defense*. /(Due to Steve Eppley.)/

/If more than half of the voters rank candidate A above candidate B, 
and don't rank candidate B above anyone, then candidate B must be 
elected with 0% probability./


Steve Eppley has defined and discussed Minimal Defense here 
http://alumnus.caltech.edu/%7Eseppley/ and here 
http://alumnus.caltech.edu/%7Eseppley/Strategic%20Indifference.htm. 
Satisfaction of this criterion implies compliance with Mike Ossipoff's 
/strong defensive strategy criterion/, although the reverse is not 
necessarily true. That criterion can be found here 
http://www.barnsdle.demon.co.uk/vote/stfree.html.



http://nodesiege.tripod.com/elections/

It does?? I don't agree with Keviln Venzke that Minimal Defense (MD) 
must be met. 



I'd be interested in seeing an example of  MD failure that you agree (or 
are content) with.



Chris continues:


[Approval] is very vulnerable to disinformation campaigns



That's a vague statement that could be said of many methods, including 
some that Chris likes. 


My statement lacked details, but that doesn't make it vague. I've 
elaborated this criticism of  Approval

a few times before.

Say in the lead-up to the election two candidates have announced that 
they will run, and accurate polling
of voters' voting intentions shows A52%, B48%. Say the media hate A, so 
others that hate A nominate
a third candidate C who is anathema to A's supporters (or at least some 
of them). Then those that hate A
set about giving C a high profile and publishing some fake polls that 
suggest that C has some chance to
win. This frightens some of the A supporters into approving B, causing A 
to win.


47: A
05: AB (disinformed timid AB preferrers)
46: B
02: CB

Approval:  B53,   A52,  C2.

What  methods that I like do you have in mind as being comparably 
vulnerable to disinformation campaigns?




Sincere preferences:

40: A
29: BC
31: CB

The C voters vote C  B. The B voters vote only B. B wins by defection.

Chris, can you find a majority who is being robbed of victory here?


No, but if  21 or more of  the C voters also defect the sincere BC 
majority solid coalition is robbed of victory and

the sincere majority loser wins.

I've repeatedly asked you to show that Approval and CR pass or fail 
Condorcet's Critrerion, by your fictitious-ranking approach. You never 
did. I asked Chris. He couldn't either. 


In your example say the 'intended rankings' are
40: A
29: BC
31: CB

On these intended rankings, C is the CW. On arriving at the polling 
place we pretend that those who
were intending to rank BC or CB are surprised to find that they have 
to use 2-slot ballots, so they each
make an arbitrary choice whether to approve (consistent with their 
intended rankings)  one candidate or two.

This could result in these actual cast approval ballots:

40: A
29: B
10: CB
21: C
Approvals: A40,  B39,  C31.

A wins, failing Condorcet.  (This is the same set of cast ballots as in 
the defection backfires because of too

many defectors example).

Chris Benham






I



election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] MAMPO is probably better than MDDA

2007-03-18 Thread Chris Benham


Kevin Venzke wrote (Feb 22,2007):

Hi.

This is the definition of MAMPO:

1. A candidate's opposition score is equal to the greatest number of
votes against him in any pairwise contest.
2. The voter ranks; those ranked are also approved.
3. If more than one candidate is approved by a majority, elect the one
of these with the lowest opposition score.
4. Otherwise elect the most approved candidate.

MAMPO satisfies FBC, SDSC, and SFC like MDDA does. But MAMPO also satisfies
Woodall's Plurality criterion.


Kevin,
I'm interested in your opinion of my stab at something similar that 
meets Irrelevant Ballots:

1 and 2 as for MAMPO.
3. Give each candidate a score that is equal to its approval score minus 
its opposition score.
4. Elect the candidate with the highest score.

With sensible approval strategy, this seems to 'perform well' (in terms 
of strategic criteria) with 3 or 4
candidates. The approval component seems to easily rescue MMPO from its 
greatest embarrassments.

One hope is that the truncation incentive of Approval and the 
random-fill incentive of  MMPO will mostly
cancel each other out.

There may be some smarter way to combine approval and pairwise 
opposition scores, perhaps weighting
them unequally. And if anyone likes it I'm open to a suggestion for a name.

Chris Benham



Hi.

This is the definition of MAMPO:

1. A candidate's opposition score is equal to the greatest number of
votes against him in any pairwise contest.
2. The voter ranks; those ranked are also approved.
3. If more than one candidate is approved by a majority, elect the one
of these with the lowest opposition score.
4. Otherwise elect the most approved candidate.

MAMPO satisfies FBC, SDSC, and SFC like MDDA does. But MAMPO also satisfies
Woodall's Plurality criterion.

Woodall's scenario showing that MDDA fails the latter:

20 ab
 5 ba
24 bc
24 ca
 9 dab
 9 dbc
 9 dca

a,b,c are preferred to d by 49,49,48 voters respectively, which are not
majorities, but ab by 62, bc by 67 and ca by 66, so that a, b and c
are all disqualified.  Thus MDDA elects d.  But d has 27 votes in total,
and so is debarred by b who has 29 first-preference votes.

MAMPO manages to elect B since D lacks majority approval, and 62 is
the lowest maximum such score.

For what it's worth. I think MAMPO does a fairly reasonable thing in only
deviating from approval when multiple candidates have a majority, and
then only in favor of one of the candidates that has a majority!

Kevin Venzke


   

   
   
___ 

  


election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Chris reply

2007-03-15 Thread Chris Benham
 more than what the Approval method guarantees--as much as I 
 like Approval. For me, as a voter, Approval would be fine. It’s the 
 other progressives who need a good rank method, because they tend to 
 have poor judgment about approving some sleazy crook known as a 
 Democrat lesser-evil. My concern is that they might keep doing the 
 same thing if we had the Approval method. Approval is still definitely 
 worth a try, because they might stop voting for the Democrat when they 
 notice that (say) Nader is outpolling the Republican. But a good rank 
 method homes in on the voter median immediately, instead of after a 
 few elections. And it isn’t proved that the LO2E progressives will 
 have the courage to ever stop voting for the Democrat. Those are the 
 reasons why I’d like a good rank method, as my first choice for our 
 public political elections. 


Without informed strategy Approval guarantees not much. Hopefully a set 
of democratic reforms that include a good rank method will
attract a lot of new voters with more courage and sense than your LO2E 
progressives.


Chris Benham



election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Trees and single-winner methods

2007-03-14 Thread Chris Benham


Juho wrote:

Here's one more election method for you to consider

Let's start from a Condorcet method (it doesn't matter much which  
one). Then we allow the candidates to form groups. Each group will be  
handled as if it was a single candidate. 

  


I reject this on the same grounds that I reject the candidate 
withdrawal option (in say IRV) and
Asset Voting:  I am only interested in single-winner methods where the 
result is purely determined
(as far as possible) by voters voting, and not by the machinations of 
candidates/parties.

Chris Benham




election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Possible Approval Winner set/criterion (was Juho--Margins fails Plurality. WV passes.)

2007-03-13 Thread Chris Benham



Juho wrote:

The Possible Approval Winner criterion looks actually quite natural 
in the sense that it compares the results to what Approval voting 
could have achieved.



I'm glad you think so.

The definition of the criterion contains a function that can be used 
to evaluate the candidates (also for other uses) - the possibility and 
strength of an approval win. This function can be modified to support 
also cardinal ratings.


In the first example there is only one entry (11: AB) that can vary 
when checking the Approval levels. B can be either approved or not. In 
the case of cardinal ratings values could be 1.0 for A, 0.0 for C and 
anything between 0.0001 and 0. for B. Or without normalization the 
values could be any values between 0.0. and 1.0 as long as value(A)  
value(B)  value (C). With the cardinal ratings version it is possible 
to check what the original utility values leading to this group of 
voters voting AB could have been (and if the outcome is achievable in 
some cardinal ratings based method, e.g. max average rating).


This concept looks vulnerable to some weak irrelevant candidate being 
added to the top of some ballots, displacing a candidate down to
second preference and maybe thereby causing it to fall out of the set 
of  possible winners. It probably has other problems regarding 
Independence

properties, and I can't see any use for it.

Chris Benham



The Possible Approval Winner criterion looks actually quite natural 
in the sense that it compares the results to what Approval voting 
could have achieved.


The definition of the criterion contains a function that can be used 
to evaluate the candidates (also for other uses) - the possibility and 
strength of an approval win. This function can be modified to support 
also cardinal ratings.


In the first example there is only one entry (11: AB) that can vary 
when checking the Approval levels. B can be either approved or not. In 
the case of cardinal ratings values could be 1.0 for A, 0.0 for C and 
anything between 0.0001 and 0. for B. Or without normalization the 
values could be any values between 0.0. and 1.0 as long as value(A)  
value(B)  value (C). With the cardinal ratings version it is possible 
to check what the original utility values leading to this group of 
voters voting AB could have been (and if the outcome is achievable in 
some cardinal ratings based method, e.g. max average rating).


The max average rating test is actually almost as easy to make as the 
PAW test. Note that my description of the cardinal ratings for 
candidate B had a slightly different philosophy. It maintained the 
ranking order of the candidates, which makes direct mapping from the 
cardinal values to ordinal values possible. The results are very 
similar to those of the approval variant but the cardinal utility 
values help making a more direct comparison with the original 
utilities of the voters.


Now, what is the value of these comparisons when evaluating the 
different Condorcet methods. These measures could be used quite 
straight forward in evaluating the performance of the Condorcet 
methods if one thinks that the target of the voting method is to 
maximise the approval of the winner or to seek the best average 
utility. This need not be the case in all Condorcet elections (but is 
one option). There are several utility functions that the Condorcet 
completion methods could approximate. The Condorcet criterion itself 
is majority oriented. Minmax method minimises the strength of interest 
to change the selected winner to one of the other candidates. Approval 
and cardinal ratings have somewhat different targets than the majority 
oriented Condorcet criterion and some of the common completion 
methods, but why not if those targets are what is needed (or if they 
bring other needed benefits like strategy resistance).


I find it often useful to link different methods and criteria to 
something more tangible like concrete real life compatible examples or 
to some target utility functions (as in the discussion above). One key 
reason for this is that human intuition easily fails when dealing with 
the cyclic structures (that are very typical cases when studying the 
Condorcet methods). In this case it seems that PAW and corresponding 
cardinal utility criterion lead to different targets/utility than e.g. 
the minmax(margins) required additional votes to become the Condorcet 
winner philosophy. Maybe the philosophy of PAW is to respect clear 
majority decisions (Condorcet criterion) but go closer to the 
Approval/cardinal ratings style evaluation when the majority opinion 
is not clear. You may have different targets in your mind but for me 
this was the easiest interpretation.


Juho


P.S. One example.
1: AB
1: C
Here B could be an Approval winner (tie) but not a max average rating 
winner in the ranking maintaining style that was discussed above 
(since the rating of B must be marginally smaller than the rating

Re: [EM] Chris reply

2007-03-13 Thread Chris Benham


Michael Ossipoff wrote:

 Chris--

 You wrote:


 Mike,
 Does this compromising one C voter have to unapprove C?

 I reply:

 No.

 Referring to this example,

 52: AC (offensive order-reversal)
 100: BA
 50: C/B



 You continued:

 ACBA. Approvals: A152, C102, B100. AC 152-50, CB 102-100, BA 150-52
 DMC and ASM elect A.

 I reply:


 You continued:

 Here if one C|B changes to B|C

 I reply:

 It doesn’t matter if it’s B/C or BC, because, as I said, the approval 
 votes don’t come into play, because there’s already an unbeaten 
 candidate, B, who therefore wins.

 You continued:

 then DMC just becomes indecisive with B and C on the same approval 
 score and pairwise tied.

 I reply:

 Pairwise tied, yes. Indecisive, no. B wins because B is the only 
 unbeaten candidate. According to DMC’s rules, B wins.

 If the C voters vote BC, approving both, then, as you said, they make 
 a pair-wise tie between B and C. B beats A and pair-ties C. B wins as 
 the only unbeaten candidate. The Approval scores don’t come into play, 
 because there already is an unbeaten candidate. At least that’s how I 
 understood the rules of DMC: If no one is unbeaten, repeatedly 
 eliminate the least-approved candidate till someone is unbeaten. 


Yes, that is doubtless the best way: elect the Schwartz winner.

 If I’ve misunderstood DMC’s rules, tell me the correct DMC rules. 

No, looks like my mistake. I'll give some reply to the rest later.


Chris Benham


  


election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Possible Approval Winner set/criterion (was Juho--Margins fails Plurality. WV passes.)

2007-03-13 Thread Chris Benham


Juho wrote:

I don't see any strong need to use the PAW criterion (or  
corresponding ratings variant) for strategy resistance or for  
election target reasons but they seem possible. They add  
complexity, but if justified for some reason, then why not. I'll try  
to think more and come back if needed.
  


I'm not suggesting that PAW be explicitly made part of the rules of any 
method, and  the PAW
criterion is met by most methods including the simplest. So I don't see 
how it  adds complexity.

The Plurality criterion is about avoiding common-sense, maybe 
simple-minded but nonetheless
very strong and (IMO)sound complaints from a significant subset of 
voters: the supporters of a candidate
that pairwise beats the winner: X ranked alone in top place on more 
ballots than Y was ranked above
bottom clearly equals 'X has more support than Y', so how can you 
justify X losing to Y?!.

PAW tries to be a generalisation of  Plurality, and less arbitrary 
because it doesn't talk about top preferences.

Chris Benham




election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] All uncovered options may be definitely defeated

2007-03-12 Thread Chris Benham


Jobst Heitzig wrote:

Unfortunately, there is no method that elects an option which is both 
uncovered and has not definite majority against it, simply because such 
options might not exist:

Example:
Pairwise defeats ABCDA, DB, CA, hence covering relation DA
Approval scores ABCD, hence definite defeats ABCD.

It seems we have to decide whether we consider definite defeats or 
covering defeats more important...

Jobst

Since these Condorcet methods that meet Definite Majority (ASM, DMC, 
Smith//Approval) all meet
Smith, then your concern about covering defeats can only be about 
situations with more than three
candidates in the Smith/Schwartz set.

For public political elections that for me is not a practical worry, 
whereas Definite Majority applies in
many relatively common-place 3-candidate scenarios.

Chris Benham





Dear Chris, 

you wrote:
  

TACC having that curious property and so electing B here shows that
it spectacularly fails the
Definite Majority criterion. Maybe that is forgivable for a  FBC
method like MAMPO, but not for a
Condorcet method that bases its result on nothing but pairwise and
approval information.



You're perfectly right here. It was before we studied definite 
majorities and found DMC that I proposed TACC. 

Unfortunately, there is no method that elects an option which is both 
uncovered and has not definite majority against it, simply because such 
options might not exist:

Example:
Pairwise defeats ABCDA, DB, CA, hence covering relation DA
Approval scores ABCD, hence definite defeats ABCD.

It seems we have to decide whether we consider definite defeats or 
covering defeats more important...

Jobst
  




election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
  


election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] DAMC

2007-03-12 Thread Chris Benham


Jobst Heitzig wrote:

Def. DAMC (Definite Absolute Majority Choice):
--
Make a list of absolute majority size pairwise defeats. 
  Process this list in order of descending approval score of the 
defeating option. Keep the defeat at hand iff (i) the defeated option 
is not already defeated by the kept defeats and (ii) the new defeat 
does not build a cycle with those defeats already kept. 
  From those options not defeated in the end, elect the most approved 
one.

In other words: We use River with 
  defeat := absolute majority size defeat
and 
  defeat strength := approval score of defeating option
and resolve the remaining ambiguity by Approval.


I'm pretty sure that this method has the following properties:
- monotonicity
- clone-proofness
- IPDA and ISDA
- immunity from absulute majority complaints (in the above sense)
- immunity from 2nd place complaints
- the winner is never defeated with absolute majority by a more approved 
option or by the most approved contender.


What I'm not sure about so far is whether using Beatpath or Ranked Pairs 
instead of River gives the same winner, and what would happen when we 
used the resorting or the definitively defeated version of DMC with 
absolute majority size defeats only.


Jobst,
Does this meet FBC/SF? 

Because I think something that fails Condorcet and  Irrelevant Ballots 
and presumably Definite
Majority would want to.

Chris Benham




  


election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Possible Approval Winner set/criterion (was Juho--Margins fails Plurality. WV passes.)

2007-03-07 Thread Chris Benham


Juho wrote (March7, 2007):

The definition of plurality criterion is a bit confusing. (I don't  
claim that the name and content and intention are very natural  
either :-).)
- http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/Plurality_criterion talks about  
candidates given any preference

- Chris refers to above-bottom preference votes below
 

/If the number of ballots ranking /A/ as the first preference is 
greater than the number
of ballots on which another candidate /B/ is given any preference, 
then /B/ must not be elected./


Electowiki definition could read: If the number of voters ranking A  
as the first preference is greater than the number of voters ranking  
another candidate B higher than last preference, then B must not be  
elected.


Yes it could and to me it in effect does (provided last means last or 
equal-last) The criterion come
from Douglas Woodall who economises on axioms so doesn't use one that 
says that with three candidates
A,B,C a ballot marked ABC must always be regarded as exactly the same 
thing as  AB truncates. He

assumes that truncation is allowed but above bottom equal-ranking isn't.

A similar criterion of mine is the Possible Approval Winner criterion:

Assuming that voters make some approval distinction among the 
candidates but none among those
they equal-rank (and that approval is consistent with ranking) the 
winner must come from the set of

possible approval winners.

This assumes that a voter makes some preference distinction among the 
candidates, and that truncated

candidates are equal-ranked bottom and so never approved.

Looking at a profile it is very easy to test for: considering each 
candidate X in turn, pretend that the
voters have (subject to how the criterion specifies) placed their 
approval cutoffs/thresholds in the way
most favourable for X, i.e. just below X on ballots that rank X above 
bottom and on the other ballots
just below the top ranked candidate/s, and if that makes X the (pretend) 
approval winner then X is

in the PAW set and so permitted to win by the PAW criterion.

11: AB
07: B
12: C

So in this example A is out of the PAW set because in applying the test 
A cannot be more approved

than C.

IMO, methods that use ranked ballots with no option to specify an 
approval cutoff and rank among
unapproved candidates should elect from the intersection of the PAW set 
and the Uncovered set


One of  Woodall's  impossibility theorems states that is impossible to 
have all three of  Condorcet,
Plurality and Mono-add-Top. MinMax(Margins) meets Condorcet and 
Mono-add-Top.


Winning Votes also fails the Possible Approval Winner (PAW) criterion, 
as shown by this interesting

example from  Kevin Venzke:

35 A
10 A=B
30 BC
25 C

AB 35-30,  BC 40-25, CA 55-45

Both Winning Votes and Margins elect B, but B is outside the PAW set{A,C}.
Applying the test to B, we get possible approval scores of A45, B40, C25.

ASM(Ranking) and DMC(Ranking) and Smith//Approval(Ranking) all meet the Definite 
Majority(Ranking) criterion which implies compliance with PAW. The DM(R) set is

{C}, because interpreting ranking (above bottom or equal-bottom) as approval, 
both
A and B are pairwise beaten by more approved candidates.


Chris Benham








election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Juho--Margins fails Plurality. WV passes.

2007-03-05 Thread Chris Benham


Michael Ossipoff wrote:

In a posting to a different mailing list, Markus pointed out that margins 
fails the Plurality Criterion, and that wv Condorcet passes the Plurality 
Criterion.

Yes.

11: AB
07: B
12: C

A Woodall example that applies. Margins elects A, yet C has more top 
preference votes than A has
above-bottom preference votes.

Chris Benham


  


election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] UncAAO

2007-03-05 Thread Chris Benham
 with a Nash equilibrium, no matter 
where the B faction puts its approval cutoff.

49 C
24 BA
27 AB

As in wv, no defensive strategy is needed under zero info conditions.  
But if you suspect that X is the CW, and you could live with X, then a 
prudent move would be to approve X and above.


For what it's worth, this all applies at least as well to ASM and DMC. 
Of course some of the
sincere BA preferrers have to at least truncate for A not to be alone 
in the Smith set.

