Ben, Lists,

Let me a add a piece to what you've said to see if we are on the same track.  I 
add this point in order to highlight some features of what Peirce is trying to 
accomplish in thinking architectonically about inquiry.  Many philosophers in 
the 20th century, especially those who are more analytic in their orientation, 
reject certain propositions that Peirce affirms about the value of working in 
an architectonic manner (that is, with a plan in hand) for the purposes of 
doing philosophy, so I'd like to make these points a bit more explicit.

Remarks that have been made by a number of contributors to the List about what 
philosophy might or might not contribute to questions about the origins of 
order in the cosmos, or the evolution of living beings from material systems, 
or the real character of the law and force of such things as gravity remind me 
of the dangers of not keeping things in a clearer order when it comes to 
setting up our explanations in both the cenoscopic science of philosophy and 
the idioscopic sciences of physics, chemistry, biology and the like.  I can't 
help but think that Peirce has pretty darned good reasons for insisting that 
doing philosophy well requires  that we reflect on matters architectonic.

The main thing I want to add to what you've said is prompted by a remark that 
Kant makes about philosophical methodology.  In the Preface of the Grounding, 
he puts a sharp edge on the claim.  He says:  "That philosophy which mixes pure 
principles with empirical ones does not deserve the name of philosophy...." (G, 
390)  Later in Section 2, Kant makes the following point about any procedure 
which does not clearly separate between different kinds of questions (e.g., 
about questions concerning the justification of the primary principles of valid 
reasoning from questions about how we human beings often do in fact think).  He 
says:  "such a procedure turns out a disgusting mishmash of patchwork 
observations and half-reasoned principles in which shallowpates revel because 
all this is something quite useful for the chitchat of everyday life." (G, 410)

Drawing on the arguments that Kant is making about the how we ought to inquire 
about in normative questions, Peirce insists that it is essential that we 
refine our methods for the sake of inquiring into the following kinds of 
questions:  

1)  What ideals should we aspire to? 
2)  What principles determine whether an action is right or wrong?
3)  What principles should govern the conduct of my thought so that my 
reasoning will be valid an my inquiries will really lead me to truth?

One of the main reasons Peirce has for making a clear plan for his inquiries 
into the normative sciences is that these kinds of questions require that we 
employ the appropriate methods.  For better or worse, the methods that have 
been developed up to this point in the history of thought are not quite what we 
need if we hope to develop better answers to the questions.  As such, we need 
to refine and develop the appropriate methods.  One of the main purposes of 
formulating an architectonic plan for philosophical inquiry into these kinds of 
questions is that we are constantly in danger of 1) perpetuating longstanding 
confusions about the phenomena that we are trying to explain, 2) failing to 
understand what is special about the subject matter of our inquiries, 3) 
failing to clarify the goals that are guiding us and 4) failing to understand 
how we should use the methods we've got to improve upon our understanding of 
1-4.

--Jeff



Jeff Downard
Associate Professor
Department of Philosophy
NAU
(o) 523-8354
________________________________________
From: Benjamin Udell [bud...@nyc.rr.com]
Sent: Wednesday, October 21, 2015 1:11 PM
To: peirce-l@list.iupui.edu
Subject: Re: [PEIRCE-L] induction's occasion

Clark, list,

I think that the relevance of the classification of research is in the light 
shed on the logical supports among fields in the build-up of knowledge. Physics 
doesn't decide which math is mathematically right, which combined mathematical 
postulates are consistent and nontrivial, and so on, instead it decides which 
maths are applicable to, and illuminating in, physics. How far can one trace 
such structures of logical dependence and independence?

Sometimes physical research leads to mathematical discovery. Conical refraction 
was simultaneously a discovery in physics and in mathematics. But even if it 
hadn't proved applicable in physics, it still would have been mathematically 
valuable. If one thinks that mathematics depends logically on biology or 
psychology, one will start asking mathematicians to study biology or psychology 
to really get to the bottom of their subject. While they might find some 
inspiration and deep examples of math there, it still seems like a more refined 
and polite version of sending the mathematicians out to work in the collective 
farms. I think that mathematicians would already be studying a lot more biology 
or psychology if they thought that such studies could support their 
mathematical findings.

