Re: [EM] IRV and Brown vs. Smallwood

2009-04-08 Thread Juho Laatu

--- On Wed, 8/4/09, Don  Cathy Hoffard dchoff...@verizon.net wrote:

 Thanks Peter for your comments
 
 Suppose that by my estimation about the electorate is
 about
 
 400: Smith, Jones, Johnson
 300: Jones, Smith, Johnson
 600: Johnson, Jones, Smith
 
 Johnson loses regardless as to whether Smith or Jones is
 eliminated
 Normal IRV with no strategy:
 Jones is eliminated in the first round and Smith wins in
 the second round.
 
 IRV with a strategy, of 101 vote switch, from Johnson
 voters to Jones 
 Smith is eliminated in the first round and Jones wins in
 the second round.
 The Johnson voters would have to except Jones as their
 second best choice.

Here's another way to describe this strategy.

If there is a Condorcet winner that will be
eliminated before the last round, then some
of the IRV voters have an interest to
compromise and vote for the Condorcet winner.
This group is large enough to make the
Condorcet winner win.

This strategy is also quite free of risks. In
the example above, if the Johnson supporters
are certain that Johnson will not win, then
they could all vote for Jones. If the last
round will be between Jones and Smith, Jones
will win anyway.

Actually it may be a quite good strategy in
IRV not to rank those favourite candidates
that do not have a chance but to rank only
those candidates that have a chance. This
increases the probability that one's most
favoured candidates with chances of winning
the election are not eliminated too early
(assuming that they might win if they could
stay in the race until the end).

Juho





  


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] IRV and Brown vs. Smallwood

2009-04-09 Thread Juho Laatu

--- On Thu, 9/4/09, Kristofer Munsterhjelm km-el...@broadpark.no wrote:

 Juho Laatu wrote:
 
  Actually it may be a quite good strategy in
  IRV not to rank those favourite candidates
  that do not have a chance but to rank only
  those candidates that have a chance. This
  increases the probability that one's most
  favoured candidates with chances of winning
  the election are not eliminated too early
  (assuming that they might win if they could
  stay in the race until the end).
 
 That's also the strategy in Plurality - don't vote for
 those candidates that don't have a chance. But if everybody
 thinks like this, you end up with the lesser of n evils.

Yes, it is true that if people do not rank
the lesser candidates they will never grow
and become major candidates. It may be more
important for many to try to influence the
future elections than to try to eliminate
some small risks in this election. And of
course in many cases one can vote also for
the lesser candidates without problems. The
described strategy is just a safe bet that
eliminates risks in these elections.

(Psychological factors are an important
topic that should be covered too.)

 One of the points of ranked voting is that you don't have to
 do that - you can vote X  Y  Z so you say I like X,
 but if I can't have X, I'd have Y before Z.

It seems that in IRV it is the safest
strategy not to rank the weak candidates
(if one only aims at winning this election
in question), but not a necessary strategy
for all situations to guarantee an optimal
vote.

If this ability
 is compromised by that voting for unpopular candidates
 dilutes the vote so much one should rather not, then why
 have ranked voting in the first place?

Words so much are important. Polls are
inaccurate, people do believe in the
chances of their favourites, there will be
changes in support, there is a need to
show support to the so far unpopular
candidates, and the risks involved in this
strategy may be small. As a result I don't
think people should and people will apply
this strategy generally in IRV elections.

There are however cases where the risks
are very real. The original example was
one. Here is another with moderate and
radical Democrats and Republicans.

Approximate support:
25: DrDmRmRr
20: DmDrRmRr
05: DmRmDrRr
05: RmDmRrDr
05: RmRrDmDr
25: RrRmDmDr

In this example all four candidates have
the risk of being eliminated early. If Dm
or Rm will be eliminated first then the
other party is likely to win. It makes
sense to the Dr and Rr supporters not to
rank their favourite first (although they
are about as popular within the party as
the other moderate candidate).

(From this point of view Condorcet methods
allow the voters to use more sincere
rankings than IRV.)

Juho






  


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] IRV and Brown vs. Smallwood

2009-04-09 Thread Juho Laatu

Sorry, fifth line was wrong, should be:

25: DrDmRmRr
20: DmDrRmRr
05: DmRmDrRr
05: RmDmRrDr
20: RmRrDmDr
25: RrRmDmDr

Juho


--- On Thu, 9/4/09, Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk wrote:

 From: Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk
 Subject: Re: [EM] IRV and Brown vs. Smallwood
 To: election-methods@lists.electorama.com
 Date: Thursday, 9 April, 2009, 7:39 PM
 
 --- On Thu, 9/4/09, Kristofer Munsterhjelm km-el...@broadpark.no
 wrote:
 
  Juho Laatu wrote:
  
   Actually it may be a quite good strategy in
   IRV not to rank those favourite candidates
   that do not have a chance but to rank only
   those candidates that have a chance. This
   increases the probability that one's most
   favoured candidates with chances of winning
   the election are not eliminated too early
   (assuming that they might win if they could
   stay in the race until the end).
  
  That's also the strategy in Plurality - don't vote
 for
  those candidates that don't have a chance. But if
 everybody
  thinks like this, you end up with the lesser of n
 evils.
 
 Yes, it is true that if people do not rank
 the lesser candidates they will never grow
 and become major candidates. It may be more
 important for many to try to influence the
 future elections than to try to eliminate
 some small risks in this election. And of
 course in many cases one can vote also for
 the lesser candidates without problems. The
 described strategy is just a safe bet that
 eliminates risks in these elections.
 
 (Psychological factors are an important
 topic that should be covered too.)
 
  One of the points of ranked voting is that you don't
 have to
  do that - you can vote X  Y  Z so you say I
 like X,
  but if I can't have X, I'd have Y before Z.
 
 It seems that in IRV it is the safest
 strategy not to rank the weak candidates
 (if one only aims at winning this election
 in question), but not a necessary strategy
 for all situations to guarantee an optimal
 vote.
 
     If this ability
  is compromised by that voting for unpopular
 candidates
  dilutes the vote so much one should rather not, then
 why
  have ranked voting in the first place?
 
 Words so much are important. Polls are
 inaccurate, people do believe in the
 chances of their favourites, there will be
 changes in support, there is a need to
 show support to the so far unpopular
 candidates, and the risks involved in this
 strategy may be small. As a result I don't
 think people should and people will apply
 this strategy generally in IRV elections.
 
 There are however cases where the risks
 are very real. The original example was
 one. Here is another with moderate and
 radical Democrats and Republicans.
 
 Approximate support:
 25: DrDmRmRr
 20: DmDrRmRr
 05: DmRmDrRr
 05: RmDmRrDr
 05: RmRrDmDr
 25: RrRmDmDr
 
 In this example all four candidates have
 the risk of being eliminated early. If Dm
 or Rm will be eliminated first then the
 other party is likely to win. It makes
 sense to the Dr and Rr supporters not to
 rank their favourite first (although they
 are about as popular within the party as
 the other moderate candidate).
 
 (From this point of view Condorcet methods
 allow the voters to use more sincere
 rankings than IRV.)
 
 Juho
 
 
 
 
 
 
       
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
 


  


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] IRV and Brown vs. Smallwood

2009-04-12 Thread Juho Laatu

One more observation about the strategy and
long term promotion of candidates.

In the polls before the election the voters
may mark all the candidates but in the actual
election they may leave out some favourites
with no chances to win in order to make sure
that their vote will not harm their favourite
candidates with chances to win.

Some votes may use the strategy when it is
needed. Some voters may use it always
(safely). Some voters may never use it. In
the presented example such a mixture of
voting behaviour would guarantee that the
radical candidates will be eliminated early
enough not to spoil the election from their
supporters' point of view.

Some information is lost in the actual
election but if there are good polls that
information may be readable there (and new
candidates will get publicity that way and
their viability will be considered before
voters decide whether to rank them in the
actual election. Long term promotion of
candidates may thus still work and new
entrants may grow even if the strategy is
actively followed.

If one wants to get full rankings also in
the actual election one could use such IRV
variants where this problem is not too bad.
I sometimes proposed forcing voters to
approve more and more candidates when their
first candidates are too weak. No candidates
are eliminated from the race, so they may
come back if they have lots of secondary
support (like the moderate candidates in the
example).

The described strategy may not materialize
very strongly in real life since voters
often are quite eager to support their first
preference candidates. But as already noted
in some scenarios (like in the example) it
would be better to apply the strategy since
using the wrong strategy (sincerity) may
lead to a bad outcome that may be clearly
visible (especially if the votes will be
published). (Alternatively some variants of
IRV could be used.)

Juho


--- On Thu, 9/4/09, Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk wrote:

 Sorry, fifth line was wrong, should be:
 
 25: DrDmRmRr
 20: DmDrRmRr
 05: DmRmDrRr
 05: RmDmRrDr
 20: RmRrDmDr
 25: RrRmDmDr
 
 Juho
 
 
 --- On Thu, 9/4/09, Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk
 wrote:
 
  From: Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk
  Subject: Re: [EM] IRV and Brown vs. Smallwood
  To: election-methods@lists.electorama.com
  Date: Thursday, 9 April, 2009, 7:39 PM
  
  --- On Thu, 9/4/09, Kristofer Munsterhjelm km-el...@broadpark.no
  wrote:
  
   Juho Laatu wrote:
   
Actually it may be a quite good strategy in
IRV not to rank those favourite candidates
that do not have a chance but to rank only
those candidates that have a chance. This
increases the probability that one's most
favoured candidates with chances of winning
the election are not eliminated too early
(assuming that they might win if they could
stay in the race until the end).
   
   That's also the strategy in Plurality - don't
 vote
  for
   those candidates that don't have a chance. But
 if
  everybody
   thinks like this, you end up with the lesser of
 n
  evils.
  
  Yes, it is true that if people do not rank
  the lesser candidates they will never grow
  and become major candidates. It may be more
  important for many to try to influence the
  future elections than to try to eliminate
  some small risks in this election. And of
  course in many cases one can vote also for
  the lesser candidates without problems. The
  described strategy is just a safe bet that
  eliminates risks in these elections.
  
  (Psychological factors are an important
  topic that should be covered too.)
  
   One of the points of ranked voting is that you
 don't
  have to
   do that - you can vote X  Y  Z so you say
 I
  like X,
   but if I can't have X, I'd have Y before Z.
  
  It seems that in IRV it is the safest
  strategy not to rank the weak candidates
  (if one only aims at winning this election
  in question), but not a necessary strategy
  for all situations to guarantee an optimal
  vote.
  
  If this ability
   is compromised by that voting for unpopular
  candidates
   dilutes the vote so much one should rather not,
 then
  why
   have ranked voting in the first place?
  
  Words so much are important. Polls are
  inaccurate, people do believe in the
  chances of their favourites, there will be
  changes in support, there is a need to
  show support to the so far unpopular
  candidates, and the risks involved in this
  strategy may be small. As a result I don't
  think people should and people will apply
  this strategy generally in IRV elections..
  
  There are however cases where the risks
  are very real. The original example was
  one. Here is another with moderate and
  radical Democrats and Republicans.
  
  Approximate support:
  25: DrDmRmRr
  20: DmDrRmRr
  05: DmRmDrRr
  05: RmDmRrDr
  05: RmRrDmDr
  25: RrRmDmDr
  
  In this example all four candidates have
  the risk of being eliminated early. If Dm
  or Rm will be eliminated first then the
  other party

Re: [EM] British Colombia considering change to STV

2009-04-30 Thread Juho Laatu

--- On Thu, 30/4/09, Raph Frank raph...@gmail.com wrote:

 On Thu, Apr 30, 2009 at 3:18 AM,
 Kathy Dopp kathy.d...@gmail.com
 wrote:
  STV has *all* the same flaws as IRV but is even
 worse.
 
 I think that it has all the same flaws, but that the damage
 they do is
 mitigated by the fact that it is a multi-seat method. 

Yes, some of the main problems of
IRV get smaller when the number of
seats increases.

 OTOH, it has
 large benefits over other PR methods.

Yes. But not necessarily superior in
all aspects.

The first problem in my mind is that
STV sets some practical limits to the
number of candidates. This means that
the voters will have less to say and
the parties will have more to say on
which candidates will be elected (bad
or good).

This limitation also favours districts
with few seats only, which then favours
large parties. In the BC proposal some
districts had only 2 seats. That may
eliminate the smallest groupings/parties
from those districts (= groups that may
get representatives in the largest
districts).

One could also develop rules that would
make the system more proportional at the
country level, balancing the bias towards
large parties that the small districts
lead to (= allow also small groupings to
get their proportional share of the seats).
Full proportionality could mean in an n seat
representative body to guarantee one seat to
all groups that have 1/n (or 1/(n+1)) of the
votes (at national level).
(I don't however recommend any radical tricks
to BC at the moment since the change is already
significant from the current state and since
complexity of the new system already seems
to be one argument against it.)

Large number of candidates is problematic
in STV since ballots get larger and
ranking sufficient number of candidates
gets tedious. I understood that in BC the
proposal is to list all the candidates of
each party together (in the candidate lists).
That at least makes it easy to see which
candidates are from the right parties.

There may be also different opinions on
how person centric vs. how ideology centric
the election in question should be. STV
represents the person centric viewpoint but
allows the voters to apply strict party
preference order as well. Methods that force
the candidates to clearly identify the
ideological grouping and subgroup that they
belong to may be more binding with respect
to how the candidate will behave after being
elected and during the campaign. These
differences are subtle, but they exist and
may have impact on how well the voters are
able to use their voting power efficiently.

 
 It allows PR while at the same time keeping the power to
 decide which
 candidates are elected in the hands of the voters, rather
 than in the
 hands of the party leadership.

Yes. Or at least voters can choose which
ones of those candidates that the party
did nominate will win..

 
 It also doesn't discriminate against independents. 

This depends also a lot on the nomination
rules (that need not be related to STV).

It may be easy or difficult for the
independents to become candidates. Since
STV elections typically don't have very
many candidates there may be a need to
not allow independents on the lists very
easily.

But once on the lists then independents
are quite equal with the candidates of the
well established parties.

 This gives party
 members more freedom to vote against the party, as they can
 still be
 re-elected if they get kicked out of the party.

Assuming that they will be on the
candidate list.

 
 Compare that to New Zealand, where if a person leaves their
 party,
 they have to resign from parliament  (Though most PR
 list countries
 aren't quite that bad).  Candidates represent the
 party, not the
 public.
 
 What is yoru view on something like CPO-STV?  This
 method collapses to
 a condorcet method in the single winner case.  Ofc, it
 is super
 complex to count.

Yes, it fixes some of the anomalies of
STV and could be claimed to yield the
ideal result. Unfortunately its complexity
makes it unsuitable for many environments
(and the small problems of STV may often
weigh much less).

(To me also open list (or tree) based
methods seem to offer interesting paths
forward. Here word forward should be read
as if the target is to move towards a
proportional multi-party system.)

(Maybe I should still note that also single-
seat and few-seat districts can be forced to
be fully proportional if one strongly wants
to keep both features (and accept some other
anomalies).)


clip

Juho





  


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] British Colombia considering change to STV

2009-05-02 Thread Juho Laatu

--- On Thu, 30/4/09, Raph Frank raph...@gmail.com wrote:

 In Ireland, the constitution requires at least 3 per
 constituency and
 over time the average number of seats per constituency is
 being
 reduced.  It is currently illegal (by statutory law)
 for
 constituencies to have more than 5 seats.  For the
 upcoming EU
 elections, Ireland's 12 seats are being returned from all 3
 seat
 constituencies.

It practice that seems to set the limits
to max 4 and min 2 parties/groupings per
constituency represented in the Dail.
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Members_of_the_30th_D%C3%A1il

  One could also develop rules that would
  make the system more proportional at the
  country level
 
 I think care needs to be taken here, as votes for a
 candidate are not
 necessarily the same as votes for a party.
 (The tree system can resolve this).

Yes, some tricks needed here.

  There may be also different opinions on
  how person centric vs. how ideology centric
  the election in question should be. STV
  represents the person centric viewpoint but
  allows the voters to apply strict party
  preference order as well.
 
 STV is actually neutral on this issue.  The voter can
 vote by party if
 they wish, or can vote by personality if they wish.

Yes, in the sense that the only problem is
complexity in the case that there are many
candidates.

 Party list systems aren't neutral at all.

Yes. Or one could say that they may
allow votes to individuals but they do
not allow voters to define any arbitrary
inheritance order of the vote (unlike in
STV).

  It may be easy or difficult for the
  independents to become candidates. Since
  STV elections typically don't have very
  many candidates there may be a need to
  not allow independents on the lists very
  easily.
 
 I assume you mean that it would be very easy for
 independents to
 clutter up the ballot, since there are so many candidates?

Yes. One could try to limit the number of
candidates to keep voting easy from the
voter point of view and to keep the size
of the ballots sheets manageable. And of
course to keep the irrelevant candidates
out (= individuals that want to be on the
list but that don't have any realistic
chances of being elected now or in the next
elections) (this last reason applies to all
methods, not only STV).

The rules could include allowing current
representatives to participate (as you
mentioned), allowing parties to nominate
candidates based on their earlier success
in the elections and allowing any party or
individual in if they collect some
sufficient number of supporter names.
Also money has been used somewhere.

(One additional point is that in elections
where the votes to an individual will be
always (or by default) votes to the party
the parties may benefit of naming numerous
candidates while in STV nomination of
numerous candidates might mean that the
party will have weaker chances of getting
maximum number of their candidates elected.)

 i.e. you meant ... Since STV elections typically can have
 many
 candidates ... ?
 
 ... or did you mean that party list systems don't have many
 choices?

I don't know what is a typical number of
candidates in one constituency in the
Irish Dail elections. In Finnish open
list elections I'm used to have some 150
candidates.

(In the Finnish model one benefit is that
voters have great freedom of picking any
candidate that they like (not the one that
the party recommends). One problem is that
the system is not proportional within
parties since within each party and
district the system elects simply those
candidates with most votes.)

  But once on the lists then independents
  are quite equal with the candidates of the
  well established parties.
 
 Right, but there are surplus transfer issues.

Are there some specific independent candidate
related surplus transfer issues (more than that
they don't have any fellow party members to
transfer votes to)?

 I would probably allow ranking of parties, so that if a
 candidate gets
 a quota (or fails to be elected), votes that he held 
 can be
 reassigned.

Could you tell a bit more about the
intended technique?

  (To me also open list (or tree) based
  methods seem to offer interesting paths
  forward. Here word forward should be read
  as if the target is to move towards a
  proportional multi-party system.)
 
 I think the tree method is superior to even open party
 lists systems.

Yes, I agree. In addition to providing
more exact proportionality I find also
the property that the voters can steer
the internal evolution of the party
interesting.

(Ability to influence = more interest
= more direct citizen driven democracy.
This line of development may be beneficial
in typical stable democracies that may
already have some flavour of stagnation
and excessive control of the party inner
circles and external interest groups in
them.)

 However, PR-STV gives even more freedom to the voters, they
 aren't
 locked into voting according to the tree inheritance
 system.

Yes.


Re: [EM] British Colombia considering change to STV

2009-05-05 Thread Juho Laatu

In order to be a bit more concrete
and to complement my other mails I
draft here one approach to combining
STV like and shorter open list/tree
style ballots. The point is to see
what could be done when the number
of candidates grows large in STV
(and to try to take in what is good
in trees).

Let's assume a simple hierarchical
system with only two levels. The
parties, groups and candidates are
named as follows.

P1
  G11
C111
C112
C113
  G12
C121
C122
P2
  G21
C211
etc.

Each voter casts one ranked ballot
that may contain any of the above
named items.

Candidates have a default tree-like
order of inheritance. Vote C121 will
be counted as a vote to candidate
C121, group G12 and party P1. This
vote has the same meaning as vote
C121G12P1ANYONE.

Vote C121C211 is the same as vote
C121C211G21P2ANYONE. Note that
I assumed that the last ranked
candidate determines the order of
inheritance (unlike in the Maltese
proposals where the first preference
determined the party). If the voter
would like the first preference to
determine the order of inheritance
she could vote e.g. C121C211G12.

If one wants to determine one's
preference order within a group
one could vote C111C118C113. This
kind of votes may be quite typical.
Such votes may be easy to count in
some methods since it is clear that
they will support G11 and P1 in any
case.

We may allow also not giving any
support to the party of the last
ranked candidate. In this case the
vote could be C211G21P2C111ANYONE.

A bullet vote with no inheritance
could with this ballot style be e.g.
C555ANYONE. Vote C555C666ANYONE
would be a traditional STV vote that
may become exhausted after C555 and
C666 have been eliminated (or elected).

Also votes where a group or a party
is ranked first are possible, e.g.
G12G14.

The examples above show what kind of
votes would be possible in general.
Any parties and groups and candidates
can thus be ranked. In addition there
are some simple default inheritance
rules (last ranked candidate followed
by her group and party) that the voter
may overrun if she so wants.

I hope the intention and meaning of
this kind of votes is clear. From a
traditional STV point of view the
group and party names are actually
just abbreviations of candidates
in those groupings. Vote C111G11P1
does thus mean:
C111
C112=C113=...=C119
C121=C122=...=C131=...=C199

From a tree voting point of view the
idea is that voters can cast short
votes, and that they are offered a
basic structure where they can easily
see the affiliations of each candidate.
(Votes that list candidates from
different branches do break the idea
of seeing easily the power balance
between different branches a bit but
also parts of this benefit(?) can be
maintained.)

This approach may easily get too
complex for such traditional STV
ballot style where all candidates
are explicitly listed. In this case
we would need rows and columns also
for the groups and parties. One
easy approach would be to use code
numbers. A vote could be simple a
list of (maybe hand written) codes,
e.g. 13 63 23 where numbers could
refer also to groupings.

One could have large posters of
candidates instead of listing them
all in the ballot sheets.
02: P1
03:   G11
04: C111
05: C112
etc.
(maybe using some nicer graphics :-)

I'll skip the more detailed analysis
of the possible seat allocation
methods for now.

Juho





  

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] British Colombia considering change to STV

2009-05-05 Thread Juho Laatu

Some systems use explicit thresholds
that cut out the smallest parties.
Many systems use districts. Use of
districts also tends to cut out the
smallest parties.

Districts also tend to favour local
groups. A pro district X group with
10% nation wide support might easily
get seats (probably in district X) but
a pro country group might not get
any seats since its support is not
focused on any particular district.

There may be cases where some country
has good reasons to cut out small
parties (although they have more
support than worth one seat) to keep
the political life of the country
stable enough, but I think there are
nowadays more countries where the
democratic systems has more problems
with too few and too stagnant parties
and political set-up.

So, in most cases I wouldn't have
anything against offering the voters
full proportionality.

(That is not to say that countries
that *want* a two party system should
not use it. But if one allows multiple
parties then groupings of size 1/n
(local or evenly spread) could well
be allowed to get one of the n seats.)

Juho


--- On Sun, 3/5/09, Anthony O'Neal watermar...@gmail.com wrote:

 It is a rather huge problem.  It
 effects the proportionately 
 surprisingly little though - all the major parties still
 win a roughly 
 fair number of seats.  Districting tends to produce
 much more 
 proportional results than the seat size would suggest, as
 random 
 political differences in geography give some smaller
 parties too much 
 support in some areas to make up for their unfair lack of
 support in 
 other other areas.  This is clear just looking at
 single-member 
 districts.  Event though the threshold is technically
 50%, it's rather 
 obviously much fairer than a party list system with a 50%
 threshold.  As 
 the number of seats gets larger, this effects seems to be
 exponential.
 
 However, IMHO, the minimum seats per district should be
 around five, or 
 at least the average amount of seats should be five or
 seven.  The fact 
 that Irelands average number of seats has dwindled so
 dramatically over 
 the years makes it clear that the big parties just can't be
 trusted when 
 it comes to proportionality.
 
 The minimum number of seats in BC-STV is two, the maximum
 seven.  
 There's really nothing from keeping them from making nearly
 every 
 district a two or three seater.  Clearly, as the
 situation in Ireland 
 shows, this is much better than single-member districts,
 but the article 
 should have been amended to state that the average number
 of seats per a 
 district should be around five, which would leave room for
 two-seaters 
 in rural districts but keep the big parties from colluding
 and 
 implementing a seat number to their favor.
 
 Juho Laatu wrote:
  --- On Thu, 30/4/09, Raph Frank raph...@gmail.com
 wrote:
 
    
  In Ireland, the constitution requires at least 3
 per
  constituency and
  over time the average number of seats per
 constituency is
  being
  reduced.  It is currently illegal (by
 statutory law)
  for
  constituencies to have more than 5 seats. 
 For the
  upcoming EU
  elections, Ireland's 12 seats are being returned
 from all 3
  seat
  constituencies.
      
 
  It practice that seems to set the limits
  to max 4 and min 2 parties/groupings per
  constituency represented in the Dail.
  http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Members_of_the_30th_D%C3%A1il
 
    
  One could also develop rules that would
  make the system more proportional at the
  country level
        
  I think care needs to be taken here, as votes for
 a
  candidate are not
  necessarily the same as votes for a party.
  (The tree system can resolve this).
      
 
  Yes, some tricks needed here.
 
    
  There may be also different opinions on
  how person centric vs. how ideology centric
  the election in question should be. STV
  represents the person centric viewpoint but
  allows the voters to apply strict party
  preference order as well.
        
  STV is actually neutral on this issue.  The
 voter can
  vote by party if
  they wish, or can vote by personality if they
 wish.
      
 
  Yes, in the sense that the only problem is
  complexity in the case that there are many
  candidates.
 
    
  Party list systems aren't neutral at all.
      
 
  Yes. Or one could say that they may
  allow votes to individuals but they do
  not allow voters to define any arbitrary
  inheritance order of the vote (unlike in
  STV).
 
    
  It may be easy or difficult for the
  independents to become candidates. Since
  STV elections typically don't have very
  many candidates there may be a need to
  not allow independents on the lists very
  easily.
        
  I assume you mean that it would be very easy for
  independents to
  clutter up the ballot, since there are so many
 candidates?
      
 
  Yes. One could try to limit the number of
  candidates to keep voting easy from the
  voter point of view and to keep the size
  of the ballots sheets manageable. And of
  course

Re: [EM] British Colombia considering change to STV

2009-05-05 Thread Juho Laatu

--- On Sun, 3/5/09, Raph Frank raph...@gmail.com wrote:

 I think a candidate list system is better though as it
 allows more
 general inheritance ordering.  Ofc, it is always going
 to be a
 tradeoff between precision and complexity (both for the
 count and for
 the voter).
 
 Closed party list
 Open party list
 Tree based lists
 Candidate list
 PR-STV

Yes. In the above list the order of
inheritance moves from a party centric
model to a vote centric model. Party,
candidate and voter impact is different
in each case (and may vary also within
the categories).