When the ballot-style allows voters to rank among unapproved candidates 
ASM and DMC
are my co-equal favourites, and when it doesn't I prefer ASM.

http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/Approval_Sorted_Margins

Chris Benham





election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] UncAAO

2007-03-03 Thread Chris Benham


Forest W Simmons wrote:

UncAAO stands for Uncovered, Approval, Approval Opposition.  Here's how 
it works:

For each candidate X, 

if X is uncovered,

then let f(X)=X,

else let f(X) be the candidate against which X has the least approval 
opposition, among those candidates that cover X.

Start with the approval winner A and apply the function f repeatedly 
until the output equals the input.  This fixed point of f is the 
method winner.


Is there any chance that someone who understands this will translate it 
into plain English?


Chris Benham




  


election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] UncAAO

2007-03-02 Thread Chris Benham



Forest W Simmons wrote:


Here are the main advantages of UncAAO over other Condorcet methods:

1.  It is resistant to manipulation ... more so than Beatpath or Ranked 
Pairs, if I am not mistaken.


2.  It always chooses from the uncovered set.

3.  It is at least as easy as Ranked Pairs to describe. No mention of 
the possibility of cycles is needed, since the covering relation is 
transitive.


4.  It is easier than Ranked Pairs or Beatpath to compute. One never 
has to check for cycles, since the covering relation is transitive.


5.  It takes into account strength of preference through appropriate 
use of Approval information.


With regards to point 1, consider the following example (sincere votes):

45 ACB
35 BCA
20 CAB


Here C is the CW. Is this example right?

This is not a Nash Equilibrium for Margins, Ranked Pairs, PC, etc. 
because the A faction can improve its lot unilaterally by reversing CB 
to BC. 

Under winning votes the C faction can take defensive action and 
truncate to 20 C.  The resulting position is a Nash Equilibrium.


Taking such defensive action causes B to win, so why would they want 
to do that when they
prefer A to B?  And I don't see why the resulting position is a Nash 
Equilibrium (according to
the definition I googled up), because the sincere CA faction can change 
the winner from  B to A

by changing their votes from  C  to CA.

*

*DEFINITION: Nash Equilibrium* If there is a set of strategies with 
the property that no player
can benefit by changing her strategy while the other players keep 
their strategies unchanged, then
that set of strategies and the corresponding payoffs constitute the 
Nash Equilibrium.



*http://william-king.www.drexel.edu/top/eco/game/nash.html

Chris Benham



 


election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] A few concluding points about SFC, CC, method choice, etc.

2007-02-15 Thread Chris Benham


Pasting from Mike's page:


/Some definitions useful in subsequent criteria definitions:/

A voter votes X over Y if he votes in a way such that if we count only 
his ballot, with all the candidates but X  Y deleted from it, X wins.


[end of definition]

Voting a preference for X over Y means voting X over Y. If a voter 
prefers X to Y, and votes X over Y, then he's voting a sincere 
preference. If he prefers X to Y and votes Y over X, he's falsifying a 
preference.


A voter votes sincerely if he doesn't falsify a preference, and 
doesn't fail to vote a sincere preference that the balloting rules in 
use would have allowed him to vote in addition to the preferences that 
he actually did vote.


[end of definition]


Strategy-Free Criterion (SFC):

/Preliminary definition: /A Condorcet winner (CW) is a candidate 
who, when compared separately to each one of the other candidates, is 
preferred to that other candidate by more voters than vice-versa. Note 
that this is about sincere preference, which may sometimes be 
different than actual voting.



SFC:

If no one falsifies a preference, and there's a CW, and a majority of 
all the voters prefer the CW to candidate Y, and vote sincerely, then 
Y shouldn't win.


[end of definition]





Michael Ossipoff wrote:

Kevin and Chris posted their criteria that they incorrectly claimed 
equivalent to SFC.


These same alternative SFCs have been posted to EM before and 
thoroughly discussed before.
In fact, we've been all over this subject before. 



So why don't you point us to where in the EM archive we can find this 
earlier discussion?  Are they in your opinion equivalent for

ranked-ballot methods?

Though Chris's and Kevin's criteria clearly are not equivalent to SFC, 
maybe someone could write a votes-only cirterion that is. First of 
all, what's this obsession about votes-only?


Some people worry that criteria that give the appearance that we have to 
read voters' minds to see if they are met are not the easiest to check for.


Now, quite aside from that,  the efforts to write a votes-only 
equivalent criterion seem motivated by a desire to not say  things 
that happen to be what I want to say. I want SFC to be about the fact 
that that majority, because they all prefer the CW to Y, and because 
there's no falsification (on a scale sufficient to change the 
outcome), can defeat Y by doing nothing other than voting sincerely.


To say it in a way that doesn't say that wouldn't be SFC. If someone 
wrote such a criterion, then I'd recognize it as a _test_ for SFC 
compliance, but not as SFC. When I say that a method passes or fails 
SFC, and someone says What's that?, then I want to tell them the SFC 
described in the paragraph before this one, the one that relates to 
the CW,  no need for other than sincere  voting by the majority and 
non-falsified voting by everyone else. If I worded it like Kevin or 
Chris, it wouldn't be self-evident why it's desirable to meet that 
criterion.


Someone could suggest that I use an alternative as the criterion, and 
save my SFC as a justification. No, I want the criterion's value to be 
self-evident.



Well its value as something distinct from the Condorcet  criterion isn't 
self-evident to me. If  this CWY majority can't elect the CW, why do 
they necessarily
care if  Y is elected or not?  

And the way you've dressed this up, I can't see how it really qualifies 
as a  strategy criterion. How are the members of this CWY majority 
supposed to
know whether or not anyone falsifies a preference?  And if they do 
know what are they supposed to do about it?


From Steve Eppley's MAM page:


/truncation resistance/ 
Proof%20MAM%20satisfies%20Minimal%20Defense%20and%20Truncation%20Resistance.htm: 
Define the sincere top set as the smallest subset
of alternatives such that, for each alternative in the subset, 
say x, and
each alternative outside the subset, say y, the number of 
voters who
sincerely prefer x over y exceeds the number who sincerely 
prefer y
over x.  If no voter votes the reverse of any sincere 
preference regarding
any pair of alternatives, and more than half of the voters 
rank some x in
the sincere top set over some y outside the sincere top set, 
then y must
not be elected. (This is a strengthening of a criterion having 
the same name

promoted by Mike Ossipoff, whose weaker version applies only when
the sincere top set contains only one alternative, a Condorcet 
winner.)



This makes some sense as a strategy criterion, being about deterring a 
faction from truncating against the members of the sincere

Smith set. The weaker version ascribed to you seems easier to test for.

How does that version differ from your present SFC?

Chris  Benham



election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Randomized MCA, new weird voting method idea

2007-02-15 Thread Chris Benham


Warren Smith wrote:

I'll describe a new voting method.  I'm not sure if it is brilliant
or crazy.  I'm also unsure how to analyse it.

1. Forest Simmons has often advanced the idea of using randomness in voting
methods inspire more voter honesty. (Lottery methods.)

2. IEVS (my simulator - see http://groups.yahoo.com/group/RangeVoting
if you want news about what IEVS is finding out)
says MCA is one of the best methods.

3. So here is a new idea intended to take advantage of both ideas.
It is a different-than-usual way to use randomness.

Consider the following randomized variant of the MCA voting method.
Voters rate each candidate either 1, 2, or 3 (3 is best).
The candidate with the most 3-ratings wins if his number of
3-ratings exceeds X% of the number of voters.
Otherwise, the candidate with the most {2- or 3-ratings} wins.

Here X is chosen randomly and is not known to the voters when casting
their votes.

The point is: if X were some fixed known constant (conventional MCA
method: X=50%), then with a huge number of voters,
it would be virtually certain the election would end in the 1st round,
or virtually certain it would end in the 2nd round. The voters
would get wise to which. Once they knew which round it was going to be,
then the election would really just be an approval-voting election,
and any advantages of the 3-slot over regular 2-slot voting, would
essentially not exist.  
  


I think the difference between virtually certain and *guaranteed* can be 
important/significant. Election methods in my book shouldn't be assumed to be
of equal merit just because they nearly always (in simulations and/or in 
practice) elect the same winner. 


Limiting voters to expressing two preference-levels is in my book 
unacceptable and three is a big
improvement. Warren, do you prefer Range3 to Approval?

When the voters are informed strategists and/or if they are mainly 
concerned that the winner come
from a certain subset of candidates, then all FBC methods have at least 
a very strong tendency to
become equivalent to Approval.

To comment on the specific method proposal: it looks crazy to me. The 
method no longer meets
3-slot Majority for Solid Coalitions:

35: A
33: BC
32: CB



If  X is revealed as 35% or lower, then A wins in the first round.

Or  3-slot Condorcet(Gross):

26: AB
25: B
25: CB
24: DB

If  X is revealed as 26% or lower, then A wins in the first round.


A faction that believes their favourite is the FPP winner might have 
extra incentive to only put that
candidate in the top slot, but apart from that the main effect of the 
change is that voters will have a
greater fear that their Worse will win in the first round so their 
incentive to ignore the middle slot
will be increased, making the method (even) more like Approval, not less.

Chris Benham



election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Condorcet and Participation, Moulin's proof

2007-02-11 Thread Chris Benham

Michael Ossipoff wrote:

 Sure, Condorcet fails Participation. And of course it would be better 
 to not fail Participation. But Partilcipation isn't about a strategy 
 dilemma. It's about an embarrassment. You know that no method can 
 aviod embarrassments of some kind or other. You know, that goes back 
 to Kenneth Arrow. 


My intention in drawing attention to that proof  was to provide 
ammunition in favour of  Condorcet, not against it. Condorcet's 
Participation failure
apparently requires there to be four candidates in a cycle, which I 
don't consider to be a practical concern.

 But I use Partilcipation when comparing Approval to IRV. Some say 
 that's dishonest, to use Participation when my favorite method, 
 Condorcet, fails Participation.


I would say that it is somewhat misleading and inconsistent, and  
counter-productive to the goals of  educating people and promoting the 
Condorcet criterion.

 But it isn't, because, unlike Condorcet, IRV has no redeeming 
 qualities to outweigh its Participation failure. 


To be charitable, that is an absurd exaggeration made purely for the 
sake of being provocative. A more intelligent and appropriate attack on IRV
could be made along the lines that it's Participation failures are much 
more severe than Condorcet's because they are possible in relatively
common-place scenarios with just three candidates and no cycle. (This 
seems to be  Auros/M.Harman's main objection to IRV.)

So it seems to me that some weakened form of  the Participation 
criterion that captures one of  IRV's problems versus Condorcet might be of
some use/interest.

Chris Benham





  


election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SFC

2007-02-11 Thread Chris Benham



Warren Smith wrote:

SFC: If no one falsifies a preference, and there's a CW, and a 
majority of all the voters

prefer the CW to candidate Y, and vote sincerely, then Y shouldn't win.
   



I must say, SFC is then rather silly. 
It says if no one falsifies a preference redundantly since it also says

a majority of all the voters prefer the CW to candidate Y
(of course they do, that followed  from defn of CW and fact nobody falsified a 
preference)
and redundanty it also says and vote sincerely (of course they do, since
nobody falsified a preference)

The criterion refers to all sincere preferences, and by falsifies it 
means order-reverse and not just truncate or
otherwise falsely equal-rank. It is about a faction whose favourite Y 
isn't the sincere CW not being able to elect Y

just by truncating.

So say sincere is

43: AB
10: BA
10: BC
37: CB

B is the CW, so there's a CW.  If  the A supporters truncate

43: A
10: BA
10: BC
37: CB

Now  CBAC,  but  no-one has falsified a preference and more than 
half the voters (a majority)
have voted sincerely expressing their preference for the (sincere) 
CW(B) over Y (A in this example,

BA 57-43),  so the criterion says that in this scenario A mustn't win.

This isn't the same as the Condorcet criterion, because  
BP/RP/MM/River(Margins) and Smith/Schwartz,IRV

all meet Condorcet but elect A.

I speculate that the reason for the confusing unusual language is to do 
with Mike's long-running propaganda

war in favour of  Winning Votes and Approval  versus Margins and IRV.

My stab at making it clearer and more technical:

If  more than half the voters vote X over Y and it is possible to 
complete truncated ballots in a way to

make X the CW, then Y must not win.


Chris Benham





election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Condorcet and Participation, Moulin's proof

2007-02-10 Thread Chris Benham


 [EM] Condorcet and Participation

*Markus Schulze * [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
mailto:markus.schulze%40alumni.tu-berlin.de

/Sun Oct 5 02:48:02 2003/

   * Previous message: [EM] lower preferences
 
http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2003-October/011029.html
   * Next message: [EM] (no subject)
 
http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2003-October/011031.html
   * *Messages sorted by:* [ date ]
 
http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2003-October/date.html#11030
 [ thread ]
 
http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2003-October/thread.html#11030
 [ subject ]
 
http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2003-October/subject.html#11030
 [ author ]
 
http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2003-October/author.html#11030




Dear participants,

this is Moulin's proof that participation and Condorcet
are incompatible.

Situation 1:

  3 ADBC
  3 ADCB
  4 BCAD
  5 DBCA

Situation 2:

  Suppose candidate B is elected with positive probability
  in situation 1. When we add 6 BDAC voters then candidate B
  must be elected with positive probability according to
  participation and candidate D must be elected with
  certainty according to Condorcet.

Situation 3:

  Suppose candidate C is elected with positive probability
  in situation 1. When we add 8 CBAD voters then candidate C
  must be elected with positive probability according to
  participation and candidate B must be elected with
  certainty according to Condorcet.

Situation 4:

  Suppose candidate D is elected with positive probability
  in situation 1. When we add 4 DABC voters then candidate D
  must be elected with positive probability according to
  participation and candidate A must be elected with
  certainty according to Condorcet.

Situation 5:

  Because of the considerations in Situation 2-4 we get
  to the conclusion that candidate A must be elected with
  certainty in situation 1. When we add 4 CABD voters then
  candidate B and candidate D must be elected each with
  zero probability according to participation.

Situation 6:

  Suppose candidate A is elected with positive probability
  in situation 5. When we add 6 ACBD voters then candidate A
  must be elected with positive probability according to
  participation and candidate C must be elected with
  certainty according to Condorcet.

Situation 7:

  Suppose candidate C is elected with positive probability
  in situation 5. When we add 4 CBAD voters then candidate C
  must be elected with positive probability according to
  participation and candidate B must be elected with
  certainty according to Condorcet.

Markus Schulze




   * Previous message: [EM] lower preferences
 
http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2003-October/011029.html
   * Next message: [EM] (no subject)
 
http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2003-October/011031.html
   * *Messages sorted by:* [ date ]
 
http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2003-October/date.html#11030
 [ thread ]
 
http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2003-October/thread.html#11030
 [ subject ]
 
http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2003-October/subject.html#11030
 [ author ]
 
http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2003-October/author.html#11030




election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] replies to recent EM posts re voting-design puzzle

2007-01-25 Thread Chris Benham



Warren Smith wrote:


Benham: Right. And how does a voter express an infinitesimal preference in
   


the Range 0-99 that you advocate?

--sorry, when I speak of range voting in mathematical analysis, I almost 
always mean
continuum range voting where all real numbers in [0,1] are castable votes.



That is convenient for you, but I've also seen the claim made in 
propaganda apparently in support of  the version/s of  Range

you propose as a practical reform.

http://www.rangevoting.org/


   1. Each vote MeaningOfVote.html consists of a numerical score
  within some range (say 0 to 99 Why99.html) for each candidate.
  Simpler is 0 to 9 (single digit range voting). Voters may also
  indicate X Blanks.html or NO OPINION Blanks.html if they
  have no opinion about a candidate. Such votes don't affect that
  candidate's average.

UNAFFECTED BY CANDIDATE CLONING: CandCloning.html Consider the 
situation where A has clones A_2 and A_3 . In the old plurality 
voting Plurality.html system, the clones split the vote and lose. 
In the Borda voting rangeVborda.html system, a party assures 
victory merely by running enough clones. In contrast, in Range voting, 
A is neither harmed nor helped. No more bitter enmity Enmity.html 
between alike candidates




As far as I am concerned, restriction to discrete sets such as {0,1,...,99} is
not really a good idea and is only done for reasons of practicality (interface 
with
old voting machines, etc).  I therefore prefer it if more and more 9s are 
allowed.  There is some
reason to believe (in fact, precisely the sort of reason Benham speaks of) that 
about six 9s
may be desirable.



I can see how by this trick you  achieve Strong FBC  and  your special  
version of   Clone Independence (ICC).



Chris Benham





election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] EM] Simmons' solution of voting system design puzzle is inadequate

2007-01-21 Thread Chris Benham



Warren Smith wrote:

Benham: By this definition Range fails ICC because voters can only express 
   

preferences among clones by not giving maximum possible score to all of 
them, thus making it
possible that if a narrow winner is replaced by a set of clones all the 
clones lose.


--no.  The definition in the problem statement said slight preferences among 
clones.
By slight, I meant, to be formal, infinitesimal.



Right. And how does a voter express an infinitesimal preference in  
the Range 0-99 that you advocate?


499: A99
251: B99C98
250: C99B98

Range average scores:  A49.401,B49.349,  C49.348

A wins, but if the {B,C} clone set is coalesced into a single candidate 
X, X wins. This is an FPP-like failure of
Clone-Winner, and  BTW  also  of  course  a failure of  Majority  for  
Solid  Coalitions  (and Condorcet).


499: A99
501: X99

Range average scores:  X49.599,A49.401

Apart from that, I gather that  Range with fewer available ratings 
slots  also qualifies as  Range Voting, so
of  course in that case it is even more difficult  for  the voter  to 
express infinitesimal preferences.


Chris Benham






election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Simmons' solution of voting system design puzzle is inadequate

2007-01-21 Thread Chris Benham


Abd ul-Rahman Lomax wrote:


Abd ul-Rahman Lomax wrote:

At 05:00 PM 1/20/2007, Chris Benham wrote:

 


By this definition Range fails ICC because voters can only express
preferences among clones by not giving maximum possible score to all of
them, thus making it
possible that if a narrow winner is replaced by a set of clones all the
clones lose.
   



Now, tell me, why should an election system provide a means for 
voters to express a preference between clones, when they consider 
them equally fit for the office?


Benham is correct that Range would not allow a voter to express a max 
score to one candidate and a lower score to another, without risking 
the loss of the second one as he described. If a voter considers two 
candidates clones, the rational vote under Range is to rate them 
identically. Favorite, between clones, is meaningless. If the voter 
has a preference, they aren't clones to the voter.




Wrong. That is not how Warren defined clones for his purpose, nor is it 
how they are regularly

defined.


*clones*
A set of alternatives, X[1], X[2], .. X[m] is a clone set provided 
that for
every alternative Z, where Z is not one of X[1], .. X[m], the 
following is true:
Every ballot that ranks Z higher than one of X[1] .. X[m] ranks Z 
higher than all of them.  Every ballot that ranks Z lower than one of 
them, ranks Z lower than all of them.  No ballot ranks Z equal to any 
of them.
As well, there must be at least one alternative outside the set of 
clones, and at least two alternatives in the set of clones.



So this:

Now, tell me, why should an election system provide a means for 
voters to express a preference between clones, when they consider 
them equally fit for the office?



is more-or-less a contradiction in terms.


Okay, so I looked up clone. It has a special meaning; the term was 
invented to apply to ranked methods. According to the current 
Wikipedia article on Strategic Nomination:


 

Clones in this context are candidates such that every voter ranks 
them the same relative to every other candidate, i.e. two clones of 
each other are never both strictly separated by a third member in 
the preference ranking of any voter, unless that member is also a fellow clone.
   



Yes.


Because of this definition, it is possible that all voters would rank 
two candidates the same, but would sincerely rate them differently,..




I think you have that the wrong way round.


