Again, I’m late—sorry about that.  But honestly people, it’s shocking how 
many posts are written between the hours of 9 p.m. and 7 a.m.  Who can keep 
up?



So this may backtrack, but I’ve been thinking about the earlier posts in 
this thread.  Say there are no secular analogies to the priest-penitent 
privilege.  Does that, in itself, justify the conclusion that it is 
favoritism for religion?



I don’t think so, or at least I’m not convinced of that right now.  Some 
people are religious; some people are not.  Some people feel a need to 
confess and receive absolution in return; others do not.  The 
priest-penitent privilege only helps those in the former group.  But that 
need not be favoritism.  Sure, it’s differential treatment, but it might be 
justified because the people aren’t similarly situated in the first place. 
(And here this ties in to Greg Sisk’s earlier posts.)



I think it helps that there are secular analogues, but I think it’s a 
mistake to require the secular analogues to match up perfectly with the 
religious one.  I think it’s a mistake because it denies the reasons why we 
want to accommodate religion in the first place: Religion is different than 
other human needs.  It may be analogous to them, but it’s never perfectly 
analogous; it inevitably differs in ways that require tailored treatment. 
The equality approach means that religious activities never get protection 
when there’s no exact secular parallel to them.  If there’s no exact secular 
parallel to confession—and of course there isn’t!—then confession doesn’t 
get protected.  More generally, I take this to be the central weakness of 
Smith (even for those who think Smith rightly decided).  It is also why—to 
pick up Sandy’s train of thought below—Widmar ends up turning into Bronx 
Household.



In Trammel, the Court goes through all the privileges in a sensible and 
attractive way.  The attorney-client privilege helps you secure legal help; 
the physician privilege helps you secure medical help; later on, the 
psychotherapist privilege will help you secure emotional help; the clergy 
privilege helps you secure spiritual help.  True enough that some don’t 
believe in spiritual help, because they think it’s bs.  But some think 
psychotherapy is bs.



If the priest-penitent privilege is conceptualized the way Sandy phrases 
it—as a “desire [of people] to unburden themselves to sympathetic 
 listeners”—then the priest-penitent privilege looks terribly 
underinclusive.  But that phrases the priest-penitent privilege at a high 
level of generality.  And at that level of generality, all the other 
privileges become terribly underinclusive as well.  The spousal privilege 
discriminates against the unmarried and against me if I confide in my best 
friend more than my wife.  The psychotherapist privilege discriminates 
against sympathetic mothers, fathers, siblings, and bartenders.  (This is 
one way Justice Scalia goes after the privilege in Redmond.)



There’s also the spectre of discrimination against religion arising if, say, 
psychotherapists got a privilege and clergy didn’t.  But I really think we 
might be better off not always thinking about this in terms of 
discrimination.  Religion seems sui generis, and unique things must be 
treated in unique ways.



Best,

Chris



From:  <mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu> 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [ 
<mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu> 
mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Thursday, December 05, 2013 5:17 PM
To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties



                My sense is that I (as someone who is irreligious) would get 
relatively little solace or even wise counsel from speaking to an average 
Catholic priest about my troubles and misdeeds, at least unless I was at 
least contemplating converting to Catholicism.  Unsurprisingly, the priest 
would respond in a way that fits well the beliefs of Catholics, but not my 
own.  (There might be some priests who are inclined to speak to the secular 
in secular philosophical terms, but I assume they aren’t the norm.)



                Religious people, then, have the ability to speak 
confidentially to those moral advisors whose belief systems they share. 
Secular people do not.



                Eugene



From:  <mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu> 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [ 
<mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu> 
mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Paul Horwitz
Sent: Thursday, December 05, 2013 9:33 AM
To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties



Is that accurate? It may vary, but I thought the privilege could be claimed 
for any confidential communication made to a clergy member in his/her 
professional capacity as a spiritual advisor. The person seeking that 
counsel need not necessarily be a co-communicant. I don't think this is just 
hair-splitting. It's not analogous to a statement that men as well as women 
can seek medical care for pregnancy.


On Dec 4, 2013, at 10:56 PM, "Levinson, Sanford V" 
<slevin...@law.utexas.edu> wrote:

Free speech doctrine, for better or worse, presumably protects (almost) 
everyone.  What is distinctive about the “clergy-penitent privilege” is that 
it protects only a particular subset of people, i.e., those who claim some 
religious identity, as against secularists who have the same desire to 
unburden themselves to sympathetic listeners but can’t assume that it is 
protected in the same way.  Aren’t we back to the conundra involving 
“conscientious objection” and the Seeger and Welch cases.  There the Court 
could adopt Paul Tillich and say that secularists, too, have “ultimate 
concerns” equivalent to religious commitments.  Can one imagine a similar 
move with regard to clergy privileges?  I support such cases as Rosenberger 
(assuming, at least, one version of the facts in that case, which may or may 
not be entirely correct) and Widmar v. Vincent on “equality” grounds, i.e., 
those who are religious should not be selected out for worse treatment than 
those who are secular.  If I can use a facility for meetings of my 
philosophy club, then I think that others should be free to use the facility 
for meetings of the “Good News Club.”  But it is telling that we’re talking 
about a “privilege” that is denied to each and every secular person (unless 
they can afford a shrink, though even there the privilege is significantly 
more constrained than is the case with a priest), and “equality” arguments 
go by the boards.



sandy



_______________________________________________
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Reply via email to