 Party list would allow a much smaller ballot.

In some sense I'd be happy with a
system where lazy voters may just
point out one candidate (or even party)
while voters with more specific needs
could cast more detailed votes (e.g.
rank the candidates within a grouping
or just pick some random individuals).

  Yes. One could try to limit the number of
  candidates to keep voting easy from the
  voter point of view and to keep the size
  of the ballots sheets manageable.
 
 I think a reasonable compromise here would be to allow
 candidates to
 register as official write-in candidates.  They could
 be given a code,
 and included on a list in the polling station.

One related topic:
When the number of candidates grows it
is possible to switch to codes only. In
the Finnish open list system ballots are
very simple. One just writes the number
of the candidate on a sheet of paper. It
would be possible to do also rankings,
maybe including party/group codes this
way. Maybe with some fixed small number
of slots in the ballot would be enough.
One has to write the numbers but on the
other hand there is no limit to the
number of candidates. Ballots are
simple.

 Also, candidates might form the tree based on geography
 rather than
 ideology.  Ofc, that would depend on what issues the
 voters think are
 important.

I tend to see geographical districts
as one form of proportionality. In
addition to ideological proportionality
requirements there may be regional
proportionality requirements. In a way
people living in district X are forced to
vote for the district X candidates.
(Typically the proportions are determined
based on number of citizens, not voters.)

(There could be also other simultaneous
proportionality requirements like sex,
ethnicity, age, religion or occupation
related. They could be mandated opinions
(like in the regional case) or voluntary
(like in the ideological case). And it is
possible to force many proportionalities
to be exact at the same time (unlike in
typical current systems where the
regional proportionality is exact and the
ideological proportionality is less exact
because ideological allocation is counted
separately at each district).)

Juho




  

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] British Colombia considering change to STV

2009-05-05 Thread Juho Laatu

--- On Tue, 5/5/09, Raph Frank raph...@gmail.com wrote:

 My preference is to use a different method of counting for
 election
 and elimination.
 
 Election: Vote is shared between all candidates at current
 rank
 Elimination: Vote is given to each candidate at current
 rank at full strength

Why only fraction of the vote in the
election case? Doesn't a vote to a
party mean that any candidate of the
party may use it at full strength?
Naturally once someone uses it it is
not available to others at full
strength anymore.

Related observation:
If there are many votes  with direct
inheritance (e.g. bullet vote C111)
then the counting process may use the
knowledge that this vote will be in
any case inherited by G11 and P1.
We can sum up this kind of votes to P1
from the beginning and allocate seats
to P1 (in top down style as in list
based methods).

  Vote C121C211 is the same as vote
  C121C211G21P2ANYONE. Note that
  I assumed that the last ranked
  candidate determines the order of
  inheritance (unlike in the Maltese
  proposals where the first preference
  determined the party). If the voter
  would like the first preference to
  determine the order of inheritance
  she could vote e.g. C121C211G12.
 
 It might be better to just have a default + override
 method.

That was my intention. = By default the
vote will be inherited along the given
tree hierarchy. All voting patterns are
still possible (=override the default).
Simplest syntax for most common votes,
complex syntax for the more uncommon
voting patterns.

 So the  'ANYONE' choice allows voters to force their
 rankings to end?

Yes, that was just my style of indicating
that no inheritance means the same as
inherited by all. Just a natural way
of expressing how some intermediate levels
are skipped. Also other syntaxes could be
used (any good proposals?).

  A bullet vote with no inheritance
  could with this ballot style be e.g.
  C555ANYONE. Vote C555C666ANYONE
  would be a traditional STV vote that
  may become exhausted after C555 and
  C666 have been eliminated (or elected).
 
 It depends on what is the most convenient.  Do we
 automatically assume
 that the voters want to expand their vote to include the
 tree or do we
 assume that the would rather bullet vote unless told
 otherwise.

The basic idea was to develop a syntax
that makes the most voting convenient.
I assumed that political tree-like
thinking is common. For some voters even
bullet votes (with default inheritance)
may be sufficient. Many others might be
happy with ranking some of some of the
closest candidates, e.g. C113C119C112,
and leave the remaining fragments of the
vote to their favourite group and party
(G11, P1).

 Also, there is an issue with inheritance between
 parties.  If the
 votes are being combined using a PR-STV method, then you
 might want
 your vote
 
 C111
 
 expanded to
 
 C111G11P1PXPY...
 
 Where party X and Y are parties picked by P1.

The tree assumption includes also option
to use also party coalitions/alliances, e.g.
A1, P12, G123, C1234. This makes it possible
to group parties (e.g. the left wing). Full
ordering as in your example (P1PXPY
instead of P1PX=PY) would require the voter
to write the inheritance order explicitly in
the ballot. Giving the remaining fragments
to the alliance would be easy (even bullet
voting would do that).

  This approach may easily get too
  complex for such traditional STV
  ballot style where all candidates
  are explicitly listed.
 
 It depends on how many candidates are running.

Yes. My assumption was to prepare for
expanding the number of candidates and
groupings. With less than 10 candidates
the voters may be required to rank so
many of them that the vote will be
complete enough. If one's favourite
party has 10 subgroups with 10 candidates
each, then listing all of them (or all
relevant of them) to guarantee that the
vote stays within the correct party will
be tedious.

 It still suffers from the counting problem if the plan is
 to have
 national level elections.
 
 It would in fact be more complex than PR-STV ballots as
 there are
 additional choices.

What is the problem that makes this
too complex? The numerous ties do add
complexity but maybe computers can
handle the counting process.

Btw, one way that this approach might
somewhat simplify things is that the
votes could be shorter than in STV.
(There might be such shortening needs
also to keep the votes unidentifiable
(to avoid vote buying and coercion).
Maybe limiting the number of entries
in the ballot could be used in some
cases for this reason.)

  vote could be simple a
  list of (maybe hand written) codes,
  e.g. 13 63 23 where numbers could
  refer also to groupings.
 
 It might be easier to have the parties allowed to register
 codes.

One factor that influences this choice
is difference between manually written
codes vs. use of voting machines.
Simple (handwritten) numbers may be
easy to read without errors and quick
to write. Mnemonic names are easier to

Re: [EM] British Colombia considering change to STV

2009-05-05 Thread Juho Laatu

--- On Tue, 5/5/09, Raph Frank raph...@gmail.com wrote:

  Btw, one way that this approach might
  somewhat simplify things is that the
  votes could be shorter than in STV.
  (There might be such shortening needs
  also to keep the votes unidentifiable
  (to avoid vote buying and coercion).
  Maybe limiting the number of entries
  in the ballot could be used in some
  cases for this reason.)
 
 Right, but it depends on how many choices there are.
 
 With 100 candidates and PR-STV, you can have potentially
 100! different votes.
 
 With 100 candidates, 30 groups and 10 parties and 4 ranks
 allowed, you
 are still looking at around 400 million different
 combination. (even
 if this is still much lower).
 
 Ofc, if most people just pick a candidate and use his list,
 then there
 would be much fewer possibilities.

Yes. One may need to go to quite low
numbers if one wants to be sure that
there will be no problems. On the other
hand in most problem cases the vote
must contain also the intended voting
pattern, which means that the part that
identifies the vote will be smaller. If
the vote would e.g. allow only three
codes, then one could try to mark a vote
to candidate C111 by ranking also two
candidates that certainly will not win.
The vote could be e.g. C999C888C111.
Pairs of candidates like C999 and C888
might be rare enough to allow some vote
buyer to mark numerous ballots.

The default inheritance rules will help
since also short votes will carry lots
of inheritance information in them.

Number of candidates and size of
districts whose results will be reported
are also important (and existence of
hopeless candidates too). I remember
one example from open list elections. A
voter was happy that she voted for her
friend as she said to her since the
results of different voting stations
were published (to her surprise) and
there was only one vote to the candidate
in question from the local voting
station. (= Also voter privacy needs to
be protected.)

- - -

Some more observations.

- -

Widespread use of the default
inheritance paths means that parties
may nominate more candidates than
before (in STV) and still keep most
of the voting power within the party.
It may also be beneficial to nominate
numerous candidates (like in open
lists today).

- -

The named parties and groups are in
a special position when compared to
groupings that might exist as a result
of many people voting them. E.g. votes
C1C2C3C4 and C2C3C1C5 generate a
group C1+C2+C3 that gets at least two
votes. The tree structure sets some
limits on what kind of groupings may
exist. We may however relax the rules
a bit. One could name also orthogonal
groups that consist of candidates of
different branches, e.g. candidates of
town X or all female candidates.
This would make it easier for the
voters (there may be many such voters)
to vote for these groups.

I noted earlier that the seat allocation
rules may also observe votes that will
be inherited by a certain group. This
may make the treatment of named and
non-named groupings somewhat different.

This kind of additional named groupings
will assist the voters. But on the other
hand they will also corrupt the basic
idea of the tree structure (to offer a
clean understandable structure of the
political world to the voters). If the
additional groups are listed only at
some special secondary place they might
not be too confusing.

Actually there could in principle be also
alternative complete hierarchies. If the
primary hierarchy is a typical political
party structure the alternative hierarchy
could be e.g. a geographical structure.
A vote to the candidates of town X could
be inherited by candidates of the
surrounding district. (A candidate could
have a code in more than one hierarchy.)

- -

One of my key points in this discussion
is to demonstrate that there is a space
and continuum of methods between open
lists / trees and STV.

The maximum number of codes per ballot
may vary for various reasons. Value 1
means actually just a basic tree method
(if there is only one hierarchy). Also
small values thus work quite well.
Larger values allow more personalized
votes (a la STV).

The space could cover also closed lists.
It would be a quite straight forward
extension to use one code to refer to
a list of candidate instead of only one.
01: C1
02: C2C3C4
A vote to 02 would have a mandatory
order of inheritance. Code 02 could
represent a party that wants to decide
itself which of its candidates will be
elected. (Voters might or might not
agree with this approach.)

This structure could also allow
candidate defined inheritance orders.
Code 02 above could be seen as a vote
to C2 with inheritance as planned by
C2. C2 could have also a different code
that would not include the inheritance
order (to allow voters to either vote
as recommended by C2 or to create their
own order of inheritance). These tricks
may again confuse the voters by giving
lots of new thoughts and patterns to the
voters (instead of relying on the 

Re: [EM] British Colombia considering change to STV

2009-05-06 Thread Juho Laatu

--- On Wed, 6/5/09, Raph Frank raph...@gmail.com wrote:

  The vote could be e.g. C999C888C111.
  Pairs of candidates like C999 and C888
  might be rare enough to allow some vote
  buyer to mark numerous ballots.
 
 Ofc, a law banning vote buying might be enough in 99% of
 cases anyway.

Yes, that may be enough in most societies.
Societies are different. In some societies
the moral deterrent is enough. Somewhere
else only fools don't cheat. Coercion
is somewhat more difficult to defend
against than vote buying because often it
takes place behind closed doors. Also
privacy problems have somewhat different
characteristics. But in general, one need
not defend more than what is necessary in
the society in question.

  Number of candidates and size of
  districts whose results will be reported
  are also important (and existence of
  hopeless candidates too).
 
 Maybe, hopeless candidates could be removed before
 announcing the results.
 
 Ofc, then you can't use the ballot imaging idea ... or you
 need some
 way of covering the selections.

Removing hopeless candidates has
problems too. Maybe they themselves want
publicity since they want to grow to
strong candidates. It is possible to set
stricter limits on who can become a
candidate. And one could also give up
all kind of ballot imaging. In STV like
methods this is unfortunately not as
easy as e.g. in Condorcet style methods
where the ballots can often be summed
up to a matrix. Of course also here one
must be careful with the level of
verifiability that the society needs
(i.e. can you trust that the votes will
be counted right or do you need special
arrangements to guarantee that).

  One could name also orthogonal
  groups that consist of candidates of
  different branches, e.g. candidates of
  town X or all female candidates.
 
 An easy way of achieving this is to allow people to be part
 of more
 than 1 group.

Yes. But I'd like to keep the primary
tree hierarchy as clean and simple as
possible to make it easy for all voters
to understand the basic structure of
the political space and to make voting
easy (and to some extent to tie the
candidates to something concrete, to
avoid vote fishing with artificial
additional lists). I.e. careful
consideration needed to determine how
easy it will be to add more groupings
and candidates.

  I noted earlier that the seat allocation
  rules may also observe votes that will
  be inherited by a certain group. This
  may make the treatment of named and
  non-named groupings somewhat different.
 
 What are unnamed groups?

If we have lots of votes where some set
of candidates (e.g. C1, C2, C3) are the
first three candidates then it could
have been beneficial for these three
candidates to name themselves as a
group or a party (if the seat allocation
rules give some reason to this). The
number of different subsets of candidates
is huge, so we can afford to check only
some of them (in this case the named
ones) during the seat allocation process.

A related point:
You mentioned that votes 10: A=B can be
seen as two sets of votes, 5: AB and
5: BA. If the quota is 8 then we neither
A nor B can be elected yet. But if A and B
form a party of two candidates, then the
seat allocation algorithm could see that
together they actually have more than one
quota of votes, and as a result one of them
can be elected. (The A=B voters might vote
for the party code.) Unnamed groupings
would not be handled the same way (since
there are too many of them to check all of
them). (This is why I earlier commented
that it would be possible to see both A
and B to have full support of all the 10
votes.) It is another question if one
should flip a coin and decide between A
and B right away or to wait for some others
to be eliminated (and votes transferred)
before doing so. I note that your interest
to keep the elimination rules different
from the election rules are related. Note
that the hierarchy allows also conclusions
like vote C111G11=G12 to contribute to the
total sum of party P1 support - although the
vote contains also strict preferences, not
only ties between all the listed codes.
(I used term direct inheritance in some of
the earlier mails to describe this kind of
votes.)

 I know in Ireland, a switch to any form of national list
 would be
 promoted on the fact that it would help to weak local
 parish pump
 politics.

Would use of larger districts alleviate
the problem? I guess also here we need a
balance between guaranteeing nation wide
local representation and keeping the
thoughts on nation wide questions.

(One radical approach (not necessarily
a good one) would be to allow voters to
vote any candidate in the whole country
but still use a seat allocation
algorithm that forces regional
proportionality.)

  Candidates C3 and C4 might not have any
  codes of their own.
 
 This would allow candidates to add names of people who had
 trouble
 with ballot access.

Yes. There have to be some rules that set
limits to who can nominate candidates and

Re: [EM] simple definition of Schulze method?

2009-06-04 Thread Juho Laatu

You could try to describe the very central
Condorcet principle in an understandable
way and then add Schulze as an attribute
(just as a name that is not explained in
detail) if you want and need to point out
that particular Condorcet method.

Maybe something like Would you like to
use the Schulze method that always elects
the candidate that would win every other
candidate?

(Depending on the formulation one may need
to add ...whenever such a candidate exists.)

Juho


--- On Thu, 4/6/09, Árpád Magosányi mag...@rabic.org wrote:

 From: Árpád Magosányi mag...@rabic.org
 Subject: [EM] simple definition of Schulze method?
 To: election-methods@lists.electorama.com
 Date: Thursday, 4 June, 2009, 4:46 PM
 Hi!
 
 I am planning to initialize a referenda in my country to
 change our voting system.
 I want to propose Condorcet, and want to draft the
 referenda question in a way which makes no room for the
 legistrator to fall back to some ancient method when there
 is no Condorcet winner. I prefer Schulze method.
 
 
 The problem is that our constitution and its interpretation
 leaves very narrow place to draft a referenda question.
 The question should be clear, and it should be simple as
 well. The criteria so far executed by our Constitutional
 Court are the following:
 
 
 There should be one question. - I need to state multiple
 criteria, and some may interpret them as several questions.
 I can reason that the question is one, which refers to a set
 of criteria which would be meaningless without each other.
 
 
 There should be no specialized word. - The average
 voter should be able to understand. So Do you
 agree to vote our parliament members with a cloneproof
 Condorcet method which always produces a winner?
 won't work.
 
 
 There should be no explanations of terms and ideas in the
 question. - The average voter should be able to
 understand. Constitutional Court ruled that ideas and
 terms which need explanations are beyond that.
 
 
 It should be easily understandable. - The average
 voter should be able to understand. Well, our whole
 constitution is built on the assumption that citizens are
 dumb. There might be some place here as I can point to the
 current text of voting law which contains D'Hont method
 as a small piece of the description of our voting system,
 and a small set of criteria is much simpler than that.
 
 
 It should be definitive. - Would you like a voting
 system which reflects the different views of voters better,
 and the winnig strategy for candidates is to cooperate
 would be rejected because there are so many interpretation
 of it.
 
 
 I think the right way would be draft the question with
 simple words through criteria which should be satisfied.
 Can you help me by proposing such simple definitions of key
 criteria? Specifically I could not find a criteria which
 would not contain beat-path and be specific to
 Schulze.
 
 
 I am sorry to ask the impossible, but we are in a dire need
 here.
 
 
 
 -Inline Attachment Follows-
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
 


  

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Some myths about voting methods

2009-06-06 Thread Juho Laatu

--- On Fri, 5/6/09, Warren Smith warren@gmail.com wrote:

 Now consider tactics.

 In contrast, with
 preferential ballot, the
 number of possible
 exaggerated-tactical-style votes is
    {Dem  Nader  Repub} 
 and  {Repub  Nader  Dem}
 which is only 2 options.

Do you have an exact definition for
what votes are acceptable as
sensible(?) rank-order votes here?

Note also that this voting style is
insane in the sense that if we get
50:DNR 50:RND then one vote to
Nader would make him the winner
(even if all others would find him
least preferred).



This discussion was mainly about the
amount of information that different
votes carry. Note however that the
meaning of the vote is already a
different story. Range votes are
richer than rank-order votes in the
sense that AB could be A=9 B=8 or
A=9 B=7. But on the other hand vote
ABC where the voter expresses
maximum preference on AB and BC
at the same time can not be expressed
in Range.

Juho




  

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] voting methods

2009-06-06 Thread Juho Laatu

--- On Fri, 5/6/09, Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr wrote:

 Hi,
 
 --- En date de : Jeu 4.6.09, Árpád Magosányi mag...@rabic.org
 a écrit :
  I guess the list might have opininons
  in this discussion.
 
 If you argue that tactical voting reduces Range to
 Approval, you can expect the response that there's no
 evidence that everyone will vote tactically, and that to the
 extent that they don't vote tactically, it's an improvement.
 And that if everyone does vote tactically, then it's reduced
 to Approval, but Approval isn't that bad.
 
 Have fun.
 
 Kevin Venzke

The to the extent that they don't vote
tactically, it's an improvement part of
such a response can be questioned. The
problem is that the tactical voters will
get more voting power than the sincere
voters. The tactical parties will win.
Parties are likely to recommend tactical
voting, not to vote sincerely. Approval
or fully approval style Range voting
could in such circumstances be better
than Range with a mix of sincere and
tactical voters.

(Intentional weak votes would be ok
though, but cases where sincere voters
cast weak votes without understanding
that would be a problem.)

Juho





  

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Some myths about voting methods

2009-06-06 Thread Juho Laatu

Yes, and ties may be allowed in
rank-order votes.

Warren Smith also assumed rank-order
ballots to be transitive. That is
not necessary. If we allow any kind
of votes then there are many more
possible rank-order votes. Most of
them are not typically needed but
the same applies to many of the
Approval vote alternatives.

Juho


--- On Fri, 5/6/09, Jonathan Lundell jlund...@pobox.com wrote:

 From: Jonathan Lundell jlund...@pobox.com
 Subject: Re: [EM] Some myths about voting methods
 To: Warren Smith warren@gmail.com
 Cc: election-methods@lists.electorama.com
 Date: Friday, 5 June, 2009, 11:15 PM
 On Jun 5, 2009, at 1:08 PM, Warren
 Smith wrote:
 
  In a 3-candidate election, there are 6=3! possible
 rank-order votes.
 
 Only if truncation is forbidden.
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
 


  

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Some myths about voting methods

2009-06-06 Thread Juho Laatu

P.S. Below I should have said that Nader
would be a Condorcet winner or winner in
Condorcet methods etc.

--- On Sat, 6/6/09, Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk wrote:

 From: Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk
 Subject: Re: [EM] Some myths about voting methods
 To: election-methods@lists.electorama.com
 Date: Saturday, 6 June, 2009, 10:51 AM
 
 --- On Fri, 5/6/09, Warren Smith warren@gmail.com
 wrote:
 
  Now consider tactics.
 
  In contrast, with
  preferential ballot, the
  number of possible
  exaggerated-tactical-style votes is
     {Dem  Nader  Repub} 
  and  {Repub  Nader  Dem}
  which is only 2 options.
 
 Do you have an exact definition for
 what votes are acceptable as
 sensible(?) rank-order votes here?
 
 Note also that this voting style is
 insane in the sense that if we get
 50:DNR 50:RND then one vote to
 Nader would make him the winner
 (even if all others would find him
 least preferred).
 
 
 
 This discussion was mainly about the
 amount of information that different
 votes carry. Note however that the
 meaning of the vote is already a
 different story. Range votes are
 richer than rank-order votes in the
 sense that AB could be A=9 B=8 or
 A=9 B=7. But on the other hand vote
 ABC where the voter expresses
 maximum preference on AB and BC
 at the same time can not be expressed
 in Range.
 
 Juho
 
 
 
 
       
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
 


  

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Schulze definition (was: information content, game theory, cooperation)

2009-06-07 Thread Juho Laatu

To me all this sounds still a bit too
complex for the referendum. I'd drop
out all the criteria, Smith set etc.
since the voters will not understand.

There is also the risk that experts
and opponents of the reform will
sabotage the referendum by digging
into the details (and thereby
proving to the voters that the
method is too complex).

The question in the referendum can
not in any case define the complete
method. It may be enough to make it
clear in the question that the method
is a ranked method (the voters may
understand even have interest in this
point) and that it is a Condorcet
method (if you want to rule out e.g.
IRV). If the question clearly points
out the group of Condorcet methods
and it will be approved, then it may
be natural to pick the Schulze method
since it is anyway the most used
Condorcet method.

It could be thus enough to say:
- The electors rank the candidates
  according to their preferences.
- If some candidate is preferred over
  all other candidates then that
  candidate shall be elected.

Juho


--- On Sun, 7/6/09, Raph Frank raph...@gmail.com wrote:

 On Sun, Jun
 7, 2009 at 7:35 PM, Árpád Magosányi mag...@rabic.org
 wrote:
 
 
 
 - The electors rank the candidates according to their
 preferences.
 
 - If there is a group of candidates all preferred over all
 candidates
 outside the group, then ignoring the candidates outside the
 group should
 not change the outcome of the election.
 
 - The winner should be choosen from the above group in a
 way that guarantees that if a candidate
 similar to an already running candidate is introduced, the
 outcome of
 the election is not changed, and the less controversial
 candidates are preferred.
 
 Reasoning below. Please point out possible mistakes and
 ways to better phrase it between the boundary conditions
 given (simple words, no expert terms like
 Schulze or beatpath, and should be
 matchable to correct mathematical definitions.
 
 
 Ok, so you are basically saying (in simple terms)
 
 A) the method is a ranked method
 B) All candidates outside the Smith set can be ignored
 without changing the result
 C) The method should be clone independent.
 
 
 That is a pretty good idea.  You are in effect defining
 the characteristics that Schulze meets and the others
 don't.
 
 Wikipedia has a table at:
 
 http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Schulze_method
 
 
 Schulze and ranked pairs are the only methods that meet
 clone independence and the condorcet rule.
 
 Does ranked pairs fail the Smith criterion?
 
 I would change B to If there is a group of candidates
 all preferred over all candidates
 outside the group, then only those candidates may win and
 the candidates outside the group may have no effect on the
 result.
 
 If you don't restrict the winner to the Smith set
 (which your rules don't necessarily), then you could end
 up with a non-condorcet method.
 
 
 Also, just because the popular/proposed condorcet methods
 are excluded by your definition doesn't mean that some
 other weird method can't be found that also meets the
 rule.
 
 It might be better to just include the reasons that you
 like Sculze and use those rules rather than trying to select
 Sculze by a process of elimination.
 
 
 
 BTW it would be nice if the wikipedia page would actually
 contain something describing Schulze method, not just the
 heuristics.
 
 
 The best I have found so far is:
 http://rangevoting.org/SchulzeExplan.html
 Therefore, my aim was to find a method that satisfies
 Condorcet,
 monotonicity, clone-immunity, majority for solid
 coalitions,
 and reversal symmetry, and that tends to produce
 winners with weak worst
 pairwise defeats (compared to the worst pairwise defeat of
 the winner
 of Tideman's Ranked Pairs
 method).
 
 Yeah.  Though, ofc, Schulze isn't allow to edit the
 article.
 
 Could someone on this list give a brief outline or the
 formal rule (actually his statutory rules are probably it)?
 
 
 
 
 -Inline Attachment Follows-
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
 


  

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Schulze definition (was: information content, game theory, cooperation)

2009-06-08 Thread Juho Laatu

--- On Mon, 8/6/09, Raph Frank raph...@gmail.com wrote:

 On Sun, Jun 7, 2009 at 11:52 PM, Juho
 Laatujuho4...@yahoo.co.uk
 wrote:
  My thinking was that if the question on the
  referendum excludes IRV, then the final outcome
  is anyway likely to be Schulze (and the
  unlikely event of choosing some other one of
  the good Condorcet methods would not be a big
  problem).
 
 But they could pick the bottom 2 runoff version of IRV, if
 all you
 want is Condorcet compliance.
 
 Some possibilities
 
 elect the condorcet winner if 1 exists, or the candidate
 with the
 most first choices otherwise.
 
 elect the condorcet winner if 1 exists or the candidate
 chosen by the
 outgoing PM otherwise.
 
 It depends on how evil the legislators are.
 

Yes. Bottom 2 version of IRV is not one
of the best Condorcet methods because of
the rather random nature of the sequential
elimination, but it is Condorcet compatible
at least.

Since one can not describe the full method
in the referendum question one has to take
some of these risks in any case. One could
try to list all the key characteristics of
the Schulze method but still the legislators
could decide to take into use ballots that
have only two slots in them (if you forgot
to include the requirement of having more
slots in the referendum question).

For these reasons and to make the voters
understand the question and to avoid giving
too much space for general complexity
arguments it may be wise to write the
referendum question without all the details
that would tie it exactly to the Schulze
method. Using e.g. River or Ranked Pairs
would probably also not be a catastrophe.

So, I tend to think that the best approach
would be to use some common language and
make the question such that it gives some
rough understanding to the voters and at
the same time eliminates the worst pitfalls.
The risks include e.g. 1) picking some bad
method due to not understanding what is good,
2) use of complexity arguments against the
Schulze method, 3) incumbents intentionally
picking a method that favours them (could be
e.g. IRV).