Chris Benham

 


election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Simmons' solution of voting system design puzzle is inadequate

2007-01-20 Thread Chris Benham


Warren Smith wrote:

Here is the current CRV web page about this problems and its (lack of) solution

We are speaking about puzzle #5 at
http://www.rangevoting.org/PuzzlePage.html

---

 Puzzle #5: Voting systems immune to clones and avoiding favorite-betrayal

Puzzle:
Two desirable properties of a voting system - both of which Range Voting has - 
are immunity to candidate-cloning (ICC) and avoiding favorite betrayal 
(AFB).
AFB: voters should never have strategic incentive to betray their favorite 
candidate by voting him below some other.
ICC: political parties should be unable to usefully manipulate an election by 
running clones of their own, or of an opposed, candidate; voters here are 
assumed to vote honestly and to have only tiny preferences (which they may 
express in their votes, if they exist) among the clones.

By this definition Range fails ICC because voters can only express 
preferences among clones by not giving maximum possible score to all of 
them, thus making it
possible that if a narrow winner is replaced by a set of clones all the 
clones lose.

Note: Many voting systems are known (beyond just variants of range voting) 
which satisfy AFB

Many?  There is MCA,  ER-Bucklin(Whole),  one or two Kevin Venzke 
methods and what else?


Chris Benham








election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Strongest pair with single transfer (method)

2007-01-18 Thread Chris Benham
Kevin,
Interesting. What (if any) harm would be done by applying this to the 
three candidates remaining
after the rest have been IRV-style eliminated?

Is there any actual criterion that this method meets but IRV doesn't?

Chris Benham



Kevin Venzke wrote:

Hi,

Here's an attempt at a method that behaves well in the three-candidate
scenario with preferences based on distance on a one-dimensional spectrum.
I would call it strongest pair with single transfer or SPST. It
satisfies LNHarm and Plurality, and doesn't suffer from the worst kind
of burial incentive. It also satisfies Clone-Loser I believe, though not
monotonicity.

My idea was to come up with a method that, in the three-candidate case
with distance-based preferences on a one-dimensional spectrum, could
elect the inner candidate in the absence of a majority favorite. I also
wanted to avoid truncation strategy (Approval, Condorcet), gross Plurality
failures (as under MMPO), and the sort of burial strategy where you give
a lower preference to a candidate whose supporters are not ranking your
candidate.

Definition:
1. The voter may vote for one first preference and one second preference.
2. The strength of a candidate, or pair of candidates, is defined as
the number of voters giving such candidates the top position(s) on
their ballots in some order. (This is as under DSC.)
3. A pair of candidates has no strength, if it includes any candidate
who is not among the top three on first preferences. (I don't like this
rule, but it's needed for LNHarm.)
4. If the strongest candidate is in the strongest pair, or stronger than
the strongest pair, then this candidate wins.
5. Eliminate the strongest candidate. The second preferences of his
supporters may be transferred to the individual candidate strengths of
the two members of the strongest pair of candidates.
6. Now, the strongest candidate in the strongest pair is elected.

examples:
40 AB
25 BC
35 CB

Strongest pair is BC; strongest candidate is A. BC is stronger than A,
so A is eliminated and 40 preferences are transferred to B's strength.
B wins.

35 AB
25 BC
40 CB

Here BC is again the strongest pair, but C is the strongest candidate and
wins immediately unfortunately.

This method is a lot like DSC, but never requires more than N^2 numbers
to be counted, whereas DSC requires 2^N if you keep track of every set.
The elimination doesn't create IRV's counting issues, since with only
two preferences taken we can just count them all.

The burial strategy works like this: Say it's A, B, and C, with B as the
middle candidate. A is expected to be the strongest candidate. Then
voters with the preference order BA have incentive to instead vote
BC. This is because if BC is the strongest pair, A will be eliminated
and hopefully transfer preferences to B. But if AB is the strongest
pair, A wins outright. As a result of this strategy, it is possible that
(despite the LNHarm guarantee) A voters would decline to give a second
preference to B, so that BA voters can't count on the A voters to
give a second preference to B.

It is only possible to eliminate the first preference winner, due to
LNHarm. It's only safe to eliminate a candidate who was going to win.
Otherwise it could happen that voters have incentive to weaken a pair
involving their favorite candidate, in order to prevent an elimination
that causes the favorite candidate to lose to the second preference.

Limiting pairs to the top three FPP candidates is necessary for LNHarm
when there are more than three candidates. Otherwise it could happen,
say, that BC is stronger than BD is stronger than A, A is eliminated,
and then C wins. Whereas if BC were weakened and BD were strongest, A's
elimination might result in B winning.

Monotonicity can be failed when the winner is not the FPP winner, he
gets more preferences, changing which pair is strongest, and causing
the other candidate in the pair to win.

I ran some simulations to try to measure this method against others. When
the only ballot types are AB, BA, BC, and CB, this method is identical
to DSC. When all 9 ballot types are allowed, this method seems to be 
strictly more Condorcet-efficient than DSC, although not by much.

I found that IRV is more Condorcet-efficient than either, except in
the scenario where only the four ballot types are permitted, and the
proportions of the BA and BC ballots are divided by 5. There IRV is
worse because it wants to eliminate B.

(With the four ballot types, IRV can elect B as long as B doesn't have
the fewest first preferences. That particular scenario is important to
me, though. DSC can elect B unless, say, the AB faction outnumbers the
BA BC factions, and also the BC CB factions.)

That's it for now.

Kevin Venzke


   

   
   
___ 
Découvrez une nouvelle façon d'obtenir des réponses à toutes vos questions ! 
Profitez des connaissances, des opinions et des expériences des

Re: [EM] New 3-slot FBC method (not)

2007-01-15 Thread Chris Benham


Oops!  Some on this list might know to be sceptical when I suggest a new 
method meets FBC.


37: WF
25: FC
07: C  (sincere is FC)
31: CW

Approvals: W68,   C63,   F62.   Top-rating scores: C38,   W37,   F 25.  
Winning threshold T =50.


No candidate has a TR score equal or above the threshold, so the least 
approved candidate F is eliminated
and then on the 25FC ballots C is promoted to top rating, boosting C's 
TR score to 56, above T so C wins.


But if the 7C voters stop betraying their sincere favourite and change 
to C=F, we get:


37: WF
25: FC
07: C=F
31: CW

Approvals: F69,   W68,   C63.   Top-rating scores: C38,   W37,   F 32.  
Winning threshold T =50.


This has the effect of boosting F's approval score so now C is 
eliminated and W is promoted to top rating on

the 31CW ballots so giving W a winning score.

So this method clearly fails FBC. I withdraw my support for this method 
because I don't like single-winner
methods that fail  Independence from Irrelevant Ballots (IIB) without 
meeting FBC.


Sorry about that,

Chris Benham



Chris Benham wrote:

I have an idea for a new 3-slot method, and if people like it I'm open 
to suggestions for a name.

(It  is similar to and partly inspired by Douglas Woodall's  ApAV method.)

 

1. Voters give each candidate a top rating , a middle rating or no 
rating.


2. Fix the winning threshold T at 50% of the total valid ballots. Give 
each candidate a score equal to
the number of ballots on which it is top-rated. If the candidate X 
with the highest score has a score

equal or greater than  T, elect  X.

3. If not, eliminate the (remaining) candidate which is given a top or 
middle rating on the fewest ballots, and
on ballots that now top-rate none of the remaining candidates promote 
all the middle-rated candidates to top-rated

and accordingly amend the scores.

4. Again, if the now highest scoring candidate X has a score of at 
least T then elect X. (T does not shrink

as ballots 'exhaust').

5. Repeat steps 3 and 4 until there is a winner. If  no candidate ever 
reaches a score of T, elect the candidate
that is top or middle rated on the most ballots (i.e. the Approval 
winner).
   




Note that in the course of the count no candidates are ever demoted on 
any ballots from middle-rated to
unrated. Both the winning threshold and the elimination order is fixed 
at the start and don't change.



 

 


election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] New 3-slot FBC method

2007-01-14 Thread Chris Benham

I have an idea for a new 3-slot method, and if people like it I'm open 
to suggestions for a name.
(It  is similar to and partly inspired by Douglas Woodall's  ApAV method.)

 1. Voters give each candidate a top rating , a middle rating or no 
 rating.

 2. Fix the winning threshold T at 50% of the total valid ballots. Give 
 each candidate a score equal to
 the number of ballots on which it is top-rated. If the candidate X 
 with the highest score has a score
 equal or greater than  T, elect  X.

 3. If not, eliminate the (remaining) candidate which is given a top or 
 middle rating on the fewest ballots, and
 on ballots that now top-rate none of the remaining candidates promote 
 all the middle-rated candidates to top-rated
 and accordingly amend the scores.

 4. Again, if the now highest scoring candidate X has a score of at 
 least T then elect X. (T does not shrink
 as ballots 'exhaust').

 5. Repeat steps 3 and 4 until there is a winner. If  no candidate ever 
 reaches a score of T, elect the candidate
 that is top or middle rated on the most ballots (i.e. the Approval 
 winner).


Note that in the course of the count no candidates are ever demoted on 
any ballots from middle-rated to
unrated. Both the winning threshold and the elimination order is fixed 
at the start and don't change.

I think this is now my favourite method that meets FBC/SF. I have it 
meeting this and Mono-raise and 3-slot Majority
for Solid Coalitions, and Plurality and  Minimal Defense.

Comparing it with MCA and ER-Bucklin(Whole)  it seems to have a less 
severe LNHarm problem and no disadvantages
that I can see except that is slightly more complicated than MCA.

Also it has several advantages over Majoritarian Top Ratings(MTR).  It 
doesn't have as bad a Clone-Winner problem.

25: AB
23: BA
45: C
07: D

MTR elects C here while my suggested method (majoritarian disapproval 
elimination? MDE) elects A.  B is a clone of
A, and if  B is dropped from the ballots then both methods elect A.

MDE  probably fails Condorcet(Gross), but doesn't as easily fail  
Condorcet Loser.

5:AB
5:BC
5:CA
3:DA
3:DB
3:DC

Here MTR elects the Condorcet Loser and  Approval Loser D. I think MDE 
can only elect a Condorcet loser who
is the Approval winner.

Also in MTR zero-info. voters  with one big sincere ratings gap (so they 
are chiefly concerned that any one of the acceptable/good
candidates defeats all the unacceptable/bad candidates) have the weird 
incentive to randomly middle-rate half the unacceptable
candidates in the hope of artificially handing out some 
majority-strength defeats. In MDE those voters should simply not middle-rate
any of the candidates (certainly none of the Unacceptables).

MTR has a saleability problem in that it uses a pairwise mechanism as 
part of its algorithm (MDD), but then fails both Condorcet and
Condorcet Loser . I think MDE's algorithm is more natural and more 
appealing to say IRV supporters.

I'm interested in any comments or corrections.

Chris Benham







election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Clone proofing Copeland

2007-01-08 Thread Chris Benham

Juho,

26: AB
25: CA
49: BC  (sincere is BA or B)


Juho wrote:

But I'll however mention some random observations that the example  
that you used made me think.
- One could also claim that these votes are a result of strategic  
voting but in another way than what you described. Instead of having  
49 voters that strategically changed their vote from BA (or B) to  
BC one could have had just one voter that strategically changed her  
vote from CA to AB. As a result numbers 25 and 26 were swapped and  
counting the first place votes gives a different result. The  
strategic voter was not able to get her #1 favourite but she could  
easily help her #2 favourite become elected.


Yes, but that is just an instance of vulnerability to the Compromise 
strategy common to all methods
that meet Majority for Solid Coalitions.

The Achilles' heel of Condorcet methods in their competition with IRV  
is their vulnerability to Burial.

- In addition to strategies one of course also has to pay attention  
to the sincere votes. What would be the best candidate to elect if  
the votes in the example were all sincere? 

Arguably maybe B, but also arguably without rating information we can't 
tell.

There is thus always a  
balance on how much one needs to protect against strategic voters  
since all such changes in the methods (in most cases) make the  
achieved utility with sincere votes a bit worse. 

I think DMC strikes a good balance.

Chris Benham




election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Clone proofing Copeland

2007-01-06 Thread Chris Benham


Simmons, Forest wrote:

Here's a version that is both clone proof and monotonic:
 
The winner is the alternative A with the smallest number of ballots on which 
alternatives that beat A pairwise are ranked in first place. [shared first 
place slots are counted fractionally]
 
That's it.
 
This method satisfies the Smith Criterion, Monotonicity, and Clone 
Independence.


More not-so-good news for this  Simmons method: it fails  mono-raise 
(aka Monotonicity).

31: AB
02: AC
32: BC
35: CA

CABC. Simmons scores:  A35,   B33,   C32.   C has the lowest score 
and wins.

But if we raise C on the two AC ballots, changing them to CA, then we get:

31: AB
32: BC
37: CA (2 of these were AC)

CABC. Simmons scores:  A37,   B31,   C32.  Now  B has  the  lowest  
score  and  wins.

So raising C on some ballots without changing the relative ranking of 
any of the other candidates has
caused C to lose,  a failure of  mono-raise.

Interestingly in both cases the method gave the same result as IRV.  In 
fact it is starting to look as
though in the 3-candidate case Schwartz//Simmons  is equivalent to 
Schwartz,IRV!

Say sincere is:

48: A
27: BA
25: CB

B is the CW, and in this case both methods (even without the Schwartz 
component) elect B.

And both methods are vulnerable to the same Pushover strategy. If from 3 
to 20 of the 48 A supporters
change their vote to CA or C or even CB, then both methods will elect A.

45: A
03: CA (sincere is A)
27: BA
25: CB

BACB   Simmons scores: A27,   B28,  C45.  A has the lowest score 
and so wins.
IRV eliminates B and likewise elects A.

28: A
27: BA
45: CB  (20 of these are sincere A!)

BACB   Simmons scores: A27,   B45,  C28.  A has the lowest score 
and so wins.
IRV eliminates B and likewise elects A.


Chris Benham


 








election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Clone proofing Copeland

2007-01-02 Thread Chris Benham


Juho wrote:

How about the smallest number of ballots on which some alternative  
that beats A pairwise is ranked higher than A?

Juho
  

No, that would have nothing like the same strength or resistance to Burial.

26: AB
25: CA
49: BC  (sincere is BA or B)

The Simmons method narrowly elects A (the sincere CW), while your 
suggestion easily elects
the Burier's candidate B.

Chris  Benham




election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Simmons cloneproof method is not cloneproof

2007-01-01 Thread Chris Benham


Warren Smith wrote:

see http://groups.yahoo.com/group/RangeVoting/message/2934
for counterexample  (plus linear program explainign how I found the 
counterexample)
wds

 Ballots:
 6: ABC
 3: CAB
 4: BCA

 A wins under Simmons voting since
 A beats B pairwise == 6 ballots count against B
 C beats A pairwise == 3 ballots count against A
 B beats C pairwise == 4 ballots count against C

 Now add two clones of A in a Condorcet cycle.

 Then A1 is beat pairwise by A2 with 1/3 of the 6 of the
 A-top ballots, i.e. 3, and ditto A2 and A3, all have 2
 A-top ballots against them.
 Plus, all the Ak have got C's toprank votes
 against them, which is 3. So in total, each A-clone
 has 5 ballots against it, while C has only 4
 ballots against it.

 Hence C is now the winner thanks to A's cloning.

 So SIMMONS IS NOT CLONEPROOF!!

 If we agree only to clone non-winners,
 or if, when cloning a winner, all voters agree to rank the clones
 EQUALLY, THEN Simmons is cloneproof.

 Proof:
 After cloning,
 the A-beats-B relations are unaffected under these constraints,
 and the number of top-rank-votes-against X are either unaltered -
 or increased (increase is only possible for nonwinner X since
 winning-X clones never pairwise-beat each other).
 QED

 However... this weakened kind of cloneproofness is a good
 deal less impressive than genuine cloneproofness.


So  Simmons meets Clone-Loser, but can fail Clone-Winner when there are 
three or more factions
in a top cycle and the candidates in one of those factions are in a 
sub-cycle. That is a very very mild
failure of  Clone-Independence and arguably not a practical worry.

If that is the full extent of the bad news (and maybe even if it isn't) 
then I think this method remains a
great contender (for best practical Condorcet method) because of its  
tremendous Burial resistance
and simplicity.

Chris Benham




election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Clone proofing Copeland

2006-12-31 Thread Chris Benham



Simmons, Forest wrote:


Here's a version that is both clone proof and monotonic:

The winner is the alternative A with the smallest number of ballots on which 
alternatives that beat A pairwise are ranked in first place. [shared first 
place slots are counted fractionally]

That's it.

This method satisfies the Smith Criterion, Monotonicity, and Clone Independence.



Warren Smith wrote:


this is an elegant method!
Note that it is IMMUNE to my DH3 pathology!
http://rangevoting.org/DH3.html
It is strategically pointless to bury (lower artificially) a rival
to your favorite below some non-entities, because if those nonentitites are 
never
ranked top, doing so makes no difference.

And it satisfies mono-add-plump and mono-append (two Woodall criteria)!

And it is simple!



Assuming these criterion compliance claims are right , so far I am very 
very impressed. Congratulations Forest!


It seems to completely dominate Schwartz,IRV which until now was one of  
my favourite Condorcet methods. I am convinced that it has an
anti-burial property  stronger than I suspected  it was a possible for 
an unadorned Condorcet method to have. One of the reasons I liked
Schwartz,IRV was that it met what I called  Dominant Mutual Third 
Burial Resistance, a criterion that said that if  there are three 
candidates
X,Y,Z and X wins, then changing some ballots from YX to YZ can't make 
Y the winner.


Well I'm quite sure this Simmons method meets Dominant Mutual *Quarter* 
Burial Resistance!


26: AB
25: CA
49: BC  (sincere is BA or B)

ABCA.  Simmons scores: A25,  B26, C49.  A has the lowest score and 
so narrowly wins.


On top of that it has the advantage over Schwartz,IRV of meeting 
mono-raise (and so isn't vulnerable to Pushover strategy), and doesn't

seem to have any disadvantage.

It definitely fails two of Steve Eppley's criteria: Minimal Defense and  
Truncation Resistance (not ones I rate highly).


/truncation resistance/ 
Proof%20MAM%20satisfies%20Minimal%20Defense%20and%20Truncation%20Resistance.htm:  
Define the sincere top set as the smallest subset 
/   / of alternatives such that, for each alternative in the 
subset, say /x/, and 
/   / each alternative outside the subset, say /y/, the number of 
voters who 
/   / sincerely prefer /x/ over /y/ exceeds the number who 
sincerely prefer /y/ 
over /x/.  If no voter votes the reverse of any sincere 
preference regarding 
any pair of alternatives, and more than half of the voters 
rank some /x/ in 
the sincere top set over some /y/ outside the sincere top set, 
then /y/ must 
not be elected. (This is a strengthening of a criterion having 
the same name 
promoted by Mike Ossipoff, whose weaker version applies only when 
the sincere top set contains only one alternative, a Condorcet 
winner.)/

/




I'm not sure about his  Non-Drastic Defense criterion, (the version) 
that says that if  Y is ranked no lower than equal-top on more than half 
the ballots and Y

pairwise beats X, then X can't win.

It has Woodall's  Symmetric Completion property, and it certainly meets 
his Plurality criterion when there are three candidates (and probably 
meets it period).


I'm happy with its performance in this old example:

101: A
001: BA
101: CB

It easily elects A. Schulze (like the other Winning Votes defeat 
dropper methods) elects B.


It meets my  No Zero-Information Strategy criterion, which means that 
the voter with no idea how others will vote does best to simply rank 
sincerely.



Chris  Benham




election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] RE : Re: Election methods in student government...

2006-12-23 Thread Chris Benham

Tim Hull wrote:

 DSC uses a somewhat interesting method - it effectively goes and 
 excludes the groups of candidates that the most people prefer a solid 
 coalition to until it finds a winner.  However, what I am wondering 
 is - what are the primary flaws of these two methods (especially as 
 compared with IRV, of which I know quite a bit about the flaws)?

DSC fails several important (in my book) criteria that are met by IRV.

DSC fails Dominant Mutual Third, which says that if  there is a set of 
candidates X that all pairwise beat all the outside-the-set candidates 
and they are solidly supported
(ranked above all the outside-the-set candidates) on more than a third 
of the ballots, then the winner must come from X.

49: A
48: B
03: CB

Here the DMT set is {B}, but DSC elects A.

(If the B voters switch to BC then B wins, a failure of  Later-no-Help.)

