Micah, nobody I know who is resisting the third party Establishment Clause 
theory that you, Nelson, and others have created based on “the general form” of 
a constitutional limit on religious accommodation. RFRA  incorporates "the 
general form" of such a limit.

Marc


From: Micah Schwartzman <mj...@virginia.edu<mailto:mj...@virginia.edu>>
Reply-To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics 
<religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu<mailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu>>
Date: Thursday, April 2, 2015 at 1:40 PM
To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics 
<religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu<mailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu>>
Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

Rick,

In Hobby Lobby, the majority says: "It is certainly true that in applying RFRA 
“courts must take adequate account of the burdens a requested accommodation may 
impose on nonbeneficiaries.” Cutter v. Wilkinson, 544 U. S. 
709<http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/544/709>, 720 (2005) 
(applying RLUIPA). That sentence quoted from Cutter relies on Caldor. These are 
both Establishment Clauses cases articulating a limit on permissive 
accommodations.

We can argue about the scope of that limit, but as Nelson said earlier, it is 
surprising to see such resistance to even the general form of it.

Micah

On Apr 2, 2015, at 10:33 AM, Rick Garnett 
<rgarn...@nd.edu<mailto:rgarn...@nd.edu>> wrote:

Dear Nelson,

I don't see that "the Hobby Lobby Court reaffirmed the principle against 
burden-shifting in religion accommodations" or that "Justice Kennedy made it 
central to his vote" if by "principle" here you mean the argument -- which, of 
course, you and several others have very ably developed and expounded -- that 
the Establishment Clause rules out (all?) legislative accommodations that 
involve or impose third-party costs (on specific, identifiable third parties).  
(I ask about "all" because my recollection is that you have said that the 
accommodation at issue in Amos was / is permissible.)  Justice Ginsburg notes 
in a footnote that "the government’s license to grant religion-based exemptions 
from generally applicable laws is constrained by the Establishment Clause" but, 
it seems to me, she did not rely on this point in her dissent, which seemed to 
me to be more about RFRA's particular elements.  Justice Kennedy says, in his 
penultimate paragraph, "[y]et neither may that same exercise unduly restrict 
other persons, such as employees, in protecting their own interests, interests 
the law deems compelling[,]" but he seems to be doing so in the context of 
applying what he and the Court call RFRA's "stringent" test and not necessarily 
to be invoking an Establishment Clause constraint.  And, Justice Alito does not 
mention the Establishment Clause at all.

I also continue to think -- although the conversation about the rule you and 
other leading scholars propose is very important -- that it is not quite the 
case that "the case law in both areas is lopsided in favor of the principle" -- 
again, if the "principle" is the fairly strong Establishment Clause constraint 
you all have proposed -- but . . . disagreement among colleagues helps make 
life interesting and I guess we just understand Caldor and Cutter differently. 
Marc DeGirolami's discussion (here:  
http://mirrorofjustice.blogs.com/mirrorofjustice/2013/12/exemptions-from-the-mandate-do-not-violate-the-establishment-clause.html)
 and Eugene Volokh's (here: 
http://volokh.com/2013/12/04/3b-granting-exemption-employer-mandate-violate-establishment-clause/)
 were, for me, helpful.

With respect to your (and others') Establishment Clause argument, I do have a 
quick question.  (I am sorry if I am forgetting an answer that you have already 
presented in your scholarship!)  Do you think we should think of the 
no-burden-shifting rule as applying, in a sense, only *after* we have 
identified whatever limits on government regulation the First Amendment might 
require (e.g., the ministerial exception), and as applying only as a constraint 
on discretionary accommodations, or should we think of the rule as kicking in 
"earlier," and as helping to fix the point where the First Amendment rights of, 
say, Hosanna-Tabor school end?  Or does it not matter?  Again, please feel free 
just to refer me to something else.

All the best,

Rick


Richard W. Garnett
Professor of Law and Concurrent Professor of Political Science
Director, Program on Church, State & Society
Notre Dame Law School
P.O. Box 780
Notre Dame, Indiana 46556-0780
574-631-6981 (w)
574-276-2252 (cell)
rgarn...@nd.edu<mailto:rgarn...@nd.edu>



To download my scholarly papers, please visit my SSRN 
page<http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=342235>



Blogs:



Prawfsblawg<http://prawfsblawg.blogs.com/>
Mirror of Justice<http://mirrorofjustice.blogs.com/>



Twitter:  @RickGarnett<https://twitter.com/RickGarnett>

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 7:07 PM, Nelson Tebbe 
<nelson.te...@brooklaw.edu<mailto:nelson.te...@brooklaw.edu>> wrote:


Thanks, Alan. Speaking again only for myself, I am open to some balancing, not 
only as to this particular principle (against burden shifting to third parties) 
but also as a general methodology, as you know. But the conversation is not yet 
at that point. Right now, the main debate is over whether the principle even 
exists in constitutional law, and what its most basic applications might be, 
not over its contours. As a matter of doctrine, the Hobby Lobby Court 
reaffirmed the principle against burden-shifting in religion accommodations, 
and Justice Kennedy made it central to his vote, but there is some troubling 
language in the opinion (see, e.g., footnote 37 and the sharp division between 
RFRA and pre-Smith cases). As a matter of application, the Hobby Lobby Court 
did not make its ruling contingent on the absence of harm to third parties. And 
in fact employees of Hobby Lobby continue to be harmed right now. And as a 
matter of theory, finally, prominent scholars continue to deny that the 
principle exists and has legal status, under either free exercise or 
nonestablishment, despite the fact that the case law in both areas is lopsided 
in favor of the principle. But again my basic answer is yes, I am open to that 
approach.

On Apr 1, 2015, at 5:46 PM, Alan E Brownstein 
<aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu<mailto:aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu>> wrote:


I appreciate your point, Nelson. And I think the principle that "private 
citizens should not have to bear the costs associated with other citizens’ 
religious observance" deserves respect. Standing alone, it would often be 
dispositive.  Where we disagree, I think, is that in religious exemption cases 
I see two principles here that deserve our respect. The one I just quoted above 
and the principle that the majority and government should not prohibit or 
burden another citizen's religious observance. I think, you can tell me if I'm 
wrong, that you would agree that this principle standing alone also deserves 
respect. If there is no harm to third parties, you would support religious 
exemptions.

Then the question becomes what do we do when these two principles are in 
conflict with each other. I don't think either trumps the other all of the 
time. I think as the harm to third parties increases, the principle that 
citizens should not have to bear the costs associated with the other citizen's 
religious observance outweighs the religious liberty principle. I understand 
you to be saying that the religious liberty principle is always trumped in 
these cases without regard to the magnitude of the costs involved.

There are a lot of religious accommodations that result in third parties 
incurring some cost.  A RLUIPA land use accommodation might result in some 
neighboring homeowner, business or farmer incurring some diminution of value in 
their property. A public university accommodation shifting move-in day so that 
it doesn't fall on the Jewish High Holy days may require a shift in the 
academic calendar that inconveniences the travel plans of specific faculty, 
students and their families. A court accommodating the religious obligations of 
a religious attorney or witness may delay or otherwise increase the cost of 
litigation. A law banning male circumcision exempts Jewish families from its 
requirements. Does the existence of harm to third parties in these situations 
and others require the invalidation of all of these accommodations without 
regard to the magnitude of the harm borne by third parties?

Alan


________________________________
From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu<mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu> 
<religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu<mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu>> 
on behalf of Nelson Tebbe 
<nelson.te...@brooklaw.edu<mailto:nelson.te...@brooklaw.edu>>
Sent: Wednesday, April 1, 2015 1:38 PM
To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights



Alan, I can’t speak for others who have been defending a principle against 
burden-shifting to third parties, but I do not believe it prohibits religion 
accommodations that result in costs to the government or to the public. Rather, 
the principle prohibits government accommodations that shift meaningful costs 
from religious citizens to other identifiable private citizens. And the reason 
for this is easy to articulate and deeply rooted — private citizens should not 
have to bear the costs associated with other citizens’ religious observance.

On Apr 1, 2015, at 4:07 PM, Alan E Brownstein 
<aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu<mailto:aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu>> wrote:

The problem I have with Jim's argument, if I understand him correctly, is that 
it seems to suggest that no religious exemption can be accepted if it causes 
any harm to a third party. (I'm not sure if Jim includes the general public or 
the public fisc in "third party.") I think many liberals believe (or at least 
they used to believe) that rights are expensive political goods. We protect 
them even if we have to incur some cost or harm to third parties or the public 
in order to do so. Of course, that leaves open the difficult question of 
determining when the price for protecting a right is too high. (And when we are 
talking about the right to discriminate in employment or public accommodations, 
leaving religious institutions aside, the price is almost always too high.) But 
I see no historical consensus that we only protect freedom of speech or 
religious liberty when the cost of doing so is zero. That certainly wasn't the 
understanding of freedom of speech that Justice Brandeis defended in his famous 
dissents on which contemporary free speech doctrine is based.

Indeed, the argument that we should only accept zero cost religious 
accommodations is not only inconsistent with the way we generally understand 
rights, it seems inconsistent with the way we evaluate government regulations 
generally. It is one thing to argue that we should reject a religious exemption 
when the harm or cost of granting it is too high. That position is consistent 
with the general cost benefit analysis we use to discuss any government 
decision. But why should we only accept zero cost religious accommodations? We 
routinely allow government to enact laws that result in some costs, burdens, 
and harms to third parties or the general public that serve a variety of 
purposes.

Alan



_______________________________________________
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu<mailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu>
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


_______________________________________________
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu<mailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu>
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

_______________________________________________
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu<mailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu>
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

_______________________________________________
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Reply via email to