I agree with Árpád Magosányi in that one
should pay lots of attention on how to
formulate the question. I'd however keep
most of the complex criteria and requirements
out since that gives too much space for
speculation and complexity arguments. And as
we know one can spend lots of time in arguing
about the benefits and problems of most of
the criteria (there are arguments for and
against all of them, and all methods have
some problems that some others do not have,
later-no-harm can be used against the
Condorcet methods, do we want winning votes
or margins for Schulze etc.).

I.e. keep it simple and close to what people
really understand. If one wants a definite
binding to the Schulze method, then one can
mention its name in the question (without
explaining the details).

Juho





  

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] voting strategy with rank-order-with-equality ballots

2009-06-08 Thread Juho Laatu

I have a rather practical approach to
strategies. Often we talk about theoretical
properties of the methods. I prefer talking
about the practical impacts (of the known
theoretical vulnerabilities) since often
the theoretical cases talk only about some
marginal cases. I'll explain more below.

Schulze and Condorcet methods in general
may sometimes be vulnerable to strategies
where voters change some  to =. You
however did not present and I do not know
situations where it would be beneficial
(strategically) to generally vote in
approval style in Schulze/Condorcet.

My practical approach is such that when
some theoretical vulnerability has been
identified I try to construct also a
practical example (in some well defined
real life environment) to see if it
really is a threat. One needs to
understand also the dynamics of the
problem in real life situations.

Topics to consider:
- how often does the vulnerability occur
- what information do the voters have
- is that information reliable
  - unreliable polls
  - opinions may change
- can voters apply the strategy on their own
  - media or party guidance may be needed
  - maybe a general rule for all elections
- does the strategy require coordination
  - agreed voting pattern
  - different strategists to vote in different ways
- will others know about the planned strategy
- are there counter-strategies?
- how bad is the change in the outcome
- can the strategy backfire

There are also many society related aspects:
- what are the impacts of strategy proposals
  - all become strategic?
  - strategists will lose support?
- what is the tradition of the society
  - strategic vs. sincere
  - is strategic voting morally acceptable
- are the voter opinions stable or changing
  - party loyalty
- are the polls used as propaganda
- is the election large or small
- do the voters make independent decisions
  - or do they follow party guidance
- number of candidates and parties and groupings
- great variety of opinions vs. just few patterns
- impact on the next elections and society
  - e.g. strategic votes to unwanted candidates

Practically all methods have vulnerabilities,
so we just need to pick methods that are good
enough in the given environment. One should
also note that often there is also the other
side of the coin. When defending against one
threat one may open doors to other threats or
otherwise make the system worse. (Note that
this also means that sometimes it is better to
have numerous weak vulnerabilities rather than
only one more serious vulnerability, i.e. just
listing the individual vulnerabilities does
not work.)

(One should btw also make sure that the
behaviour of the used method can be justified
also with sincere votes. Electing a wrong
candidate with sincere votes is about as bad
as electing a wrong candidate due to strategic
voting.)

Based on this kind of checklists I think
it is often quite easy to quickly come into
conclusion on if the discussed vulnerability
is a serious threat or just theoretical.

The theoretical vulnerabilities are important
as a basis of the studies but often practical
examples of typical but bad situations that
may occur in the given environment demonstrate
better what the actual performance level of
some proposed system is.

Practical group strategies that can be applied
by individuals without central coordination
are the most interesting ones. Counter
strategies are already much less interesting
(things are already quite bad if people really
start using them).

Now back to the discussed methods. It is
characteristic to Schulze and Condorcet
methods that their vulnerabilities are
severe in the sense that in some cases some
group may indeed (at least in theory) change
the outcome of the election, but those
strategies are not very easy to identify,
not very common and may easily backfire. As
a general rule voters' best strategy is
often to vote sincerely. In Range one big
problem is that exaggeration seems to work
quite generally. For example in a typical US
presidential election a general
recommendation of all Democrats to vote D=max
R=min is not a bad strategy to follow. In
Condorcet finding a working strategy (other
than sincerity) that could be generally
recommended to the voters would not be that
easy.

Juho


--- On Tue, 9/6/09, Warren Smith warren@gmail.com wrote:

 One problem is nobody really has a
 good understanding of what good strategy is.
 
 If one believes that range voting becomes approval voting
 in the
 presence of strategic voters (often, anyhow)...
 
 One might similarly speculate that
 strategic voters in a system such as Schilze beatpaths
 ALLOWING ballots
 with both  and = (e.g. AB=C=DE=F is a legal
 ballot)  usually the
 strategic vote
 is approval style i.e. of form A=B=CD=E=F, say, with
 just ONE .
 One might then speculate that Schulze, just like range,
 then becomes
 equivalent to approval voting for strategic voters.
 
 Well...  how true or false is
 that?   Is Schulze with approval-style
 

Re: [EM] tactical voting vs different methods

2009-06-11 Thread Juho Laatu

--- On Thu, 11/6/09, Árpád Magosányi mag...@rabic.org wrote:

 2009/6/10 Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk
  I just want to agree with this
  viewpoint. I have seen e.g. claims
  that Condorcet (that can elect
  compromise candidates) would favour
  candidates that have no strong
  opinions. But I haven't found any
  serious basis behind these claims.
  In all methods candidates try to
  seek optimal position and often
  that is close to the centrist
  opinions. But differences between
  different methods don't seem to
  be very meaningful. Other matters
  in the societies are more important
  in determining the behaviour and
  style of the candidates.

 I guess that Schulze's favour-weak-beathpath property
 is example of  favouring cooperation against
 confrontation.
 Any proof or rrebuttal is welcome.

This property may have some benefits
in some situations but in general I
think the impact that this property
will have on candidate behaviour may
be quite marginal for the following
reasons.

- Condorcet elections often have a
  Condorcet winner
- If not, then most Condorcet methods
  decide the same way anyway in most
  cases
- If not, then the impact of the
  beatpath property may not be very
  strong
- And if it is, still the candidates
  may not understand this
- And if they understand, they may
  also understand that it seldom has
  any impact

It may very well be that other factors
like e.g. the verbal description of
the method (words like weak beatpath)
may have more impact on the behaviour
of the candidates than the actual
technical properties of the methods.



If I try to think hard what impact the
Condorcet methods in general might have
on the bevaviour of the politicians it
seems that the interest to collect
second preferences might have some impact.
That means that the candidates are less
likely to say that the supporters of the
neighouring groups (that may contain
potential second preference voters)
would be totally wrong. This however
applies also to methods where the
candidate tries to make supporters of
the other groups change their first
preference opinions. I can't draw any
clear conclusions from this.

One more attempt. Electoral systems and
methods that clearly react to changes in
voter opinions may make the politicians
less arrogant towards the voters, and
maybe towards the other representatives
of the voters as well. That would speak
to some extent in favour of Condorcet
methods leading to a more harmonious
society.

  (Some methods favour large parties
  and that may mean some interest in
  emphasizing the role of unified
  powerful parties etc, but I'm still
  quite far from saying that this
  would determine the style of
  competition between the candidates.)

 I think that favouring large parties is not the same as
 favouring cooperation.
 Actually I would be content with a method which
 converges to a state where there are at least four major
 parties. I regard two-party system too static.

Yes, the impact may not be meaningful.
The impact may also be reverse in the
sense that if some method never gives
a chance to some minority opinions
then the major party candidates might
intentionally never co-operate with
those people. (And this might again be
cancelled by some major party taking
a positive attitude towards this
minority in order to win them on its
own side.)

 Could you point me to studies about this?

I'm afraid no. I don't have any such
good material.


The interest to grab voters in all
directions seems to be a general
method independent trend. On the
other hand we have seen that in
some societies also negative
campaigning has become an equally
important trend. Probably the
moral values of the society and
voter judgement will have much
higher impact on the behaviour
than the used election method.

A compromise seeking society
might decide to use Condorcet
methods but use of Condorcet
methods may not make the society
more compromise seeking. The
overall positive impact of well
working methods that let the
voters decide was the best example
I could find on methods influencing
the behaviour of the politicians.
No strong links to the Schulze method
in particular yet (except that one
can always market methods that one
thinks are good in a positive spirit
and thereby make the voters trust the
system more and as a result make the
democracy work better and make the
politicians less self-centred and
better listeners).

Juho





  

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] tactical voting vs different methods

2009-06-11 Thread Juho Laatu

--- On Thu, 11/6/09, Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr wrote:

 In Schulze you foremost want to defeat every other
 candidate head-to-head.
 If we are even looking at beatpaths, all candidates have
 failed their 
 first goal.

Yes, in Schulze and other Condorcet
methods the primary goal can be said
to be to be the Condorcet winner /
win all other candidates.

  I think that favouring large parties is not the same
 as
  favouring cooperation.
  Actually I would be content with a method which
  converges to a state where there are at least four
 major
  parties. I regard two-party system too static.
  
  Could you point me to studies about this?
 
 Does it have to be a single-winner method?

Yes, multi-party systems are usually
built on (proportional) multi-winner
methods. Condorcet methods work well
in a multi-party setting when one has
to elect one single winner in some
election.

Juho




  

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] voting strategy with rank-order-with-equality ballots

2009-06-16 Thread Juho Laatu

Yes, well organized and undivided groupings
tend to have somewhat more voting power
than fragmented collections of similar
minded people.

There may be many reasons why people can
trust that there will be also other voters
that will vote similarly, e.g.
1) A well coordinated group with explicit
   or implicit voting recommendations.
2) I think this way and I plan to use my
   one small vote this way. I assume that
   there are many people that have similar
   preferences. Probably they will have
   similar thoughts and they will vote in
   some similar way. Therefore I can trust
   that my vote will be part of a trend
   that will have some meaningful impact
   in these elections.

These are the two extremes. One with lots
of coordination and one that is simply
based on the logic that although I make
my decisions totally independently and
alone there will be others that are
likely to have similar thoughts.

These considerations may include also
strategic thinking.  A US voter could e.g.
be confident that many of the Nader
supporters will vote for Gore (and many of
them will vote for Nader).

One can thus study group strategies and
group based equilibrium without assuming
that there would be some central
coordination of the groups and their
strategies.

Maybe my point is just that if the voter
feels that his/her opinions are not very
exceptional he/she can trust that there
will be a large number of people thinking
and voting in the same or similar way.
Although the weight of one vote is
marginal, in most cases it is wiser to
base one's decisions on how to vote on the
assumption that one will not be alone. In
a way one can thus influence with the 10%
or whatever meaningful voting power that
may well change the outcome of the
election.

(Note also that people who vote for some
improbable candidate, e.g. themselves,
and are sure that their vote will be
marginal may still do so for other
reasons than in the hope of becoming
elected (a bit like some of the Nader
voters). Even few votes might be
meaningful as a protest or to make that
candidate's election more probable in
the next elections or to increase
his/her weight in some totally
different arena.)

Juho


--- On Wed, 17/6/09, Raph Frank raph...@gmail.com wrote:

 On Tue, Jun 9, 2009 at 4:50 PM, Juho
 Laatujuho4...@yahoo.co.uk
 wrote:
  Do you mean that one individual vote
  practically never changes the result
  of a large election?
 
  One can see this from two viewpoints.
  1) can I change the result
  2) can I and similar minded people
    together change the result
 
 Well, you only control yourself.
 
 In principle, groups where it is expected that you vote +
 where your
 are asked if you bothered could tend to have higher
 turnouts.
 
 However, once you actually are in the polling booth, then
 you can
 somewhat ignore the issue of how the person got
 there.  (but it would
 still have an effect on how you model other voters'
 behaviour.)
 


  

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Influence of a single vote (was Voting strategy etc.)

2009-06-18 Thread Juho Laatu

--- On Thu, 18/6/09, Michael Allan m...@zelea.com wrote:

  Juho Laatu wrote:
   Do you mean that one individual vote
   practically never changes the result
   of a large election?
  
   One can see this from two viewpoints.
   1) can I change the result
   2) can I and similar minded people
     together change the result
  
 Raph Frank wrote:
  Well, you only control yourself.
  
 For perspective: The influence of an individual vote on the
 results is
 expected to be different between private and public
 systems.  The
 actual influence of a private vote is usually exactly
 zero.  I guess
 it depends a little on the voting method, but it's almost
 always zero
 in FPTP.
 
 On the other hand, the influence of a public vote is
 usually positive,
 though incalculable.  It is incalculable because the
 weight of a
 public expression per se cannot be felt in a strictly
 subjective,
 individual context.  It can only be felt in an
 inter-subjective,
 social context.
 
 Juho, you're perhaps making the opposite mistake?  You
 look at private
 voting from an inter-subjective persepective.  I don't
 think that's
 valid.  The vote itself can have no influence on the
 behaviour of
 other voters.  It typically has no influence at all,
 except on the
 voter herself.  So it's purely subjective.

In elections votes are typically kept
secret until counted. So they are not
supposed to influence the decision of
other voters.

My thinking was that although one vote
does not influence the decisions of
others, the factors that influenced the
voting behaviour of one voter are mostly
the same also for other voters, and
similar minded voters are therefore
likely to make similar decisions. The
individual voter may thus trust that
other voters will be there (except if
his/her opinions are marginal) and
together they will influence the outcome
of the election. = Unless I'm alone,
we can influence.

Juho


 
 (What's also interesting is the objective perspective of
 manipulation.
  But that means looking at the influence of money and
 power, and not
  votes per se.)
 
 -- 
 Michael Allan
 
 Toronto, 647-436-4521
 http://zelea.com/
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
 


  

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] First Condorcet cycle ever spotted in a national presidential election (!?! apparently)

2009-12-09 Thread Juho Laatu

It is also interesting to separate different types of cycles.
I'll assume that the number of voters is high.

1) Weak cycle (random cycle, noise level cycle, or noise generated  
cycle)

- the looped candidates are almost tied
- can be a result of some almost random variation in the votes
- one could say that this kind of a loop is one special version of a tie
- any of the looped candidates could be the winner (no big violation  
against any of the majority opinions)

- the expected winner may change from day to day (in the polls)

2) Strong cycle (stable cycle, rational cycle, cycle with a stable  
identifiable reason)
- there is some specific reason that has led to the formation of this  
loop (not random variation in the votes)

- the reason behind the cycle can be described (maybe multiple theories)
- the cycle / opinions are strong enough to carry over daily/weekly  
fluctuation in the opinions


3) Strategic cycle
- a special case
- artificially generated (result of strategies that some voters have  
applied)

- not based on sincere opinions

Weak cycles may well exist when we have candidates that are close to  
tied. Strong cycles are more interesting since then we must have some  
specific reason behind them and the opinion is stable and clear. There  
are such situations but I believe they are not too common in real life.


One example of a strong cycle is a situation where candidate A  
promotes strongly topic T1 and slightly T2, candidate B promotes  
strongly T2 and slightly T3, and candidate C promotes strongly T3 and  
slightly T1. Many of the voters are mainly interested in one topic  
only (T1, T2 or T3). Each topic has about as many supporters. As a  
result a stable rational cycle is may well emerge. (This example is  
based on having a special set of candidates with looped opinions or  
campaigns. Do you have also some other kind of potential (real-life,  
rational, large election) strong cycles in mind?)


Juho



On Dec 10, 2009, at 1:31 AM, Jameson Quinn wrote:


2009/12/9 seppley sepp...@alumni.caltech.edu
Without studying details of the three Romanian candidates and the  
voters'
preferences, the explanation of this majority cycle cannot be known  
for

sure.

However, consider a case of three very similar candidates. The voters'
preferences in each of the three possible pairings would be nearly  
tied
(approximately 50% preferring each candidate over each other  
candidate).

In such a case, a cycle involving three small majorities would not be
rare. Almost an even bet?

Not rare, you're right. However, what you are describing is  
essentially something like a random elections model or perhaps a  
Dirchlet model, which, according to WDS's table of calculations,  
for 3 or 4 serious candidates, have probabilities of Condorcet  
cycles somewhere in the range of 6-18% - which is certainly nothing  
to be shocked about when it happens by chance, but also a good deal  
less than an even bet.



--Steve
--
Jameson Quinn wrote:
 This is good math, and very interesting, but it doesn't speak at  
all about
 the politics of the matter. Have you figured out any tentative  
explanation
 for the Condorcet cycles you postulate? Why would, for instance,  
OBG
 voters be more common than OGB voters, yet in the mirror-image  
votes,
 BGO voters more common than GBO ones? (I realize that the  
Condorcet

 cycle does not require exactly that circumstance, but it suggests
 something
 of the kind).

 I understand that any such explanation would be post-hoc and  
speculative,

 yet it is still worthwhile to make the attempt.

 Jameson

 2009/12/8 Warren Smith warren@gmail.com

 preliminary page on Romania 2009 election now available here

 http://rangevoting.org/Romania2009.html

 The results are not as impressive as I originally thought they were
 going to be.
 --
 Warren D. Smith

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for  
list info



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for  
list info



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] IRV vs Plurality (or is it about Range? maybe it should be about Condorcet.)

2010-01-28 Thread Juho Laatu

On Jan 29, 2010, at 3:36 AM, robert bristow-johnson wrote:



On Jan 28, 2010, at 5:13 PM, Juho wrote:


On Jan 28, 2010, at 10:33 PM, robert bristow-johnson wrote:


On Jan 28, 2010, at 3:12 PM, Juho wrote:


On Jan 28, 2010, at 8:20 PM, robert bristow-johnson wrote:

...
it's amazing that anyone touts Range as the most strategy free.   
the more handles one finds on a control device (think of the  
ballot as such) or the more positions one can set the knobs to,  
the more one has to strategize on how to control it to one's  
intent.


The basic Range strategy is unfortunately present in almost all  
elections,


i don't see how it would be with a simple ranked-order ballot.   
especially, if decided by Condorcet, you cannot exaggerate your  
rankings.  if you like A better than anyone and you like B better  
than C, then there is nothing to be gained by any other ranking  
than ABC.  if you really hate C, you can rank a bunch of other  
candidates you don't care about between B and C.  but it doesn't  
change how the election would work between the candidates A, B,  
and C.


Yes, the main rule in Condorcet is that sincere voting is enough.  
Condorcet has also strategic vulnerabilities but in most  
environments one can expect those problems to be so marginal that  
sincere voting will be dominant and is the most practical  
strategy for all voters.



again, other than to attempt to throw an election (decided by  
Condorcet rules) into a cycle, i can't think of any situation where  
it would serve any voter's political interests to rank a less  
preferred candidate higher than one that is more preferred.  and,  
it's hard for me to imagine such a strategy serving the voter(s)  
using it, since it could be anyone's guess how the cycle that they  
create gets resolved.


To be exact, one could also break an already existing cycle for  
strategic reasons (compromise to elect a better winner). And yes, the  
strategies are in most cases difficult to master (due to risk of  
backfiring, no 100% control of the voters, no 100% accurate  
information of the opinions, changing opinions, other strategic  
voters, counterstrategies, losing second preferences of the targets of  
the strategy).


Juho




--

r b-j  r...@audioimagination.com

Imagination is more important than knowledge.





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for  
list info



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Condorcet strategy spreadsheet (was, ...maybe it should be about Condorcet...)

2010-01-31 Thread Juho Laatu
Yes. It is not easy to give exact numbers on how often strategies are  
possible in Condorcet. Your calculations give one good estimate on the  
frequency of some of the key vulnerabilities. I tried to list also (in  
my old mail below) additional factors that make the strategies even  
less useful in practice. They may be quite difficult to estimate  
numerically since different societies may have quite different levels  
of willingness to apply strategies, different party structure,  
possibility to control and coordinate the voters, acceptance of  
strategic behaviour etc.


Another approach to resistance against strategies is to study when and  
how the voters should apply some strategy. One may have generic  
strategy recommendations that voters may apply in Condorcet elections.  
Or alternatively specific recommendations for one election when one  
already has some opinion polls available (and when one can pick the  
voter opinions by hand - maybe some realistic set of votes though). I  
haven't seen any good generic recommendations that could be applied in  
typical real life political elections. Even the second challenge of  
election specific recommendations based on already available  
information is hard to meet.


There have been quite a number of (non-political) Condorcet elections  
but I have not seen anyone point out any obvious strategic  
opportunities even after the elections. Maybe this also says something  
about how common the vulnerabilities are (more experiments needed  
though).


So, even when there is a theoretical vulnerability that some set of  
voters could use to improve the end result from their point of view by  
altering their votes, that may still be quite far from practical  
implementation of the strategy. Have you maybe generated some rules  
that the voters or parties/candidates could recommend to implement  
some of the strategies in real life?


Juho


On Jan 29, 2010, at 6:17 PM, Jameson Quinn wrote:




2010/1/28 Juho Laatu juho.la...@gmail.com

To be exact, one could also break an already existing cycle for  
strategic reasons (compromise to elect a better winner). And yes,  
the strategies are in most cases difficult to master (due to risk of  
backfiring, no 100% control of the voters, no 100% accurate  
information of the opinions, changing opinions, other strategic  
voters, counterstrategies, losing second preferences of the targets  
of the strategy).


Yes. Some months ago, when I proposed Score DSV voting, I did some  
playing with a spreadsheet to see the true individual benefit and  
social cost of various types of strategy in various 3-way condorcet  
tie scenarios. A link to the spreadsheet is here. There's a lot more  
black magic there than I care to explain fully - that's why I didn't  
share this earlier - but I think that something like this is useful  
in exploring the nature of strategies. So, I'm putting it out there  
for any geeks like me who are interested. Here's a quick (that is,  
incomplete) explanation of how it works. If you want to skip the  
technical details, there's a couple paragraphs about what I learned  
from it at the end of this message.


...

The voting system used, in all cases, is Score DSV. This is a system  
which uses Range ballots and meets the Condorcet criterion. As a  
Condorcet tiebreaker, it is intended to give the win to the  
candidate whose opposing voters would be, overall, least motivated  
to use strategy to defeat her. (Of course, this least is after the  
normalization step. This is inevitable since normalization is the  
only mathematical means of comparing preference strength across  
voters.) Still, while the mechanics of Score DSV are unusual for a  
Condorcet system, its results are not so much. A typical Condorcet  
system would give results which are broadly comparable. (Actually,  
since only the 3 candidate, no-honest-equalities case is considered,  
the winner and all non-equal-ranking-based strategies are mutually  
identical for a large set of Condorcet systems, including, IIANM,  
Schultz, Tideman, Least Margin, and others, but not Score DSV).


The spreadsheet works by first creating a 3-way Condorcet tie  
scenario. To do so, you set 7 parameters, the red numbers in the  
blue area. Feel free to change the red numbers, but please, if you  
want to change the spreadsheet in another way, use a copy. The basic  
parameters are:


-In the column num voters, the size of the three pro-cyclical  
voting groups - ABC, BCA, and CAB. Without loss of generality, the  
first group is the largest.
-To the right of each voter number is the average vote within that  
group. All groups vote 1 for their favorite of the three candidates  
and 0 for their least favorite, but you can change their honest  
utility for the middle candidate to any number between 0 and 1.
-The voter population is assumed to have some anticyclical voters  
(ACB, CBA, and BAC). However, you do not set these numbers directly

Re: [EM] Condorcet question - why not bullet vote

2010-06-16 Thread Juho Laatu

On Jun 16, 2010, at 11:49 PM, Peter Zbornik wrote:


Juho,

we have the example
49: A
48: BC
3: CB

you wrote to me:
- C loses to B, 3-48. In winning votes the strength of this loss is  
48.
- B loses to A, 48-49. In winning votes the strength of this loss is  
49.
- A loses to C, 49-51. In winning votes the strength of this loss is  
51.


Thus: If the three C voters will truncate then they will win  
instead of B in winning votes based Condorcet methods.


This is correct, if proportional completion is not used (see page 42  
in http://m-schulze.webhop.net/schulze2.pdf)
If proportional completion is used (which I would recommend) then B  
wins.


Yes, the example applies to (typical) winning votes based methods.  
Other approaches like margins and the referenced approach may provide  
different results.




If proportional completion is used, then we need to fill in the  
preferences of the ones who did not vote:

We have 100 voters.
- C loses to B, 3-48, means 49 voters did not vote. We split each  
voter into two: the first has weight 3/51 of a vote and the second  
48/51, which gives a total score of 49*3/51+3 vs 49*48/51+48
- B loses to A, 48-49, means 3 voters did not vote. We split each  
voter into two: the first has weight 48/97 and the second 49/97,  
which gives a total score of 3*48/97+48 vs 3*49/97+49

- A loses to C, 49-51, means all voters voted.

Thus after the proportional completion, the vote tally is the  
following:
- C loses to B, 5,88-94,12. In winning votes the strength of this  
loss is 94,12.
- B loses to A, 49,48-50,52. In winning votes the strength of this  
loss is 50,52. (delete this link first)


What link?

- A loses to C, 49-51. In winning votes the strength of this loss is  
51.


Thus B wins if proportional completion is used. C wins without  
proportional completion.


There are many different approaches to measuring the preference  
strength of the pairwise comparisons. Winning votes and margins are  
the most common ones. The referenced approach would be a third  
approach. It seems to be the proportion of the given votes. Correct?


94,12 = 100/(3/48+1), i.e. the proportion of the preferences (48:3)  
scaled in another way (100/(1/x+1))


(Shortly back to the original question. Unfortunately I don't have any  
interesting proportion specific truncation related examples or  
properties in my ind right now.)


Juho






Best regards
Peter Zborník

On Wed, Jun 16, 2010 at 9:35 PM, Juho juho.la...@gmail.com wrote:
On Jun 16, 2010, at 9:39 PM, Peter Zbornik wrote:

In what situations will bullet voting help my candidate to win  
(considering the advanced Condorcet systems)?


Here's one more example where a reasonably small number of strategic  
voters can change the result.


49: A
48: BC
3: CB

If the three C voters will truncate then they will win instead of B  
in winning votes based Condorcet methods.


Juho







Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for  
list info



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for  
list info



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Statistical analysis of Voter Models versus real life voting

2011-01-29 Thread Juho Laatu
Simplified models can be used to prove something about real life if one 
assumes that the model is accurate enough for the situation in question. 2D 
models are often very good in demonstrating and visualizing some properties of 
voting methods. But they can thus not be assumed to prove some generic results 
(with no assumptions on the applicability of the used model).

For many cases Yee and 2D models, with some chosen voter distribution etc. may 
work very well, but one has to check and justify their applicability well 
before drawing any strong conclusions.

Juho Laatu



On 28.1.2011, at 15.49, Leon Smith wrote:

 There are a couple different (honest) voter models that have commonly
 been used.   The two used in Warren's Bayesian Regret simulations and
 ranked Yee diagrams come to mind, of course.
 