DSC fails Condorcet Loser, which says that a candidate that is 
pairwise beaten by every other candidate mustn't win

38: A
19: BCD
17: BDC
10: CB
03: CD
10: DC
03: DB

DSC fails Condorcet Loser by electing A.

This is also a failure of  Dominant Mutual Third (DMT), by not electing B.

IRV is invulnerable to the Burying strategy.

49: A
48: BA
03: CB

DSC elects A, but if the BA voters change to BC then their  burial 
strategy against A succeeds and B wins.

DSC has a random-fill incentive and so fails what I call No 
Zero-Information Strategy. In the 0-info. case the DSC voter
gets a better expectation by strictly ranking all the candidates, if 
necessary at random; whereas the IRV voter does best to
rank sincerely.

I think of DSC as just FPP that has been minimally improved to meet  
Clone-Winner and  Majority for Solid Coalitions.

Chris Benham




election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] RE : Re: Election methods in student government...

2006-12-23 Thread Chris Benham

Chris Benham wrote:

 38: A
 19: BCD
 17: BDC
 10: CB
 03: CD
 10: DC
 03: DB 

My example here of  DSC failing both  DMT and Condorcet Loser works, but 
not quite what I meant to type:

38: A
19: BCD
17: BDC
10: CD
03: CB
10: DC
03: DB

(I've corrected it below as well).

Chris Benham



 Tim Hull wrote:

 DSC uses a somewhat interesting method - it effectively goes and 
 excludes the groups of candidates that the most people prefer a 
 solid coalition to until it finds a winner.  However, what I am 
 wondering is - what are the primary flaws of these two methods 
 (especially as compared with IRV, of which I know quite a bit about 
 the flaws)?


 DSC fails several important (in my book) criteria that are met by IRV.

 DSC fails Dominant Mutual Third, which says that if  there is a set 
 of candidates X that all pairwise beat all the outside-the-set 
 candidates and they are solidly supported
 (ranked above all the outside-the-set candidates) on more than a third 
 of the ballots, then the winner must come from X.

 49: A
 48: B
 03: CB

 Here the DMT set is {B}, but DSC elects A.

 (If the B voters switch to BC then B wins, a failure of  
 Later-no-Help.)

 DSC fails Condorcet Loser, which says that a candidate that is 
 pairwise beaten by every other candidate mustn't win

 38: A
 19: BCD
 17: BDC
 10: CD
 03: CB
 10: DC
 03: DB

 DSC fails Condorcet Loser by electing A.

 This is also a failure of  Dominant Mutual Third (DMT), by not 
 electing B.

 IRV is invulnerable to the Burying strategy.

 49: A
 48: BA
 03: CB

 DSC elects A, but if the BA voters change to BC then their  burial 
 strategy against A succeeds and B wins.

 DSC has a random-fill incentive and so fails what I call No 
 Zero-Information Strategy. In the 0-info. case the DSC voter
 gets a better expectation by strictly ranking all the candidates, if 
 necessary at random; whereas the IRV voter does best to
 rank sincerely.

 I think of DSC as just FPP that has been minimally improved to meet  
 Clone-Winner and  Majority for Solid Coalitions.

 Chris Benham





election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] majoritarian top ratings (MTR)

2006-12-23 Thread Chris Benham



Kevin Venzke wrote:

Hello,

My favorite method lately I'll call majoritarian top ratings or MTR.
I don't believe it has been suggested on the list. Here is the definition:

1. The voter gives every candidate the top rating, the middle rating,
or no rating at all, which is the bottom rating.

2. Say that a candidate X is defeated by a majority if more than half
of all voters assign some other candidate Y a strictly higher ranking
than they assign to X.

3. Elect the top candidate in the ordering of candidates wherein a 
candidate X is above candidate Y when X is not defeated by a majority
while Y is, or (when this makes no distinction) when X received the top
rating on more ballots than did Y.
  

Kevin,
Is there some reason apart from simplicity that you use MDD instead of  
CDTT?

5:AB
5:BC
5:CA
3:DA
3:DB
3:DC

All except D has a majority-strength defeat, but D is pairwise beaten 
10-9 by every other
candidate.

CDTT  can't be just the Condorcet loser, as the MDD set is here.

Advantages of this:
1. FBC
2. (my interpretation of) minimal defense
3. limited later-no-harm, in that you can't hurt your top-rated candidates
by listing middle-rated candidates.

I suppose you can add the 3-slot versions of  Smith(Gross) and  
Majority for Solid Coalitions.

Disadvantages:
1. fails Plurality (although not as egregiously as MMPO)
2. potential for burial strategy (although with the usual countermeasures)
  


Take the 0-info. voters whose main or only preference is between candidates 
they regard as acceptable and all the others they regard as unacceptable
(i.e. they have one big gap in their sincere ratings). For them the sincere
way of voting would be to ignore the middle slot and just submit an approval 
vote, putting all the unacceptables in the bottom slot.

But in fact their best strategy is to randomly select half the unacceptables
and put them in the middle slot, maybe causing one that would otherwise beat
an acceptable candidate to be disqualified.

With information, the middle slot would mainly become a cynical strategy-tool
for factions to try to disqualify the most electible candidate/s in rival 
faction/s. The effect of that could be the election of a turkey with little
sincere support.

MTR of course fails Independence from Irrelevant Ballots (IIB), and also 
Clone-Winner (unless the defence but these are ratings ballots, and a set of
clones must by definition share the same rating is invoked).

25: AB
23: BA
45: C
07: D

C wins, but if the irrelevant 7D ballots are removed then A wins.

If instead one of the {A,B} clones are removed then the other will win (i.e. 
if
the clone-set is replaced by a single candidate X which is top-rated by all 
those
who voted AB or BA, then X will win).

It seems to me that FBC/SF compliance is just so expensive and to me 
uninspiring
and negative minded. My favourite 3-slot method definitely remains 3-slot 
DMC.
FBC complying methods generally at least verge on being strategically equivalent
to plain Approval (in the case of MTR, with extra burial opportunities and a 
random-fill
incentive).


Chris Benham





election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Election methods in student government...

2006-12-21 Thread Chris Benham


Tim Hull wrote:

 So far, all I have came up with which seems to potentially be a good 
 method is a variant of sequential proportional approval voting.  Under 
 the system, single winner elections would be simple approval voting.  
 However, for multi-winner elections each student would begin with a 
 set number of points equal to the number of seats to be elected.  
 Votes would be counted as in normal SPAV, and each weighted according 
 to the number of points each student has remaining.  Every time a 
 voter elects one of their choices, they would use up one of their 
 points.  This seems a little more understandable than standard SPAV, 
 and it hurts groups that share some preferences with the majority less.


Tim,
Your gives voters a very big incentive to not vote for someone who they 
believe will win anyway.
In the extreme case there could be a very popular candidate X that fails 
to be elected because everyone knew that X would win the first seat,
so didn't vote for X to avoid losing (using up) a point.

Take this election for 4 seats.

11: ABCD
05: D
09: EF

By my calculations with your  suggested method, it elects  DEAF. The ABC 
faction erred by approving D.

11: ABC
05: D
09: EF

Now the winners are AEBF.  That isn't a proportional or fair result. D 
has a Droop Quota and should be elected (or squeezed out in a tiebreaker,
but here the EF list easily wins the last seat). The winners should be 
D, two from ABC and one from EF.

For a good single-winner method, I suggest DMC(Ranking). Voters rank 
candidates they approve, equal-ranking allowed. Elect the Condorcet winner
if there is one. Otherwise eliminate the least-approved candidate until 
one of the remaining candidates X is pairwise undefeated by any of the other
remaining candidates. Elect the first X to appear.

I also very much like the full version of DMC (that allows voters to 
rank among unapproved candidates by entering an approval cutoff/threshold).
Even  3-slot DMC that uses a 3-slot ratings ballot, top two slots 
interpreted as approval and default placement  in bottom slot, is in my 
opinion
better than Approval or any other 3-slot method.

http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/DMC

I might have some PR suggestions in a later message.

Chris Benham







election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] reply to Juho Laatu on range voting

2006-12-18 Thread Chris Benham


Warren Smith wrote:

First:
A theorem ( http://rangevoting.org/AppCW.html )
indicates that range and approval voting both return the honest-voter Condorcet
winner if all voters act strategically.  Basically, if we are not in
the prettiest cloud but rather in the I love/hate Nixon emotional mode,
then we vote max or min on Nixon.  Assuming all voters do that with
their threshold placed somewhere between the two candidates they judge as most 
likely to win,
(which they do because they are not strategic idiots)
and assuming one of these two happens to be the honest-voter Condorcet winner, 
then
theorem: Range  Approval both will elect the honest-voter Condorcet winner, 
but meanwhile
Condorcet methods often will fail to do so.  [Juho Laatu claims misleadingly
that RV may still elect the Condorcet winner with quite good probability  
(but only with probability).  Actually, under these assumptions, the 
probability is 1.
Further, Condorcet methods with strategic voters will elect the honest-CW with
merely a probability strictly below 1.]

I can't see that this set of assumptions is really that much different 
from those needed to say that FPP will certainly elect the
sincere CW.  [And I can't see anything remotely misleading about 
Juho's statement].

Second:
The claim that honest Range Voters can have their votes 
outweighed by large factors by strategic ones, is correct.  However, 
(1) at least their honest 
vote will never actually work against them (e.g. compared to not voting at all)

The chance of that happening in practice is very small, I'd say 
insignificant if  the Condorcet method meets mono-raise (like Schulze
and DMC and most others). Those methods also allow equal-ranking at the 
top, so voters in fear of being bitten by Participation
failure can avoid it by submitting approval votes.

(2) their honest statement X is my favorite in their vote, will never hurt 
them.

You mean their honest statement X is *one* of my favourites (plural) 
will never hurt them (assuming you mean hurt them in comparison
to some other way of voting).

..consider a Condorcet election.  Gore loses to Bush thanks to a Nader spoiler
effect.  The Nader voters complain the voting system penalized us for 
honestly ordering
Nader top, Gore second. If we had had range voting we could have expressed our
honest ordering, without being penalized.

If the election is close enough in comparison to the number of available 
slots on the range ballot, then the Nader voters can of course
still be penalised  for honestly ordering Nader top, Gore second.

Second:
The claim that honest Range Voters can have their votes 
outweighed by large factors by strategic ones, is correct.  However,..

Anyhow such outweighing
  

(b) is entirely their own fault and hence is self-correcting over time and not 
a
valid attack on the voting system.

  

I reject the idea that voting honestly is a fault. The voting system 
should try to minimise the advantage of  strategists over
sincere voters, and of informed strategists over less well informed and 
zero-info. strategists. It should give the voter a clear
way of voting sincerely, and if there is a zero-info. strategy it should 
be straight-forward and similar to sincere voting.

A minimum standard is that the voting method should give good results in 
the zero-info. case with strategic voters.

Say sincere ratings are:

48: A10B4C0
47: B10C6A0
04: C10B4A0

B is the Condorcet and big sincere ratings winner, but if these voters 
all use the best 0-info. Range/Approval strategy
C the sincere ratings loser (SU worst) wins.


Chris Benham






election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Scott Ritchie's FAVS criterion - uniquely favors range voting

2006-12-17 Thread Chris Benham


Warren Smith wrote:

Yes to Chris Benham; I independently came up with a very similar IRV 
FAVS-violation example
and posted it on 
http://groups.yahoo.com/group/RangeVoting/message/2716
http://groups.yahoo.com/group/RangeVoting/message/2708

To Scott Ritchie, yes, I just invented the name FAVS and IFAVS (incomplete 
info version).

Perhaps FAVA is better name than FAVS.

N.Tideman told me, however, that he does not consider FAVS-satisfaction 
necessarily to
be a good thing.  In fact, he thinks it is probably a bad thing.

So what is that is supposed to be good about satisfying  FAVS ?


Chris Benham


election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Scott Ritchie's FAVS criterion - uniquely favors range voting

2006-12-16 Thread Chris Benham


Warren Smith wrote:

About Scott Ritchie's feel alike vote same FAVS criterion
that all members of a feel-alike group should want to vote the same.

FAVS is falsified by IRV if incomplete information:
  either A or B need 5 more votes to surpass the hated C and/or the 50% mark
  (but you do not know which) and your group has 10 votes.  So split them.

I am not sure whether FAVS is satisfied by IRV in complete information 
scenarios.

I don't know why you are not sure, because I pointed out in my last post 
that methods like IRV that are vulnerable
to Pushover strategy fail this FAVS criterion.

Suppose these are the known voting intentions:

48: A
27: BA
25: CB

On these votes, IRV eliminates C and elects B. The 48A supporters can do 
nothing to elect A if they all vote uniformly
(because if they give their first preference to A any second preferences 
won't be counted and obviously if they all give
their first preference to B or C then they will simply elect whichever 
one it is), but if  from 3 to 20 of them change their first
preference vote to C then B will be eliminated and elect A.

45: A
03: CA  (or C, or CB; sincere is A)
27: BA
25: CB

Apart from just offending mathematical elegance, this vulnerability to 
Pushover strategy is the reason why I care about
methods failing mono-raise.

Chris Benham


  


election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Is there a criterion for identical voters casting identical ballots?

2006-12-13 Thread Chris Benham


Scott Ritchie wrote:

I was thinking about corporate elections today, and how under some
voting systems an individual would want to strategically vote by
submitting multiple, different ballots.  I soon realized that this was
generalizable to multiple voters with identical preferences in any
election.

Basically, something like If a group of voters share the same
preferences, then their optimal strategy should be to vote in exactly
the same way.
  

Scott,
Are you referring to 0-info. strategy, or to informed strategy?

Chris Benham



election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Is there a criterion for identical voters casting identical ballots?

2006-12-13 Thread Chris Benham



Scott Ritchie wrote:


On Wed, 2006-12-13 at 21:06 +1030, Chris Benham wrote:
 


Scott Ritchie wrote:

   


I was thinking about corporate elections today, and how under some
voting systems an individual would want to strategically vote by
submitting multiple, different ballots.  I soon realized that this was
generalizable to multiple voters with identical preferences in any
election.

Basically, something like If a group of voters share the same
preferences, then their optimal strategy should be to vote in exactly
the same way.


 


Scott,
Are you referring to 0-info. strategy, or to informed strategy?

Chris Benham
   



Good point.  STV is only violated with informed strategy, I think
(though I may be wrong), while SNTV may be violated with 0 info.

Does size of the electorate and of my group count as information for
our purposes, or is information just the preferences of other voters?

Our purposes? This criterion is *your* idea! :)  But if it refers to 
informed strategy, I don't see the

point of limiting the type of  information.

Maybe you can have more than one version of the criterion, varying 
according to to the amount and type

of information this group of voters has.

Assuming this faction is perfectly informed and coordinated, methods 
like IRV that fail mono-raise and are

vulnerable to the Pushover strategy certainly fail this criterion.

Also Approval Margins Sort(AMS) aka Approval-Sorted Margins fails it.

http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/Approval_Sorted_Margins

Suppose the voting intentions are:
44: A|B
46: B| 
07: C|A

03: CB|

AMS is a Condorcet method that uses ranked ballots with approval cutoffs 
(signified by | ).
On these votes A is the CW and wins. Assuming that only the 46 B voters 
are informed and strategy minded,

what can they do to make B win the election?

If they all vote the same way they can't elect B, but if 30 of them vote 
BC| and the other 16 vote B|C, then

B wins.

44: A|B
16: B|C
30: BC|
07: C|A
03: CB|

Now the approval order is  B49,  A44,  C40.
AB and CA. The approval margin between A,C (4) is smaller that that 
between B,A(5) so the first
correction to our order of candidates is for A and C to swap positions 
to give  B49, C40, A44.

This order is now in harmony with the pairwise defeats (BCA) so B wins.

If instead the 46B supporters had all voted  B|C  then  A would have 
won, and if they'd all voted BC|

C would have won.

Note that this strategising couldn't have worked  with  DMC  (my 
favourite  in this genre) because  it  has  an
anti-burial property  (I call  Approval Dominant Mutual Third Burial 
Resistance) that says that if there are
three candidates XYZ, and X wins and is exclusively approved on more 
than a third of the ballots, then changing

some ballots from YX to YZ can't change the winner to Y.

http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/Definite_Majority_Choice

Chris Benham


election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Sainte-Lague, part 3

2006-12-07 Thread Chris Benham


MIKE OSSIPOFF wrote:

The very first use of the Presidential Veto was when George Washington 
vetoed a bill to apportion the house by LR/Hamilton. We used 
d'Hondt/Jefferson for a while. There was later another bill to enact 
LR/Hamilton. It passed and wasn't vetored, and LR/Hamilton was used for a 
while--till someone pointed out the bizarre paradoxes that it's subject to: 
Some people move from another state to your state, causing your state to 
lose a seat. 

Mike,
Can you (or anyone) explain or give a demonstration of  how this 
LR/Hamilton apportionment method
could do that?


Chris  Benham

election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Range Voting Strategy

2006-11-10 Thread Chris Benham

Warren Smith wrote:

 Kevin Venzke posted some news about range voting strategy.
 I have now written considerably more extensive simulator than his
 (but inspired by his) and the results are interesting.
Somewhat contrary to what Venzke seemed to be concluding,
 my conclusion is that honest range voting (scaled
 so you score the best candiate the max, the worst the min,
 and the rest linearly interpolated)  is an impressively
 good voting strategy in the random voter zero info statistical setting.
   http://rangevoting.org/RVstrat3.html

 wds
 

  

 C. Scaled sincerity. Voter linearly transforms utilities to make best 
 have rescaled utility 1,
 worst 0, and rest linearly interpolated, then uses that as her vote

 E  Mean-based thresholding. The voter gives max to every candidate at 
 least as good as
 the average value of all candidates, and gives min to the others



This doesn't surprise me very much. How does the number of slots on the 
ratings ballot
(the granularity of the Range ballot) affect this? Since E is the best 
strategy with more than
about 10 voters, and with Approval these two strategies are the same, 
does that mean that
from this point of view the fewer the better?  Then is Half-Approval 
(Range 3) better in this
respect than Range 100?

One slightly interesting approval strategy you didn't list: approve all 
candidates preferred to
all the candidates below the biggest sincere ratings gap between any two 
consecutively ranked
candidates.  I think it takes more than three candidates for this to 
differ from E.

Chris Benham
















  


election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Majority Criterion, hidden contradictions

2006-11-08 Thread Chris Benham

Abd ul-Rahman Lomax wrote:

If a method allows voters to express a strict preference, and 
Approval does, but it also allows voters to do something else, does 
this mean that voters who *have* expressed a strict preference, in 
the manner that the election method permits, are to be considered as 
not having expressed this preference merely because the method did 
not allow them to take the alternate path without expressing a strict 
preference?

Typically completely stupid question.

How can a voter express a strict preference in Approval.

Is there a means to do it?

That voters may do something else, which is express a group 
preference *is irrelevant*. Or is it relevant? How?

Suppose we have a lot of hampers of food to give away. We have larger 
ones that contain more
than one type of food, and smaller ones that contain only one type. We 
then invite recipients to
each choose one only hamper to take home.  So yes, some of these people 
could have expressed
a strict preference for a certain type of food and a few might have, 
but we never asked them to
and those that did paid the price of getting less food.

What in the 
criterion covers this contingency?

For especially obtuse morons, it comes under the heading of  criteria 
that apply to ranked ballot
methods. Approval isn't a ranked ballot method, so we ask if the 
voters each have a candidate they mean
to rank alone in first place on a ranked ballot, can we (reasonably, 
reliably, consistently) infer from the ballots
they submit who those candidates are?

The answer for FPP is obviously Yes. For this purpose an FPP ballot 
can properly be considered to be
simply a ranked ballot that doesn't allow equal-ranking at the top. The 
fact that the lower preferences
are ignored or invisible or don't exist is irrelevant.

I'm not sure that Benham said exactly what he intended to say..

I did. I'm normally careful to do that.

We assume that voters intend to do what they did.

For criteria that apply to ranked ballots, we assume that the voters 
mean to submit a
ranked ballot. Venzke and Woodall interpret Approval ballots as ranked 
ballots
with all the ranked candidates approved and the numbers indicating the 
order in
which they are ranked  obscured.

