Ben, Gary, List,

We are having work done on our house so I'm having to work on a mix of mobile 
devices w/o access to files … 

With ref to your last, one of the reasons that I like that early example of 
Peirce's about Wisdom and Charity is that it makes plain that the designations 
Case, Fact (Result), Rule are relational roles not ontological properties of 
premisses. This is of course analogous to and probably derivative of the 
corresponding situation with Object, Sign, and Interpretant roles. 

P.S. I've always found that the name Result tends to confuse people as it is 
not the result of the inference in question except in the deductive case and so 
I prefer to use the name Fact that I picked up from other medievalists like 
W.S. McCulloch.

Regards,

Jon

http://inquiryintoinquiry.com

> On Apr 29, 2016, at 6:25 AM, Benjamin Udell <baud...@gmail.com> wrote:
> 
> Gary R., list,
> I got careless in my previous message. 
> I said that "There is F, ergo anything is F" ("∃F∴∀F") would be abductive; 
> however, in a stipulatedly non-empty universe, its conclusion entails its 
> premiss, and so for my part I would rather call it inductive than abductive, 
> at least in the "usual" universes. A better candidate for a toy example of an 
> abduction to a rule would be "There is FG, ergo anything F is G" 
> ("∃FG∴∀(F→G)"). These are silly examples, but I like the idea of being able 
> to sort out even the simplest inference schemata into deductive, inductive, 
> and abductive, in terms of entailment relations between the premiss set and 
> the conclusion. In the second example, "∀(F→G)" is arguably a selective 
> generalization of "∃FG". 
> Also in considering the beans example, I forgot that it's just one way of 
> instancing Barbara and its inversions. After all, Barbara is named for its 
> vowels as a mnemonic for the universality and affirmativity of its 
> propositions - AAA. So, in a universe in which mammals are not _defined_ as 
> warm-blooded air-breathing live-young-bearers:
> 
> Result:  All whales are warm-blooded, breathe air, and bear live young.
> Rule: All mammals are warm-blooded, breathe air, and bear live young.
> Ergo Case: (Plausibly) all whales are mammals.
> The "case" there is itself a new rule. I'm not sure whether that's an example 
> of what Peirce means by abductive generalization, but there it is. 
> Best, Ben
>> On 4/28/2016 3:10 PM, Benjamin Udell wrote:
>> 
>> Hi, Gary,
>> 
>> I agree with most of what you say, only I don't see hypothesization of a 
>> rule in the beans example. On the other hand, Peirce is explicit about 
>> hypothesizing a new general (or rule) in the 1903 quote.
>> 
>> [....] The mind seeks to bring the facts, as modified by the new discovery, 
>> into order; that is, to form a general conception embracing them. In some 
>> cases, it does this by an act of _generalization_. In other cases, no new 
>> law is suggested, but only a peculiar state of facts that will "explain" the 
>> surprising phenomenon; and a law already known is recognized as applicable 
>> to the suggested hypothesis [....] 
>> (From "Syllabus", 1903, EP 2:287 
>> http://www.commens.org/dictionary/entry/quote-syllabus-syllabus-course-lectures-lowell-institute-beginning-1903-nov-23-some
>>  )
>> Moreover, Peirce in a draft circa 1896 (CP 1.74) said "Kepler shows his keen 
>> logical sense in detailing the whole process by which he finally arrived at 
>> the true orbit. This is the greatest piece of Retroductive reasoning ever 
>> performed." Clearly, Kepler was looking for a rule, not merely for a special 
>> circumstance, to explain an orbit.
>> 
>> The problem, which has been nagging at me for a while (and I have read too 
>> little of the secondary literature), is how to distinguish, in a reasonably 
>> simple way, such abductive inference from induction?
>> 
>> Now, by "generalization" Peirce usually meant what many would call 
>> _selective_ generalization. That's his hint to us there.
>> 
>> I've tried to think in terms of the hypothesizing of a hidden special 
>> circumstance, e.g., a hidden mechanism, that would have to happen by a new 
>> rule in order to make sense at all. But, how much of this hidden special 
>> circumstance does one really need to conceive of, in order to conceive of a 
>> new rule? I've also wondered whether it's a matter of considering rules as 
>> special circumstances at some level of abstraction, likewise as one may 
>> consider integers as singulars at some level of abstraction, in an abstract 
>> universe of discourse.
>> 
>> But complications make me distrustful in questions of elementary 
>> distinctions among inference modes. Remembering Peirce's idea of selective 
>> generalization as a hint, it occurs to me that maybe it's a matter of a need 
>> to select among the characteristics to extend. That's where some guessing 
>> comes in. That is, Kepler's math may represent a character of the appearance 
>> of orbits, but the orbits actually observed at that time might be accounted 
>> for in other ways, and Kepler's math might conceivably have worked just by 
>> accident up till then. Well, in Kepler's case, his ultimate solutions could 
>> hardly plausibly have worked just by coincidence, but there are plenty of 
>> cases where a mathematical model fits the past by accident and turns out to 
>> lack predictive value. 
>> 
>> So, in the schema for abductive inference to a rule, maybe there should be a 
>> premissual admission of characters that seemed salient, not all of which are 
>> extended by inference to the whole. That very selection may amount to an 