 Given access to enough data of fully-ranked,  it seems to me that it
 should be possible,  especially with a Yee model,  to somehow
 determine how well that model fits real life.   Is a 2-d euclidean
 plane a with voters ranking based on distance from the candidates a
 reasonable model?   How would you analyze this?
 
 Best,
 Leon
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] a question about apportionment

2011-05-08 Thread Juho Laatu
Luckily Condorcet can use both ranking and rating style ballots (because 
rankings can always be derived from the more complex rating information). If 
one uses ratings, voting in Condorcet is easier than in Range in the sense that 
the voter need not care what numeric scale one uses. The first guess is good 
enough. Ratings A=1 B=2 C=3, A=1 B=2 C=9 and A=1 B=6 C=9 are equal in Condorcet.

It is difficult to say how much a typical voter would spend time and effort to 
consider strategic aspects when voting. In Range the scale that one uses is 
important. Ballots A=1 B=2 C=9 and A=1 B=9 C=9 have a very different strategic 
impact. In Condorcet a typical voter need not care about strategies while in 
Range a typical voter should consider what the optimal strategy is (unless the 
Range voter wants to cast a sincere vote without any wish to cast a strong 
strategic vote, and unless strategies would become usable in some Condorcet 
election).

Sincere voting in Range may thus be easy. Sincere ratings in Condorcet should 
be as easy or easier. In competitive Range elections every voter should 
consider what strategy tho choose (and how to rig the vote accordingly) while 
in Condorcet one may assume that regular voters need not worry about strategies.

Juho



On 9.5.2011, at 6.53, Jameson Quinn wrote:

 How hard it is to vote in each system is an empirical, not a theoretical 
 system. The evidence is pretty clear that it is easier for most people to 
 rate candidates on an absolute scale - whether numeric or verbal - rather 
 than ranking them relative to each other. That is true despite the fact that 
 it is illogical, that in some sense it should be easier to give a ranked vote 
 which contains less information. But the fact remains: people can usually 
 vote faster, with less ballot spoilage, and with less self-reported 
 difficulty, under Range as compared to Condorcet.
 
 2011/5/8 Dave Ketchum da...@clarityconnect.com
 One of his thoughts caught my eye.
 
 On May 8, 2011, at 1:32 AM, ⸘Ŭalabio‽ wrote:
 
With Condorcet, one must rate many candidates and then one must 
 resolve cycles.  I prefer scorevoting.
 
 We do not usually say rate with Condorcet but, thinking:  Two thoughts fit 
 together for Score.
 We optimize the ratings but, before we can really do that, we need to order 
 the candidates from best to worst.
 
 In Condorcet we also need to order the candidates - so it makes sense to 
 separate this shared task before comparing the differences in the systems.  
 So now, comparing the systems:
 
 For either, order the candidates from best, that this voter hopes wins, to 
 the collection of worst that this voter equally dislikes and wants to help 
 none of.
 
 For Score distribute ratings equally, with equal ratings ok for equal liking 
 - trivial effort.  Then optimize ratings - perhaps for each trio, B/S/W, 
 adjust S up to help S beat W, or down to help B beat S - THIS is LABORIOUS.
 
 For Condorcet simply rank as sorted, with equal rankings ok, and leaving 
 worst unranked - trivial effort.  DONE, for the voter is not concerned with 
 cycles, a task for the method when there are three or more nearly tied 
 candidates that form a cycle.
 
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I hit upon why rating is easier than ranking.

2011-05-09 Thread Juho Laatu
In sincere / non-competitive Range mid-range default value could make sense. If 
0 is the neutral value, then a negative value would mean that the voter prefers 
a random unknown candidate to that candidate.

In competitive elections the default value should normally be the lowest value 
/ ranking for the reason that you mentioned. It is not good if the most unknown 
candidates are considered better than the most known ones by default. It may 
well be that in a competitive Approval style election with more than two 
candidates the well known candidates will get more bottom ratings than top 
ratings (i.e. there are many bullet votes).

Juho



On 10.5.2011, at 2.03, Kevin Venzke wrote:

 Hi,
 
 So, not everybody knows that you can have equal ranking and truncation in
 rank methods. But how about this idea that the default rating in Range
 ought to be mid-range (i.e. half an approval)? Is this defensible? It
 seems to me you'd get write-ins winning much of the time.
 
 Or, if write-ins aren't allowed to profit from this rule, I have to ask
 why you should have this half-vote privilege just for getting your name
 on the ballot...? Is the assumption that if people had the opportunity
 to learn about you, you must have some merit, even if the voters didn't
 bother? Or would the write-in restriction just be a kludge to prevent
 total chaos?
 
 Kevin Venzke
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Continuous bias

2011-05-16 Thread Juho Laatu
On 16.5.2011, at 15.30, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 Juho Laatu wrote:
 The final of the Eurovision Song Contest of this year was held last
 saturday. In the vote all countries give points to the songs of all
 other countries (that made it to the final). The voting traditions
 are a bit biased. Countries tend to give high points to their
 neighbours or otherwise similar countries. Countries are not allowed
 to vote for themselves, but minorities living or working in some
 country may have considerable impact since they may have sympathies
 also towards some other country. All this means that in addition to
 voting for good songs people vote also for their best friends.
 Eurovision Song Contest is a friendly competition though, and a major
 carnival, and people don't worry too much about this kind of (well
 known) voting patterns. Maybe they are just part of the fun and even
 one essential part of the competition. But as a person interested in
 voting I started wondering if this kind of voting patterns could be
 fixed or eliminated.
 (...)
 Would this approach maybe be useful and practical somewhere? What
 other approaches there are to eliminate this kind of systematical
 bias?
 
 There's a problem with this sort of blind compensation, because the method 
 itself can't know whether the bias is because a country is consistently good 
 or because the other countries consistently favor that country.

If the country is consistently good, then all countries should give it lots of 
points. In that case the factors will remain low for all countries. They will 
get higher only if someone gives (continuously) more points to some song than 
others do. The given vote is thus compared to the average result of that song 
only (not to the average points of all the other songs, which is a constant 
number).

 
 Say, for instance, that country X somehow gets very good at making Eurovision 
 songs, so it wins a lot more often than would be expected by chance. Then 
 your compensation scheme would make it harder for X to win; X is punished, 
 ratchet effect style, for being good. It gets even more blurry when you 
 consider that the countries reward each other according to popularity - 
 perhaps the people of the Eastern European countries like the kind of music 
 they themselves make, for instance, so that the bias is indirect rather 
 than direct?

Let's say some country makes good songs, and it will get 12, 10 or 8 points 
from most countries every year. It gets maybe 10 points on average from all the 
other countries. In that situation a country that gives it 12 points gets a 
factor of 1.2 which is very low. So, support of good songs will not be punished 
(or only very lightly). On the other hand giving 12 points to a country that 
gets on average 0.5 points several years in a row yields a high factor (24). 
Voting for bad songs is thus a more likely way to gain high factors (for that 
country with bad songs).

It is true that the method to some extent punishes Eastern European countries 
for liking eastern style songs. Is not the intention of the method to punish 
for sincere musical opinions. Probably that factor is however not high if 
Eastern European countries support each others as a (reasonably) unified group. 
Within a group is is also not possible to give all countries 12 points in the 
Borda like method of the Eurovision Song Contest. Note also that the assumption 
that the Eastern European countries support their own songs more than the 
Western European countries do already implies that the Western European 
countries must prefer their own songs. They will thus be equally punished, 
which makes the method neutral again. The next problem is what happens if 
different blocks are of different size. In the case that the size of some 
(sincere musical) blocks is two, they will be punished more. But still they 
would (usually) be punished less than in the case of strategic support between 
the two countries since in the strategic (/friendly) case the quality of the 
songs would have no impact on the points given to each others. (The factors 
will be low if their points vary according to the quality of the song.)

The method thus relies on that it is not a common case that one country always 
likes the songs of another country (good or bad from and good or bad from the 
point of view of all the countries). Even if that happens, this probably does 
not have much impact on who wins. It would be however good not to unnecessarily 
reduce the points of any country. But it is not easy to separate strategic 
voting from sincere constant and song quality independent to some country.

In the Eurovision Song Contest countries tend to produce songs that are liked 
in all the participating countries (also this fact has been criticized). The 
Eurovision Song Contest thus does not probably suffer too much from this 
phenomenon. But there might be other elections where the grouping effect and 
candidates that are intended

Re: [EM] Continuous bias

2011-05-16 Thread Juho Laatu
On 16.5.2011, at 15.49, Markus Schulze wrote:

 Hallo,
 
 currently, there is the tradition to give 12, 10, 8 points
 always to its political/ethnic/geographic neighbours. I recommend
 that a Condorcet method should be used to reduce the effects of
 this voting behaviour. As Condorcet methods put less emphasis on
 first preferences, the above voting behaviour would be nivellated
 over all countries.
 
 Markus Schulze

Yes, Condorcet methods might be good. Also Borda seems to be quite good in the 
Eurovision context since I have not heard of countries giving 0 points to good 
songs that are so good that they might threaten their victory of their 
favourite songs or their favourite countries (with bad songs). The usual Borda 
strategies are thus probably not used. Range style methods would be more 
problematic since all the points could be given to few favourites.

Condorcet and other ranking based methods may also be vulnerable to continuous 
bias. I was trying to find some defence also against one country always ranking 
some other country first. Similar factors could be counted and the weight of 
the pairwise preferences of the favoured countries (over others) could be 
reduced (I mentioned this shortly in the initial mail too).

The current method gives high points only to ten best songs. It thus emphasizes 
the impact of being among the few best songs. Condorcet could support also 
songs that all find acceptable but not spectacular (=among the top ten). I 
don't believe this difference would make a big impact anyway. Condorcet would 
be a good method for Eurovision. It would not eliminate the continuous bias 
problem very efficiently though. (And as already noted few times, there may not 
be any need to reduce that continuous bias in the Eurovision Song Contest in 
the first place.)

Condorcet counting process is a bit more difficult to follow than the Borda (or 
Range) counting process. That may make it a bit less fun in big real-time shows 
like the Eurovision Song Contest. (Note that votes needed to beat all the 
others could be a nice way to indicate the state of the vote calculation 
process to the real-time audience of millions of viewers. :-)

Juho




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] remember Toby Nixon?

2011-05-25 Thread Juho Laatu
For a legislature one could use also multi-winner and proportional methods, but 
I think the question was what single-winner method to recommend. (I'd probably 
recommend proportional methods for most multi-winner elections, unless the 
community explicitly wants to have a two-party system.)

Jameson Quinn mentioned the kingmakers. Delegating the power to decide who 
will win to one or few candidates is risky since (depending on the environment) 
that might lead to buying personal benefits, instead of basing the decision on 
one's sincere opinions or doing only political trading.

Kristofer Musterhjelm mentioned the possibility that the limitations of current 
voting machines might limit the maximum number of candidates to rank.

Good sigle-winner methods tend to require evaluation and some knowledge of at 
least all the major candidates. Maybe ranking is not much more difficult than 
other simpler approaches like approval. Different ballot types might be used, 
depending on the preferences of the community. If the complexity of allocating 
some preference strength (e.g. a rating) to at least all major candidates is 
not too much, (almost) any Condorcet method would be a good first guess.

(Alternatively also Range could be used for clearly non-competitive (and 
non-majority-based) polls / elections. But probably the question addressed 
competitive political elections only.)

To pick one of the Condorcet methods one might use criteria related to 
simplicity, performance with sincere votes, performance with strategic votes 
(hopefully an maybe likely strategies will be marginal in Condorcet), ability 
to explain and visualize the results, easy marketing. All Condorcet methods 
tend to give the same winner in almost all real-life elections since in most 
cases there is a Condorcet winner, and even if not, the winner still tends to 
be the same, and even if it was not, then it will be difficult to say which one 
of the about equal candidates should really have won.

Matt Welland discussed the Approval strategies. The strategy of approving some 
of the frontrunners and not approving some of them is well known. Therefore it 
makes sometimes sense to distribute fake (or hand picked) polls. One may also 
distribute different polls or other messages to different target audiences. I 
wrote something about this few years ago. See 
http://lists.electorama.com/htdig.cgi/election-methods-electorama.com/2006-December/019127.html.

Juho





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] remember Toby Nixon?

2011-05-26 Thread Juho Laatu
On 26.5.2011, at 7.10, matt welland wrote:

 On Thu, 2011-05-26 at 01:07 +, fsimm...@pcc.edu wrote:
 matt welland wrote ...
 
 The only strategy in
 approval is to hold your nose and check off the front runner you 
 despise because you don't want the other front runner you despise 
 more to win.
 
 The main problem is determining (through the disinformation noise) who the 
 front runners really are. 
 Suppose the zero-information front runners to be candidates A and B, but 
 that the media created front 
 runners are C and D.  If everybody votes for one of these two falsely 
 advertised front runners, then they 
 become the front runners, but only through self fulfilling prophecy.
 
 When unbiased polls are not drowned out by the big money, this is no 
 problem.  But after the Citizens 
 United decision, we have to assume that disinformation is the rule, not the 
 exception.
 
 For me it seems we are so far from a point were discerning the front
 runner is anything but blindingly obvious (at least in the US) that it
 is a complete non-issue. Did any of the alternative candidates get into
 the two digit range in 2008? The third party candidates are so
 irrelevant that after a couple searches I still hadn't found a link that
 mentioned the percentage results to put in this post. I would be
 thrilled if when voting I even *considered* dropping my vote for the
 lesser horror front runner in an approval vote.

Approval would be a perfect start for the US (assuming that you want to get rid 
of the two party dominance). It would work fine as long as the small 
parties/candidates remain small. When there are more than two potential 
winners, then Approval will face some strategy problems, and possibly also some 
of the discussed strategic poll related problems. When such problems 
materialize, then it would be time to change the system again. And at that 
point the probability of people wanting to return back to the old FPTP and two 
party domination would maybe be smaller.

 
 These concerns are like bikeshedding, we are arguing about the paint
 color and we don't even have a roof, walls or foundation, hell, we don't
 even agree on the plans.

On this list there are many people with their own inventions and favourite 
methods, and people who love to study all the possibilities. They may be less 
all over the place if one makes the difference between theoretical studies and 
practical implementations. Also pointing out the target environment will reduce 
the number of possible choices. For example to me Approval is not an ideal 
theoretical general purpose single winner method, but if we discuss about 
possible next steps for some single winner elections in the US (where FPTP is 
used today), and we state getting rid of the two party dominance, then Approval 
is an excellent choice (maybe not to last forever, but a perfect tool for the 
current problem anyway).

There may also be endless debates e.g. on the properties of the numerous 
Condorcet variants. Many people on this list agree that Condorcet methods are 
excellent general purpose single winner methods for competitive majority 
oriented elections. But if the need to rank (or rate) all major candidates is 
too much, then some simpler ballots should be used. And it is difficult to get 
an agreement on which one of the Condorcet methods is the ultimate best one, 
but that doesn't matter too much since all of them work quite well when 
compared to many of their competitors.

 
 That doesn't mean the debate on this list is not important, it is very
 important, but I come full circle to my post from a while back. When the
 knowledgeable experts can't put out a unified front there will be no
 moving forward.

I would have liked this list to find some general agreements on what methods 
should be generally recommended for practical use in different environments and 
traditions. That has not happened during the years. With clearly defined 
targets (e.g. a practical and politically acceptable solution for some 
particular election in the US within n years), maybe people on this list can at 
least point out the properties of various approaches. I don't expect consensus 
on one particular choice. I don't expect people to jointly sign any petition to 
support one chosen approach. Since the theoretical / scientific / web community 
is not organized, maybe support should be sought from some more traditional 
forms of political campaigning (lobbying, political activists, political 
movements, initiative with a support group).

 
 Sorry, it's hard to watch a country which had so much potential to make
 the human condition better for people all around the world, turn a bit
 uglier, meaner and, yup, more fascist every day. I suspect that the only
 thing that can turn this around in a sustainable way is a change in the
 voting system but without a crystal clear rallying cry from the experts
 for *ONE* method that will never happen.
 
 Truth is that the goals of this list 

Re: [EM] remember Toby Nixon?

2011-05-26 Thread Juho Laatu
On 26.5.2011, at 4.35, robert bristow-johnson wrote:

 being that they choose the same winner in the case that there are only 3 
 candidates in the cycle, i would recommend Tideman over Schulze (sorry 
 Marcus) for the simplicity of explanation.  while getting a Condorcet cycle 
 is expected to be rare enough, how often in real elections in government, 
 would you expect a situation where RP and CSSD will arrive at a different 
 result?

If there are only few candidates and clear political agendas and clear 
differences between them, then cycles of 3 are probably much more common than 
cycles of 4. If there is a large number of quite equal candidates and no 
dominant or clear preference orders among the voters, then cycles of 4 and 
higher could be almost as common. In that case the differences between methods 
that differ only on cycles of 4 become relevant, maybe not very critical 
though. The choice between margins and winning votes could impact the results 
sooner. I guess Schulze is by default winning votes based. Ranked pairs maybe 
more margins oriented(?). But one could use either depending on one's 
preferences.

If you are looking for simplicity then maybe also minmax should be considered 
since it (the margins version) simply measures the number of required 
additional voters to beat all others. That is easy to explain, and also to 
visualize the results during the counting process (one should pay some 
attention also to this kind of real-time visualizations). It may pick also 
outside the top cycle in some extreme situations where the losses within the 
cycle are worse than the losses of some compromise candidate outside the cycle. 
Good or bad (to always respect the clone independence or to pick the least 
controversial winner), maybe a matter of taste.

Juho





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Statement by this list (was Remember toby Nixon)

2011-05-27 Thread Juho Laatu
On 27.5.2011, at 10.01, Jameson Quinn wrote:

 This thread, like this list, has two purposes - practical advocacy and 
 mathematical exploration.

One could divide the field also further by making a difference between 1) 
practical advocacy, 2) practical exploration of real life examples, 3) 
practical method exploration in general, and 4) mathematical (theoretical) 
exploration. These could mean respectively e.g. 1) active participation in 
politics, 2) using the current status of some country / election as a basis for 
the work, 3) general recommendations for presidential elections, and 4) 
delegation of one's vote to an intelligent computer in a future dystopia, or 
maybe just plain mathematical properties of some methods.

 
 On the practical advocacy front, I'd propose a process:
 0. We discuss get some degree of informal consensus on this process itself - 
 I imagine it will take about a week, so say, before Sunday June 5th.
 1. We draw up a statement which details the serious problems with plurality 
 in the US context, and states that there are solutions. Leave a blank space 
 for a list of acceptable solutions. This statement, when finished (after step 
 3) would be signable by any members of this list, completely at their own 
 option.

Good approach. I have one comment on the target statement. Expression problems 
with plurality in the US context contains the assumption that the traditional 
two-party system in not the correct solution for the US. Expression and states 
that there are solutions refers to possible solutions at some general and 
neutral level. This latter formulation is a theoretical statement that does not 
yet say what the US should do. This is interesting from the point of view that 
US citizens might want to say what the US should do in this question while the 
non-US-citizens might be happy with stating the theoretical facts and possible 
options only.

There could thus be two levels. One for practical advocation and political 
activism within some country and one for general opinions, coming from neutral 
experts (maybe unwilling to take position on the internal matters of that 
country). That is, category 1) vs. categories 2) and 3) in my list above.

 2. We take a vote on what options to list. We can use betterpolls.com, 
 remembering that the scores there are -10 to 10, and negative/positive is 
 mapped to approval/disapproval.

Voting could be a more difficult process than collecting the list of options 
using sone informal consensus as in point 0. In general I tend to rely on 
some single person (or few) taking a leading role in creating such a paper that 
it can be agreed my some critical mass. One can also produce serially multiple 
versions of the list and paper to find the best combination (that the creators 
and as large group of supporters as needed are happy to sign).

 3. We list the options and the winner(s) in the statement and sign it.
 4. When we have a good number of signatures, we put out a press release to 
 some bloggers who've shown an interest in the issue (e.g. Andrew Sullivan)

Would we be the list of supporters? That sounds easier than using the name of 
this list.

 
 My hope is that, despite the varied opinions, we could say something clearly 
 and strongly enough to have an impact.

I'm sure there are many points where most (or at least many credible) experts 
agree and that would bring useful information to politicians, practical 
reformers and regular voters. Maybe it would take some strong individual(s) 
dedicated to this kind of practical matters to extract those opinions out from 
the rest of the experts.

I'd be happy to see some general statements with wide consensus among experts 
on how the voting practices could be improved allover the world (i.e. also 
practical facts that can support real life decisions in addition to personal 
opinions and mathematical facts).

Juho


 
 JQ
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Remember Toby

2011-05-28 Thread Juho Laatu
On 28.5.2011, at 23.16, robert bristow-johnson wrote:

 
 On May 28, 2011, at 3:41 PM, S Sosnick wrote:
 
 
 On 27-May-2011, Jameson Quinn, wrote, I agree [with Juho Laatu].  If 
 minimax is twice as likely
 to be adopted, because it's simpler, and gives 95% of the advantage vs. 
 plurality of the
 theoretically-best Condorcet methods, then it *is* the best.  And besides, 
 if we try to get
 consensus on which is the absolutely best completion method, then almost by
 definition, we're going to end up arguing in circles (cycles?).
 
 I also agree.  More noteworthy, however, is that Nicolaus Tideman does, too. 
  At page 242 of
 Collective Decisions and Voting (2006), he says, If voters and vote 
 counters have only a slight
 tolerance for complexity, the maximin rule is the one they would reasonably 
 choose.
 
 will minimax of margins decide differently than ranked pairs?  if the cycle 
 has only three candidates, it seems to me that it must be equivalent to 
 ranked pairs.

With cycles of three maybe the main difference between the most popular methods 
is the choice between margins and winning votes. In addition to that minmax may 
elect outside the top cycle in the rare case that the defeats within the top 
cycle are all stronger than any of the losses of some candidate outside the top 
cycle.

 
 is there any good reason to use minimax of winning votes (clipped at zero) 
 over minimax using margins?

I guess the usual arguments on e.g. strategic voting and strength of pairwise 
comparisons apply on this comparison in both directions. If one looks for 
simplicity and ease of explaining the method and ease of following the vote 
counting process, then margins has some advantages since, as said, it always 
measures the number of additional (first preference) votes each candidate would 
have needed (or would still need) to beat all other candidates.

  it seems to me that a candidate pairing where Candidate A just squeaks by 
 Candidate B, but where a lotta people vote should have less weight than a 
 pairing where one candidate creams the other, but fewer voters weighed in on 
 it.

In margins pairwise victory of 55-45 is as strong as 35-25. In winning votes 
55-45 is as strong as 55-5. In the margins example 35 is not a majority but it 
is 40% bigger than 25 (while 55 is only 22% bigger than 45). In the winning 
votes example both victories have majority but in the latter one the winning 
side has more than ten times the number of votes of the other side. It is hard 
to say what kind of a rule would be ideal for all elections. Minmax(margins) in 
a way relies on the required additional voters philosophy when measuring the 
strength of preferences. (There are also other approaches to measuring the 
pairwise preferences, like counting the proportion, e.g. 55/45 = 122%.)

Juho


 
 --
 
 r b-j  r...@audioimagination.com
 
 Imagination is more important than knowledge.
 
 
 
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Remember Toby

2011-05-28 Thread Juho Laatu
On 29.5.2011, at 1.33, Kevin Venzke wrote:

 Margins elects A here:
 35 AB
 25 B
 40 C
 
 Is this going to be defensible when this method is proposed? Can you
 argue a case for A without mindreading off of the blank areas of the 
 ballots?

I guess the common assumption is that the unranked candidates are considered to 
be tied at the last position. So, vote B should be read BA=C.

(The intended meaning of B and BA=C is thus the same by default. Some 
methods may however have an implicit approval cutoff at the end of the 
explicitly ranked candidates. In that case vote B should be interpreted B | 
A=C and BA=C should be interpreted BA=C |, but I consider that to be a 
special case. If the voter has some preference between A and C (and she wants 
to express it), then the voter should mark that in the ballot, since otherwise 
there is no other sensible interpretation but that A and C should be treated as 
equal. If there are so many potential winners in the election that one can not 
expect all voters to rank all potential winners, then we may lose some of the 
information that the voters wanted to give. I'm not sure if I answered properly 
to the mindreading point here but those were my thoughts anyway.)

Why would margins elect A then? The explanation is simple from the margins 
point of view. If we elect A then there are 40 voters saying that C should have 
been elected instead of A and 5 less saying than A is better. If we elect B 
then there are 35 voters saying that A should have been elected instead of A 
and 10 less saying than B is better. If we elect C then there are 60 voters 
saying that B should have been elected instead of C and 20 less saying than C 
is better. From that point of view A is the least controversial winner. A would 
need only 6 additional votes to become a Condorcet winner and beat all others.

 the voters give you a single majority decision (more than half the
 voters) and that's the one you don't respect?

That could happen in margins. It is possible that the winner is opposed by a 
majority of the voters, and in all other pairwise comparisons the winning side 
has less than majority of the votes, but those comparisons are stronger when 
measured as difference between winning and losing side (e.g. 30: AB, 21:B, 49: 
C). I'm not sure when majorities should be given precedence and what majorities 
that would mean. In large elections there is seldom a majority of all the 
people or the whole electorate. In the case of margins above in all the 
pairwise comparisons the winning side had majority of all the voters that 
wanted to express their opinion in that pairwise contest (although not a 
majority of all the valid ballots of that election).

Juho




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Statement by this list (was Remember toby Nixon)

2011-05-28 Thread Juho Laatu
On 29.5.2011, at 2.09, James Gilmour wrote:

 On 27.5.2011, at 10.01, Jameson Quinn wrote:
 1. We draw up a statement which details the serious problems 
 with plurality in the US context, and states that there are 
 solutions.
 
 Juho Laatu  Sent: Friday, May 27, 2011 9:43 PM 
 Good approach. I have one comment on the target statement. 
 Expression problems with plurality in the US context 
 contains the assumption that the traditional two-party system 
 in not the correct solution for the US. 
 
 I would respectfully suggest that this statement is not correct.  I don't 
 think JQ's statement says or implies anything about the
 traditional two-party system.  But even if the electors and voters in the 
 USA wanted and voted only for the traditional two-party
 system, there could be, and probably would be, problems with plurality, even 
 in the US context.  Plurality frequently distorts the
 voters' wishes, is inherently unstable, and even when it delivers acceptably 
 balanced representation overall there are often
 electoral deserts where one party or the other has almost no representation 
 despite having significant voting support there, even
 when there are only two parties.
 
 And I think you need to distinguish between the two types of election that 
 occur in the US context: election to a single-office
 (city mayor, state governor, etc); and election to a representative 
 assembly (city council, state legislature with upper and lower
 houses, federal legislature with upper and lower houses).  These two types of 
 election present different opportunities for securing
 representation of the voters within a system of representative democracy.  
 These are more fundamental issues that I would suggest
 you need to address, and they are quite independent of any consideration of 
 the number of parties (or the number of effective
 parties) that might come later.
 
