So suppose the law specifically required the employer to pay directly to a 
clinic its charges for an employee's abortion. The employee has an abortion at 
a clinic, tells the clinic to send the bill to the employer, and the employer 
then must pay the bill on pain of fines that will put the employer out of 
business. The employer is a practicing Catholic who follows the Church's 
teachings. Is this a substantial burden on the employer's exercise of religion? 
Will anyone argue that this is not?
Now what if the law is changed to require the employer to buy insurance for 
employees that specifically and only covers abortion procedures?

And now what if the law is changed to require the employer to buy health 
insurance that covers lots of health costs and also covers abortions? Can we 
say that there no longer is a substantial burden on the employer's exercise of 
religion because now the employer is required to do more?

Of course there is a long history of careful, thoughtful moral analysis that 
treats the directness of a person's involvement in an action as a key indicator 
of  the person's moral responsibility for it. It is not idiosyncratic at all 
for the employer to believe that he or she is being coerced into violating 
religious conscience by being required specifically to subsidize an activity 
that he or she believes is wrong, and, even worse, by being required to agree 
specifically to subsidize that activity by entering into a contract providing 
for it to be subsidized.

This is not at all the same thing as paying a salary that an employee may use 
in a way that the is contrary to the employer's religious beliefs (for example, 
obtaining an abortion). The payment of the salary does not require the employer 
to agree specifically to subsidize that activity. But by entering into a health 
insurance contract that specifically covers abortions, the employer does so 
agree and is, according to a very reasonable moral analysis, complicit.

If you pay taxes, you do not have to enter into an agreement that your money 
may be used to wage war or to pay for other things that you could not, as a 
matter of religious conscience, be involved in. The government requires you to 
pay the taxes, and then the government decides what to do with the money, with 
no need for you to agree at all. Same for payment of a salary that the employee 
may use as the employee chooses. You do not have to agree that the employee may 
obtain an abortion, nor do you pay the salary to allow the employee to obtain 
the abortion; you are not complicit.

The court in this case in effect chose its own version of moral casuistry, and 
decided that an action that would not, on the court's view, create complicity 
in an action, could not as a matter of law burden the employer's exercise of 
religion. That is the same as the court deciding that a tenet of the employer's 
religion is false, because the moral analysis that leads to the conclusion of 
complicity is part of the employer's religious beliefs.

Of course the finding of a substantial burden does not end the analysis. If we 
assume that the govt interest is compelling, we have to ask whether the govt 
can accomplish its purposes without violating the religious conscience of the 
employer (or the taxpayer); is the government using an approach that minimizes 
the imposition on religious conscience (the least restrictive means requirement 
of RFRA)? The government could not function if every taxpayer had a veto over 
how his or her taxes were used. But a health care system can cover abortions or 
whatever procedures the govt wants to cover without requiring religious people 
to agree specifically to subsidize what they consider to be religiously 
prohibited. Employers who refuse to buy health insurance for employees that 
cover such procedures can be taxed for not doing so, in an amount that is 
sufficient to allow the govt to provide supplemental insurance policies to 
employees who want them. The employer may not like having to pay a tax that 
could be seen to subsidize an activity with which he or she disagrees on 
religious grounds (though money is fungible and thus it isn't clear that this 
tax money is being used to pay for abortions). But under this approach the 
employer is not forced to violate his or her religious conscience by agreeing 
to subsidize the activity. A few employers may believe payment of such a tax 
violates their religious conscience; if so, they can refuse to pay the tax, and 
the govt can use its normal coercive means to collect an unpaid tax. Unless the 
employer believes that armed resistance is required (consider a tax to 
subsidize slavery), even such an employer's religious conscience will not be 
violated when the tax is taken.

Note that there is a real imposition on religious freedom when a person is 
required to agree specifically to subsidize an action that violates the 
person's religious conscience. This is analogous to Barnette; you can be 
required to pay taxes to support a government you consider to be illegitimate, 
but you cannot be required to agree to support it; you cannot even be required 
to say that you agree to support it.

Brad is right.

Mark S. Scarberry
Professor of Law
Pepperdine Univ. School of Law



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Steven Jamar
Sent: Saturday, September 29, 2012 8:50 PM
To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

I find the court's argument strong here.  You pay a salary, you pay FICA, you 
pay unemployment insurance, you pay pension benefits, you pay vacation time, 
holidays, and so on.  And you provide health insurance benefits.  Some of those 
who have health insurance will use contraceptives.  Just like some will use 
their salaries for gambling, or fornication, or contraception, or alcohol, or 
illegal drugs, or whatever else the religion of the employer thinks is wrong.  
Health insurance is a benefit like any other, for purposes of this analysis.

Steve



On Sep 29, 2012, at 11:11 PM, Brad Pardee wrote:


Second, they state, "[T]he contribution to a health care plan has no more than 
a de minimus impact on the plaintiff's religious beliefs than paying salaries 
and other benefits to employees."  The parallel is false, though.  There are no 
limitations on what an employee can do with his salary (apart from things that 
are illegal on their own, i.e., drugs).  A health care plan, however, is not 
open-ended.  It lays out specifically what the plan pays for and how much.  
Certain procedures are covered.  Certain procedures are not.  Using certain 
providers will result in a different deductible or copy than using others.

--
Prof. Steven D. Jamar                     vox:  202-806-8017
Associate Director, Institute for Intellectual Property and Social Justice 
http://iipsj.org
Howard University School of Law           fax:  202-806-8567
http://iipsj.com/SDJ/



"A word is not a crystal, transparent and unchanged, it is the skin of a living 
thought and may vary greatly in color and content according to the 
circumstances and the time in which it is used."



Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes in Towne v. Eisner, 245 U.S. 418, 425 (1918)







_______________________________________________
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Reply via email to