I think Abd's real-world propaganda concerns are misplaced. In 
situations where
FPP elects a majority winner, supporters of that candidate will usually 
have enough
pre-poll information to know to use the exclusively approve your 
favourite strategy.
In fact usually it will be known in advance who the two front-runners 
are, and if the
voters in general adopt the sensible approve the front-runner I prefer 
to the other
plus all the candidates I prefer to both of them strategy then of 
course in practice
Approval will always elect a majority favourite.

Approval is in much bigger trouble in comparison to IRV, which *does* 
have it all
over Approval in terms of  majority-related guarantees (except perhaps 
for Minimal
Defense).

Promoting Approval versus IRV requires continually hammering  Favourite 
Betrayal
Criterion, ultimate simplicity and huge bang for buck, and Minimal 
Defense.


Chris Benham





  


election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] RE : Re: RE : Majority Criterion, hidden contradictions

2006-11-06 Thread Chris Benham






Abd ul-Rahman Lomax wrote:

  

  
  

  No, Range does this. If we assume that voters
express their expected value for the various
candidates, the expected value for the voters,
collectively, is the sum of the individual expectations.
  

Sure, but I don't see how this assumption can be taken for granted.

  
  
No election method can extract information from the voters and use it 
to determine the winner if the voters do not express the information.

The assumption cannot be taken for granted, which is exactly why I 
expressed it as an assumption. However, what is being said is that if 
people use Range sincerely and honestly, Range will maximize expected 
value, summed over all the voters.


  

Yes, but how many of "the people"?

90: A9B1 (sincere is A9B1)
10: B99A0 (sincere is B5A3)

All the voters have a sincere low opinion of both candidates, but 90%
think that A is 900%
better than B and yet B wins (with only 10% of the voters not being
"sincere and honest").

  
Consider a diagnostic tool, a questionnaire to be filled out to 
determine health status and medical treatment. If people lie on the 
questionnaire, the results will be suboptimum.

Now, the question then becomes, will people lie? Some will, depends 
on the definition of "lie."
  

The definition is fuzzy because the voters are not even being asked a
clear unambiguous
question.

  
Here is the paradox: if voters care little about whether or not A or 
B wins, but want A to win, they can distort the rating of B. For the 
condition to be true, the voters must simultaneously "care little" 
and care enough to lie about their true preferences.
  

That rests on the false assumption that it is (significantly) more
bother to lie than to tell the truth.
In fact it seems to me to be less bother. I can well imagine being sure
that I prefer A to B but
not sure exactly what my honest rating of each is, so I'd find it
easier to vote A max. and B min.

  
My real point is that we don't know, very well, how voters will 
actually behave. We very much need real-world examples, theory will 
only take us so far.

  
  
If we can't make this assumption then there is no guarantee that Range
will outperform a majoritarian method in terms of expected value.

  
  




  

We can certainly be sure majoritarian methods will outperform Range in
the worst-case scenarios.


Chris Benham



election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] RE : Ranked Preference benefits

2006-11-03 Thread Chris Benham
l the candidates are in the initial DM set, so C is eliminated and then
the "new DM set" is {R} so R wins.




  Example 4. Some of the large party voters think C is good but  
majority of them think C is no good.

15: LCR
30: LCR
14: RCL
26: RCL
15: CL=R

Initial approvals: L45, C44, R40
CR, CL, LR, so initial DM set is {L,C}.
Initial top preferences: L45, R40, C15.

C is eliminated and L wins (agreeing with your method).


Chris Benham






election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] RE : Ranked Preference benefits

2006-11-03 Thread Chris Benham
Juho,

 You mentioned strongest indicated preference gap as the approval  
 cut. How about defining it dynamically so that one would find the  
 strongest preference relation that still has non-eliminated  
 candidates at both sides of it? (like in RP) 

CB: I did. Or if I didn't make it clear, I meant to. Otherwise there 
wouldn't be any point to the lower ranked  preference gaps.

 Interpreting ballots as approving all candidates above the  strongest 
 indicated preference gap...

 Recalculate (among remaining candidates) the DM set and repeat the  
 whole process until an X is elected. 

When we repeat the whole process, strongest indicated preference gap 
refers to preference gap among remaining candidates.

BTW, the initials RP are well taken by  Ranked Pairs so if  your 
method is going to stick around maybe it should have a different name. 
The name
ranked preferences seems to just refer to the ballot style, which has 
been previously on EM called a  dyadic ballot.

Chris  Benham



Juho wrote:

 On Nov 3, 2006, at 19:50 , Chris Benham wrote:

 Juho wrote:

 On Nov 2, 2006, at 1:29 , Kevin Venzke wrote:

 Juho, --- Juho [EMAIL PROTECTED] a écrit :

 Example 1. Large party voters consider C better than the other  
 large party candidate, but not much. 45: LCR 40: RCL 15:  
 CL=R Ranked Preferences elects L. (first round: L=-10, C=-70,  
 R=-20; second round: L=-10, R=-20)

 In my opinion, if C is able to convince *every voter* to  
 acknowledge that he is better than the major party alternative,  
 then C is surely not a bad result.

 There is no need to convince every voter. This example is  
 simplified (for readability) but not extreme since there could  well 
 be a mixture of different kind of votes. (See e.g. example  4.) The 
 utility of C could be really low to the voters even though  it was 
 ranked higher than the worst candidate (in Range terms e.g.  R=99, 
 C=1, L=0). One of the key points of Ranked Preferences is  that also 
 weak preferences can be expressed and they may have impact.

 CB: So in your example is electing C a bad result or not?!


 I'd say it would be a bad result. If we only knew the flat  
 preferences then C would be a good choice (Condorcet winner). But  
 when we know the preference strengths electing C doesn't look  
 sensible. We may have different ways to estimate at which point C  
 should not be elected. Range would give one style of measuring it.  
 Ranked preferences gave another one which I think is quite natural.

 I'd prefer methods where voters can simply vote sincerely without  
 considering when it is beneficial to truncate and when not.

 Yes, don't we all.  You like methods  that  meet  Later-no-Harm   
 and  Later-no-Help, so how
 then is your method supposed to be better than IRV?


 This is a topic that I was planning to write more about. Ranked  
 Preferences actually can support also IRV style voting in addition to  
 Condorcet style flat preferences and many kind of more complex  
 styles. IRV style ballots would look like ABCDE. If all  
 voters vote this way the behaviour of the method resembles IRV.  
 Voters are thus not forced to vote in IRV style but they can do so if  
 they so want, possibly for defensive reasons (later-no-harm etc). The  
 tied at bottom rule has also a similar defensive impact.

 I have no clear proofs (due to complexity and insufficient background  
 work) but I believe the Ranked Preferences method quite well balanced  
 e.g. in the sense that voting IRV style is not the only or  
 recommended or optimal way to vote but just one of the alternatives,  
 for voters that really feel that way. I hope the readers of this list  
 will point out any potential weaknesses.

 I hope the method is better than IRV for the same reasons I believe  
 it is (in some/many aspects) better than Condorcet. It is more  
 expressive and therefore takes voter preferences better into account.  
 Maybe without introducing too many weaknesses that would spoil the idea.

 Condorcet voters need not leave non-approved candidates unlisted.  I 
 think Ranked Preferences provides some improvements. I'll try to  
 explain. If A and B voters would all truncate we would end up in  
 bullet voting and falling to a plurality style election. Not a  good 
 end result. 45: LC=R 40: RC=L 15: CL=R

 Since it gives the same winner as your suggested method, why not?


 It gives the same winner in this particular case but not in general.  
 And of course I try to make the method more expressive than  
 Condorcet, not less expressive :-). (Range easily becomes Approval in  
 competitive situations. I don't want Condorcet (or Ranked  
 Preferences) to become Plurality.)

 I think it is a problem of basic Condorcet methods that they  easily 
 elect the centrist candidate.

 No, that is their theoretical strength.


 I agree that ability to elect centrist candidates is one of their  
 strengths. I just want to add that centrist Condorcet winners are not  
 always

Re: [EM] Ranked Preferences, example calculations

2006-10-30 Thread Chris Benham
, the language is technical.

 Remember, the sincere vote here was A99B98.


CB: The ranking was sincere but as I explained, the ratings maybe not.


 This is more interesting:

 36: A99B98C0
 18: B99B98C0
 46: C99A0=B0

 This time the AB faction have a comfortable enough majority to win 
 without insincere equal-ranking, and
 A (the Condorcet and IRV winner) wins.  But Range (like Approval) is 
 vulnerable to a form of
 Burial with a nasty defection incentive.

 36: A99B98C0
 18: B99A0=C0   (sincere is BAC)
 46: C99A0=B0

 The 18 B voters have defected from the AB coalition by insincerely 
 changing from B99A98
 to B99B0=C0, and Range rewards their dishonesty (and disloyalty) by 
 electing B.


 Now, why would they do this? Only if they strongly prefer B to A. But 
 this contradicts the initial conditions.

CB: Range only allows voters to express one strong (by your 
definition) preference (between two candidates or two sets of  
equally-ranked candidates). In the initial conditions
the B supporters strongest preference was BC. Of course their sincere 
BA preference doesn't have to be all that strong for them to want to 
make B win.


 . And yet we imagine that the B voters are going to lie about their 
 preference, in cahoots with each other, in order to elect B?

CB: Who (besides you) mentioned anything about them being in cahoots 
with each other?  No coordination is needed. As long as the other 
factions vote the same way, individual members of the B faction can try 
the strategy without any risk of it back-firing (and it can work if only 
some of them do it.)



 The Majority Criterion properly applies (i.e., is desirable) to binary 
 elections. It gets dicey when there are more than two choices.

CB: Why on earth is that, in your book?  Strength of preference is 
all-important when there are three candidates, but not two?


Chris Benham




election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Ranked Preferences, example calculations

2006-10-29 Thread Chris Benham






Abd ul-Rahman Lomax wrote:

  At 11:34 PM 10/27/2006, Chris Benham wrote:
  
  
Abd ul-Rahman Lomax wrote:



  That is, healthy group decision process follows certain general 
principles. The Majority Criterion neglects an important part of this.

  

That is because it is about *elections*, which of course isn't 
necessarily the beginning and end of  "healthy group decision process".

  
  
For some reason, Chris continues to insist upon the specious 
distinction between elections and general decision-making process. 
The term "election" covers any kind of choice being made; however 
usage focuses on the selection of one candidate out of a number, for 
single-winner, or of multiple candidates out of a larger number, for 
mutiple-winner. And we also assume, generally, for the purposes of 
this list, that elections are of candidates, and the candidates are 
people who will hold an office.

But for a group to select candidates or to select a pizza involves, 
properly, the same considerations. Pizza is almost certain to be less 
important a choice, but the importance of the choice only should mean 
that greater care would be taken. Not that a different process is involved.
  

CB: No.I see "group decision making process" as spread out along a
continuum with "informal consensus"
at one end and civil war or violent "mob rule" at the other. Abd sees
elections as (in his view undesirably)
substituting for consensus and wants to change them into mechanisms for
reaching a formal consensus,
whereas I think they should more properly be seen as tough competitions
that substitute for civil war.

A group of people ordering pizza are presumably a freely associating
group of friends, so all are 
considerate of the other's strong preferences (and "needs") and no-one
wants to oppress anyone or
listen to anyone whingeing while they are trying to enjoy their pizza.
(And of course if anyone is really unhappy
they can presumably just leave the group and not starve.)So in that
case of course the group would
probably quickly come to an informal consensus, and if there *was* any
formal "voting" then I suppose
some variation of Range or Approval would do and may be best.

But suppose in an experiment to please Abd, the pizza orderers aren't
friends and maybe even dislike 
each other, they are very hungry and there won't be enough pizza to
satisfy everyone's hunger and the 
people are locked in the room with nothing to eat but this pizza they
are ordering. Then "informal consensus"
will tend to break down and we will have a scenario more appropriate
for a tough election. Voters might
have incentive to vote for a variety others dislike in the hope they
will then get a bigger share.

  

The only substantial argument I see against Range is that the method 
is allegedly vulnerable to strategic voting. *But what we have now is 
what Range would look like if everyone votes strategically.*


So Range would not make things worth, unless... unless honest people 
vote intermediate values, and dishonest people vote the extremes, and 
there are enough of these dishonest people that election results are 
warped as a result.

However, I have argued that this can only happen when the honest 
people do not have a strong preference. When they have, and express, 
a strong preference, and they are in the majority, the dishonest 
people can try what they may, they can only nudge the results among 
candidates strongly preferred by the majority.
  

A "strong preference" for *what* exactly?.. that a single candidate be
elected, that a single candidate
not be elected, that the winner come from a certain set, what?


  
Essentially, some writers treat the vulnerability of Range to 
strategic voting as if it were a proven thing. They simply assume it. 
It has *not* been proven, far from it. And it seems to me that this 
is a false charge against Range.

  

It would. It is obvious to anyone with a clue that it is.

  
E
  
  

  That is, if the majority does not want to please the minority, it 
does not care if they are devastated by the outcome of the 
election, if their attitude is "they should get over it," then they 
can easily get what they want. Just vote it as a strong preference.

  

The problem with Range is that if  "the majority" are not self-aware 
and coordinated, they cannot
"easily get what they want".

  
  
On the contrary, the condition being described was that the majority 
had a strong preference. Under Range, all they need to do is vote 
that preference as a strong one. What coordination does this take?

  

Again "strong preference" for what exactly? And how strong is "strong"?

  
This has been stated so many times by Warren, but obviously it bears 
repeating. The best vote in Range is a sincere one. Sure, partisans 
may distort

[EM] EM: 10 Steps to Repair American Democracy for only $2.99 on Amazon.com, forwarded from Steven Hill

2006-10-25 Thread Chris Benham
Dear friends,

I thought you might be interested in knowing about an amazing bargain --
right now Amazon.com is offering my book 10 Steps to Repair American
Democracy for only $2.99.  Yes, you read that correctly, only $3!  I
thought it must be a mistake, but one person I know just bought 40 copies at
that price. Plus the shipping will be free for any order over $25, so this
is an incredible bargain. Just in time to do some early Christmas shopping,
at three dollars apiece 10 Steps to Repair American Democracy will make a
great stocking stuffer. Ten books for $30 (and with free shipping for orders
over $25, it's the same price to buy nine books as to buy six). I don't know
how long this terrific price will last, it may be only for a limited time,
so get them while you can.  Here's a link to 10 Steps on Amazon

http://www.amazon.com/gp/product/0976062151 

Steven Hill's 10 Steps to Repair American Democracy is as practical as it
is insightful, offering innovative ways to fix our broken political system.
Read it, roll up your sleeves, and get to work.
--- Arianna Huffington

We are fortunate to have Steven Hill's latest book, 10 Steps to Repair
American Democracy. He identifies ten critical problems with our democracy
and offers concrete solutions to each one. 10 Steps is a blueprint for a
reinvigoration of our republic.
 -- from the foreword by Hendrik Hertzberg, The New Yorker
 
If you don't mind, please forward this to your own email lists. My apologies
if you receive it more than once. 

Yours,

Steven Hill

P.S. in case you are interested, my recent lecture to the Cambridge Forum
about 10 Steps to Repair American Democracy can be viewed on the web at
http://forum.wgbh.org/wgbh/forum.php?lecture_id=3221. 


election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Majority Criterion poor standard for elections

2006-10-24 Thread Chris Benham

Simmons, Forest wrote:

It seems to me that if there is a majority winner, then she should at least 
have a chance of winning.  What if we chose by random ballot from among all of 
the candidates that have a majority beat path to the Range winner (with a 
final approval vote to ratify this choice)?
 

  

  

Why not just automate that and with one trip to the polls elect the 
winner of the pairwise comparison between the Range winner and a 
randomly chosen candidate with a beatpath to the Range winner, to make a 
pretty terrible method  (but still better than Range) with a strong 
random element?

Chris  Benham

election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Condorcet + IRV completion?

2006-10-16 Thread Chris Benham


Andrew Myers wrote:

Here's an obvious idea that must have been considered before. How about 
using the basic Condorcet method, but running IRV on the Schwartz set, 
if any? Are there any known results on how well this 
works/vulnerabilities/etc.?


  


Andrew,
Yes. Douglas Woodall has demonstrated that dropping the non-members of 
the Schwartz/Smith set
from the ballots and then applying IRV  causes the resulting method to 
fail both mono-add-plump
and mono-append, two very weak (normally easy to meet) criteria that I 
rate a essential.

He refers to IRV as AV (Alternative Vote) and the Smith set as CNTT 
(Condorcet(Net) Top Tier):

abcd 10
bcda  6
c 2
dcab  5

All the candidates are in the top tier, and the AV winner is a.  But
if you add two extra ballots that plump for a, or append a to the two
c ballots, then the CNTT becomes {a,b,c}, and if you delete d from all
the ballots before applying AV then c wins.



But instead we don't need to even mention the Schwartz or any other set 
in the algorithm:

Before the first and each subsequent IRV elimination, check to see if 
the there is a single candidate X
with no (among remaining candidates) pairwise losses. As soon as an X 
appears, elect X.

That *does* meet mono-append and mono-add-plump, with no disadvantage 
compared to the other
method.  Like IRV, it still fails mono-raise.

In common with IRV and Schulze it meets the Plurality criterion and  
Clone Independence. In common
with other IRV methods, we lose IRV's Later-no-Harm and  Mono-add-Top.

I like it, with above-bottom equal preferences not allowed so as to make 
Pushover (turkey raising)
strategy more difficult.

It has the property that when there are three candidates XYZ, and  X 
wins with more than a third of the
first preferences, then changing some ballots from  YXZ  to  YZX 
can't change the winner to Y.

The other property that it has in common with IRV but not Schulze etc. 
is that in the zero-information case
regardless of how the voter rates the candidates the voter has no 
strategy that is better than sincere ranking.

Some dislike the fact that it fails Minimal Defense.

49: A
24: B
27: CB

Here it elects A.

46: AB
44: BC  (maybe was BA or B)
10: C

Here I like the fact that it elects A. Meeting both MD and the 
anti-burial property  (Dominant Mutual Third Burial Resistance?)
would force the method to elect C.

Chris Benham

election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] DH3 pathology, margins, and winning votes

2006-08-28 Thread Chris Benham




Warren,

Re: [EM] DH3 pathology, margins, and
winning votes 

--- In [EMAIL PROTECTED],
Chris Benham [EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:

 Warren,
 I have two main points in reply to your "DH3 pathology"
anti-Condorcet
 argument.

  DH3 scenario with strategic votes by the A- and B-voters.
#voters
  Their Vote
  37 CA,BD
  32 ADB,C
  31 BDA,C
 
  Then the pairwise tallies are going to be:
 
  Definitely A,B  D  C
  Probably C  A,B
 
  In which case we (probably) have a Condorcet cycle scenario.
(It is
  actually two 3-cycles which share the common DC arc.) The
weakest
  defeats in these cycles are CA,B which means, under both
every
  Condorcet rule I know of (since I think they all are
equivalent in the
  3-cycle case) and Borda, that one of {A,B} is going to be the
winner.
 
  I verified that A wins in the 50-50 mixture case under
Tideman ranked
  pairs RankedPairs.html, Schulze beatpaths
SchulzeComplic.html, and
  basic Condorcet by using Eric Gorr's Condorcet calculator
  http://www.ericgorr.net/condorcet/
using this input
 
 37:CABD
 37:CBAD
 32:ADBC
 32:ADCB
 31:BDAC
 31:BDCA

 The first is that those "defeat-dropper" style algorithms (like
 Beatpath, Ranked Pairs, River,MinMax) that as you say are all
equivalent
 in the 3-cycle case
 are not my favourites. I prefer both DMC ('Definite Majority
Choice',
 which allows voters to enter approval cutoffs) and Schwartz,IRV
(which
 elects the
 member of Schwartz set highest ordered by IRV on the original
ballots).

--Can you go thru how those two new methods would work?

CB: Certainly.

Schwartz,IRV:
"Identify the members of the Schwartz set, but drop no candidates from
the ballots.
Commence a normal IRV count. When all but one Schwartz set member x has
been
eliminated, elect x".