 JG

Ok, I agree that plurality may have problems also within an otherwise well 
working two-party system. And a two-party country might well have single winner 
elections that are not partisan and contain several candidates that are not 
associated with the two parties. Or maybe we want to have a method that allows 
both parties to nominate more than one candidate. In all these cases we might 
need also improved methods.

Juho







Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Remember toby

2011-05-29 Thread Juho Laatu
On 29.5.2011, at 3.53, fsimm...@pcc.edu wrote:

 I agree with Kevin.  Winning Votes is much better and easier to defend.

Kevin Venzke referred to the number of disappointed voters on the winning side 
(that will be overruled in the case of a top cycle). That's one concern. I have 
some problems finding good explanations behind the winning votes philosophy. 
One problem is that also the losing side votes should have some weight. 51-49 
seems almost tied and 50-0 seems almost unanimous (although only half of the 
voters gave their opinion on this pairwise comparison).

49: AB
49: C
2: BC

In this example there seem to be two large parties, one of which has two 
candidates (good and bad). In addition there are 2 voters that don't vote like 
the others do. It is not easy to me to defend the WV philosophy that B should 
win this election.

In margins one can discuss if 55-45 should really be equal to 15-5 but to me it 
seems that margins is at least roughly in the correct direction all the time 
anyway.

 But I still think that we should go with a method that is does not require 
 the voters to rank the 
 candidates.
 
 From simplest to less simple but still simple enough:
 
 1. Asset Voting
 2. Approval
 3. DYN
 4. MCA
 5. The Bucklin Variant of Venzke and Benham

Filling an Approval ballot is technically easier than filling a Condorcet 
ballot (there can be many different kind of ballots). But isn't Bucklin already 
in in the Condorcet category of complexity (=to give rankings or ratings to at 
least all potential winners)? If one has only limited number of slots available 
(like in some of the methods), then the interesting question is how good 
results will Condorcet methods give if the number of ranks is limited to some 
fixed number (to make voting and/or ballot format simpler).

Although Approval ballots can be simpler technically, the complexity of 
strategy selection in Approval may make it more complicated than Condorcet 
voting in the minds of some voters at least. One argument in favour of (the 
simplicity of) Condorcet methods is thus that usually strategic thinking is not 
needed. Giving one's sincere rankings is already enough and with good 
probability the best strategy for all voters.

Juho








Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Remember Toby

2011-05-29 Thread Juho Laatu
On 29.5.2011, at 5.07, Kevin Venzke wrote:

 Hi Juho,
 
 --- En date de : Sam 28.5.11, Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk a écrit :
 Margins elects A here:
 35 AB
 25 B
 40 C
 
 Is this going to be defensible when this method is
 proposed? Can you
 argue a case for A without mindreading off of the
 blank areas of the 
 ballots?
 
 I guess the common assumption is that the unranked
 candidates are considered to be tied at the last position.
 So, vote B should be read BA=C.
 
 (The intended meaning of B and BA=C is thus the
 same by default. Some methods may however have an implicit
 approval cutoff at the end of the explicitly ranked
 candidates. In that case vote B should be interpreted B |
 A=C and BA=C should be interpreted BA=C |, but
 I consider that to be a special case. If the voter has some
 preference between A and C (and she wants to express it),
 then the voter should mark that in the ballot, since
 otherwise there is no other sensible interpretation but that
 A and C should be treated as equal. If there are so many
 potential winners in the election that one can not expect
 all voters to rank all potential winners, then we may lose
 some of the information that the voters wanted to give. I'm
 not sure if I answered properly to the mindreading point
 here but those were my thoughts anyway.)
 
 The mindreading point is that you are having to say if the voters
 wanted to say something they could have said it. I'm not sure this will
 be persuasive because you can't offer an assurance that those voters
 could vote that way without risking something. This is why I suggest that
 you had better force voters to rank everyone in a margins method.

In som sense margins does this. Vote B gives the same result as half vote 
BAC and half vote BCA together. Or statistically the results are the 
same if all uncertain voters will flip a coin and vote either way.

 
 In WV A and C will be considered as equal, too - it just won't count
 that voter as a schizophrenic who always feels 50% cheated no matter what
 happens between the two.

This was not an easy explanation :-).

Juho


 
 Kevin
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Generalized symmetric ballot completion (was Hybrid/generalized ranked/approval ballots)

2011-05-29 Thread Juho Laatu
On 29.5.2011, at 16.06, Peter Zbornik wrote:

 On the other hand I might rather prefer My Political Opponent to be elected 
 than Pol Pot.
 Thus a ballot on the form AXMy Political OpponentPol Pot, might be a good 
 idea to allow.

I like this kind of explicit cutoffs more than implicit ones (at the end of the 
ranked candidates) since implicit cutoff easily encourages truncation. If 
people like to truncate their strongest opponents we might end up having bullet 
votes only. That would mean that we would be back in plurality, and all useful 
information of the ranked votes would be gone.

The explicit cutoff works well in elections where it is possible not to elect 
anyone (maybe keep the old elected alternative, or maybe arrange a new election 
after a while). One could also have elections where there are many possible 
outcomes, e.g. a seat for 6 months or a seat for 2 years (A2yBC6mD). In 
these cases it is possible to measure quite reliably which candidates fall into 
which categories (e.g. approvable enough). The detailed rules on how to 
interpret e.g. a pairwise defeat to a cutoff entity have to be agreed.

Using the cutoff to give negative votes to candidates below the cutoff line 
(in the sense that such negative votes would really decrease their chance of 
winning candidates above the cutoff line) may be problematic since people could 
start giving negative votes to their worst competitors as a default strategy.

There have been also various proposals allowing strength of preference to be 
expressed (e.g. ABCDE).

Juho





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Generalized symmetric ballot completion

2011-05-30 Thread Juho Laatu
 is guaranteed.
  
 Maybe an election type could be devised which makes a bottom-up proportional 
 ranking. At the start of the election, as many seats as there are candidates 
 are elected, then in each subsequent round one candidate is dropped util we 
 have a Condorcet winner. 
  
 Example: start with six candidates and elect five of them in a five-seat 
 Condorcet-STV election, check if we have a Condorcet winner, if not, out of 
 these five, elect four of them in a four-seat election and check if we have a 
 Condorcet winner if not elect three of them in a three-seat election. Amon 
 the three elected there is always a Condorcet winner.
  
 Well, it's a new method at least.Could be worth trying out, maybe it will 
 help resist burying or have some other nice properties.
  
 Do you or anyone else around on this list have a reference to where the 
 debate between IRV and Condorcet stands today (pros and cons of the methods 
 respectively)?
  
 Personally I am not yet convinced that Condorcet is a better method than 
 IRV when it comes to resisting tactical voting.

They are quite different methods with respect to strategic voting. To me the 
promise of Condorcet methods is that in typical political elections they may 
avoid (rational) strategic voting even completely. If there is a top level 
cycle, then people may afterwards think I should have voted that way, but it 
is not easy to know what to do (except to vote sincerely) before the election. 
In IRV one may end up sooner in situations where e.g. some voter group knows 
that it should compromise (and thereby improve the result of the election). 
This may happen e.g. when a Condorcet winner is about to be eliminated at the 
first round and as a result the other side is likely to win. This example is 
not really on resisting tactical voting but on requiring tactical voting. 
Maybe this describes my first thoughts on this topic well enough. I will not 
try to prove these claims here (that would require too many lines of text :-). 
IRV had some problems at least in Burlington in 2009 (the Condorcet winner was 
eliminated).

To summarize my thoughts also after reading the mail...
- I like explicit cutoff marks when they carry a clear agreed message that 
voters can easily and sincerely (not to implement a strategy) rank (e..g. 
between acceptable and non-acceptabe candidates)
- Ranked ballots can thus be efficiently used for collecting also additional 
information in addition to basic ranking data
- In elections where there is no clear cutoff information to be collected, 
basic rankings will work fine (i.e. no need for fixes in the basic case, it 
works fine as it is)
- There are many possible rules on how to take the cutoffs into account in the 
vote counting process (check impact on strategic voting)

Juho



  
 Best regards
 Peter Zborník
  
  
 On Sun, May 29, 2011 at 4:29 PM, Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk wrote:
  
 On 29.5.2011, at 16.06, Peter Zbornik wrote:
  
  On the other hand I might rather prefer My Political Opponent to be 
  elected than Pol Pot.
  Thus a ballot on the form AXMy Political OpponentPol Pot, might be a 
  good idea to allow.
  
  
 I like this kind of explicit cutoffs more than implicit ones (at the end of 
 the ranked candidates) since implicit cutoff easily encourages truncation. If 
 people like to truncate their strongest opponents we might end up having 
 bullet votes only. That would mean that we would be back in plurality, and 
 all useful information of the ranked votes would be gone.
  
 The explicit cutoff works well in elections where it is possible not to elect 
 anyone (maybe keep the old elected alternative, or maybe arrange a new 
 election after a while). One could also have elections where there are many 
 possible outcomes, e.g. a seat for 6 months or a seat for 2 years 
 (A2yBC6mD). In these cases it is possible to measure quite reliably 
 which candidates fall into which categories (e.g. approvable enough). The 
 detailed rules on how to interpret e.g. a pairwise defeat to a cutoff entity 
 have to be agreed.
  
 Using the cutoff to give negative votes to candidates below the cutoff line 
 (in the sense that such negative votes would really decrease their chance 
 of winning candidates above the cutoff line) may be problematic since people 
 could start giving negative votes to their worst competitors as a default 
 strategy.
  
 There have been also various proposals allowing strength of preference to be 
 expressed (e.g. ABCDE).
  
 Juho
  
  
  
  
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
  
  
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Generalized symmetric ballot completion

2011-06-01 Thread Juho Laatu
On 31.5.2011, at 12.58, Peter Zbornik wrote:

 That would be, I think the smallest improvement on IRV, which could make a 
 positive change in real life and would support centrist candidates.

From the Condorcet criterion point of view, the Condorcet winner is a good, 
often centrist candidate. If Condorcet criterion is one of the targets to be 
met, then IRV could be modified appropriately. One simple trick that has been 
proposed is to eliminate the pairwise loser of the two candidates with least 
votes (instead of eliminating always the candidate that has least votes).

(If IRV is used to pick candidates for a second round, and if centrists are 
interesting, then maybe Condorcet winners should be kept.)

 - Using explicit cutoff just as an extra candidate that voters can use as a 
 strategic tool to generate big defeats to some candidates is more problematic 
 (you can try to bury someone under X without any risk of electing X)
 You can try to bury someone under all other candidates anyway. Introducing a 
 null-candidate as a cuttoff does not change that.

Yes, but in traditional burial there is always a risk that when voters lie 
that candidate Z is better than it is (in order to bury someone) that 
introduces also a risk of electing Z, and that is one key factor that makes 
burial strategy usually too dangerous to try. If there is a candidate that 
can be used for burying but that can not be elected, burying may become less 
risky and therefore more common.

 My approach to the various criteria is that one should take into account also 
 how much some method violates some criterion. No proper method meets them 
 all. Condorcet methods are very good from this point of view in the sense 
 that although they fail Later-no-harm there is usually and by default no 
 harm ranking also later candidates. Same with burial. They are vulnerable 
 to burial but usually and by default one need not worry about burial (=not 
 a practical strategy in typical large public elections with independent 
 voters).
  
 OK for public elections, but for a political party, where voting strategy is 
 the name of the game?

The risk of rational strategies increases if the election is competitive (all 
political elections tend to be), the number of voters is small, their voting 
behaviour can be reliably and centrally coordinated (e.g. direct commands from 
one's own party), information on the planned strategy does not leak out to 
others, when the preferences of all voters are already known (maybe there 
already was a test vote), and when other groups are probably not going to use 
any strategies. If there are multiple parties that may apply strategies and 
counter strategies things come more complicated again. Things may become more 
complex also if some groups try to fool others or hide information by giving 
false messages and false data in polls (maybe in a coordinated way) before the 
actual election. In small elections strategies may thus become easier, but 
still, it is hard to generate any easy rules that could be followed by a 
strategic grouping to implement rational and successful strategies in Condorcet 
methods. My understanding thus is, good for almost any competitive elections.

Actually I have asked on this list couple of times for good strategy advices 
for practical elections (i.e. 100% accurate information of the given votes + 
option of exactly one grouping to change their voting behaviour after the 
election will not do (this is how the vulnerabilities are typically described 
on this list and elsewhere)) but I have not seen any yet. (I have my own 
favourites for the weakest spots, none of them not terribly weak, but I'd like 
others to step out and tell how Condorcet methods can be fooled best when the 
available information is just few inaccurate and contradictory polls, and the 
opinions are likely to still change a bit before the election day.)

 Do you have any references for your statements concerning usually and by 
 defaults?

That was just my way of saying that vulnerabilities exist but they tend to be 
marginal.

 If there is a top level cycle, then people may afterwards think I should 
 have voted that way, but it is not easy to know what to do (except to vote 
 sincerely) before the election.
  
 I don't aggree. There is polling and the voter normally knows who is the 
 biggest competitor to the favored candidate. The competitor is buried. The 
 voters for the competitor bury your favorite candidate, and the winner is a 
 nobody that no-one cared enough about to out-maneuver and noone supports, 
 but also noone dislike. In a polarized environment that is not an unlikely 
 scenario.

Are you saying that general burying of one's competitors is a rational strategy 
for all voters? I.e. is that strategy likely to bring more benefits than 
problems? I believe that in most cases burial is harmful to the strategist.

 I do not personally like the idea of keeping the voter uninformed of the 
 workings 

Re: [EM] Remember Toby

2011-06-01 Thread Juho Laatu
On 1.6.2011, at 5.46, fsimm...@pcc.edu wrote:

 I agree with Kevin that elect the CW if there is one, else elect the 
 candidate ranked (or ranked above last) on the greatest number of ballots is 
 plenty simple, and is much 
 more satisfactory than MinMax or Copeland in other respects.

In what sense is the above mentioned implicit approval cutoff + Approval to 
resolve is the best simple method? If compared to MinMax, is it maybe easier 
to explain to the voters, more strategy free, or yields better winners? Would 
an explicit approval cutoff be fine (to allow full rankings to be given)?

Juho





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Remember Toby

2011-06-08 Thread Juho Laatu
On 1.6.2011, at 13.48, Kevin Venzke wrote:

 Hi Juho,

Hi,

I was busy with other activities for a while but here are some comments.

 
 --- En date de : Mer 1.6.11, Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk a écrit :
 I agree with Kevin that elect the CW if there is one,
 else elect the 
 candidate ranked (or ranked above last) on the
 greatest number of ballots is plenty simple, and is much 
 more satisfactory than MinMax or Copeland in other
 respects.
 
 In what sense is the above mentioned implicit approval
 cutoff + Approval to resolve is the best simple method?
 If compared to MinMax, is it maybe easier to explain to the
 voters, more strategy free, or yields better winners? Would
 an explicit approval cutoff be fine (to allow full rankings
 to be given)?
 
 It is surely easier to explain than MinMax,

If we talk about the sincere voting procedure, then MinMax voter only needs to 
rank candidates, but if loops are resolved using implicit Approval, then the 
voter should know in addition to the idea of ranking that truncation means that 
the remaining candidates are not approved. The voter needs to decide where to 
truncate. Or alternatively one could let the voters vote without knowing that 
truncation means disapproval. That would give more power to those that have the 
knowledge (although not very much if approvals are expected to come into play 
only seldom). I note also that if we don't tell to the voters how their ballots 
will be interpreted, then all Condorcet methods become very similar from the 
sincere voting procedure point of view (just rank the candidates sincerely and 
that's it).

If explanation to regular voters should contain strategic voting aspects, then 
the methods become more complex to the regular voter. I don't know if voters 
should be trained to use of approval as a tie breaker or if those properties 
should be hidden from the voters as discussed above. Burial would be even more 
difficult to explain (but maybe not recommended to the voters). In Approval all 
voters are expected to vote strategically (=decide where to put the cutoff), 
but if one uses approval only for tie breaking then one need not be as careful 
as with normal Approval.

If we talk about the vote counting process (with sincere votes) and how to 
explain it, then we have a two phase explanation (=Condorcet winner, and 
alternatively sum of all the ticks in the ballots if there is no Condorcet 
winner) vs. a one or two phase MinMax explanation (elect the candidate worst 
worst defeat is least bad. MinMax(margins) is quite simple since it is enough 
to refer to the number of additional votes each candidate would need to win all 
others (if doesn't already). None of the explanations is quite obvious to 
average voters if one has to explain the difference between having a Condorcet 
winner and not having a Condorcet winner. The MinMax(margins) specific 
explanation is maybe easiest (and still fair, clear and exact enough) to 
present without talking about the probabilities of having or not having a top 
cycle.

If we seek simplicity, I'd be happiest to explain the voting procedure simply 
just rank the candidates and use the MinMax(margins) additional votes 
explanation if the voters need to know how the votes are counted.

 has more obvious burial 
 disincentive (especially if the comparison is to margins),

All Condorcet methods have a burial incentive with some variation between 
different methods. I don't know why margins would be more problematic than 
winning votes. I mean that they have different kind of vulnerabilities and 
disincentives, and it is not straight forward to say which ones are more 
problematic. Also Condorcet with approval as a tie-breaker has its own burial 
problems, although the approval cutoff introduces also some risk to the burying 
strategy. I'll give one example of a burying strategy when approval is used for 
tie-breaking.

49: AB
02: BA
49: C

A wins. But if the two B supporters vote BC, then there is a cycle, implicit 
approvals will be used, and B wins.

One possible comment to this strategy problem is that A supporters could 
truncate and not approve B (that seems to come from the same party or the same 
coalition at least). In that case all the big groupings could simply bullet 
vote and only the small ones would rank their second favourites. That approach 
could kill the chances centrists that are not the first candidates of one of 
the major groupings as potential compromise candidates and Condorcet winners.

It seems I have to give one more example to cover also cases where the 
difference between major an minor candidates is not that clear.

26: AB
25: BA
49: C

Again, if two of the B supporters vote BC, then B wins. If some A and B 
supporters truncate in order to defend against burying or as a general safety 
measure against the other competing grouping (A and B supporters may not guess 
right which one of them will have more votes), then C wins. Before the election 
A and B

Re: [EM] Remember Toby

2011-06-08 Thread Juho Laatu
Here are some random observations about the SODA method.

There should be a full definition of the method somewhere.

If there are three candidates and their declared preferences are ABC, BCA 
and CAB, the method may introduce some additional problems. If most voters 
delegate, then we may easily have a cycle (easier than usual). It will not be 
easy to decide who will delegate votes to the others.

If we have a centrist candidate (C) and left wing (L) and right wing (R) 
candidates, then it is problematic for C to decide whether to declare CLR or 
CRL. Some of C's right wing oriented supporters might be lost if C decides to 
declare CLR. C could ask for help from a less known person C2 to take part in 
the election C2's declared preferences could be C2CRL. Now the right wing 
oriented supporters of C will have a more sensible way to vote. Since C will 
not not rank C2, there is not much risk that C2 will be elected. One step 
further, maybe C could be allowed to give two preference orders, CLR and 
CRL. Then we are not far from allowing any preference order and full rankings.

The votes could be delegated in multiple ways. The nominated candidate could 
decide how many to approve (in one or several phases). The nominated candidate 
could delegate the vote to the next one in chain so that the next one in chain 
would get also the right to delegate (or not) the vote further (using the 
original preference order).

There is some smoke in the room in the sense that always when some nominated 
persons are given the right to decide the destiny of large number of votes 
(=delegated power), there is a possibility of trading the votes. One can 
imagine that some candidates would take part in the election only or mainly for 
this purpose - to get some votes and then decide how (how far in the chain) to 
sell them. (The price could typically be e.g. a nice seat in some office.)

That's enough for now,
Juho




On 5.6.2011, at 7.01, Jameson Quinn wrote:

 Message contents: 
 Section 1. When isn't SODA more condorcet compliant than condorcet methods
 Section 2. Smoke-filled rooms?
 Section 3. What are we looking for, anyway? (in this thread)
 
 
 Section 1. When isn't SODA more condorcet compliant than condorcet methods
 
 2011/6/4 fsimm...@pcc.edu
 For the benefit of those who are advocating ranked ballots in order to 
 achieve Condorcet Compliance,
 
 note well that Jameson has a good argument that SODA, a simple method that 
 uses only a Plurality
 style ballot, is more Condorcet Compliant than most well known Condorcet 
 methods.
 
 I believe that is true in a practical sense. However, I should note that I'm 
 not claiming that SODA achieves the impossible. As with other methods, 
 (attempted) strategy could spoil its condorcet compliance. I'll explain how, 
 and why I think that wouldn't happen.
 
 First off: I'd like to note that I'm mostly worried about burial strategy 
 here. Generally, favorite betrayal strategy is useful to break an honest 
 Condorcet cycle to your advantage, while burial is useful to create a false 
 cycle which gives you some advantage. Since I think that honest cycles will 
 be rare, I'm more worried about the latter. Also, psychologically, most 
 people have a much higher propensity for burial than for favorite betrayal. 
 At any rate, in all the discussion that follows, I will assume that there is 
 an honest pairwise champion (CW).
 
 So, in SODA, burial/truncation is still possible in several ways:
 1. A candidate could cause a cycle through burial, and thus avoid the (known, 
 unique, strong, stable) Nash equilibrium for the honest pairwise champion. 
 However, that can only work to their advantage if the other candidates 
 actually believe that the false, strategic preference order, or if they 
 manage to exploit a dishonest strategic mistake by another candidate. I 
 believe that high-profile frontrunner candidates could not plausibly claim a 
 false preference order, so this strategy would be ineffective.
 2. Individual voters could use truncation (not burial, because it's 
 approval). For instance, voters could prevent their votes from being 
 delegated in order to engage in games of chicken to ensure that their 
 preferred near-clone was elected. This is a fundamentally unnecessary risk, 
 however. The near-clone with an honest lead does not need such tactics, and 
 the near-clone who is behind will probably need a dangerously large number of 
 voters to do such tactics. I don't see how this could be coordinated on an 
 effective scale in real life without backfiring.
 3. Individual voters could vote for false flag minor candidates whose 
 honest preference ordering happened to be the strategic burial ordering that 
 they sought. I find this totally implausible, though; this requires a level 
 of cold-bloodedness and sophistication that only a tiny portion of people 
 have.
 
 So when is SODA voting more condorcet-compliant than Condorcet methods? When 
 there is an honest 

[EM] Defensive strategy for Condorcet methods

2011-06-08 Thread Juho Laatu
There has been quite a lot of discussion around the strategic vulnerabilities 
of Condorcet methods on this list recently. In general I think Condorcet 
methods are one of the least vulnerable to strategies, and in most typical 
elections their vanilla versions are simply good enough. In the case that 
people would start voting strategically there is one interesting defensive 
strategy that has not been discussed very much. The defensive strategy is to 
not tell your sincere opinions in the polls. Most Condorcet strategies are 
based on quite accurate understanding on how others are going to vote. If I 
expect someone to play foul play, I might just refuse to give the required 
information to them, and recommend others to do the same. (Also giving planned 
false information to mislead the strategists is possible, but more difficult.)

This approach does not work about irrational voters that will bury anyway, just 
in case that might help. But the point is that in Condorcet elections the best 
strategy, in the absence of good information on the preferences, is to vote 
sincerely. In real life this strategy could be mentioned as a possibility in 
the case that strategic voting becomes threatening. The outcome hopefully is 
such that all parties, experts and media would recommend voters to vote 
sincerely and not try strategies. That would be better to all than having to 
live without the interesting polls. What do you think? Is this a way to drive 
away possible evil spirits and strategy promoting parties, experts and media?

Juho






Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Defensive strategy for Condorcet methods

2011-06-08 Thread Juho Laatu
On 8.6.2011, at 16.33, Jameson Quinn wrote:

 It's easy to minimize the problems with one's preferred systems, and focus on 
 the problems with other systems you see as competing for mindshare. It's 
 not even dishonest: the truth is that, compared to the giant issues with 
 plurality, any good system has problems that are minor, but that on the other 
 hand such minor problems would still be a hurdle in convincing voters to make 
 a switch.
 
 But I don't think it's getting us much of anywhere to argue this back and 
 forth.
 
 Let's imagine these minimizing-the-issues points were all granted, on all 
 sides. Say Condorcet had negligible strategy, Range strategy were always 
 unbiased, and SODA had no smoky rooms. (I think that all three propositions 
 are close enough to true to use as an approximation.) I think that it's 
 undeniable then that SODA would have the simplest balloting and Range the 
 best results.
 
 So I, personally, don't see the attraction of Condorcet when compared to 
 other proposals.

I think the attraction of Condorcet methods is in that they 1) can collect very 
well sincere ranking information, 2) work also in competitive environments, 3) 
offer a sound basis for majority based elections (Condorcet criterion). 
Condorcet methods chat can be seen as a major local optimum in the methods 
space.

Range is a nice method for some environments. It differs from Condorcet methods 
in 1) since it can not collect sincere ratings reliably, 2) since it has some 
Approval like problems in competitive elections when the number of potential 
winners is higher than two (while Condorcet's problems can be claimed to be 
typically negligible), 3) since it (=sincere ratings) is not majority based. 
One might consider the sum of ratings philosophy to lead to better winners 
than the majority decides philosophy. Even if on prefers the sum of ratings 
philosophy, majority decides philosophy could be considered better in 
competitive elections since one can not expect voters to provide sincere 
ratings if they have also the ability to decide by majority (as e.g. in two 
candidate Range elections). Range is thus a nice method, but mainly for 
environments that are non-competitive and where we want to follow the sum of 
ratings philosophy. This was one argument why Condorcet can be considered to 
be a clear local optimum in the typically competitive political elections.

In SODA simplicity is one of the main targets. Although it has some nice 
properties like electing often Condorcet winners and avoiding many strategy and 
smoke filled room related problems, I'm not sure that it would automatically 
offer more than Condorcet methods do. Because of its simplicity and its ability 
to argue benefits over plurality it may be a good candidate in environments 
that now use plurality.

I.e. all good methods but I still tend to think that for competitive political 
elections Condorcet methods may provide a quite good local optimum. In 
Condorcet the ballot filling procedure is more complex than in SODA, but if 
that is not a problem, then Condorcet might work very well in most typical 
political elections (maybe the strategy problems will not appear, maybe also 
that poll related defensive strategy that I mentioned could be used if 
something strange happens).

 But... I'd rather find a way to agree than fight about it. In my other recent 
 message, I suggested that we put forward SODA and one simple Condorcet method 
 as the practical proposals in some statement which people here could sign on 
 to.