>> idea new to the case. Moreover, some of the characters may be formulated 
>> (e.g., mathematically) in a new way, the idea new to the case. Still, doubts 
>> nag at me. These may be patterns of abductive inference, but my sense is 
>> that one needs to be able to distinguish abductive inference (to a rule) 
>> from induction even in ridiculously crude cases.
>> 
>> The idea of induction is that of inference from a part or fragment of a 
>> system to the whole. Yet it is possible to state any inference to a rule 
>> without any reference to a positively granted larger whole.  If I conclude 
>> that, for any F, F is G , then I have not asserted or entailed in the 
>> conclusion the existence of a whole or even of a part of the population of F 
>> 's. Induction and testing, however, do need a positively granted larger 
>> whole to test.  When one abduces to a rule, it may simply be that one 
>> "attenuates" one's focus to the rule itself, the rule as embodying a kind of 
>> real necessity, and _that_ rule, taken as itself real, indefinitely 
>> projectable across a population not yet contemplated, etc., is what is new 
>> to the case. So, the implausibly crude ampliative inference "There is F, 
>> ergo anything is F" ("∃F∴∀F") would be abductive, not inductive (in a 
>> stipulatedly one-object universe, it would be a reversible deduction). Well, 
>> I've been pottering         around with these ideas for a while and I 
>> haven't gotten much farther.
>> 
>> Best, Ben
>>> On 4/27/2016 12:42 PM, Gary Richmond wrote:
>>> 
>>> Ben, list,
>>> 
>>> You gave Peircean examples whereas the rule (or law) is already known 
>>> either before or after the surprising fact. This seems all well and good to 
>>> me for certain types of             abductions, say, those involved in 
>>> sleuthing, Sherlock Holmes style.
>>> 
>>> But what of those inquiries in which the rule (law) is not known, but is 
>>> exactly the hypothesis of the             inquirer? This is to say that 
>>> scientists sometimes come to uncover laws hitherto unkown or unrecognized 
>>> (such as those hypothesized by Newton, Darwin, Einstein, Planck, etc.)
>>> 
>>> I have sometimes thought that in that context--that is, of someone 
>>> hypothesizing a law not previously known--that, modifying the 1878 bean 
>>> example you gave:
>>> 
>>> Suppose I enter a room and there find a number of bags, containing 
>>> different kinds of beans. On the table there is a handful of white beans; 
>>> and, after some searching, I find one of the bags contains white beans 
>>> only. I at once infer as a probability, or a fair guess, that this handful 
>>> was taken out of that bag. This sort of inference is called _making an 
>>> hypothesis _. It is the inference of a _case _ from a _rule _ and _result 
>>> _.  (CSP)
>>> 
>>> the situation might look something like this (although I'm not sure that 
>>> any bean example will quite do for this purpose.
>>> 
>>> Suppose I enter a room and find a large number of bags which I know to 
>>> contain different kinds of beans. Near one bag I find a handful of white 
>>> beans (the surprising fact) and I make the supposition (the hypothesis) 
>>> that that particular bag of beans is all white. I examine the bag of beans 
>>> (make my experiment) and find that the bag in question does indeed contain 
>>> only white beans (the rule). (GR)
>>> 
>>> Well, it may turn out that I know beans about abduction, but it does seem 
>>> to me that the scientifically most fruitful and significant hypotheses are 
>>> those where the law (rule) is not know in advance and is only supposed by 
>>> the scientist, again, exactly as the hypothesis .
>>> 
>>> Peirce gives an example of that kind of hypothesis, one which is, shall we 
>>> say, fresh at the time (the rule or law not being previously known):
>>> 
>>> Fossils are found; say, remains like those of fishes, but far in the 
>>> interior of the country. To explain the phenomenon we suppose the sea once 
>>> washed over the land (CP 2.625).
>>> 
>>> Now suppose that a historian of the region in which those fish fossils were 
>>> found, himself finding documents showing that a large caravan of traders 
>>> had brought large quantities of dried fish into that region, pooh-poohs my 
>>> sea washing over the land hypothesis, which I have already imagined (for 
>>> some good reasons) to have happened in other parts of the world as well. 
>>> Thus, as other investigators find many other places, including deserts, 
>>> etc., containing many fish fossils where there was no possibility of any 
>>> fish trade occurring, my hypothesis takes hold and is in time accepted 
>>> quite generally by the scientific community.
>>> 
>>> (Another, not unrelated example, would be that of continental drift.)
>>> 
>>> It seems to me that Peirce intended to cover both kinds of hypotheses even 
>>> in his bean illustrations as he offers examples of both (the fossil example 
>>> is preceded by what I referred to above as a sleuthing type of example). 
>>> Any help which you or others can offer towards clarifying this matter--of 
>>> someone hypothesizing a rule or law not previously known--would be 
>>> appreciated.
>>> 
>>> Best,
>>> 
>>> Gary R
>>> 
>>> 
>>> 
>>> Gary Richmond 
>>> Philosophy and Critical Thinking 
>>> Communication Studies 
>>> LaGuardia College of the City University of New York 
>>> C 745 
>>> 718 482-5690
>>> 
>>> On Tue, Apr 26, 2016 at 11:49 AM, Benjamin Udell wrote:
>>> 
> 
-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .




Reply via email to