For this method I favour allowing truncation, but not above bottom
equal-ranking.
It is much better than Schwartz//IRV, which drops non-Schwartz set
members from
the ballots before applying IRV. Of course Smith verus Schwartz isn't
a big deal.

Definite Majority Choice.
"Voters submit ranked ballots with approval cutoffs. Truncation and
equal-ranking allowed.
Ballots with no approval cutoff specified are interpreted as approving
all candidates ranked 
above bottom or equal-bottom.
Eliminate all candidates that are pairwise beaten by a more approved
candidate.
Among the remaining candidates, one (x) will pairwise beat all the
others.
Elect x."

http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/DMC

Several other algorithms are equivalent. Also quite good in my opinion
is the simple version with 
no approval cutoffs which just interprets all ranked (above
equal-bottom) candidates as approved .

My current favourite method that uses high-intensity range ballots is
this "automated version":

"Inferring ranking from ratings, eliminate all non-members of the
Schwartz set.
Then interpret the ballots as approving those candidates that they rate
(among those remaining) 
above average (and half-approving those they rate exactly average).
Based on these thus derived approvals, and again inferring ranking from
ratings, apply DMC."


 My second point is that in your scenario the A and B supporters
seem
 mainly concerned to elect their favourites, so in that case why
wouldn't
 they simply be guided in their strategy by their favourite
candidates? Seeing how
 they stand in the polls, it would be in the interests of both A
and B to
 make a preference-swap deal at the expense of C. That way they
each increase
 their chances of being elected form below 33% to about 50% without
anyone
 having to flirt with the car-crash.

--That sounds like naive bunk.
The problem with that is, how the hell do voters "make a deal" with
each other? This whole "deal" idea is a myth. It is unenforcable and
votes are secret ballot and nobody can make a deal with a gazillion
voters anyhow even if it were enforceable and verifiable.

CB: "Naive bunk"? It is regular practice in Australian elections for
seats in Parliament.
Admittedly this is helped a lot in most jurisdictions by truncation not
being allowed.
The candidates are normally obliged to register "tickets" with the
electoral commission
in advance of the election, partly so attempts to manipulate the result
by distributing bogus 
"how-to-vote" cards can be detected and stamped on.

Unless there is automatic and/or long standing cooperation based on
ideological affinity
the parties/candidates negotiate preference deals with each other.
Party volunteers on
election day hand out how-to-vote cards to voters on their way in to
vote. Most voters
take at least one and follow one of them.

In your example, based on the sincere preferences, the candidates seem
to be about equidistant
from each other on the "political spectrum". With a clear front-runner
(C) and the other two
(A and B) too close to call, the A and B candidates both gain a lot
from swapping preferences.

If the vo

Re: [EM] DH3 pathology, margins, and winning votes

2006-08-28 Thread Chris Benham
Warren,

BTR-IRV can entirely eliminate the Smith set
and elect some nonmember.

How can it possibly do that?


Chris Benham



Warren Smith wrote:

Sorry, my last email was in error:  BTR-IRV can entirely eliminate the Smith 
set
and elect some nonmember.

wds

election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info

  


election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] DH3 pathology, margins, and winning votes

2006-08-26 Thread Chris Benham




Warren,

  
DH3 scenario with strategic votes by the A- and B-voters. 

  
#voters 
Their Vote 
  
  
37 
CA,BD 
  
  
32 
AD=B=C 
  
  
31 
BD=A=C 
  

  

Aren't the A and B voters here (in effect) just truncating?

Chris Benham


Warren Smith wrote:

  Sorry, for some reason, the hyperlink in my previous post was omitted.
Let me try again:
   http://rangevoting.org/WinningVotes.html


  




election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Report of the Irish Commission on Electronic Voting

2006-08-04 Thread Chris Benham

I've been advised that this is important and recently released.

http://www.cev.ie/htm/report/download_second.htm


Chris Benham



election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Forwarded from Steven Hill, his WA Post oped: Will Your Vote Count in 2006?

2006-08-04 Thread Chris Benham






Will Your Vote
Count in 2006?
By
Steven Hill
Special to
washingtonpost.com's
Think Tank Town
Tuesday, August 1, 2006; 11:56 AM 
http://www.washingtonpost.com/wp-dyn/content/article/2006/08/01/AR2006080100561.html

Watching
Mexico live through a controversial presidential
election was like holding up a mirror to our own election difficulties
in
recent years. As we round the corner and head toward the upcoming
November
elections -- with control of the Congress up for grabs -- what can
Americans
expect? Will our votes count? There is both cause for worry, as well as
signs
that effective voting reform advocacy is paying off.
The
root cause of our troubled elections is that,
unbelievably, the U.S. provides less security, testing, and oversight
of our
nation's voting equipment and election administration than it does to
slot
machines and the gaming industry. Our elections are administered by a
hodgepodge of over 3000 counties scattered across the country with
minimal
national standards or uniformity. Widely differing practices on the
testing and
certification of voting equipment, the handling of provisional and
absentee
ballots, protocols for recounts, and training of election officials and
poll
workers makes for a bewildering terrain.

  

  
  
  
  
  
  About Think
Tank Town
  
  Washingtonpost.com
edits and publishescolumnssubmitted by10 prominent think tanks on a
rotating basis every other weekday. Each think tankis free to choose
its authors and the topics it believes are most important and timely.
Here are the participating organizations:
  
  American Enterprise Institute
 
  
  Brookings Institution  
  
  Cato Institute  
  
  Center for American Progress
 
  
  Center for Strategic and International Studies
 
  
  Council on Foreign Relations
 
  
  Heritage Foundation  
  
  New America Foundation  
  
  RAND Corporation  
  
  Urban Insitute 
  
  
  
  
  

  

The
three federal laboratories testing voting
equipment and software operate with little government oversight. They
are
called "independent testing authorities," even though two of them have
donated tens of thousands of dollars to GOP candidates and the
Republican
National Committee. The shoddy testing and certification procedures are
greased
by a revolving door between government regulators and the industry.
Former
secretaries of state from California, Florida and Georgia, once their
state's
chief regulator, became paid lobbyists for the corporate vendors after
stepping
down from public office, as did a former governor of New Hampshire.
Several
secretaries of state in 2004 served as co-chairs of the George W. Bush
re-election campaign for their state; one of these oversaw the election
in
which he ran -- successfully -- for governor.
Conflicts
of interest have crept like a weed into
nearly every crevice of election administration. Making matters worse,
the
powers-that-be appear uncertain about what a secure election
administration
system actually looks like. This was painfully obvious at the Voting
Systems
Testing Summit in November 2005, which marked the first time that top
federal
regulators, vendors, testing laboratories, election administrators,
computer
scientists and fair elections advocates came together in one place. No
one
could articulate a comprehensive inventory of the many problems in
securing the
vote, much less the solutions. Instead, there was a lot of
finger-pointing and
excuses.
Clearly,
the biggest threat to the integrity of our
elections is not the shortcomings of any particular type of
computerized voting
equipment but the fact that -- like the failed rescue effort following
Hurricane Katrina -- no one seems to be steering the ship. There is no
central
brain or team that has a handle on all aspects of the process,
developing best
practices or a roadmap that states and counties can follow. Tragically,
while
Congress has appropriated $3 billion for buying new voting equipment,
the money
is arriving before there are necessary standards in place to ensure the
money
is not wasted.
Yet
these legitimate concerns also must be kept in
perspective, lest we spiral into a paralyzing paranoia. There are a
number of
positives. Election security activists are more mobilized than ever and
they
are having an impact. They have raised the profile of these issues to
the point
of national urgency. Their efforts, once considered the actions of
fanatical
gadflies, are being increasingly cited by respected election
bureaucrats.
Former President Jimmy Carter and Secretary of State James A. Baker III
were
co-chairs of a 2005 bipartisan commission which warned that "software
can
be modified maliciously before being installed into individual voting
machines.
There is no reason to trust insiders in the election industry any more
than in
other industries."
Reform
advocates' increased credibility has 

Re: [EM] voting reform effort in DENVER - PLEASE HELP

2006-06-11 Thread Chris Benham
-winner alternatives 
to IRV, your list should include
both versions of  Definite Majority Choice(DMC): the one that interprets 
all ranked candidates as
approved (of course allowing truncation), and the one that allows voters 
to enter an approval cutoff
so that they can rank unapproved candidates.

This has two simple definitions:
(1) Elect the CW if there is one. If not, eliminate (drop from the 
ballots) the least-approved candidate.
Repeat until there is a winner.
(2) Eliminate all candidates that are pairwise-beaten by a more-approved 
candidate. One of the
remaining candidates x will pairwise beat all the other remaining 
candidates. Elect x.

This method meets Condorcet, Clone Independence and Mono-raise.

Number 4 on your list is all wrong. As I understand it, BTR-IRV stand 
for Bottom Two Runoff-IRV,
which at each stage eliminates the pairwise-loser of the  two remaining 
candidates with the fewest top-preferences.
It's just an attempt to smuggle a not very  good Condorcet method past 
IRV supporters.
Neither it nor the method you define is equivalent to Condorcet with 
Plurality completion.

The method you define is  Coombs or one of the two versions of  Coombs 
(the worse one). It is far worse than
IRV. The version you give fails Majority Favourite.  It is possible 
that a candidate with more than half the first
preference votes will be eliminated. (The other version has a majority 
stopping rule).


Chris  Benham




election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Correlated Instant Borda Runoff, without Borda

2005-12-23 Thread Chris Benham
Dan,

Dan Bishop wrote:

*** EXAMPLE: CLONE-TRANSFER APPROXIMATION OF IRV ***

Consider the election method:

count the first-choice votes of each candidate
while no candidate has a majority of the vote:
eliminate the last-place candidate
transfer that candidate's votes to their most-correlated candidate
elect the candidate with a majority of a vote

I  can't  see any justification for this (versus proper IRV) at all. If 
we eliminate candidates and transfer
votes, then I can't see how we can justify not transferring them exactly 
where they want to go (or any
point in not doing that).

As I understand it,  Kuhlman's  Correlated Instant Borda Runoff  was 
conceived of as way of  decloning
Borda.  IRV  is already Clone Independent, and so doesn't need  decloning!


Chris  Benham



election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] [ER] FBC-complying Margins-like method (?)

2005-12-19 Thread Chris Benham
Kevin, Warren, other FBC freaks,

I've recently had an idea for a FBC-complying  Margins method.

Voters rank the candidates, equal-ranking and truncation allowed.
(1) Make  pairwise comparisons. Treating pairwise defeats by margins 
that are smaller
 than or equal to the number of ballots on which both candidates are 
ranked equal-top
as pairwise equalities,  eliminate candidates that are not in the 
smallest non-empty set of 
candidates that are pairwise undefeated by any outside-the-set candidates.

(2)If  more than one candidate remains, drop eliminated candidates from 
the ballots and
then delete ballots that make no ranking distinction between remaining 
candidates, and repeat
step 1.

(3) Repeat steps 1 and 2 as many times as possible. (If  at any stage 
only one candidate remains
then that candidate is the winner.)

(4) If  after step 3 more than one candidate remains, then with ballots 
that rank both the candidates in
a pairwise comparison equal-top used to modify the defeat margins by 
counting as  whole single votes
for the pairwise loser (so that some margins can be negative, but not so 
that any pairwise defeats can
be reversed); change the pairwise defeat by a smallest margin to an 
equality; and as in step 1 again
eliminate candidates that are not in the smallest non-empty set of 
candidates that are pairwise undefeated
by any outside-the-set candidates.

(5) If more than one candidate remains, then again drop eliminated 
candidates from the ballots and then
delete ballots that make no ranking distinction between remaining 
candidates.

(6) Keep repeating steps 4 and 5 until  only one candidate remains.

In common with  MDD,ER-Bucklin(whole) I  think it meets Majority for 
Solid Coalitions  and  Condorcet(Gross).
But unlike that method, it meets  Independence from Irrelevant Ballots.


Chris  Benham






election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] [ER] FBC-complying Margins-like method (?)

2005-12-19 Thread Chris Benham
Kevin,

Yes  I am sure you are right, thanks.  Probably then I'll stick with 
MDD,ER-Bucklin(whole) as
my favourite FBC  method.

Chris  Benham



Kevin Venzke wrote:

Chris,

--- Chris Benham [EMAIL PROTECTED] a écrit :
  

Kevin, Warren, other FBC freaks,

I've recently had an idea for a FBC-complying  Margins method.

Voters rank the candidates, equal-ranking and truncation allowed.
(1) Make  pairwise comparisons. Treating pairwise defeats by margins 
that are smaller
 than or equal to the number of ballots on which both candidates are 
ranked equal-top
as pairwise equalities,  eliminate candidates that are not in the 
smallest non-empty set of 
candidates that are pairwise undefeated by any outside-the-set
candidates.

(2)If  more than one candidate remains, drop eliminated candidates from 
the ballots and
then delete ballots that make no ranking distinction between remaining 
candidates, and repeat
step 1.



There are two reasons why I don't believe this can work.

1. You're using a beatpath concept. Although you're replacing certain
wins with pairwise ties, it could be that a pairwise tie between X and
Y is what causes them to be excluded from the top tier. Replacing wins
with ties only helps to satisfy FBC when it's clear that a tie between
X and Y is at least as good for them as one of them beating the other.

2. You're eliminating candidates and recalculating. I think all you
can afford to do is disqualify candidates without recalculating anything.
Elimination makes it difficult to foresee what a specific vote is capable 
of doing across multiple rounds. It's much the same issue as Raynaud
or Nanson failing monotonicity.

Kevin Venzke



   

   
   
  


election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Bucklin PR ?

2005-11-21 Thread Chris Benham
Kevin,

I see from your response to the Electowiki  Method support poll  that 
you nearly  support the ER-Bucklin(whole)  single-winner method,
and  that for  Legislative election methods you like possibly a 
proportional approval scheme.

What do you think of  this PR version of  ER-Bucklin(whole) ?

Voters rank  candidates, truncatation and equal-ranking ok.
The winning threshold  to elect the first winner is a Droop quota 
(number of valid ballots/number of seats +1).
(1) Commence the ER-Bucklin(whole) process until the candidate with the 
highest score has a winning threshold.
Declare that single candidate elected.
(2) Reduce the weight of all the ballots that contributed to the 
winner's tally by an equal amount which sums to a Droop quota.
(3) Based on these reweighted ballots, the reduced number of unfilled 
seats, and not counting as valid any now exhausted ballots,
reset the  Droop quota.
(4) Repeat  the above three steps until all the seats are filled.


Chris Benham

election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] oped in Mercury News on Citizens' Assemblies (forwarded from Steven Hill)

2005-11-19 Thread Chris Benham

From: Steven Hill, New America Foundation 

Dear friends, I have an oped in yesterday's San Jose Mercury News about
Citizens' Assemblies as a vehicle for political reform. I thought you would
find it interesting. Please forward to your lists and others interested.

Thanks,

Steven Hill


In Canada, regular folks are put to work on reforms
By Steven Hill
San Jose Mercury News
Wed, Nov. 16, 2005
http://www.mercurynews.com/mld/mercurynews/news/opinion/13180228.htm 

Despite voters rejecting Gov. Arnold Schwarzenegger's attempts to end-run
the Legislature, that does not mean voters don't want change. California's
political leaders must try to pick up the pieces of what is left of state
politics. The challenges are daunting, particularly because both the
governor and Legislature have lost so much credibility.

The question is: How do we move forward? One of the solutions may lie across
the border in Canada. It's called a Citizens' Assembly, and it was on
display last year in the province of British Columbia. The government there
turned over to the people the task of basic political reform, and by doing
so took the partisanship out of the process, something California badly
needs.

Here's how it worked: The government randomly selected 160 average citizens
to participate in the Citizens' Assembly, like selecting a jury pool. The
Assembly had 80 women and 80 men from all of the province's 79 electoral
districts. It was an independent, non-partisan body charged with a
particular focus: to examine British Columbia's electoral system, and how
their winner-take-all system was performing in determining who got elected
to the Legislature.

This effort was unique. Often such task forces are dominated by the usual
political insiders or good-government activists. Nowhere in the world had
randomly selected citizens with no history of interest in electoral reform
been so empowered to shape major proposals. Yet the work of the Assembly was
unanimously endorsed by the political parties in the Legislature and
community leaders.

The Assembly's tenure was divided into three phases: Learning about reform,
January-March 2004; public hearings, May-June; and deliberations,
September-November. They met on weekends, their expenses and a small per
diem paid for by the government. They were visited by top experts from all
political perspectives who gave them the benefit of their knowledge and
analysis.

The Assembly delivered a final report in December 2004. It voted 146-7 to
toss out its longtime winner-take-all, single-seat district electoral system
and replace it with a proportional representation system. ``This really is
power to the people,'' enthused Jack Blaney, the chair of the Citizens'
Assembly.

The Assembly's proposal was submitted by the legislature directly to the
voters in a referendum last May. Because the Citizens' Assembly was composed
of average citizens, their recommendation had tremendous legitimacy with the
public. A robust 58 percent of voters supported the measure.

The Citizens' Assembly in British Columbia focused on the electoral system,
but the focus just as well could have been on other aspects of the political
system. In California, a Citizens Assembly could focus on redistricting
reform or campaign finance reform; or reforming our broken primary system
and the electoral system.

The Citizens' Assembly solves a real dilemma: How do we enact meaningful
political reform, which California so badly needs, when both the governor
and the Legislature have conflicts of interest that induce them to
manipulate the rules in their favor?

Citizens' Assemblies could be important vehicles for modernizing our
political system because trust is placed in average citizens who have more
credibility than the political class. If you truly believe in democracy,
that's where trust belongs.

In the mid-1990s, a California Constitutional Revision Commission
deliberated on some of these fundamental issues, but it was too timid and
politically weak to enact change. The Citizens' Assembly points the
direction that Schwarzenegger and Democrats in the Legislature should lead.
The governor opened the debate with redistricting reform, but now is the
time to inject fairness and non-partisanship into state politics. What
better way than by establishing a Citizens' Assembly that empowers average
citizens to decide what political reform is best for California?




STEVEN HILL is an Irvine senior fellow with the New America Foundation and
author of ``Fixing Elections: The Failure of America's Winner Take All
Politics'' (www.fixingelections.com). To find out more about British
Columbia's Citizens' Assembly, visit www.citizensassembly.bc.ca  



election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Two round system (improved Approval version)

2005-11-18 Thread Chris Benham
Juho,
I see from the Method support poll that you are  close to 
supporting  a  Two round system.

I  regard the  normal  version of this, where both rounds are by 
Plurality and the top two from the
first round run off in the second, as pretty awful. The only criterion 
compliance advantage it has
over FPP is  Condorcet Loser, and generally the only thing good about it 
is that its equivalent to
IRV when there are three (or fewer) candidates.

One attempted improvement I've seen suggested  is to use Approval in the 
first round, and then
have the two most approved candidates run off in the second. 
Unfortunately that would be a
strategy farce because rich parties with some hope of  coming first in 
the Approval round will have
an incentive to gain an unfair advantage by each running two candidates, 
plus many voters will have
incentive to engage in easy Pushover strategizing by approving both 
their sincere favourite/s and the candidate
that they think their favourite can most easily beat in the second 
round. With too much of that, it is possible
that both of the finalists will be turkeys.

I've recently had an idea on how to fix this without, say, having votes 
cast in the first round also count in the
second.

The first round uses approval ballots. If there is a second round, it 
is between two candidates.
The first candidate to qualify for the second round is the Approval 
winner (A)
Of  those candidates B whose approval scores would exceed A's if  
ballots that approve both or neither of
A and B were altered so that they only approve of B, select as the 
second qualifier the candidate that is most
approved on ballots that don't approve A.
If there are none such candidates B, then there is no second round and  
A is elected.

Of course it is possible to automate this into a single-round method 
that uses ranked ballots with an approval
cutoff, but that would fail the Plurality criterion, the Irrelevant 
Ballots criterion and probably some (maybe more
serious) others. (Here by round I mean trip to the polling stations, 
with the results of any previous round in the
same election known to the voters.)

49: A
24: B
27: CB  (CB, both approved)

Here the two finalists are B and C.   In the single-round version, C 
would win, failing the Plurality criterion.