Yes, it would be good to find better agreement on what would be good methods 
for practical elections. Based on this discussion I see Condorcet methods as 
good general purpose single-winner methods for competitive environments. Range 
is good only for certain environments as discussed above. SODA may be good 
especially when simplicity of the voting procedure is sought.

In SODA I'm most worried about the Approval related problems, maybe also 
possible trading of votes, but it is an excellent idea and method anyway. In 
general a good approach when recommending different methods could be to list 
sincerely the benefits and problems and recommended use for each good method 
(good = can be considered to be a local optimum in some environments). The list 
of recommended methods could be a long one, a short one, targeted for certain 
target audiences or maybe all possible (single-winner and/or multi-winner) 
environments.

Juho



 
 Jameson
 
 2011/6/8 Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk
 There has been quite a lot of discussion around the strategic vulnerabilities 
 of Condorcet methods on this list recently. In general I think Condorcet 
 methods are one of the least vulnerable to strategies, and in most typical 
 elections their vanilla versions are simply good enough. In the case that 
 people would start voting strategically there is one interesting defensive 
 strategy that has not been discussed very much

Re: [EM] Remember Toby

2011-06-08 Thread Juho Laatu
On 8.6.2011, at 16.15, Jameson Quinn wrote:

 
 
 2011/6/8 Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk
 Here are some random observations about the SODA method.
 
 There should be a full definition of the method somewhere.
 
 I've posted a full definition. However, this definition included my 
 additional step of recounting the top two without mutually-delegated votes. 
 In further off-list conversation with Forest, I've realized that this 
 addition, while it may be marginally helpful, does not fundamentally change 
 the dynamics of the situation, and so is not worth the extra complexity. 
 Here's the full definition without it:
 
 1. Before the election, candidates (including declared write-ins) submit full 
 rankings of other candidates. Equality and truncation (equal-bottom) is 
 allowed in these rankings. These rankings are made public.

I'm just wondering what the difference between a declared write-in and a 
regular candidate is. Maybe declared write-ins are candidates that have failed 
to meet some of the nomination criteria and that therefore will not get their 
own row in the ballot sheet or will not get a candidate number of their own 
(depends on what kind of ballots are in use, but the point is that voter must 
write their full name in the ballot). These declared write-ins must probably 
register themselves anyway as candidates in order to officially declare their 
preferences. Maybe votes to write-ins that have not officially declared their 
preferences are not allowed in the election at all. Or maybe votes to them are 
just always non-delegated approval votes.

 
 2. Voters submit approval ballots, with up to two write-ins. Do not 
 delegate is a valid write-in.

Your definition seems to define also the used ballot format. That's ok although 
often the formal descriptions of methods don't cover this. Note that most 
countries of the world don't use the write-in option. Is this a recommendation 
that if they start using SODA they should support write-ins in general or that 
they should have a write-in slot to support the do not delegate feature?

 
 3. All approvals are counted for each candidate. Bullet votes for each 
 candidate are also counted. These totals are made public.
 
 4. After a brief period (probably a couple of weeks) for analyzing and 
 discussing these first-round results, all candidates, in a simultaneous and 
 temporarily-secret ballot, decide how many rank levels (from their initial 
 ranking in step 1) to delegate to. They may not delegate to candidates they 
 ranked at the bottom (since this is strategically identical to delegating to 
 nobody and withdrawing from the race). If A delegates to B, a number equal to 
 A's bullet votes is added to B's approval total.

I note that

- candidates must delegate all or no votes, and all to the same level

- couple of weeks is a long time to wait for the results

- those couple of weeks probably include lost of negotiations, maybe to the 
level of agreeing how every candidate delegates (or at least a group that has 
power enough to agree what the outcome is)

- I guess temporarily-secret means that the final vote of each candidate will 
be published afterwards

- these rules assume one round of voting (i.e. not e.g. approvals that could be 
extended step by step)

- empty votes are not allowed (maybe not necessary to ban, and many candidates 
could effectively cast an empty vote anyway, e.g. by not approving anyone else 
but themselves)

 
 5. The candidate with the highest approval total after step 4 wins.

Depending on the environment the winner could be agreed already before the 
second round, or alternatively all candidates would just, one by one, cast the 
vote that they consider best, and the end result could be a surprise.

  
 
 If there are three candidates and their declared preferences are ABC, BCA 
 and CAB, the method may introduce some additional problems. If most voters 
 delegate, then we may easily have a cycle (easier than usual). It will not be 
 easy to decide who will delegate votes to the others.
 
 Actually, the strategy in such a cycle is simple and stable. Say C has the 
 fewest bullet votes. C has no hope of winning

C could still win, if for example candidate B would be happy to compromise and 
approve C.

 , so C delegates to A

Is there moral pressure and an agreed rule that the one with least bullet votes 
should at east approve one/some of the others?

 , so B delegates to C, so A delegates to B.

These are logical consequences after C's decision if B and A can be sure that 
the previous steps in this chain of decisions will be implemented with 
certainty.

C however does not like the idea of B winning. C could cancel his plan to 
delegate to A, and he could tell this to A. A could then cancel his plan to 
delegate to B (if he trusts C). A would win. A and C would be happier.

Actually any two of the candidates could make an agreement on the winner. They 
could also agree e.g. that X will be the president and Y

Re: [EM] Defensive strategy for Condorcet methods

2011-06-08 Thread Juho Laatu
On 8.6.2011, at 18.58, Jameson Quinn wrote:

 
 In SODA I'm most worried about the Approval related problems,
 
 Do you mean the near-clone game-of-chicken problems?

Yes.

 These apply to WV Condorcet methods too (although less-obviously to an 
 unsophisticated voter), and with margins, there is the opposite burial 
 problem:

All methods have problems. We need to evaluate their importance in practical 
elections one by one.

 
 35: AB
 25: B
 40: C
 
 What if, instead of being a game of chicken between A and B

Did B already truncate?

 , this is a trick where A is burying their natural ally C?

Many strategies have such mirror images.

 
 In general, I think that by reducing the number of players in the game of 
 chicken, and providing perfect information to those players, SODA does more 
 to avoid these problems than any non-asset, non-revoting-runoff system I can 
 think of off the top of my head. The game of chicken is not an easy problem 
 to solve, because if you try too hard, you end up with the opposite problem.

Yes, finding the best balance is not always easy. At least it takes time to 
identify and analyze all the possible scenarios and their problems.

Btw, I tend to think that often it is even better to fail multiple criteria 
than only few. The reason is that when one violates multiple criteria then it 
may be possible to violate each one of them only so little that it does not 
cause andy meaningful problems. The weakest link of a chain may be strongest 
when one does not spend all one's available resources and material in making 
only few of the links as strong as possible.

  
 maybe also possible trading of votes, but it is an excellent idea and method 
 anyway. In general a good approach when recommending different methods could 
 be to list sincerely the benefits and problems and recommended use for each 
 good method (good = can be considered to be a local optimum in some 
 environments). The list of recommended methods could be a long one, a short 
 one, targeted for certain target audiences or maybe all possible 
 (single-winner and/or multi-winner) environments.
 
 From my experience talking to normal people not already interested in voting 
 or math, I think that it is very important to keep your list of proposals 
 short. 1 is good, 2 is tolerable, 3 is approximately pointless, and anything 
 more is clearly counterproductive.

My experiences in negotiations say that it is usually best to have only one 
proposal, with one option that the decision makers can then solve in the 
correct way. :-)

  
 
 Since I understand that I'm probably not going to convince the condorcet 
 supporters here, I'm willing to include a Condorcet proposal.

Do you think it is a mistake to include Condorcet methods? Of course this 
depends on where you are going to make that proposal. If Condorcet methods do 
not have any chances, then it may be better not to include them, except as 
targets that can be shot down to make some other methods look better :-). But 
if we are talking about practical promotion of methods, the environment may 
require the input to be written for that environment only. Theoretical material 
that aims at collecting best available information together is a different 
animal.

  Since I value offering a simple option, I think that proposing (Some 
 Condorcet) or SODA is better than just advocating (Some Condorcet). Still, I 
 strongly urge that our statement should not go beyond two well-explained 
 proposals, though it should endorse by simple mention a number of other 
 systems (Schulze, Range, MCA, MJ...).

I think I covered these matters already in another mail. I don't know yet what 
your targets are (what kind of a paper, for what audience).

Juho



 
 Jameson 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Challenge2 - give an example where MFBC is violated for Condorcet methods

2011-06-08 Thread Juho Laatu
On 7.6.2011, at 10.53, Peter Zbornik wrote:

 I'd say that FBC (and LNH) is quite a big problem for Condorcet
 methods, at least for someone (like me) who think sincere voting
 should be the norm.

One could also claim that in typical political elections Condorcet methods will 
work fine, and people need not worry about the fact that these methods fail FBC 
and LNH. FBC does not mean that there would be a clear need to consider 
betraying one's favourite candidate, and LNH does not mean that there would 
be a clear need to consider truncating one's vote in order not to harm oneself. 
A much better advice to the voters is to vote sincerely. (And I note again that 
I have not seen good general advices on how people could in practice exploit 
the theoretical vulnerabilities of Condorcet methods in real elections.)

 It seems that there is a risk, that Condorcet methods are reduced to
 plurality-like methods due to voting strategies that exploit the fact
 that FBC and LNH do not hold.

That could happen in principle, but I believe in most environments that would 
not be the case. And even if that would happen, probably those fears (leading 
to bullet voting or plurality-like methods) would be irrational.

Juho







Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Defensive strategy for Condorcet methods

2011-06-08 Thread Juho Laatu
On 9.6.2011, at 1.31, Kevin Venzke wrote:

 Hi Juho,
 
 --- En date de : Mer 8.6.11, Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk a écrit :
 There has been quite a lot of
 discussion around the strategic vulnerabilities of Condorcet
 methods on this list recently. In general I think Condorcet
 methods are one of the least vulnerable to strategies, and
 in most typical elections their vanilla versions are simply
 good enough. In the case that people would start voting
 strategically there is one interesting defensive strategy
 that has not been discussed very much. The defensive
 strategy is to not tell your sincere opinions in the polls.
 Most Condorcet strategies are based on quite accurate
 understanding on how others are going to vote. If I expect
 someone to play foul play, I might just refuse to give the
 required information to them, and recommend others to do the
 same. (Also giving planned false information to mislead the
 strategists is possible, but more difficult.)
 
 This approach does not work about irrational voters that
 will bury anyway, just in case that might help. But the
 point is that in Condorcet elections the best strategy, in
 the absence of good information on the preferences, is to
 vote sincerely. In real life this strategy could be
 mentioned as a possibility in the case that strategic voting
 becomes threatening. The outcome hopefully is such that all
 parties, experts and media would recommend voters to vote
 sincerely and not try strategies. That would be better to
 all than having to live without the interesting polls. What
 do you think? Is this a way to drive away possible evil
 spirits and strategy promoting parties, experts and media?
 
 I don't see this working because you will never be able to disguise who
 the frontrunners are.

I agree that there is always some information on the popularity of different 
candidates (also without any polls). But does this mean that it would be a 
working strategy (=likely to bring more benefits than harm) e.g. to always bury 
one of the assumed frontrunners under one of the assumer non-frontrunners? Is 
there some well known strategy that would work in this situation?

 
 In my recent simulations, when some voters saw the advantage of using
 burial strategy

Was this decision (saw the advantage) based on highly inaccurate information 
like being able to guess who the frontrunners might be?

 , the defensive strategy used in response seems to be
 compromise strategy, as opposed to truncation or burial-in-turn, things
 that risk ruining the result.
 
 That is, there are voters who know they can't expect to gain anything
 by voting sincerely, so they play it safe.

I agree that there are situations where some voters will not lose anything by 
using whatever strategy with even some infinitesimal hope of improving the 
outcome (e.g. when they know that otherwise the worst alternative will win). 
But how can they know (based on the limited available information) that sincere 
voting will not help them? Do they know for certain that some strategy is more 
likely to help (and not harm) them?

 
 So I expect that methods with greater burial incentive will just have
 more (voted) majority favorites

I didn't quite get this expression. Would this be bullet voting by majority or 
what?

 , and candidate withdrawals

Does this mean having only few candidates or ability to withdraw after the 
election and thereby influence the counting process or...?


I didn't quite catch what the impact of this to the usefulness of the reduced 
poll information based defensive strategy would be. Could you clarify. Did you 
say that already very rough information on which candidates are the 
frontrunners would give sufficient information to the strategists to cast a 
working (=likely to bring more benefits than harm) strategic vote (in Condorcet 
methods in general or in some of them)?

Juho



 , to avoid the
 problem. (You still can't use Borda.)
 
 Kevin Venzke
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Remember Toby

2011-06-09 Thread Juho Laatu
On 9.6.2011, at 4.51, Dave Ketchum wrote:

 On Jun 8, 2011, at 1:32 PM, Juho Laatu wrote:
 On 8.6.2011, at 16.15, Jameson Quinn wrote:

 2. Voters submit approval ballots, with up to two write-ins. Do not 
 delegate is a valid write-in.
 
 Your definition seems to define also the used ballot format. That's ok 
 although often the formal descriptions of methods don't cover this. Note 
 that most countries of the world don't use the write-in option. Is this a 
 recommendation that if they start using SODA they should support write-ins 
 in general or that they should have a write-in slot to support the do not 
 delegate feature?
 
 Nothing said here of ballot format except for being Approval and capable of 
 two write-ins.  Do not delegate is a command entered as if a write-in.

I was thinking about the write-ins. They were actually mentioned already in the 
previous bullet, but this bullet said that there should be two such slots. I 
guessed that if there are such write-in slots, maybe there is also an 
assumption that regular candidate names are listed next to the write-ins. I 
could at least guess what kind of ballot was intended.

Alternatives to what I described above could include ballots and elections that 
do not recognize write-ins (I guess write-ins are not an essential part of the 
SODA method anyway). One could also e.g. vote based on candidate numbers and 
white ballots to write those numbers in. I thus considered the ballot format 
that I imagined based on the description to be maybe one good approach but not 
the only possible or mandatory format for SODA.

Juho





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Remember Toby

2011-06-09 Thread Juho Laatu
On 9.6.2011, at 5.04, robert bristow-johnson wrote:

 i still think this Asset thingie is crappy.  it is *immaterial* how 
 candidates rank or value the other candidates.  the only thing that matters 
 is how the electorate values the candidates.
 
 No Smoke-Filled Rooms!!!

Yes, there are risks. If one wants the electorate to make the decision, then 
delegation may be problematic.

My default example that tries to point out the line between direct and 
delegated elections is this one:  Millions of voters vote on who will be the 
president; voting power is delegated to candidates; one of the candidates will 
get the power to decide; that candidate (= one of the voters) then can and will 
decide if the next president is A or B.

One problem is that millions of voters may feel disappointed since this one 
person made the final decision instead of them. One problem is that people may 
fear that this person traded his vote for money or political position or 
something else. One problem is that some of the supporters of this deciding 
candidate chose A instead of their favourite B. In SODA this last problem is 
reduced because of the pre-declared preferences, but still a voter with 
preference order CXYBA could have bullet voted for candidate C with 
declared preference order CXYAB.

So, at least the voters should be made well aware that in these elections there 
may be some trading before the final decision.

Juho






Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Challenge2 - give an example where MFBC is violated for Condorcet methods

2011-06-09 Thread Juho Laatu
 
that voters could as well forget their existence and just vote sincerely 
without any worries instead. I guess i also assumed that voters would wake up 
if something special around these strategies starts happening some day (i.e. 
they can forget the topic and expect others to warn them if something special 
happens some day around this topic).

Maybe a better (more neutral and descriptive) term (instead of typically 
irrational) to describe this kind of strategies could be e.g. no need to 
consider or no need to worry (at least not until further notice by the 
experts).

Juho


 
 Best regards
 Peter Zbornik
 
 On 6/8/11, Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk wrote:
 On 7.6.2011, at 10.53, Peter Zbornik wrote:
 
 I'd say that FBC (and LNH) is quite a big problem for Condorcet
 methods, at least for someone (like me) who think sincere voting
 should be the norm.
 
 One could also claim that in typical political elections Condorcet methods
 will work fine, and people need not worry about the fact that these methods
 fail FBC and LNH. FBC does not mean that there would be a clear need to
 consider betraying one's favourite candidate, and LNH does not mean that
 there would be a clear need to consider truncating one's vote in order not
 to harm oneself. A much better advice to the voters is to vote sincerely.
 (And I note again that I have not seen good general advices on how people
 could in practice exploit the theoretical vulnerabilities of Condorcet
 methods in real elections.)
 
 It seems that there is a risk, that Condorcet methods are reduced to
 plurality-like methods due to voting strategies that exploit the fact
 that FBC and LNH do not hold.
 
 That could happen in principle, but I believe in most environments that
 would not be the case. And even if that would happen, probably those fears
 (leading to bullet voting or plurality-like methods) would be irrational.
 
 Juho
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Remember Toby

2011-06-09 Thread Juho Laatu
On 9.6.2011, at 11.23, Jameson Quinn wrote:

 2011/6/8 robert bristow-johnson r...@audioimagination.com

  (this is worse than IRV.)   i (and i would hope that most intelligent 
 voters) do *not* want someone else voting for me in elections.
 
 And in SODA, you and anyone else who feels that way can easily make sure it 
 doesn't happen. Why do you want to deny me and the people who feel like me 
 the right to

If we assume that it is ok to allow each voter to decide if he/she will 
delegate or not, there is still one smaller problem left. If the ballot would 
contain also option I will delegate my vote to myself then both paths would 
be in a rather similar position. Now those voters that do not want to delegate 
their vote (to others for further decisions on how the vote will influence the 
outcome of the election) have more limited choices (only fixed approvals) than 
those that delegate. Only the delegated votes may make further decisions based 
on the outcome of the first round and negotiations between the rounds. A voter 
that does not want to delegate may be interested in active participation in the 
second round too.

Juho







Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Defensive strategy for Condorcet methods

2011-06-09 Thread Juho Laatu
On 9.6.2011, at 5.28, Kevin Venzke wrote:

 Hi Juho,
 
 --- En date de : Mer 8.6.11, Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk a écrit :
 --- En date de : Mer 8.6.11, Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk
 a écrit :
 There has been quite a lot of
 discussion around the strategic vulnerabilities of
 Condorcet
 methods on this list recently. In general I think
 Condorcet
 methods are one of the least vulnerable to
 strategies, and
 in most typical elections their vanilla versions
 are simply
 good enough. In the case that people would start
 voting
 strategically there is one interesting defensive
 strategy
 that has not been discussed very much. The
 defensive
 strategy is to not tell your sincere opinions in
 the polls.
 Most Condorcet strategies are based on quite
 accurate
 understanding on how others are going to vote. If
 I expect
 someone to play foul play, I might just refuse to
 give the
 required information to them, and recommend others
 to do the
 same. (Also giving planned false information to
 mislead the
 strategists is possible, but more difficult.)
 
 This approach does not work about irrational
 voters that
 will bury anyway, just in case that might help.
 But the
 point is that in Condorcet elections the best
 strategy, in
 the absence of good information on the
 preferences, is to
 vote sincerely. In real life this strategy could
 be
 mentioned as a possibility in the case that
 strategic voting
 becomes threatening. The outcome hopefully is such
 that all
 parties, experts and media would recommend voters
 to vote
 sincerely and not try strategies. That would be
 better to
 all than having to live without the interesting
 polls. What
 do you think? Is this a way to drive away possible
 evil
 spirits and strategy promoting parties, experts
 and media?
 
 I don't see this working because you will never be
 able to disguise who
 the frontrunners are.
 
 I agree that there is always some information on the
 popularity of different candidates (also without any polls).
 But does this mean that it would be a working strategy
 (=likely to bring more benefits than harm) e.g. to always
 bury one of the assumed frontrunners under one of the
 assumer non-frontrunners? Is there some well known strategy
 that would work in this situation?
 
 No, I wouldn't say that. I do think there are methods that offer two
 bad options and one of them is burial, though.

(There is no working strategy, but there are some options??)

 
 
 In my recent simulations, when some voters saw the
 advantage of using
 burial strategy
 
 Was this decision (saw the advantage) based on highly
 inaccurate information like being able to guess who the
 frontrunners might be?
 
 What? The voters are participating in repeated polling, and have the
 ability to see not just each poll's outcome but what they could have
 accomplished by doing anything else. Buriers see that burial is an
 advantage if the opposing side is sincere. When pawn-supporting voters
 compromise, the buriers have no reason to revert to sincerity. (They
 don't even know what sincerity is.)

You seem to assume repeated polling, sufficiently accurate results, unchanging 
results, similar results from all the polling companies, no intentionally 
misleading polls, no meaningful changes in behviour before the election day, no 
interest to give false information in the polls, maybe no impact of planned 
strategies on the voting behaviour of others, good enough control of the 
strategists (if needed).

 
 If what you're asking is whether this could be thwarted by not revealing
 any polls to the voters, then I can't address that. My voters have to
 have polls in order to learn how the method works.

In some methods like Approval poll information is needed to cast a vote in line 
with the typical recommendations on how to vote (= approve one of the 
frontrunners etc.). One could also have Approval elections without such 
information. In that case voters would not vote strategically but would maybe 
mark those candidates that they approve for the job.

In Condorcet the basic assumption is however that voters can sincerely rank the 
candidates. Doing so tends to improve the outcome of the election. The strategy 
of making polls unreliable may thus improve the outcome of the election.

 
 , the defensive strategy used in response seems to be
 compromise strategy, as opposed to truncation or
 burial-in-turn, things
 that risk ruining the result.
 
 That is, there are voters who know they can't expect
 to gain anything
 by voting sincerely, so they play it safe.
 
 I agree that there are situations where some voters will
 not lose anything by using whatever strategy with even some
 infinitesimal hope of improving the outcome (e.g. when they
 know that otherwise the worst alternative will win). But how
 can they know (based on the limited available information)
 that sincere voting will not help them? Do they know for
 certain that some strategy is more likely to help (and not
 harm) them

Re: [EM] Remember Toby

2011-06-09 Thread Juho Laatu
Yes, that's about it. But of course the situation is still somewhat 
uncomfortable to regular voters that are not interested and active enough to 
register themselves or that are unwilling to reveal their preferences to all 
(i.e. no secret vote allowed), but that would like to participate also in the 
second round.

Juho



On 9.6.2011, at 12.49, Jameson Quinn wrote:

 
 
 2011/6/9 Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk
 On 9.6.2011, at 11.23, Jameson Quinn wrote:
 
 2011/6/8 robert bristow-johnson r...@audioimagination.com
 
  (this is worse than IRV.)   i (and i would hope that most intelligent 
 voters) do *not* want someone else voting for me in elections.
 
 And in SODA, you and anyone else who feels that way can easily make sure it 
 doesn't happen. Why do you want to deny me and the people who feel like me 
 the right to
 
 If we assume that it is ok to allow each voter to decide if he/she will 
 delegate or not, there is still one smaller problem left. If the ballot would 
 contain also option I will delegate my vote to myself then both paths would 
 be in a rather similar position. Now those voters that do not want to 
 delegate their vote (to others for further decisions on how the vote will 
 influence the outcome of the election) have more limited choices (only fixed 
 approvals) than those that delegate. Only the delegated votes may make 
 further decisions based on the outcome of the first round and negotiations 
 between the rounds. A voter that does not want to delegate may be interested 
 in active participation in the second round too.
 
 Technically speaking, SODA as defined allows this. Register as a write-in, 
 declare your preferences (thus voluntarily ceding your right to a secret 
 ballot), bullet-vote for yourself, and you are free to participate in the 
 second round. The system is still satisfied, because second-round voters 
 still have perfect information on the declared preference order of all other 
 second-round voters.
 
 However, this would create logistical problems if it were too common an 
 option. Simply publishing thousands of declared preference orders (desirable 
 in the first round and mandatory in the second) would be difficult. And by 
 increasing the number of second-round voters, the advantage that it's easier 
 to ensure cooperation in a smaller group (to resolve the near-clone 
 chicken) would be lost.
 
 Ideally, then, the rules for declaring yourself as a write-in and 
 pre-announcing your preferences would contain some hurdle(s) just high enough 
 to keep people from doing it frivolously. Something like a minimum-length 
 candidate statement and a $25 dollar filing fee would be plenty; heavy enough 
 to keep thousands of people from doing it, but light enough to be an 
 insignificant burden to anyone who's remotely serious about it.
 
 Jameson
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Defensive strategy for Condorcet methods

2011-06-10 Thread Juho Laatu
On 10.6.2011, at 3.04, Kevin Venzke wrote:

 Hi Juho,
 
 --- En date de : Jeu 9.6.11, Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk a écrit :
 No, I wouldn't say that. I do think there are methods
 that offer two
 bad options and one of them is burial, though.
 
 (There is no working strategy, but there are some
 options??)
 
 Absolutely. I'm being honest when I say I don't know how I would vote
 in the simplest election. If all I know is that my preference order is
 ABC and the frontrunners are A and B, what should I do? Let's go over
 it.
 
 1. Vote sincerely, ABC. On a gut level I *don't want* to do this. B
 is the candidate I am trying to beat. Why do I want to help him beat C?

Maybe you strongly dislike C and therefore want to make sure that C does not 
win.

You however mentioned that A and B are the frontrunners. Maybe C has no chance 
of winning this election (with sincere votes at least). In that case it does 
not (technically) matter how you will rank C. But also in this case (where C is 
totally irrelevant in this election) you could have secondary goals (the 
primary goal is to decide who wins this time). Maybe you want to discourage C 
and his supporters so that they would not try again in next elections, or maybe 
you want to tell all the people how many people think C and C's party is no 
good (people might follow your opinion). Maybe you want to vote sincerely in 
order to encourage also others to do so and avoid elections becoming a 
playground of strategists. You could also vote sincerely because you want the 
election to act as a poll that measures the opinions of the society reliably 
and will offer guidance to the decision makers for the next few years.

 This can actually help B and it will never help A. I feel like a sucker
 if I expose myself to this risk for no possible benefit. I do not need
 to know whether there is *really* a threat; it makes no sense for me.

I guess the Condorcet logic should be that the risk of indicating your sincere 
opinion (BC) harms you with such a low probability that it doesn't matter. The 
benefits (maybe secondary) are bigger than the risk.

 
 2. Lie, and vote ACB. Now I'm a bad guy who you think must have some
 strategy in mind for picking this manner of voting.

Maybe strategic, maybe misled to think that ranking C above B would always 
decrease the chances of B to win, maybe you want to discourage B by showing 
that he is not much more popular than C.

 If I thought B voters
 were going to use this same strategy against me then in voting like
 this I might just be defending myself.

You are also taking a risk that C will win, despite of not having any chances 
with sincere votes. If many A and B supporters rank C second and C has also 
some first preference supporters, C could become a Condorcet winner.

