I agree with Chip about the political realities of a public option. Even if 
that option were politically viable, I don’t see how the public option can be 
considered a less restrictive alternative in cases dealing with exemptions from 
regulations.

Employers have previously brought free exercise challenges to things like 
federal minimum wage laws and equal pay laws. Those challenges have been 
rejected. But if an employer has a religious objection to paying the minimum 
wage, the government could step in and pay a salary supplement. If an employer 
has a religious objection to paying women as much as men, the government could 
step in and make up the difference directly. United States v. Lee would have 
also come out differently – the government could have chipped in the missing 
social security payments there, too.

And so on and so on: virtually every regulation governing health, safety, wage, 
working conditions – any regulation that requires a private party to do 
something – could be rewritten so that the government performs the action 
itself. If the “public option” is considered to be a less restrictive 
alternative, then we’re in a world of state-run everything.


On Feb 20, 2014, at 7:01 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
<mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu<mailto:mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu>> wrote:

Two quick points before I have to prepare for class:

We are on a slippery slope when we refer to someone as seeking to have “the 
government[] … authorize [it] to act on religious beliefs in ways that harm 
others,” when what is at stake is whether the government can force that person 
to do something for others in violation of religious conscience. This comes 
very close to saying that the government authorizes whatever it does not 
prohibit.

Political considerations should play no role when we ask whether the government 
has another way to advance its interests. Regardless of whether the people or 
their representatives would choose to use that other way, it must be treated as 
available for purposes of constitutional analysis. The choice not to use it may 
show that the government is not terribly committed to advancing the particular 
interest that is at stake, but in any event a refusal of the government (a 
government by the people, right?) to utilize a means of furthering its 
interests is not a reason for limiting the freedoms of those who do not want to 
be used to advance that interest. The costs of using the alternative may be 
relevant, but the refusal of the people to authorize its use is not.

Mark

Mark S. Scarberry
Professor of Law
Pepperdine Univ. School of Law





From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu<mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu> 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Thursday, February 20, 2014 3:44 PM
To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: recommended Hobby Lobby posts

Very good questions, Alan. Three replies (in reverse order of your questions):

1.  Other rights contexts (like free speech) where third party costs are 
present -- Religion is different.  The Establishment Clause is a limit on the 
government's power to authorize one party to act on religious beliefs in ways 
that harm others.   Government vigorously protects labor speech in the 
workplace, even though it may lead workers to unionize and cost employers money 
(way more than de minimis in some cases).   But Thornton v. Caldor explicitly, 
and the Title VII line of cases about religious accommodation (in these, 
implicitly) impose limits on the power of A to shift costs to B to protect A's 
religious commitments.

2.  Less restrictive means (and the power of government to provide 
contraceptive services directly to employees of firms that refuse to insure for 
coverage of those services).  If Hobby Lobby wins, its female employees, and 
the female dependents of all employees, will lose the controverted coverage.  
For some of them, that will mean they cannot afford the safest and most 
effective contraception (perhaps a hormonal IUD, close to $1000 initial 
outlay).  That the government can/might/should fill the gap for these employees 
cannot be a sufficient reason to accept Hobby Lobby's RFRA claim, because the 
government may very well NOT fill the gap. Imagine the politics of the 
gap-filling legislation -- a public option, government financed, for 
contraceptives that some people believe are abortifacients.  Likely to be 
enacted sometime soon?  And if government does not fill that gap, then these 
women and others similarly situated take the full brunt of the loss.   They 
will not have the coverage that, within a few years, almost every woman in the 
U.S. will have. That consequence presents a serious Establishment Clause 
problem, and RFRA should be construed to avoid it.

3.  Why de minimis?  Why not allow even more than de minimis cost-shifting when 
the burden on the objecting company or its owners is substantial?  As we know 
from Caldor, Cutter, Texas Monthly, and Amos, the lines here are not bright.  
How much cost-shifting is more than the Establishment Clause will tolerate is a 
matter of degree.  The beauty of "de minimis" as the line is 1) it comes from a 
relevant body of law, related to employer-employee relations,  2) it therefore 
arrives with legal momentum and quantitative precedent; and 3) it offers 
symmetry between employees and employers re: how much cost each can impose on 
the other.  (Alan, you might prefer the Title VII standard for religious 
accommodation to be more generous to employees than "de minimis."  But that's 
not the law.)

Chip

On Thu, Feb 20, 2014 at 4:26 PM, Alan Brownstein 
<aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu<mailto:aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu>> wrote:
With regard to Jim’s post (and Chip and Bob’s piece), I appreciate the argument 
that in employment cases RFRA should be interpreted the same way that Title VII 
has been interpreted  --- essentially denying all RFRA claims that would impose 
more than  de minimis costs on third parties or the public. But I have several 
questions about it.

First, if we accept Chip and Bob’s argument that accommodating Hobby Lobby 
would impose significant and serious costs on third parties, resolving this 
case against Hobby Lobby doesn’t require an interpretation of RFRA that is as 
limiting as the one that they propose.  Aren’t there harms that are more than 
de minimis, yet not sufficiently costly to justify the substantial burdening of 
religious liberty?

Second, exactly why should the scope of RFRA be so drastically constrained in 
employment cases? What  distinguishes these kinds of cases from other 
accommodation cases – many of which will also impose some costs on third 
parties, the state, or the general public?

Third, many commentators have argued that the cost of accommodating Hobby Lobby 
should be construed to be the cost of the government setting up an alternative 
insurance framework for providing contraceptive coverage for the employees of 
religiously exempt employers. The literal cost of doing so may not be very 
high. There are ways of conditioning the granting of any accommodation to 
offset whatever those costs may be to a considerable extent. Providing 
insurance coverage would not require administratively complex, individualized 
interventions by the government. And, for many of us, the government providing 
health care coverage is the most desirable and efficient way of extending 
health insurance coverage in our society in the first place. The use of 
employers as a conduit for providing coverage provides few if any advantages in 
comparison to a government insurance program. So if we are focusing on the cost 
of accommodating Hobby Lobby, why isn’t this the cost we should be evaluating.

Typically in other rights contexts, we focus on the cost of mitigation, not the 
potential harm of unmitigated consequences. Thus, if an unpopular speaker wants 
to speak in a location where his message is likely to poorly received, the 
government cannot silence the speaker on the grounds that allowing him to speak 
would cause disorder and damage to property or persons. Instead, the harm would 
be the cost of hiring sufficient police and public safety personnel to maintain 
order at the event. Typically, except in the most egregious cases, the 
government does not have a compelling state interest in avoiding those 
financial costs of mitigation.

Alan

On a different note, I want to second Marty's recommendation of the symposium 
over at SCOTUS Blog. Specifically, I highly recommend folks take a look at Chip 
and Bob's piece, which makes an important argument calling for symmetry between 
the treatment of employee accommodations under Title VII and employer 
accommodations under RFRA (in both cases this avoids establishment concerns 
raised by exemptions that impose more than de minimis burdens on others). Chip 
and Bob's piece is available 
here:http://www.scotusblog.com/2014/02/symposium-religious-questions-and-saving-constructions/

- Jim


_______________________________________________
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu<mailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu>
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.



--
Ira C. Lupu
F. Elwood & Eleanor Davis Professor of Law, Emeritus
George Washington University Law School
2000 H St., NW
Washington, DC 20052
(202)994-7053
Co-author (with Professor Robert Tuttle) of "Secular Government, Religious 
People" (forthcoming, summer 2014, Wm. B. Eerdmans Pub. Co.)
My SSRN papers are here:
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=181272#reg
_______________________________________________
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu<mailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu>
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

_______________________________________________
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Reply via email to