A simpler version which is more often decisive in the first round but 
has a greater later-harm problem would
only consider the candidate that is most approved on ballots that don't 
approve the approval winner
(i.e. has the greatest approval opposition to the approval winner) for 
the  position of second qualifier.

In the above example that would be A, who would be rejected and so B 
would be elected in the first round.
But then the C supporters could have got C into the second round (with 
A) by only approving C.

One possible problem with this idea of mine is that it may not be widely 
seen/understood as legitimate that there may
be a candidate or candidates that  don't make it into the second round 
but have a higher approval score than the
second qualifier. The only way around that is to relax the insistence 
that only two candidates go into the second
round, and say that all candidates with approval scores higher than the 
second qualifier's also qualify for the second
round.  (If there are more than two candidates in the second round, then 
if we want to keep it a binary-input system,
Approval should be used instead of FPP.)

In the above example that would presumably mean that again B would be 
elected in the first round, unless perhaps A
volunteers to drop out, because otherwise all three candidates qualify.

I  bring this up for jurisdictions which for some reason want to keep 
having two election rounds, each with the voters
giving simple binary inputs.  Do  you think the French will like it?


Chris  Benham






election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] simple question (I think)

2005-11-16 Thread Chris Benham
Rob,

rob brown wrote:

 For instance, say there is no Condorcet winner.  Candidates A, B and C 
 all have 8 pairwise wins.  D has 7.  Could D still be chosen as the 
 winner by any reasonable method?

Yes. The method that just counts the number of pairwise wins is called 
Copeland.  It  hopelessly fails Clone Independence (Clone-Loser) and 
Rich Party.

Imagine that that there are three candidates, each with the same number 
of pairwise wins, and the Condorcet method elects X.
Say  that the top cycle is  XZYX
Now say we add a clone of  Y, that every voter ranks directly below Y.
Now Y and Z will each have an extra pairwise win, one more than X and so 
now (by the Copeland criterion) X must lose to Z or Y.

Adding a clone  of  a losing candidate (not to say adding a 
Pareto-dominated candidate)  has changed the winner.

Parties and factions  that run more candidates will have an absurd and 
unfair advantage.


Chris  Benham




election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] STV-PR is not reweighted IRV and not House-Monotonic (was corrections to older posts re IRV public election data)

2005-11-12 Thread Chris Benham


Warren Smith wrote:

Arguably STV multiwinner elections are still of interest for single-winner
purposes since the FIRST winner is a single-winner IRV winner.
  

This  seems to imply that multi-winner STV  meets House-Monotonicity:

No candidate should be harmed by an increase in the number of seats to 
be filled, with no change in the profile.

It doesn't  and  shouldn't.  Multi-winner STV  is not  re-weighted IRV.
In this Dec.1914 article, Woodall  discusses this.

http://www.mcdougall.org.uk/VM/ISSUE3/P5.HTM
http://groups.yahoo.com/group/election-methods-list/files/wood1994.pdf


He mentions this example:
2 seats.
36: AD
34: BD
30: CD

Condorcet supporters would all agree that the best candidate to fill a 
single seat is D, but to fill two seats the
Droop proportionality criterion (DPC) says that we must elect A and B.

Quoting from that article:

 The most important single property of STV is what I call the /Droop 
 proportionality criterion/ or /DPC/. Recall that if /v/ votes are cast 
 in an election to fill /s/ seats, then the quantity /v//(/s/ + 1) is 
 called the /Droop quota/.

 * *DPC.* If, for some whole numbers /k/ and /m/ satisfying 0  /k/
   = /m/, more than /k/ Droop quotas of voters put the same /m/
   candidates (not necessarily in the same order) as the top /m/
   candidates in their preference listings, then at least /k/ of
   those /m/ candidates should be elected. (In the event of a tie,
   this should be interpreted as saying that every outcome that is
   chosen with non-zero probability should include at least /k/ of
   these /m/ candidates.)

 In statements of properties, the word should indicates that the 
 property says that something should happen, not necessarily that I 
 personally agree. However, in this case I certainly do: DPC seems to 
 me to be a /sine qua non/ for a fair election rule. I suggest that any 
 system that satisfies DPC deserves to be called a /quota-preferential/ 
 system and to be regarded as a system of proportional representation 
 (within each constituency)-an STV-lookalike. Conversely, I assume that 
 no member of the Electoral Reform Society will be satisfied with 
 anything that does not satisfy DPC.

 The property to which DPC reduces in a single-seat election should 
 hold (as a consequence of DPC) even in a multi-seat election, and it 
 deserves a special name.

 * *Majority.* If more than half the voters put the same set of
   candidates (not necessarily in the same order) at the top of
   their preference listings, then at least one of those candidates
   should be elected.


It  is possible for multi-winner STV to fail to elect the IRV winner. 
Adapting an old example from Adam Tarr:

3 seats,  100 ballots..
08: FRRLRMRML
02: RFRLRMRML
04: RLRFRMRML
07: LRMRRML
15: MRLRMLR
16: MLMRLRL
15: MLLMRFLLR
13: LMLFL
11: LFLML
09: FLLMLMR

The  IRV winner is Lucky Right(LR),  but 3- winner  STV elects first 
ML, then Left, then  MR.

The Droop quota is 25. Moderate Left(MR)  is the only candidate that 
starts with a quota so is first elected.
Then 15/31 of  Moderate Left's surplus 6 votes go to Left, which raises 
Left from 24 to  26.903 so now Left
has a quota and so is second elected.
The other 16/31 of  ML's  surplus 6 votes go to  MR, raising MR from 15 
to 18.09677votes.
Then MR also gets all of  L's surplus of  1.903 votes (all originally 
from ML)  to raise L's score to 20 votes.

The tallies for the remaining unelected candidates are FR8,   R6,   
LR7,  MR20,  FL9.
None have a quota so we eliminate R, which gives FR10,  LR11,  MR20,   FL9.
None have a quota so we eliminate FL, which gives FR10,  LR11, MR29.
MR now has a quota so is the last candidate elected.

In the IRV election the elimination order is R, FL, FR, MR, ML, L.


Chris Benham










  


election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] STV-PR is not reweighted IRV and not House-Monotonic (was corrections to older posts re IRV public election data)

2005-11-12 Thread Chris Benham




Warren Smith wrote:



  Arguably STV multiwinner elections are still of interest for single-winner
purposes since the FIRST winner is a single-winner IRV winner.
  

  

This  seems to imply that multi-winner STV  meets "House-Monotonicity":

"No candidate should be harmed by an increase in the number of seats to 
be filled, with no change in the profile".

It doesn't  and  shouldn't.  Multi-winner STV  is not  "re-weighted IRV".
In this Dec.1914 article, Woodall  discusses this.

http://www.mcdougall.org.uk/VM/ISSUE3/P5.HTM
http://groups.yahoo.com/group/election-methods-list/files/wood1994.pdf


He mentions this example:
2 seats.
36: AD
34: BD
30: CD

Condorcet supporters would all agree that the best candidate to fill a 
single seat is D, but to fill two seats the
"Droop proportionality criterion" (DPC) says that we must elect A and B.

Quoting from that article:

The most important single property of STV is what I call the Droop 
proportionality criterion or DPC. Recall that if v votes are 
cast in an election to fill s seats, then the quantity v/(s 
+ 1) is called the Droop quota. 
DPC. If, for some whole numbers k and m satisfying 0 
 k = m, more than k Droop quotas of voters put the 
same m candidates (not necessarily in the same order) as the top m 
candidates in their preference listings, then at least k of those 
m candidates should be elected. (In the event of a tie, this should be 
interpreted as saying that every outcome that is chosen with non-zero 
probability should include at least k of these m candidates.) 

In statements of properties, the word "should" indicates that the property 
says that something should happen, not necessarily that I personally agree. 
However, in this case I certainly do: DPC seems to me to be a sine qua 
non for a fair election rule. I suggest that any system that satisfies DPC 
deserves to be called a quota-preferential system and to be regarded as a 
system of proportional representation (within each constituency)-an 
STV-lookalike. Conversely, I assume that no member of the Electoral Reform 
Society will be satisfied with anything that does not satisfy DPC. 
The property to which DPC reduces in a single-seat election should hold (as a 
consequence of DPC) even in a multi-seat election, and it deserves a special 
name. 
Majority. If more than half the voters put the same set of candidates 
(not necessarily in the same order) at the top of their preference listings, 
then at least one of those candidates should be elected. 

It  is possible for multi-winner STV to fail to elect the IRV winner. 

Adapting an old example from Adam Tarr:

3 seats,  100 ballots..
08: FRRLRMRML
02: RFRLRMRML
04: RLRFRMRML
07: LRMRRML
15: MRLRMLR
16: MLMRLRL
15: MLLMRFLLR
13: LMLFL
11: LFLML
09: FLLMLMR

The  IRV winner is "Lucky Right"(LR),  but 3- winner  STV elects first 
ML, then Left, then  MR.

The Droop quota is 25. Moderate Left(ML)  is the only candidate that 
starts with a quota so is first elected.
Then 15/31 of  Moderate Left's surplus 6 votes go to Left, which raises 
Left from 24 to  26.903 so now Left
has a quota and so is second elected.
The other 16/31 of  ML's  surplus 6 votes go to  MR, raising MR from 15 
to 18.09677votes.
Then MR also gets all of  L's surplus of  1.903 votes (all originally 
from ML)  to raise L's score to 20 votes.

The tallies for the remaining unelected candidates are FR8,   R6,   
LR7,  MR20,  FL9.
None have a quota so we eliminate R, which gives FR10,  LR11,  MR20,   FL9.
None have a quota so we eliminate FL, which gives FR10,  LR11, MR29.
MR now has a quota so is the last candidate elected.

In the IRV election the elimination order is R, FL, FR, MR, ML, L.


Chris Benham














election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] STV-PR is not reweighted IRV and not House-Monotonic (was corrections to older posts re IRV public election data)

2005-11-12 Thread Chris Benham




Sorry about the multiple posting. 
In my explanation below of the STV procedure for my example, I wrote:

  Then MR also gets all of  L's surplus of  1.903 votes (all originally 
from ML)  to raise L's score to 20 votes.

Of course it is MR whose score is raised to 20 votes. (corrected
version below).

Chris Benham





Chris Benham wrote:

  
  Warren Smith wrote:

  
  
Arguably STV multiwinner elections are still of interest for single-winner
purposes since the FIRST winner is a single-winner IRV winner.
  

  
  
  This  seems to imply that multi-winner STV  meets "House-Monotonicity":

"No candidate should be harmed by an increase in the number of seats to 
be filled, with no change in the profile".

It doesn't  and  shouldn't.  Multi-winner STV  is not  "re-weighted IRV".
In this Dec.1914 article, Woodall  discusses this.

http://www.mcdougall.org.uk/VM/ISSUE3/P5.HTM
http://groups.yahoo.com/group/election-methods-list/files/wood1994.pdf


He mentions this example:
2 seats.
36: AD
34: BD
30: CD

Condorcet supporters would all agree that the best candidate to fill a 
single seat is D, but to fill two seats the
"Droop proportionality criterion" (DPC) says that we must elect A and B.

Quoting from that article:

The most important single property of STV is what I call the Droop 
proportionality criterion or DPC. Recall that if v votes are 
cast in an election to fill s seats, then the quantity v/(s 
+ 1) is called the Droop quota. 
DPC. If, for some whole numbers k and m satisfying 0 
 k = m, more than k Droop quotas of voters put the 
same m candidates (not necessarily in the same order) as the top m 
candidates in their preference listings, then at least k of those 
m candidates should be elected. (In the event of a tie, this should be 
interpreted as saying that every outcome that is chosen with non-zero 
probability should include at least k of these m candidates.) 

In statements of properties, the word "should" indicates that the property 
says that something should happen, not necessarily that I personally agree. 
However, in this case I certainly do: DPC seems to me to be a sine qua 
non for a fair election rule. I suggest that any system that satisfies DPC 
deserves to be called a quota-preferential system and to be regarded as a 
system of proportional representation (within each constituency)-an 
STV-lookalike. Conversely, I assume that no member of the Electoral Reform 
Society will be satisfied with anything that does not satisfy DPC. 
The property to which DPC reduces in a single-seat election should hold (as a 
consequence of DPC) even in a multi-seat election, and it deserves a special 
name. 
Majority. If more than half the voters put the same set of candidates 
(not necessarily in the same order) at the top of their preference listings, 
then at least one of those candidates should be elected. 

It  is possible for multi-winner STV to fail to elect the IRV winner. 
  
  Adapting an old example from Adam Tarr:

3 seats,  100 ballots..
08: FRRLRMRML
02: RFRLRMRML
04: RLRFRMRML
07: LRMRRML
15: MRLRMLR
16: MLMRLRL
15: MLLMRFLLR
13: LMLFL
11: LFLML
09: FLLMLMR

The  IRV winner is "Lucky Right"(LR),  but 3- winner  STV elects first 
ML, then Left, then  MR.

The Droop quota is 25. Moderate Left(ML)  is the only candidate that 
starts with a quota so is first elected.
Then 15/31 of  Moderate Left's surplus 6 votes go to Left, which raises 
Left from 24 to  26.903 so now Left
has a quota and so is second elected.
The other 16/31 of  ML's  surplus 6 votes go to  MR, raising MR from 15 
to 18.09677votes.
Then MR also gets all of  L's surplus of  1.903 votes (all originally 
from ML)  to raise MR's score to 20 votes.

The tallies for the remaining unelected candidates are FR8,   R6,   
LR7,  MR20,  FL9.
None have a quota so we eliminate R, which gives FR10,  LR11,  MR20,   FL9.
None have a quota so we eliminate FL, which gives FR10,  LR11, MR29.
MR now has a quota so is the last candidate elected.

In the IRV election the elimination order is R, FL, FR, MR, ML, L.


Chris Benham










  
  


election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
  




election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Beatpath and SSD aren't manipulable. Manipulable is barking up the wrong tree.

2005-11-08 Thread Chris Benham
MIKE OSSIPOFF wrote:


 Warren--

 You wrote:

 I would expect  it [beatpath] is extremely manipulable.

 I reply:

 Critics of pairwise-count methods speak of how they're vulnerable to 
 two offensive strategies:

 Truncation and offensive order-reversal.

 And, for all Condorcet methods other than Condorcet(wv), they're 
 right. All Condorcet methods that don't use winning-votes are a 
 strategic mess, just as you suspect. But wv is different. You're 
 ignoring the distinction between different kinds of Condorcet. 


46: AB
44: BC   (sincere is B or BA)
10: C

The defeat-dropper style  Condorcet(wv) method you refer to here 
elects B.

This looks a lot like vulnerability to  offensive order-reversal  (aka 
Burial strategy) to  me.


Chris  Benham




election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] MDD,ER-Bucklin (whole)

2005-10-19 Thread Chris Benham




Participants,
I've recently had the idea that ER-Bucklin (whole) could be improved
by combining it with the 
"Majority-Defeat Disqualification" (MDD) component from MDD//Approval
(MDDA).

So I suggest MDD,ER-Bucklin(whole) as my favourite method that
meets FBC.

"Voters rank the candidates, truncation and equal-ranking allowed.
If not all candidates are majority-strength pairwise beaten
(i.e."dominated") by some other candidate,
then "disqualify" (but not drop from the ballots) those that
are. 
If only one candidate remains, that candidate wins.
If more than one candidate remains, commence the ER-Bucklin(whole)
process until (at least) one of
the not-disqualified candidates has a vote tally greater than (or equal
to) half the total number of valid
ballots.
At that point elect the not-disqualified candidate with the highest
vote tally."

[The "(or equal to)" bit isn't traditional, but I suspect as a fine
point it is good.]

To explain "the ER-Bucklin(whole) process":
"In the first round each ballot contributes a whole vote each to the
tallies of those candidates they rank top or 
equal-top.
In the second round, ballots that have contributed to the tallies of
less than two candidates each contribute
a whole vote each to the tallies of candidates they rank second or
equal-second. 
(Ballots that in the first round contributed to the tallies of more
than one candidate do nothing in the second round)
In the third round, if there is one, ballots that have contributed to
the tallies of less than three candidates now 
contribute a whole vote each to the tallies of candidates they rank
third or equal-third.
And so on."

Or as it is better explained at the Electowiki:

  If a ballot lists n candidates as tied in kth place, count that
ballot as a whole point for all n candidates beginning in the kth round.
  
  Note: A candidate is ranked in kth place on a given ballot if
there are k-1 candidates who are ranked strictly higher. For exampe, a
ballot marked AB=C=DEF=G=H=IJ should be considered to
rank A to in 1st place, B, C, and D in 2nd place, E in 5th place, F, G,
H, and I in 6th place, and J in 10th place. Thus, the ballot would not
count in favor of E until the 5th round, and it would not count in
favor of J until the 10th round. 
  This rule is perhaps unique in that it satisfies both the "favorite
betrayal" criterion and the Majority
criterion for solid coalitions. 

If the majority-disqualified candidates were dropped from the
ballots, then Bucklin's compliance with Mono-raise would (I presume)
be lost.
(If I'm wrong about, then there probably isn't any reason not to just
first drop them from the ballots, making the method the simpler and
more 
"intuitive" MDD//ER-Bucklin(whole).)

I think the only criterion compliance of plain ER-Bucklin(whole) that
we lose is "Later-no-Help", which I don't expect anyone will miss.

What we gain is "Smith-Condorcet (Gross)" (which means that the winner
comes from the smallest non-empty set of candidates that all 
majority-strength pairwise beat any and all outside-the-set
candidates) and the Strategy-Free Criterion (SFC) .
Electowiki definition of SFC:


  If a Condorcet candidate exists, and if a majority prefers this
candidate to another candidate, then the other candidate should not win
if that majority votes sincerely and no other voter falsifies any
preferences. 
  In a ranked method, it is nearly equivalent to say: If more
than half of the voters rank x above y, and there is no
candidate z whom more than half of the voters rank above x,
then y must not be elected. 




The method meets FBC/Sincere Favourite, Majority for solid
coalitions/Mutual Majority, the Plurality criterion, Smith(Gross), SFC
(and GSFC?).

It fails Clone Independence (doubtless both Clone-Winner and
Clone-Loser), Later-no-Harm, Independence from Irrelevant Ballots,
No Zero-Information Strategy.

Compared to plain ER-Bucklin(whole), this method would have a less
severe Later-no-Harm problem. In ER-Bucklin(whole), if the voter 
has a big sincere approval cutoff, the s/he should equal-rank above it
and truncate below it. 
In MDD,ER-Bucklin(whole), if the voter's sincere approval cutoff is
above the most preferred member of the anticipated sincere Smith 
set then it is probably safe to truncate below that candidate.

In my view the worst feature of this method is its bad clone problem.
Also I dislike methods that fail Irrelevant Ballots (in the same spirit
as the "Blank Ballots Criterion").

But combining FBC with Majority for solid coalitions and Smith(Gross)
in my view makes it an ok package, better than MDDA.


Chris Benham










election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] full ranks in MDDA (not)

2005-10-17 Thread Chris Benham


Warren Smith wrote:

A. I would prefer it if MDDA actually forbids approving everybody e.g. by 
saying
if you rank them all, then the last is automatically disapproved.  Then we 
are
sure and do not have to depend on this assumption.


  

I  agree with this, and the same for all implicit approval methods.

B. If last-not-approved-only behavior is very common then the result will be
AntiPlurality voting to do the approvals.  AntiPlurality voting is a very 
bad system
in which with strategy a dark horse always wins.  So this gives me bad vibes.
Seem to me this might happen in a substantial subclass of elections - then 
things
could still be bad, albeit in a different way.

I  agree with this, but MDDA is being promoted for public political 
elections with a lot winning-probability information
and a lot of  strategic voters (who are happy to truncate and 
Compromise-compress).


Chris Benham




election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Warren: MDDA vs RV, 10/16/05

2005-10-16 Thread Chris Benham
Mike,
You wrote:

There's only one way to count RV or Approval 
ballots: Add them up.

In the case of RV ballots, there is also  Average Rating and  Median 
Rating  and also
rankings can be inferred and used.