 But outside of that possibility,
 maybe I just don't have any good options?

How about sincerity as the default rule?

If others are likely to generate (sincerely or by strategic votes) a loop, then 
your strategic options are a bit different than otherwise. But it is hard to 
know if there will be a cycle or not. I will not try to analyze all the 
alternatives here, but there are still many options and many risks.

 
 3. Bullet-vote for A. Nope, not if this is margins. That's just splitting
 the difference or flipping a coin.

Isn't that how it should be? AB=C is pretty much the same as sincere opinion 
I don't know which one is better, I might as well flip a coin.

 It's childish to vote like this.
 But actually, I think I might vote this way, just because I wouldn't have
 to feel like either a sucker or a jerk for doing it.

It's your duty as a good citizen to give your sincere rankings and this way 
help the society to better know the opinions of the citizens. Falsifying your 
preferences is a bit like cheating. Right?

 
 What? The voters are participating in repeated
 polling, and have the
 ability to see not just each poll's outcome but what
 they could have
 accomplished by doing anything else. Buriers see that
 burial is an
 advantage if the opposing side is sincere. When
 pawn-supporting voters
 compromise, the buriers have no reason to revert to
 sincerity. (They
 don't even know what sincerity is.)
 
 You seem to assume repeated polling, sufficiently accurate
 results, unchanging results, similar results from all the
 polling companies, no intentionally misleading polls, no
 meaningful changes in behviour before the election day, no
 interest to give false information in the polls, maybe no
 impact of planned strategies on the voting behaviour of
 others, good enough control of the strategists (if needed).
 
 Your description isn't that unfair. Changes are possible, but most methods
 and scenarios become pretty stable.

Last minute changes in opinions are possible. Their strength may be different 
in different societies and depending on random factors like last week debates, 
new revealed scandals etc.

 
 I am skeptical about the concept

[EM] C//A (was: Remember Toby)

2011-06-10 Thread Juho Laatu
On 9.6.2011, at 4.54, Kevin Venzke wrote:

 Hi Juho,
 
 --- En date de : Mer 8.6.11, Juho Laatu juho.la...@gmail.com a écrit :
 I was busy with other activities for a while but here are
 some comments.
 
 
 --- En date de : Mer 1.6.11, Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk
 a écrit :
 I agree with Kevin that elect the CW if there
 is one,
 else elect the 
 candidate ranked (or ranked above last) on
 the
 greatest number of ballots is plenty simple, and
 is much 
 more satisfactory than MinMax or Copeland in
 other
 respects.
 
 In what sense is the above mentioned implicit
 approval
 cutoff + Approval to resolve is the best simple
 method?
 If compared to MinMax, is it maybe easier to
 explain to the
 voters, more strategy free, or yields better
 winners? Would
 an explicit approval cutoff be fine (to allow full
 rankings
 to be given)?
 
 It is surely easier to explain than MinMax,
 
 If we talk about the sincere voting procedure, then MinMax
 voter only needs to rank candidates, but if loops are
 resolved using implicit Approval, then the voter should know
 in addition to the idea of ranking that truncation means
 that the remaining candidates are not approved. The voter
 needs to decide where to truncate. Or alternatively one
 could let the voters vote without knowing that truncation
 means disapproval. That would give more power to those that
 have the knowledge (although not very much if approvals are
 expected to come into play only seldom). I note also that if
 we don't tell to the voters how their ballots will be
 interpreted, then all Condorcet methods become very similar
 from the sincere voting procedure point of view (just rank
 the candidates sincerely and that's it).
 
 If explanation to regular voters should contain strategic
 voting aspects, then the methods become more complex to the
 regular voter. I don't know if voters should be trained to
 use of approval as a tie breaker or if those properties
 should be hidden from the voters as discussed above. Burial
 would be even more difficult to explain (but maybe not
 recommended to the voters). In Approval all voters are
 expected to vote strategically (=decide where to put the
 cutoff), but if one uses approval only for tie breaking then
 one need not be as careful as with normal Approval.
 
 I don't recommend that voters not be instructed on how the method is
 supposed to work.
 
 I think with C//A it is easier to explain how to find the winner, and
 the strategy becomes obvious. No defeat strengths are involved. MinMax
 has its strategy too, and this is harder to perceive because the method
 rules are harder to understand.

If we are taking about simple explanations to regular voters then maybe all the 
strategy related aspects should be considered not-simple.

C//A's counting process is quite simple (to explain) although its counting 
process has two phases that differ from each others. I don't think e.g. the 
elect the candidate that needs least number of additional votes to beat all 
others would be more complex.

 
 If we talk about the vote counting process (with sincere
 votes) and how to explain it, then we have a two phase
 explanation (=Condorcet winner, and alternatively sum of all
 the ticks in the ballots if there is no Condorcet winner)
 vs. a one or two phase MinMax explanation (elect the
 candidate worst worst defeat is least bad. MinMax(margins)
 is quite simple since it is enough to refer to the number of
 additional votes each candidate would need to win all others
 (if doesn't already). None of the explanations is quite
 obvious to average voters if one has to explain the
 difference between having a Condorcet winner and not having
 a Condorcet winner. The MinMax(margins) specific explanation
 is maybe easiest (and still fair, clear and exact enough) to
 present without talking about the probabilities of having or
 not having a top cycle.
 
 You have to explain CW either way.

Not necessarily, but that need might pop up. For example in the MinMax(margins) 
explanation above (elect the candidate that needs least number of additional 
votes to beat all others) CW is not mentioned. Some voters might however start 
wondering in what kind of situations the winner does not win all others. In 
that case that individual voter might need someone to explain that sometimes 
there is a CW and sometimes not.

 
 If we seek simplicity, I'd be happiest to explain the
 voting procedure simply just rank the candidates and use
 the MinMax(margins) additional votes explanation if the
 voters need to know how the votes are counted.
 
 When I think of simplicity I mean that the voters would actually 
 understand how the method works.
 
 I don't think you will have much luck proposing methods if you don't
 think voters need to understand them. Can you find an angle / sales 
 pitch that dodges this?

I believe most people are not interested in the vote counting process. The 
voting procedure and general idea of the method must be easy to understand

Re: [EM] Remember Toby

2011-06-10 Thread Juho Laatu
On 9.6.2011, at 5.48, Jameson Quinn wrote:

 
  It seems I have to give one more example to cover also
  cases where the difference between major an minor candidates
  is not that clear.
 
  26: AB
  25: BA
  49: C
 
  Again, if two of the B supporters vote BC, then B wins.
  If some A and B supporters truncate in order to defend
  against burying or as a general safety measure against the
  other competing grouping (A and B supporters may not guess
  right which one of them will have more votes), then C wins.
  Before the election A and B groupings could both claim that
  they are bigger and therefore they should truncate, and all
  the voters of the other grouping should rank also the
  candidate of the other grouping.
 
  This second example comes close to the traditional Approval
  strategy related problems where near clone
  parties/candidates fight about who must approve whom. The
  strategic problems of approval as a tie-breaker and winning
  votes are also quite closely related.
 
 The method isn't perfect, no.
 
 I don't believe this kind of scenario has a good resolution. I think in
 practice one of those candidates will drop out, and while that's bad,
 I don't think we can do much about it.
 
 I'm not claiming that this scenario has a perfect resolution, but I do think 
 that SODA does pretty well here. By providing perfect information on which 
 group is bigger (25 vs 26 in the above), by reducing the players in the game 
 of chicken from thousands to two, and by providing incentives in terms of 
 future credibility to those two players to behave in at least an 
 arguably-honest fashion, I think that SODA would dramatically reduce the 
 chances of a car crash, or even the wrong car ending up in the ditch.

In this example SODA certainly is an improvement over basic Approval. There is 
a risk that some A and B supporters will cast bullet votes without delegation. 
Does that mean that one should try to discourage this kind of truncation. 
Actually the method already does so if bullet vote by default means that the 
vote is a delegated vote. Maybe the most risky scenarios are just like in this 
example, and things would be quite ok if voters that do not delegate would 
approve at least two candidates.

Juho


 
 JQ
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] C//A (was: Remember Toby)

2011-06-11 Thread Juho Laatu
On 11.6.2011, at 6.09, Dave Ketchum wrote:

 Why are we here?
 
 It certainly made sense to come and explore.
. We find ourselves asking the voters to do some truncating.
. Counters may have to adjust counting ballots.
 
 Among the many variant Condorcet methods there are various ways of handling 
 cycles that are close to defining CWs - why not start from here, especially 
 for such cycles?

I like this thinking since I have been advertising the simplicity of elect the 
candidate that needs least number of additional votes to beat all others :-). 
That is a clear (one possible) extension of the Condorcet criterion.

Why are we here then? I tend to think that the reason is the fact that 
Condorcet methods have some vulnerabilities like interest to compromise and 
burial. Especially burial looks bad since there some grouping can potentially 
make their favourite win by falsifying their preferences (compromising is less 
dramatic than this). In an otherwise excellent method these vulnerabilities 
look even worse. We don't have a tradition of using Condorcet methods in 
competitive elections, so we don't really know how people will react to them, 
and that makes us fear that they might even collapse. As a result there have 
been active studies on how Condorcet methods could be defended and how 
Condorcet voters could defend themselves in case something goes badly wrong. 
Since there have been lots of studies, there has been also lots of focus on 
these vulnerabilities. Various campaigns in favour of different methods may 
also seek problems in other methods, and one needs to defend against such 
claims. 
 All this has made strategic questions maybe the most central topic in 
Condorcet related discussions. And still, we don't even know how much different 
strategies will be a problem in real life elections. My hunch is that they may 
be less of a problem than all this discussion might imply.

When we have discussed all the strategies for long, the other line of 
discussion, namely performance with sincere votes, has not received equal 
attention. I think it s also essential that when a method picks some candidate 
we have clear reasons why just this candidate was chosen. Otherwise the method 
may look just like a random collection of rules that pick a random winner. 
Condorcet methods are however never quite that bad since we can assume that in 
many elections there is a Condorcet winner and we can quite well explain why 
that candidate was a good choice. There are people who may not like the idea of 
electing sometimes someone with less first preference support than some other 
candidates, but we have to live with that and either claim that the Condorcet 
approach is the best one or at least one reasonable one (and that we have not 
seen any better rules that would work also in competitive majority based 
elections).

One more essential reason behind not having clear answers to why it is 
difficult to identify agree what the best methods are is the existence of 
cyclic group preferences. Such cyclic preferences do not follow the thinking 
patterns that we are used to when discussion about linear / transitive 
preferences. We expect the opinions of individual voters to follow these rules, 
but we should not treat group opinions the same way. Individuals can quite 
easily say which candidate they like best. But we need some completely new 
thinking to be able to address the question which candidate is the best for a 
group.

Anyway, although there are many complexities on the path, I think we should be 
able to find few exact formulations on which candidate could be considered to 
be the best. Such rules may vary depending on the needs of the society but I'm 
sure some of the rules are good general purpose rules too. And of course we 
have to take into account that we can only use rules that do not lead into 
problems in the area of strategies (we know that e.g. number of pairwise losses 
may not be a good rule in environments where people can nominate any number of 
candidates). If we assume that real world experiences will show that in many or 
most societies people can refrain from (other than marginal) strategic 
activities when using Condorcet, we might be in a position to pick the 
Condorcet method that we consider ideal from the sincere ballots and best 
winner point of view. And if that is not the case, maybe we can try tricks like 
the false polls trick that I advertised in other mails to force peop
 le back to decent voting practices rather than change the method to some other 
method that does not elect as good candidates with sincere votes.

All in all, even though there can be no perfect voting methods I'm quite 
hopeful that we can do pretty well here.

Juho






Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Defensive strategy for Condorcet methods

2011-06-11 Thread Juho Laatu
On 12.6.2011, at 0.26, Kevin Venzke wrote:

 Hi Juho,
 
 --- En date de : Ven 10.6.11, Juho Laatu juho.la...@gmail.com a écrit :
 --- En date de : Jeu 9.6.11, Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk
 a écrit :
 No, I wouldn't say that. I do think there are
 methods
 that offer two
 bad options and one of them is burial,
 though.
 
 (There is no working strategy, but there are some
 options??)
 
 Absolutely. I'm being honest when I say I don't know
 how I would vote
 in the simplest election. If all I know is that my
 preference order is
 ABC and the frontrunners are A and B, what
 should I do? Let's go over
 it.
 
 1. Vote sincerely, ABC. On a gut level I
 *don't want* to do this. B
 is the candidate I am trying to beat. Why do I want to
 help him beat C?
 
 Maybe you strongly dislike C and therefore want to make
 sure that C does not win.
 
 Sure... If...
 
 You however mentioned that A and B are the frontrunners.
 Maybe C has no chance of winning this election (with sincere
 votes at least). In that case it does not (technically)
 matter how you will rank C. 
 
 With sincere votes at least you're right, I can do whatever I feel like
 doing. I can be insincere. So can everyone thinking along the same lines.
 
 But also in this case (where C
 is totally irrelevant in this election) you could have
 secondary goals (the primary goal is to decide who wins this
 time). Maybe you want to discourage C and his supporters so
 that they would not try again in next elections, or maybe
 you want to tell all the people how many people think C and
 C's party is no good (people might follow your opinion).
 
 This is all possible, but mostly I figure C is just a candidate who has
 only earned attention from me because I have to think about what to do
 with him strategically on my ballot.
 
 I don't usually hate the also-rans, though I do tend to wonder if they
 are qualified. They don't get that much press.
 
 Maybe you want to vote sincerely in order to encourage also
 others to do so and avoid elections becoming a playground of
 strategists. 
 
 It seems like that would work backwards. If I vote sincerely I am making
 it safer for others to lie.

Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote about thresholds. If the society thinks that it is 
ok to vote strategically, then many may do so. If you vote strategically, 
others will be tempted to follow you.

 
 You could also vote sincerely because you want
 the election to act as a poll that measures the opinions of
 the society reliably and will offer guidance to the decision
 makers for the next few years.
 
 Will you argue this for sincere Range voting as well?

The thresholds with Range are very different. In competitive elections 
normalization and Approval strategies are so obvious that people must forget 
sincere ratings, go over the threshold, and start voting strategically. Sincere 
Range may however work fine for judges in sports events.

 
 As a voter, I think I know best... Thus I don't want to vote sincerely
 if this creates a risk for me. Now if I lie, there is a risk as well,
 but only if there is actually a danger that C will win due to voting
 shenanigans. That has little to do with *me*, that would be what other
 voters are doing anyway.
 
 This can actually help B and it will never help A. I
 feel like a sucker
 if I expose myself to this risk for no possible
 benefit. I do not need
 to know whether there is *really* a threat; it makes
 no sense for me.
 
 I guess the Condorcet logic should be that the risk of
 indicating your sincere opinion (BC) harms you with such
 a low probability that it doesn't matter. The benefits
 (maybe secondary) are bigger than the risk.
 
 Well, the risk from voting CB is also quite low, and there is actually
 some potential benefit there. Doubly so if most voters think as you do
 and go with the sincere route.

But if voting CB is obvious to you, maybe it is obvious to all ABC voters. 
That could already mean quite a number of votes. And that could mean trouble. 
Maybe BAC voters would do the same. I wonder how many strategists it would 
take to make C a Condorcet winner.

Or would your CB vote be just marginal noise in the election and only very few 
ABC and BAC voters would vote that way? In that case we can tolerate it.

 
 The frustrating thing is that the B:C contest shouldn't matter... When
 I consider what to do with it I am mostly thinking with my A vs B hat
 on.
 
 2. Lie, and vote ACB. Now I'm a bad guy who
 you think must have some
 strategy in mind for picking this manner of voting.
 
 Maybe strategic, maybe misled to think that ranking C above
 B would always decrease the chances of B to win, maybe you
 want to discourage B by showing that he is not much more
 popular than C.
 
 Why misled? I don't believe that ranking CB always hurts B any more than
 I think that ranking BC always *helps* B defeat A. No always about it.

You are an expert, so you do know. But it seems plausible that there are always 
some voters that rank the worst

Re: [EM] C//A (was: Remember Toby)

2011-06-11 Thread Juho Laatu
On 12.6.2011, at 2.07, Kevin Venzke wrote:

 Hi Juho,
 
 --- En date de : Ven 10.6.11, Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk a écrit :
 I don't recommend that voters not be instructed on how
 the method is
 supposed to work.
 
 I think with C//A it is easier to explain how to find
 the winner, and
 the strategy becomes obvious. No defeat strengths are
 involved. MinMax
 has its strategy too, and this is harder to perceive
 because the method
 rules are harder to understand.
 
 If we are taking about simple explanations to regular
 voters then maybe all the strategy related aspects should be
 considered not-simple.
 
 C//A's counting process is quite simple (to explain)
 although its counting process has two phases that differ
 from each others. I don't think e.g. the elect the
 candidate that needs least number of additional votes to
 beat all others would be more complex.
 
 The explanation may not be not much more complex. It is the strategy where
 I say MinMax is more complicated and, more importantly, hard to grasp.

I recommend sincere voting. Teaching multiple strategies to regular voters is 
far too difficult.

 If
 you teach someone how C//A works, I think you get the strategy
 understanding almost for free.

What is the general guidance? Maybe to rank those candidates that the voter 
approves.

 I don't see any way to go from the terse
 MinMax definition to an instinctive understanding of the strategy (or,
 if you wanted to suggest it, the reasoning why you wouldn't need a
 strategy).
 
 It may be undesirable that C//A has an approval strategy component at
 all, but that is a different question to my mind.
 
 If we talk about the vote counting process (with
 sincere
 votes) and how to explain it, then we have a two
 phase
 explanation (=Condorcet winner, and alternatively
 sum of all
 the ticks in the ballots if there is no Condorcet
 winner)
 vs. a one or two phase MinMax explanation (elect
 the
 candidate worst worst defeat is least bad.
 MinMax(margins)
 is quite simple since it is enough to refer to the
 number of
 additional votes each candidate would need to win
 all others
 (if doesn't already). None of the explanations is
 quite
 obvious to average voters if one has to explain
 the
 difference between having a Condorcet winner and
 not having
 a Condorcet winner. The MinMax(margins) specific
 explanation
 is maybe easiest (and still fair, clear and exact
 enough) to
 present without talking about the probabilities of
 having or
 not having a top cycle.
 
 You have to explain CW either way.
 
 Not necessarily, but that need might pop up. For example in
 the MinMax(margins) explanation above (elect the candidate
 that needs least number of additional votes to beat all
 others) CW is not mentioned. Some voters might however
 start wondering in what kind of situations the winner does
 not win all others. In that case that individual voter might
 need someone to explain that sometimes there is a CW and
 sometimes not.
 
 This feels like a shell game to me. The concept of beat all others is
 what you need to explain. I don't care whether you call it CW or avoid
 the term.

Ok, that explanation could be called also an extended CW rule (nothing more 
needed).

 
 If we seek simplicity, I'd be happiest to explain
 the
 voting procedure simply just rank the candidates
 and use
 the MinMax(margins) additional votes explanation
 if the
 voters need to know how the votes are counted.
 
 When I think of simplicity I mean that the voters
 would actually 
 understand how the method works.
 
 I don't think you will have much luck proposing
 methods if you don't
 think voters need to understand them. Can you find an
 angle / sales 
 pitch that dodges this?
 
 I believe most people are not interested in the vote
 counting process. The voting procedure and general idea of
 the method must be easy to understand (but no mathematically
 exact description is needed). People are happy enough if the
 method seems good enough and experts and their own party are
 not complaining about its possible problems.
 
 If we take for example a country that uses D'Hondt to
 allocate seats, only some voters are able to explain how the
 D'Hondt allocation is actually counted. Most voters vote
 happily despite of this and have considerable trust on the
 method.
 
 It is possible that the complexity of a method will be used
 against it in some reform campaigns but maybe that's a
 different story. This is not really a problem of the regular
 voters but just a campaign strategy. Defendability in
 campaigns is a valid separate topic for discussions though.
 
 Sorry, I thought that was part of this topic. It is a great part of my
 concern here.

Ok, also that is a major concern if there are people who want to use all the 
propaganda that they can get in their hands against you.

 
 has more obvious burial 
 disincentive (especially if the comparison is
 to
 margins),
 
 All Condorcet methods have a burial incentive with
 some
 variation

Re: [EM] C//A

2011-06-12 Thread Juho Laatu
On 11.6.2011, at 13.30, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 Juho Laatu wrote:
 On 9.6.2011, at 4.54, Kevin Venzke wrote:
 Hi Juho,
 --- En date de : Mer 8.6.11, Juho Laatu juho.la...@gmail.com a
 écrit :
 I was busy with other activities for a while but here are some
 comments.
 
 I think with C//A it is easier to explain how to find the winner,
 and the strategy becomes obvious. No defeat strengths are involved.
 MinMax has its strategy too, and this is harder to perceive because
 the method rules are harder to understand.
 If we are taking about simple explanations to regular voters then
 maybe all the strategy related aspects should be considered
 not-simple.
 C//A's counting process is quite simple (to explain) although its
 counting process has two phases that differ from each others. I don't
 think e.g. the elect the candidate that needs least number of
 additional votes to beat all others would be more complex.
 
 I think voters could be confused over that where one truncates actually 
 matters to the method. That is, the method isn't resolvable if everybody 
 votes untruncated and there's a cycle; no single ballot can break the tie 
 unless it also breaks the cycle. Further, if only some people truncate, that 
 would give power to them.
 
 So yes, the implied double use of the ballot could add more complexity. 
 Instead of the complexity being in front (seemingly complex method), it's 
 in the back, somewhat akin to the strategy equilibria you can get in the 
 seemingly simple plain Approval method.

Cutoffs add information but implicit cutoffs may also decrease information 
because of truncation. That could make the winner less ideal than with fully 
ranked (also ties possible) votes. All available information may help solving 
ties.

 
 Not necessarily, but that need might pop up. For example in the
 MinMax(margins) explanation above (elect the candidate that needs
 least number of additional votes to beat all others) CW is not
 mentioned. Some voters might however start wondering in what kind of
 situations the winner does not win all others. In that case that
 individual voter might need someone to explain that sometimes there
 is a CW and sometimes not.
 
 One doesn't have to explain the concept of the CW in least reversal Condorcet 
 or Copeland either, nor Tideman or (I think) Schulze.
 
 Even for the Condorcet-IRV hybrid methods, you could slink your way out of 
 defining the CW. For instance:
 
 Repeatedly eliminate the Plurality loser among uneliminated candidates until 
 one of the remaining candidates beats all the other remaining candidates 
 one-on-one.
 
 This defines the CW indirectly without mentioning the name CW itself. The 
 winner of this method isn't a true CW either, because it's only a CW  with 
 regards to the uneliminated candidates.
 
 Perhaps you could define Minmax, as an algorithm, like this:
 
 A candidate beats another if more voters prefer the former to the latter 
 than the latter to the former.
 
 If a candidate beats another, the strength of his victory is equal to how 
 many voters prefer the former to the latter (WV).
 
 If a candidate beats another, the strength of his victory is equal to the 
 number of voters preferring the former to the latter, less the number of 
 voters preferring the latter to the former (Margins).
 
 If a candidate is beaten by another, the other candidate's victory is his 
 defeat.
 
 Elect the candidate whose worst defeat is least.
 
 (Possible tiebreak: Break ties by electing the candidate whose second worst 
 defeat is the least. Break further ties by third worst, fourth worst, and so 
 on. If the tie remains after all defeats have been considered, flip a 
 coin/ask the legislature/random voter hierarchy.)
 
 Some methods pass the Condorcet criterion without seeming Condorcet-like at 
 all. Nanson and Baldwin, for instance, look like Borda IRV. BTR-IRV always 
 keeps the CW in the running and so also elects the CW when there is one. None 
 of these examples are monotone, but hey.
 
 If we take for example a country that uses D'Hondt to allocate seats,
 only some voters are able to explain how the D'Hondt allocation is
 actually counted. Most voters vote happily despite of this and have
 considerable trust on the method.
 It is possible that the complexity of a method will be used against
 it in some reform campaigns but maybe that's a different story. This
 is not really a problem of the regular voters but just a campaign
 strategy. Defendability in campaigns is a valid separate topic for
 discussions though.
 
 It might be useful to look at places that have complex methods and find out 
 how they got passed. As far as I know, the (quite complex, computer 
 calculated) Meek's method is used in certain New Zealand elections. How did 
 that happen? How did the voters accept it? Perhaps some of that knowledge can 
 be applied to electoral reform elsewhere.

My best guess is that there were some active individuals with marketing skills

Re: [EM] C//A

2011-06-12 Thread Juho Laatu
On 12.6.2011, at 2.17, fsimm...@pcc.edu wrote:

 Another solution is to infer the rankings from range style ballots. (As a 
 retired teacher I find iot easier to 
 rate than to rank, anyway.)

Maybe the default ballot formats should also have names or something. A rating 
based ballot could be such that there is a row for each candidate name, and 
then there are columns from 9 to 0, and then the voter ticks some marks in 
the ballot. A ranking based ballot could be such that there is a row for each 
candidate name, and then there are columns from 1st to 10th, and then the 
voter ticks some marks in the ballot. These ballots were however almost 
similar. What ballot format did you assume? Maybe ballots that have a box where 
the voter can write a number (rating). Maybe a voting machine that can 
rearrange the candidates on the screen in the correct ranking order. Maybe a 
voting machine where the voter pushes buttons (next to the candidate names) one 
by one. Maybe a white paper where the voter can write the numbers of the ranked 
candidates in the correct order. My point is just that maybe we should have 
some definitions for the most common ways to fill a ballot (or u
 se a voting machine).

Juho






Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] C//A (was: Remember Toby)

2011-06-14 Thread Juho Laatu
On 13.6.2011, at 5.37, Kevin Venzke wrote:

 Hi Juho,
 
 --- En date de : Sam 11.6.11, Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk a écrit :
 --- En date de : Ven 10.6.11, Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk
 a écrit :
 I don't recommend that voters not be
 instructed on how
 the method is
 supposed to work.
 
 I think with C//A it is easier to explain how
 to find
 the winner, and
 the strategy becomes obvious. No defeat
 strengths are
 involved. MinMax
 has its strategy too, and this is harder to
 perceive
 because the method
 rules are harder to understand.
 
 If we are taking about simple explanations to
 regular
 voters then maybe all the strategy related aspects
 should be
 considered not-simple.
 
 C//A's counting process is quite simple (to
 explain)
 although its counting process has two phases that
 differ
 from each others. I don't think e.g. the elect
 the
 candidate that needs least number of additional
 votes to
 beat all others would be more complex.
 
 The explanation may not be not much more complex. It
 is the strategy where
 I say MinMax is more complicated and, more
 importantly, hard to grasp.
 
 I recommend sincere voting. Teaching multiple strategies to
 regular voters is far too difficult.
 