Moreover, one may suppose (as Peirce did) that the most general classifications 
will bear out logical structure, and that the layout of the city of research 
will come to reflect the collective structure of the subject matters like 
constellations above. One likes to see what that 'total population' of subject 
matters shapes up to look like in terms of parameters. I imagine that Peirce 
liked that. It seems philosophical enough. Peirce put such classification into 
'Science of Review', which he also called 'Synthetic Philosophy'. At any rate 
such classification applies cenoscopic philosophy. If one extends parameters 
from a number of sample cases, one may even predict that there ought to be, or 
come to be, a certain field of study.

***

It's true, 'impatience' and 'suspense' seem strong words for the emotion 
belonging to the occasion of (attenuative) deduction. I'm thinking of a feeling 
of curiosity about the future such that one wishes to shorten by deduction the 
wait till discovery. You suggest the word 'dissatisfaction'. One could think of 
a feeling of dissatisfaction with the facts known or hypothesized so far, as if 
they seemed coy, or insufficient for a worthwhile conclusion, to which one 
responds by managing to deduce a worthwhile conclusion. Yet "dissatisfaction" 
as the occasion of deduction seems too vague. Surprise and perplexity could 
also be taken as kinds of dissatisfaction. If we take seriously Peirce's idea 
that deduction _predicts_, then the idea of at least some mild feeling of 
suspense or impatience seems to follow logically enough as belonging to 
deduction's occasion. If one has abduced a hypothesis about which one cares, 
and can't think of a deductive, distinctive testable prediction, one is left to 
feel impatient for time's eventual confirmation or overturning of one's 
hypothesis in the natural course of events. Note also the nice opposition 
between surprise, perplexity, etc., and suspense. Well, I guess there's to 
brood on the question some more.

Best, Ben

On 10/21/2015 2:28 PM, Clark Goble wrote:

On Oct 21, 2015, at 11:25 AM, Benjamin Udell wrote:

The positivists divided sciences into formal (i.e., mathematics and deductive 
logic) and factual. I never got clear on where they put philosophy, I suspect 
they hoped to make it into a formal science.

I think they differed among themselves on this, although I’m not an expert on 
the Vienna circle. (And especially not the 19th century positivists) It seemed 
that the spirit of the mid-20th century was to attempt to reduce philosophy to 
other matters. Either becoming clear on our semantics that would dissolve most 
problems or to reduce it to a kind of foundationalist epistemology of judgments 
with the rest being clear formalism. It was in most ways a rather bad dead end 
for philosophy IMO. Fortunately people drug themselves out of it while 
(hopefully) taking what was useful from both critiques.

I’ll confess that I’ve never quite understood the drive to taxonomy on these 
matters. (This is one Peircean drive I’ve never been able to quite embrace) If 
for only the reason that any practical analysis seems such a mix of different 
taxonomies. I just never quite was clear what the point was. Certainly keeping 
clear what one is doing (semantics vs. ontology) and so forth is important. But 
one can become clear on the parts one is doing while acknowledging that the 
item under analysis is usually a mix.

Perhaps I’m wrong in this though.

As to my question, I think I was getting myself into some contortions about 
deduction because in some half-conscious way I was still introducing the idea 
of conflict. Now, Peirce said that deduction is for prediction. That by itself 
is enough to suggest that an emotion of impatience belongs to the occasion of 
deduction — an impatience with the vagueness of the future, or the coyness of 
the present in telling us it — one doesn't want to wait for nature to take its 
course, one wants to find out ahead of time, on the basis of accumulated data, 
what is the fate, for example of the Milky Way. (It turns out to be on a 
collision course with the Andromeda galaxy.)

I think you’re right although I’m not sure impatience gets at the feeling quite 
right. I think dissatisfaction is perhaps more apt since impatience implies a 
time component that’s not always present.

-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .




Reply via email to