And there are probably other ways. On the RV list, someone mentioned the 
idea of
discarding outliers as in Olympic scoring.


Chris  Benham



  


election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] which voting methods fail WMW?

2005-10-06 Thread Chris Benham




Warren Smith (Wed.Oct.5):


  wds:
 Robla failed to mention that range voting *does* obey a weakened form of
the majority-winner criterion (call it "WMW").  Specifically:
"If a strict majority of the voters regard X as their unique favorite, then
   they, acting alone without regard to what the other voters do, can force his election."
I don't know about you, but I personally regard WMW as a more-desirable critrion for
a voting system to obey, than Anderson 1994's MW criterion.
  
  
  
  
Chris  Benham:
Are there any  methods actually  *fail*  this criterion?   Borda perhaps?

  
  
--response by wds:
yes, Borda fails it.  So does the somewhat Borda-like method used
on the Island of Nauru.  So does Coombs' IRV-like voting method.
Also Ken Arrow's favorite voting method (or so I heard) the Arrow-Raynaud method,
fails this test.

Range voting, however, passes this test.
wds


Warren,
I've seen Coombs defined with and without a majority-stopping rule.
(To me not having it seems worse and odd). I assume you are referring
to the version without:
http://cec.wustl.edu/~rhl1/rbvote/desc.html
The candidate with the largest last-rank total
is eliminated. The last-rank totals are recalculated and the step
repeated until only one remains. 

The other version seems more common:
http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/Coombs%27_method

  Each voter rank-orders all of the candidates on their ballot. If
at any time one candidate is ranked first (among non-eliminated
candidates) by an absolute majority of the voters, then this is the
winner. As long as this is not the case, the candidate which is ranked
last (again among non-eliminated candidates) by the most (or a plurality of) voters is
eliminated. 

BTW, do you know for sure that one of these definitions is incorrect?
Obviously the version with the stopping-rule meets your WMW criterion.

I am sure that "Arrow-Raynaud" is the same as plain "Raynaud"
(sometimes spelt "Reynaud") which is a method that meets the Condorcet
criterion.
What according to you is its definition, and can you give an example of
it failing your WMW criterion?


Chris Benham









Election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] majority winner and range condorcet methods

2005-10-05 Thread Chris Benham

This from Warren Smith (Tue.Oct.4):


Robla failed to mention that range voting *does* obey a weakened form of
the majority-winner criterion (call it WMW).  Specifically:
   If a strict majority of the voters regard X as their unique favorite, then
  they, acting alone without regard to what the other voters do, can force his 
election.
I don't know about you, but I personally regard WMW as a more-desirable 
critrion for
a voting system to obey, than Anderson 1994's MW criterion. 


Warren,
Are there any  methods actually  *fail*  this criterion?   Borda perhaps?


Chris  Benham



Election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Andrew Gumbel: Steal this Vote: Dirty Elections and the Rotten History of Democracy in America.

2005-09-28 Thread Chris Benham
Andrew Gumbel is the LA-based correspondent of the UK paper The 
Independent. He's written a book,Steal this Vote:Dirty Elections and 
the Rotten History of Democracy in America, published by Nation Books.


If your computer has speakers, you can listen to this RadioNation 
podcast of him discussing the contents of his book.


http://www.podcast.net/show/6336

I found it very interesting.


Chris Benham

Election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Definition of sincere approval voting (was FBC comparison: WV, margins, MMPO, DMC)

2005-09-19 Thread Chris Benham




Kevin,

  --- Chris Benham [EMAIL PROTECTED] a crit :
  
  
 This is my proposed clear definition:
 "An  'approval vote' is one that makes some approval distinction among 
 the candidates. It is sincere if 
 (1)the voter sincerely prefers all the approved candidates (or single 
 candidate) to all the not approved candidates (or single candidate), and
 (2) it is how the voter would vote without any knowledge or guess as to 
 how other voters might vote."

  
  
I have trouble with (2). We could assume that "how the voter would vote"
means optimal, above-mean approval strategy. But obviously that is a
problem for a definition of "sincerity." It would also make approval
satisfy NZIS.

I don't have a big problem with plain Approval satisfying NZIS. Of
course Approval is promoted as a
method that invites voters to strategize.


  Otherwise we could choose to not define "how the voter would vote." But
in that case nothing prevents a strategically unwise vote from being
sincere, so that I don't see how DMC could satisfy NZIS. 

If , by some absolute standard in the voter's mind, the voter sincerely
"approves" at least one but not all of the candidates
then "sincere approval" is clearcut. I suppose if this isn't the case
then as you say if we leave undefined "how the voter
would vote" there is still 0-info. approval strategy (so plain
Approval doesn't really meet NZIS).


  You would have
to claim that DMC has no zero-info approval strategy.

It seems clear that DMC has no zero-info. *ranking* strategy. (Is that
what you meant?) But unless we define "sincere approval"
as "optimal zero-information approval ('strategy')", then DMC
perhaps doesn't fully meet NZIS.


Chris Benham





Election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Definition of sincere approval voting (was FBC comparison: WV, margins, MMPO, DMC)

2005-09-18 Thread Chris Benham




Kevin,


  --- Jobst Heitzig [EMAIL PROTECTED] a crit :
  
  
 We could discuss whether insincere equal ranking for top is more dishonest or whether approving
 one more candidate is more dishonest...

  
  
In my opinion, insincere equal ranking is more insincere than approving
an additional candidate.
  

I strongly agree with this.


  "Sincere approval voting" isn't even clearly
defined.

I've seen one definition that says that as long as the voter sincerely
prefers all the candidates s/he approves to all the ones s/he doesn't,
then the "approval vote" is sincere. To me this is mainly a bit of
sophistry for the purpose of promoting Approval.

This is my proposed clear definition:
"An 'approval vote' is one that makes some approval distinction among
the candidates. It is sincere if 
(1)the voter sincerely prefers all the approved candidates (or single
candidate) to all the not approved candidates (or single candidate), and
(2) it is how the voter would vote without any knowledge or guess as to
how other voters might vote."

By this definition, DMC (like IRV and unlike WV) meets "No
Zero-Information Strategy". No method can make it impossible for
well-informed
strategists to sometimes have an advantage, but it irks me that WV has
non-obvious fairly sophisticated strategy for "zero-information" voters
(random-fill and if you have a big ratings gap, equal-rank above it).


Chris Benham





Election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Re: approval strategy in DMC (automated)

2005-09-14 Thread Chris Benham

Q,


I've made a slight change on the DMC page on electowiki.

I've extended the definition somewhat:  the ballot is a combination of ordinal
ranking (equal ranks allowed) and approval rating.  The approval rating
information can be either binary approval (approved/not-approved) or
finer-grained cardinal ratings ([1,0,-1] or [100,99,...,1,0]).  I think this is
more of a difference in implementation than the method, since the initial
ordering is by total approval.

In the above case, a more graduated cardinal rating (say 100-0) would allow a
voter to approve weaker candidates with a low, but non-zero, rating.

Using fine-grained  CR ballots with some range like 0 to 100, or even 
-100 to 100, so that there are always
many more possible grades (slots) available than there are candidates 
allows at the cost of greater counting

complexity  what is in my opinion a big improvement:

(1) Inferring rankings from ratings, eliminate non-members of the 
Schwartz  set.


(2) If more than one candidate remains, interpret each  ballot to be 
approving those remaining candidates that it
rates higher than the mean of  it's ratings of the remaining candidates, 
and half-approving  those that it rates at exactly

this mean (and of course not approving those it rates below.)

(3) Based on the inferred rankings  and the step(2) construed approvals, 
use  Definite Majority Choice (DMC) to

elect the winner.

The idea is that voters don't need to have any idea of what the chances 
of any of the candidates being elected are, and
voters who (in the manual version) would approve or not approve all 
the candidates except one sure loser are not

unfairly disadvantaged.
A while ago I proposed  Automated-Approval Margins which is identical  
except  that in step(3)  Approval Margins
replaces DMC.  Also possible would be in step (3) to ignore the 
rankings and just use (construed) Approval, but at

the time I looked at that and decided it wasn't as good on strategy grounds.

BTW, I think  unadorned DMC with an explicit approval cutoff  (so that 
voters can rank candidates they don't approve)
is an excellent practical proposal for public political elections.   I 
am opposed to  blindly vote my favourite's ticket idiot
boxes (which will just give rich parties incentive to sponsor lots of  
fake candidates), and to  the proposed rule


that if some candidate gets more than 66% approval, then the candidate 
with

greatest approval wins.


This is an arbitrary complication that would cause the method to fail  
Majority Favourite and  Irrelevant Ballots.



Chris  Benham





Election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Approval variants of MinMax

2005-09-03 Thread Chris Benham

Forest,
You recently wrote on the new Yahoo Condorcet list, beginning by 
referring to  Beatpath, Ranked Pairs, River and MinMax:


However, recently Jobst showed that if one measures defeat strength by 
total
approval (of the victor in the pairwise defeat) then all four of these 
competing

methods coalesce into one method.

This fact would seem to resolve the controversy unless it turned out 
that total

approval was not a good way to measure defeat strength.

However, it seems to be better than winning votes or margins. The 
defensive
properties of winning votes that are normally obtained by defensive 
truncation
can usually (if not always) be obtained by raising the approval cutoff 
instead

of truncating the rankings.

Therefore, I suggest that we adopt MinMax(Total Approval) as the Condorcet
proposal.


Is  your first sentence above also true of  MinMax (Approval Margins) 
and  the  MinMax (Winner's Exclusive Approval)?
By the latter I mean measuring the defeat strength by the number of 
ballots that approve the pairwise winner and not the pairwise loser,

as advocated by James Green Armytage.


Chris Benham

Election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] medians and Heitzig's approval-voting strategy

2005-08-31 Thread Chris Benham

Warren,


--aha.  So by median candidate you do not mean what I thought you meant
(namely, in an N-canddt election, the top-quality floor(N/2) are above median)
but rather median in the prior distribution of probabilities of winning.

But wait, that would be even more insane, since the policy of
voting only for the candidates with above-median prior election 
probability, would be a policy that would completely disregard the

quality of the candidates.


My understanding of Weinstein's approval strategy is this:
Approve your favourite (or equal favourites). If the remaining (so far 
unapproved) candidates are on more
than one of your preference-levels, then approve the candidate/s on your 
next-from-the-top  preference-level if
you consider that the probability that one of the candidates you prefer 
less than this/these candidate/s  will win
is greater than the probability that one of the candidates you prefer 
more will win.  And so on.


This strategy seems sane to me, and probably right for voters who only 
have a ranking.



Chris Benham

Election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] question/comments re DMC

2005-08-30 Thread Chris Benham




Warren,
You and Jobst recently had this exchange about Definite Majority
Choice (DMC) and Range voting. You begin by quoting
one of Jobst's "15 reasons to support DMC".


  6. Robustness against "noise" candidates.. cloneproof...
  
  WS:  --also true of range.
  
  
JH: Could you say more precisely what you mean here?


WS:--Range voting is immune to clones in the sense that any number of cloned
candidates, all of whom get the same rangevote scores, can be added to the scene,
and the election winner will remain unchanged (except perhaps for replacement by a clone).

Also, if "noise" candidates are added who have no hope of winning, then the range votes
with noise scores being adjoined  for the new candidates, will still yield the same winner
and indeed the same totals.

Many other voting schemes have these properties (and many also do not
have these properties) but in range's case it is particularly self-evident.

Range only has this property in a technical sense, in a way that is
connected with its technical failure of May's axiom, i.e. it
doesn't reduce to FPP when there are only two candidates. 

Suppose that in the period leading up to the election it is known for
sure that two candidates will stand, A and B. A is a left-wing
candidate that is hated by big money and its mass media. B is a
centre-right candidate that they like. Reliable but perhaps not widely
published polls give A52%, B48%. The method to be used in the
election is Range, and with just these two candidates standing
the voters have no reason not to give maximum points to their preferred
candidate and minimum to the other resulting in a solid win
for A. 
How to change B from being the majority loser to the "super-majority
consensus candidate"? Easy! A third candidate, C is nominated.
C is a horror far-right candidate. Maybe some of A's supporters are
members of some ethnic/racial/religious minority that the C
candidate says he's in favour of persecuting. Anyway, now all the mass
media have to do now is to convince some of A's supporters
that C has some chance of winning the election, or just that they
should give a maximised sincere vote.

So without C we have:
52: A99, B0
48: B99, A0
A wins 5148 to B4752.

With C added and some of A's supporters conned and/or frightened,
this could become:
47: A99, B0, C0
05: A99, B98, C0
46: B99, A0, C0
02: C99, B98, C0

Now B wins: B5242, A5148, C198. (Approval is also vulnerable to
this scenario.)
Note that in this example the voted and sincere (binary) pairwise
preferences are AB 52-48, AC 52-2, BC 98-2.

I think DMC is a very very good (possibly the best) single-winner
method to propose for public office elections if we insist on
Condorcet 
and Mono-raise.


Chris Benham

.






Election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] 64 vs 65, post for purpose of annoying Jobst Heitzig

2005-08-30 Thread Chris Benham

Warren,


Incidentlally, since you claim because you cannot explain the precise meaning 
of a range vote
of 64 versus 65, therefore range voting is somehow horribel and inexplicable...
and you like DMC...  I ask explain to me the precise meaning of
`I approve of Bush.'

Pretty difficult, isn't it?   And also probably strategy dependent - it depends 
who
are Bush's opponents, in practice.   All of this is quite analogous to range 
vote
values.   (Annoyance mission completed.)
wds

I dislike plain Approval because it more-or-less forces voters to 
concern themselves with strategy and the winning probabilities of
the candidates. Using a concept of  absolute inflexible approval in a 
method like DOC  I used to object to on the same grounds.
But now I see that it is mathematically convenient  and seems to  
resonate in the real world.


My attempt to precisely define  I approve of  Bush:
 If  the ballot constrains me to equally help a set of candidates 
(which I nominate) to defeat any non-member candidates, I  put Bush

in that set. I prefer Bush to any candidate that I don't approve.



Chris  Benham

Election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Typo: DMC, not DOC

2005-08-30 Thread Chris Benham

Below is my previous post, corrected:

Warren,

Incidentlally, since you claim because you cannot explain the precise 
meaning of a range vote
of 64 versus 65, therefore range voting is somehow horribel and 
inexplicable...

and you like DMC...  I ask explain to me the precise meaning of
`I approve of Bush.'

Pretty difficult, isn't it?   And also probably strategy dependent - 
it depends who
are Bush's opponents, in practice.   All of this is quite analogous to 
range vote

values.   (Annoyance mission completed.)
wds

I dislike plain Approval because it more-or-less forces voters to 
concern themselves with strategy and the winning probabilities of
the candidates. Using a concept of  absolute inflexible approval in a 
method like DMC  I used to object to on the same grounds.
But now I see that it is mathematically convenient  and seems to  
resonate in the real world.


My attempt to precisely define  I approve of  Bush:
 If  the ballot constrains me to equally help a set of candidates 
(which I nominate) to defeat any non-member candidates, I  put Bush

in that set. I prefer Bush to any candidate that I don't approve.



Chris  Benham


Election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Center for Range Voting Formed

2005-08-12 Thread Chris Benham

Adam,
You wrote (Fri.Aug.12):


* OK, in the interest of fairness, here is one winning-votes Condorcet
strategy that is arguably superior to sincerity.  This is from Blake
Cretney.  It's pretty simple: if you have a sincere tied ranking, it's
better to rank those candidates in some random order than to rank them
equally.  So in stead of ranking three candidates tied for fourth,
rank them 4, 5, 6, (in some order) and kick any candidates below
fourth down two slots.  There are situations where this strategy can
hurt you, but on average (aggregating over a large number of voters
with similar preferences) it will not.

 

I  don't  think you have that quite right. In  the defeat-dropper 
style winning-votes Condorcet methods you refer to, if  the voter 
sincerely ranks some candidates
equal-bottom,  then the voter's best zero-information strategy is to 
strictly rank them all at random (i.e. to  random-fill). In addition 
to that, if  above-bottom
equal-ranking is allowed, then if  the voter has a sufficiently large 
gap in his/her sincere ratings  he/she should  equal-rank above that gap.



Chris  Benham

Election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Re the official definition of condorcet

2005-08-12 Thread Chris Benham

Warren,
You  quoted:


1. condorcet.org definitions page:
Name: Condorcet Criterion 
Application: Ranked Ballots 
Definition: 
If an alternative pairwise beats every other alternative, this alternative must win the election. 
Pass: Black, Borda-Elimination, Dodgson, Kemeny-Young, Minmax, Nanson (original), Pairwise-Elimination , Ranked Pairs, Schulze, Smith//Minmax, Sum of Defeats 
Fail: Borda, Bucklin, Coombs, IRV



And remarked:


(Note that, revealingly, they do not consider range voting or
plurality voting to either pass or fail.)

Maybe you missed  Application: Ranked Ballots.   Blake Cretney doesn't 
classify  RV or  plurality voting (aka FPP) as ranked-ballot methods. 
He  is  referring only to methods that
reduce to  FPP  when there are  two candidates, so  there is no 
ambiguity  about his  meaning of  pairwise beats.


For  a method  to meet the CC, it must allow the voters to express all  
their pairwise  (binary) preferences  or in other words their full 
ranking. That cuts out FPP, Approval and
limited-slot  ballot methods with fewer available slots than there are 
candidates.  Then  it must elect  any candidate that pairwise beats all 
the others.  X  pairwise beats Y  if  more

voters rank X above Y  than vice versa.  No  ambiguity that I can see.

A Range Voting ballot  with many more available slots than there are 
candidates does allow the voter  to give his/her full rankings. It can 
be regarded as simply a ranked ballot
with some extra extraneous ratings information on it.  But just because 
RV uses this extra information,  I  don't see any need  to  
generalize  the  CC  to  accommodate it.



This no-hyperlink choice is in fact a plausible way to go because then the condorcet 
criterion is about the logical self-consistency of a method, as opposed to the consistency 
of method A as judged using method B, which is kind of an unfair pre-biased way to judge A.


Voting methods don't have any feelings or rights, so  therefore this 
alleged  unfairness  doesn't matter.



Chris  Benham








 



Election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Irrelevant Ballots criterion

2005-07-13 Thread Chris Benham

Participants,
I've  come up with a criterion I like, in part inspired by  the  Blank 
Ballot Criterion.  As that criterion is currently worded in the Electowiki:


The addition of one or more blank ballots cannot change the winner. 


I don't think is very useful because any method can easily dodge it 
simply by including a rule that blank ballots aren't counted.


I propose the Independence from Irrelevant Ballots criterion:

If  candidate X  pairwise loses to all other candidates and is ranked 
no higher than equal bottom on all ballots except those that plump for X,

then if  ballots that plump for X  are deleted the winner must not change.

I  think this covers Russ's intention in the way he proposed the Blank 
Ballot Criterion:


No method that depends on majority defeats can pass this criterion 
if it defines a majority it terms of the total number of voters.


So Irrelevant Ballots can somewhat embarrass  CDTT,IRV:
49: A
24: B
27: CB
03: D
(103 ballots)
The CDTT  is {ABC} and  CDTT,IRV elects  A, but if we delete the 
irrelevant 3D ballots then A drops out of the CDTT

and the new CDTT,IRV winner is C.

Woodall's  Descending Acquiescing Coalitions (DAC) method doesn't use 
any majority concept, but in this excellent example from M.Harman (aka 
Auros) it stumbles on

Irrelevant Ballots:
03: D
14: A
34: AB
36: CB
13: C

ABCD 100
ABC   97 (eliminate D)
BCD  52 (eliminate A)
AB D  51 (eliminate C, B wins)

DAC elects B, but if we delete the irrelevant 3D ballots then C wins.

A perhaps-more-elegant, stronger version that applies to methods that rank a 
candidate last could be called
Strong Independence from Irrelevant Ballots (BTW, I am happy for these to be 
abbreviated by dropping the Independence from bit).

Deleting ballots that plump for the candidate ranked last must not change the 
winner.

But so far I think the main weak version is more useful. (BTW, plump in this context 
means bullet-vote)

Chris Benham





Election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


  1   2   3   >