 I'm not sure this is the same question. You can recommend whatever you
 want, but this is not what I think is sought at the stage where you are
 trying to propose something.

Do you mean that MinMax without strategic guidance would be a strategic mess, 
or what?

 
 If
 you teach someone how C//A works, I think you get the
 strategy
 understanding almost for free.
 
 What is the general guidance? Maybe to rank those
 candidates that the voter approves.
 
 Do we even need general guidance? I guess vote for who you approve is
 ok, even though approve is too vague for my own tastes. Personally, I 
 am going to use something similar to better than expectation strategy.

Ok, it could then be close to normal Approval strategy, with sincere rankings 
added for the approved candidates.

 
 You have to explain CW either way.
 
 Not necessarily, but that need might pop up. For
 example in
 the MinMax(margins) explanation above (elect the
 candidate
 that needs least number of additional votes to
 beat all
 others) CW is not mentioned. Some voters might
 however
 start wondering in what kind of situations the
 winner does
 not win all others. In that case that individual
 voter might
 need someone to explain that sometimes there is a
 CW and
 sometimes not.
 
 This feels like a shell game to me. The concept of
 beat all others is
 what you need to explain. I don't care whether you
 call it CW or avoid
 the term.
 
 Ok, that explanation could be called also an extended CW
 rule (nothing more needed).
 
 I didn't understand what that sentence is referring to.

I referred to the MinMax(margins) explanation elect the candidate that needs 
least number of additional votes to beat all others that can be seen to refer 
to CW since it actually is an extended CW definition itself (it counts required 
additional votes instead of just requiring that the number of required 
additional votes should be 0).

 
 This is how I see it, as far as explanations.
 
 MinMax(margins): we want the candidate who beats all others. If we don't
 have one we take the candidate who needs the fewest addditional votes.
 (You can combine this into one sentence but I am unsure you get a lot of
 points for that.)

Ok, see the short MinMax(margins) definition above.

 
 C//A: we want the candidate who beats all others. If we don't have one,
 we take the candidate with the most votes in total.

votes = explicit rankings (or alternatively: votes = higher tan last place 
rankings)

 
 With both methods we have to explain the same concept to start with. I
 think the difficulty of explanation is about the same. The difference is
 that the strategy implications of Minmax's part two are much more
 opaque.

Ok, you seem to refer also to strategic implications that maybe (?) should be 
explained and included as part of the general definition of the method. Or 
maybe the idea is that otherwise strategies will confuse the voters after they 
start wondering about them (?).

 The theory that this opacity makes it harder to strategize under
 Minmax is not obvious to your audience either. All that's obvious is
 I'm not sure I get it. That is what I see as a liability.
 
 It is possible that the complexity of a method
 will be used
 against it in some reform campaigns but maybe
 that's a
 different story. This is not really a problem of
 the regular
 voters but just a campaign strategy. Defendability
 in
 campaigns is a valid separate topic for
 discussions though.
 
 Sorry, I thought that was part of this topic. It is a
 great part of my
 concern here.
 
 Ok, also that is a major concern if there are people who
 want to use all the propaganda that they can get in their
 hands against you.
 
 I think this should be expected. When I see all the anti-IRV arguments

Re: [EM] Defensive strategy for Condorcet methods

2011-06-14 Thread Juho Laatu
On 13.6.2011, at 17.33, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 Kevin Venzke wrote:
 
 Is Condorcet//FPP a bad method?
 
 I agree with Jameson Quinn, the gap is too far and so it could be quite 
 tempting to compromise as in FPTP (and failing that, to engineer a cycle if 
 your candidate has great first place support).
 
 Smith,FPP... perhaps better, but there's still a gap between the Condorcet 
 and the FPP part.
 
 If you want something that deters burial strategy, how about what I called 
 FPC? Each candidate's penalty is equal to the number of first-place votes for 
 those who beat him pairwise. Lowest penalty wins.
 Burying a candidate may help in engineering a cycle, but it can't stack more 
 first-place votes against him. Unfortunately, it's not monotone.
 
 Finding the most strategy-resistant monotone Condorcet method is an 
 interesting problem. If you permit approval cutoffs, UncAAO and C//A are 
 probably quite good, but if not... what, I wonder? Perhaps some Ranked Pairs 
 variant where winning contests are sorted ahead of losing contests, and then 
 sorted further by FPP score of the first person in the ordering (e.g. A for 
 AB and B for BA)? Or some Maxtree generalization. Who knows?

Yes, this is an interesting problem and the FPC approach is an interesting 
approach. Maybe the number of problem and potential for improvements could be 
the burial strategy. One can study the resulting cyclic preferences and try to 
identify who are strategists and not let them win anyway. I see the FPC 
philosophy coming from this direction.

So, let's focus on burial and the most typical cases there. Let's study the 
simplest and probably most common case where there are three candidates and 
they form an artificial loop as a result of someone using the burial strategy.

There are three candidates (A, B, C). A is the sincere Condorcet winner, B is 
the strategist, and C is the candidate that B supporters use to bury A.

FPC could reduce strategic behaviour if C is a weak candidate that does not 
have as many first place supporters as A and B. In that case A gets only  a 
small number of penalty points. And as a result the sincere Condorcet winner 
wins. This is a good result from strategy avoidance point of view. One problem 
is however that not all burials follow this pattern. One could have e.g. votes 
35: AB, 25: BA (= strategic BC), 40: C. Now C has the highest number of 
first place preferences.

First preferences is thus one way to analyze the loop of three in order to find 
the A, B and C roles there. Another possible (but far less common) 
problem with first preferences is that some of the candidates might have 
clones. There could be two candidates A1 and A2 instead of one A. In that case 
the first preference support of A1 and A2 would be lower. Also number of minor 
candidates and their position on the political map may have an impact since 
they all tend to steal some first preference votes from A, B and C.

Another approach to analyzing the cycle would be to check the defeat strengths. 
Thera are problems also in this approach. In some typical scenarios the BC 
pairwise victory os strong, but not in all scenarios.

A third approach would be to check the number of voters that gave an opinion on 
each pairwise comparison (instead of typically ranking them equal last). In 
some scenarios comparison A vs. B could have low number of indicated opinions 
(e.g. in my example above). But again, not all burial scenarios will follow 
this pattern. (The expected overall popularity and voter's distance to 
different candidates have an impact on the probability of giving a pairwise 
opinion on some pairwise comparison.)

One could also analyze the actual ballots to see which how near clones those 
three candidates are. A and C are not near clones since B could not bury A 
under a clone of A. B and C are not near clones since B could not bury A under 
a clone of B. So, if there are near clones, they must be A and B. In my example 
above A and B are indeed sincere clones. But in the strategic votes the clone 
relationship is lost.

It seems that it is not very easy to draw reliable conclusions from the matrix 
or the actual ballots. Maybe the probability of different burial scenarios is 
different and therefore we could make some statistical guesses on which 
candidates are in which roles. Our guess should be such that the winner is 
either the sincere Condocet winner A (= no harm done) or C (= disincentive to 
bury). We should thus just avoid electing B and rewarding the strategists. Of 
course it would be good if the method would elect a decent winner also in the 
case of a sincere loop.

There are also cases where we can not draw any conclusions. One basic example 
is a symmetric loop. Maybe the strategic / actual votes are 33: ABC, 33: 
BCA, 33: CAB. The sincere opinions of the B supporters were maybe 33: 
BAC. We know that B is the strategist (according to our naming convention) 
but the method can not make a 

Re: [EM] Defensive strategy for Condorcet methods

2011-06-15 Thread Juho Laatu
On 15.6.2011, at 14.23, Kevin Venzke wrote:

 Hi Juho,
 
 I have to trim this due to being short on time.

Thanks, compact opinions are always a good approach.

 In margins (and maybe in other variants too) ties
 should
 not carry any other additional meaning but that
 the voter
 didn't support XY nor YX.
 
 In a general context it is really unclear to me what
 this means. It's
 like an IRV-oriented criterion that assumes you're
 doing eliminations.
 It may be completely possible to satisfy you on this
 point, and also 
 have a method that I don't find irritating. From what
 you've literally
 written here I don't even see how it excludes WV.
 
 There are maybe two ways to understand what the election
 methods do. 1) Elect the candidate that is best according to
 some (sincere) philosophy based on the given (hopefully)
 sincere opinions of the voters. 2) Generate a set of
 (whatever kind of) rules and let the voters cast their votes
 in the best way they can to make the outcome best possible
 for themselves. In the first approach we should have an
 interpretation on what ranking two candidates equal means
 from the utility and sincere preference point of view. If
 the intended meaning of equal ranking is the same as
 flipping a coin (and often it is about the same), then also
 the results should be the same (in the first
 interpretation). In the second interpretation any rules are
 ok as long as other stated requirements are met (e.g. equal
 treatment of all voters).
 
 WV is not excluded even in the first interpretation if
 there is a good explanation (that corresponds to some
 sincere philosophy) to why pairwise defeat strengths are
 measured the way WV does. It is quite natural to say that
 the number of voters on the opposing side is an important
 criterion (but may leave open the question does the number
 of voters in favour of that candidate have some meaning as
 well). I think the margins (sincere) philosophy is easier to
 explain than the WV philosophy.
 
 But with the first approach, with people being sincere, you shouldn't
 have to worry about equal ranking or truncation for the most part. Then
 WV and margins are the same.

In the first approach people *can* be sincere since the methods measures 
sincere opinions well enough, picks the winner based on the corresponding 
sincere philosophy, and is strategy free enough so that this sincere state of 
affairs will not break. I believe WV would be sufficient in real elections. It 
may well be strategy free enough for most needs. People may interpret equality 
as equality, and also equal last positions / truncation might not be considered 
strategic but sincere. Even if truncation would be generally interpreted as 
approval, still people might be happy with it and vote sincerely according to 
this philosophy. If WV some day would give somewhat strange results (like B 
winning with votes 49: AB, 2: BC, 49: C) people could accept also that since 
probably the votes would not be as extreme and simple and uniform as in the 
given example (probably people would call the result just nearly a tie). WV 
is thus not strategy free nor perfect otherwise but probably goo
 d enough to be able to live in the first category in most political elections.

Juho






Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Something better than wv for Schulze's CSSD

2011-06-23 Thread Juho Laatu
On 22.6.2011, at 2.53, fsimm...@pcc.edu wrote:

 I am more convinced than ever that the best way to measure defeat strength in 
 Beatpath (aka CSSD) is 
 by giving the covering relation the highest priority

Being uncovered is a positive criterion in the sense that it tries to improve 
the outcome with sincere votes. Also positive criteria have the problem that 
all of them can not be met at the same time. I drafted one cyclic example to 
see how this criterion and another positive criterion, the worst defeat 
criterion, relate to each others.

33: ABDC
16: ADCB
33: CBAD
17: DCBA

Here candidate A is good from the worst defeat point of view in the sense that 
it is only two votes short of being a Condorcet winner (and having majority of 
first preferences). The worst defeats of all other candidates are considerably 
worse. But A is covered by B, and according to the covering rule above that 
would mean that A can not win.

The point is thus that although covered candidates may sometimes be less good 
than others, they may sometimes be also better than others, e.g. from the worst 
defeat / number of required extra votes point of view. In this example the 
covered candidate could well be considered to be the best winner.

The votes in this example do not have any very obvious mapping to some real 
life situation. One approximate explanation could be that almost 50% of the 
voters support A. All those that do not support A prefer both B and C to A. 
That is why A loses to two candidates (slightly) and becomes a covered 
candidate. D is a more complex candidate to explain (but some extra candidates 
are needed to build the required loop).

Another example of a covering relation in a loop could be a situation where we 
have three parties in a loop. At least one of the parties has several 
candidates. They all beat all candidates of one of the other parties, and are 
beaten by all candidates of the other one of them. Within our party there is a 
clear order of preference between different candidates, and therefore the 
weaker candidates are covered by the stronger ones. In this situation it would 
make sense not to elect any of the covered candidates. But on the other hand in 
this kind of scenarios also the worst defeats (and strongest beatpaths) agree 
with the covering relation. In this example the covering relation is thus a 
natural argument in favour of the covering candidates against the covered ones, 
but adding the covering rule does not improve the method since also other 
criteria agree on which candidates are good and which ones are bad.

The votes could be e.g.
33: A1A2A3B1B2B3C1C2C3
33: B1B2B3C1C2C3A1A2A3
33: C1C2C3A1A2A3B1B2B3

The question then becomes if there are situations (examples) where use of the 
covering rule would clearly (or likely) improve the outcome of the method 
(and where defeat strengths (or defeat strength based beatpaths) would elect 
some clearly worse candidate). In the first example the covering rule may 
have led to a worse winner (or what do you think). I may try to find one more 
example where the covering rule would improve the results (of other rules). 
Anyone else, any good candidates?

Many good positive criteria tend to give the same winners. One has to pay 
special attention to cases where they give different results in order to see 
which ones of those rules should rule in such situations. Beatpath is not 
perfect, so there is potential for improvements. Winning votes sometimes give 
strange results with sincere votes. Also Smith set can sometimes be questioned. 
On my part the jury is still out on if there are situations that justify using 
(the usually good) covering rule to be included in the method to improve the 
results with sincere votes. It seems that there are some cases where the use of 
the covering rule could make the results also worse. I'm waiting for examples 
that would show that also the reverse is true. (For the sake of completeness I 
note also that different societies / elections may have slightly different 
needs, and therefore the fine-tuning of the methods might differ.)

Juho






Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Remember Toby

2011-06-23 Thread Juho Laatu
What is the difference between least extra votes and MinMax(margins)? Isn't 
least extra votes pretty much the definition of MinMax(margins)? (assuming 
that the extra votes rank the candidate in question first)

Juho



On 22.6.2011, at 10.28, Jameson Quinn wrote:

 My impression was that the remember Toby thread(s) was (were) inclining 
 towards advocating simpler systems than CSSD. I heard more support for C//A, 
 minimax, and SODA.
 
 Separately, I agree that it's best to describe a system by focusing on the 
 outcome rather than the procedure. The difference is not so large for C//A 
 and SODA; for minimax, though, that inclines one to the least extra votes 
 description. (Although with a covering Smith set  4, this is not technically 
 identical to minimax, I'm happy to ignore that difference, or even to 
 actually use the least extra votes system instead of minimax.)
 
 JQ
 
 2011/6/21 fsimm...@pcc.edu
 As I remember it, when Toby settled on CSSD, we made a huge psychological 
 mistake: we got bogged
 down in the description of the CSSD algorithm for the public proposal.  I 
 think that was a fatal mistake,
 and I would like to propose a strategy for avoiding that mistake in the 
 future.
 
 It was a mistake because it gave the impression that to understand the 
 proposal, you have to
 understand a detailed algorithm.
 
 Here’s an analogy:
 
 Complicated Version of the law of refraction:
 Snell’s law says that the ratio of the signs of the angles of incidence and 
 refraction are equal to the
 ratios of the speeds of light in the respective media at the interface where 
 the refraction takes place.
 This is way too technical for the average man on the street.
 
 Simple version of the law of refraction: Fermat’s Principle's says that light 
 takes the path of least time.
 The man on the street can understand this.  Snell’s law gives a way of 
 finding that path of least time for
 the technician.
 
 What is analogous to Fermat’s principle in the context of CSSD?
 
 Answer: the beatpath winner idea.  We elect the alternative A with the 
 strongest beatpaths to the other
 alternatives.  This means that for each alternative B, alternative A has a 
 stronger beatpath to B than B
 does to A.  Once the concept of a beatpath is explained (and that its 
 strength is that of the weakest link)
 then the man on the street can understand this definition of the method.  The 
 CSSD algorithm is the
 technical part like Snell’s law,that the man on the street doesn’t have to 
 worry about.
 
 
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Eric Maskin promotes the Black method

2011-06-24 Thread Juho Laatu
On 24.6.2011, at 3.47, Paul Kislanko wrote:

 Marcus wrote:
 Maskin's argumentation doesn't work because
 of the following reason: Whether an election
 method is good or bad depends on which criteria
 it satisfies. 
 
 
 
 Now, if good and bad are defined by which criteria methods satisfy, it
 seems to me that having introduced judgement we need judges to define
 the goodness of each criterion. And if there are more than 2 judges to
 decide the goodness of more than two criteria, there is no unambiguous way
 to consolidate the opinions of the judges.

In addition to defining how important each criterion is we must also estimate 
how much each method violates some criterion. Since we can not meet all 
criteria (e.g. being strategy free) and not all interesting criteria at the 
same time it often makes sense to violate some criteria just a little, so that 
from practical point of view the method is about as good as if it meth that 
criterion fully. One bad violation of some key criterion may thus be worse than 
violating multiple criteria just a little. The number of criteria that some 
method meets of course has no meaning, only the importance of those criteria 
has, and maybe also other factors that have no named criterion representing 
them.

 
 I think Maskin's arguent is actually a really old one - if there's a CW
 nobody really has a complaint (though there are pathological cases where the
 CW is disliked by a majority of the voters...)

This expression s a bit confusing. Majority of the voters may have some other 
candidates that they prefer to the CW but there is no majority that would 
prefer one single candidate x to the CW.

 and if there's not a CW use
 Borda (or Bucklin or ...) considering only the smallest Smith Set.

There can be many opinions on if one should always pick the winner from the 
Smith Set.

 
 Logically, all we're talking about here is how to order alternatives in
 pairwise ABCA loops, right?

Well, yes but, in principle there is no need to order the candidates but just 
pick one winner, and if that loop does not contain all the candidates, then 
there is also the option to elect the winner from the other candidate.

 If we don't like Y=Borda we can start talking
 about what Y should be if there's a need to have a Y. 

Yes, there are also better options. (although Borda may not be too terrible 
here if we assume that usually we have a CW and people don't care too much who 
will be elected if there is a tie (=top loop))

Juho









Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] real world 9-winner election using RRV

2011-06-25 Thread Juho Laatu
Should the order be a proportional order or a best single winner order? I 
guess both are possible although so far the assumption obviously was 
proportional set or proportional order.

Juho



On 26.6.2011, at 1.21, Warren Smith wrote:

 The musical group who wanted me to process their election, actually wanted, 
 not
 a list of 9 winners, but actually an ordering of all 16 candidates,
 top 9 being the winners.
 
 
 -- 
 Warren D. Smith
 http://RangeVoting.org  -- add your endorsement (by clicking
 endorse as 1st step)
 and
 math.temple.edu/~wds/homepage/works.html
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] What's wrong with the party list system?

2011-07-03 Thread Juho Laatu
On 3.7.2011, at 18.49, Kathy Dopp wrote:

 Someone from Europe on this list recently said that they did not like
 the party list system.  Why not?  Party list seems like a fair, simple
 system of electing legislators who represent people in approximately
 the same proportion that they exist in the electorate.  I have not
 found a better-sounding proportional system yet. So, what's wrong with
 the party list system?

I think list based methods are quite ok.

Some reasons why people don't like them:

- They don't like parties in general, they prefer methods like STV where there 
are (in principle) only individual candidates. In STV you can rank all your 
favourite candidates in the order you like without considering where on party 
changes to another. In list based methods you can usually vote only for one 
candidate.

- A vote to a candidate of a party will support all the candidates of that 
party (although you might hate some of them).

- In closed list based methods parties will dictate quite strongly which 
candidates will be elected. Note however that in open list based methods 
parties have no say on which ones of the nominated candidates will be elected.

- List based methods typically do not support proportionality within the party. 
In open lists typically those candidates that get most personal votes will be 
elected.

- People may like candidates that are totally independent and not tied to the 
command hierarchy of some party.

- Some people have complained that in open lists parties easily nominate some 
public figures (like TV stars) to collect votes. And often those public figures 
will be also elected. (This problem is present also in the closed lists.)


Some arguments that support the use of list based methods:

- They can offer very accurate proportional representation (depends on various 
parameters like district size and number of elected candidates).

- If there are very many candidates, then the idea of STV to rank all the 
candidates or many enough of them does not work very well. It is a tedious job 
to rank more than one hundred candidates.

- Ballots can be very simple and they need not be printed for each election 
just in time. E.g. just a blank paper where one writes the number of the 
preferred candidate.

- Parties offer a clear structure to the political field. People know what the 
candidates of certain party will stand for. Candidates can not market 
themselves with different conflicting arguments to different voter groups.

- With party lists people don't need to study numerous candidates and 
understand their opinions in detail in order to cast a sophisticated vote. That 
makes voting easier to people that are not very interested in politics. Knowing 
your party is enough. Identifying the best candidate within that party is not 
very crucial if the vote goes anyway to the best party.

- Some people like closed lists since they tend to elect people that have been 
found to be good and efficient within the party. (On the other hand this is a 
feature that some people hate, i.e. giving too much power to the party and 
lading figures within the party, and keeping the power within those circles 
that already have the power.)


One could also enhance the list based methods by combining them and STV style 
systems (e.g. less ranking needed if one ranks only candidates of one's own 
party). One could also enhance the list structure to a tree structure to 
support also party internal proportionality, or to give a better and easy to 
understand structure to the political space.


All in all, I think list based methods are good methods for proportional 
elections. And they can be improved if needed. You need to choose whether you 
want closed or open lists. They may not be good methods for elections where 
there is no existing party structure and where one does not want to create one 
(e.g. in some associations that are purely individual based).

Juho




 
 -- 
 
 Kathy Dopp
 http://electionmathematics.org
 Town of Colonie, NY 12304
 One of the best ways to keep any conversation civil is to support the
 discussion with true facts.
 
 Fundamentals of Verifiable Elections
 http://kathydopp.com/wordpress/?p=174
 
 View some of my research on my SSRN Author page:
 http://ssrn.com/author=1451051
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] What's wrong with the party list system?

2011-07-03 Thread Juho Laatu
On 3.7.2011, at 20.44, Toby Pereira wrote:
 The problem I have with party list systems is that you do not elect 
 individuals but organisations, who can then put in who they like.
 
Closed and open party lists have different philosophy. Basic closed lists 
contain an ordered list of candidates and one elects candidates starting from 
the beginning of the list. In basic open lists parties have no say on which 
ones of the nominated candidates will be elected (people vote for individual 
candidates, and candidates with most personal votes will be elected).

Juho






Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] What's wrong with the party list system?

2011-07-04 Thread Juho Laatu
This was a good overall description of party list proportional 
representation. I wrote few (actually quite many) minor comments below.

On 4.7.2011, at 2.06, James Gilmour wrote:

 First we have to recognise that there is no one voting system called party 
 list proportional representation.  There are probably
 as many variants of party-list PR as there are countries and jurisdictions 
 using such a system for their public elections.
 However, these party-list PR voting systems fall into two broad categories: 
 closed-list party-list PR and open-list party-list
 PR.
 
 In both closed and open versions of party-list systems the order of the 
 candidates in each party's list is determined by the
 relevant political party.

Why do all say this? It is possible that in all used systems parties determine 
the order. But it could be of no importance from the election result point of 
view. It could be just e.g. a random or alphabetical order, possibly determined 
by the election officials. In closed lists the order is essential but not 
necessarily in open lists.

  Different countries have different rules about how that is to be done and 
 different parties have
 different procedures within those rules for ordering the lists.  Some parties 
 exercise very strong centralised control; other
 parties are much more democratic and give every member a vote.
 
 In closed-list systems the voters can vote only for a party.  Seats are 
 allocated to parties by an arithmetic formula, usually
 d'Hondt (favours parties with more votes) or Sainte-Laguë (favours parties 
 with fewer votes).

I think Sainte-Laguë could be said to be neutral with respect to party size. It 
is at least less biased than D'Hondt. (D'Hondt is also not grossly biased. It 
clearly favours large parties in the allocation of the remaining fractional 
seats. Full seats will be allocated accurately.)

  Candidates take the seats allocated
 to their respective parties strictly in the order in which they are named on 
 their parties' lists.
 
 In open-list systems the voters can also mark a vote for a candidate but 
 usually only for one candidate.  Votes for a candidate
 are counted as votes for that candidate's party and seats are allocated to 
 the parties by an arithmetic formula, usually d'Hondt or
 Sainte-Laguë as in closed-list party-list systems.  When candidates are 
 allocated to the seats won by each party, the votes for each
 candidate within the relevant party are taken into account (in different ways 
 in the various implementations).  Sometimes the
 candidates' votes can change the order in which they are allocated to the 
 party's seats.
 
 The main objection to party-list voting systems is that they are centred on 
 the registered political parties and not on the voters.

I think they are very much centered on the voters, just like most other voting 
systems. They just assume that the political field is organized and can be 
divided into parties or other maybe more election specific lists of candidates. 
(In addition many but not all list based methods allow also parties to 
determine to order in which candidates are elected.)

 (Of course, such systems cannot be used in non-partisan elections.)  The 
 prime objective of all party-list voting systems is to
 deliver PR of the registered political parties.

... and other (non-registered) groupings of candidates and candidates running 
alone.

  Party-list voting systems entrench the political power of the political 
 parties
 (especially the central party machine) at the expense of the voters.

Maybe in the form of the party determined order in the closed lists. Otherwise 
maybe not more than in any other party based political system. I however note 
that methods that provide proportionality also within parties may reduce the 
power of the central party machine since then the opinions of the voters 
become more visible. Party lists don't exclude such proportionality although 
they usually do not provide any party internal proportionality. One more thing 
is that methods where candidates run as independent citizens and join together 
as parties or other groupings only after the election put at least 
psychologically more weight on the party independent role of the 
representatives. Also voters' ability to vote across party border lines (as 
e.g. in STV) may have some similar psychological effects.

  This is most certainly true of closed-list party-list voting
 systems where the voters have no say in which candidates are elected.  
 Open-list systems do allow the voters some say in which of
 the parties' candidates should be elected

Not some say but possibly also all say. In the beginning of the mail you 
said that there are two categories, closed-list party-list PR and open-list 
party-list PR. It s a matter of taste in which of those categories one puts 
those methods where voters have some say on which candidates will be elected 
(could depend on e.g. if voters vote for parties/lists or 

Re: [EM] What's wrong with the party list system?

2011-07-04 Thread Juho Laatu
On 4.7.2011, at 4.08, Kathy Dopp wrote:

 Thanks for the responses.  In response to the party leaders having too
 much control, I believe it is possible to make party-lists on the
 fly from voters' own rank choice ballots in a way that the most voters
 would naturally support -- which would put the control into voters'
 hands and treat all voters fairly and the same (unlike IRV and STV).
 As soon as I have time, I'll write it up.

Yes. One could use primaries to determine the order of candidates in the closed 
lists. One could enhance open lists by using STV (or e.g. some Condorcet based 
proportional method) to build a hybrid method that provides proportionality 
also within parties. One could also use tree like lists to implement more 
accurate proportionality within parties. There are many tricks to reduce the 
possible problems of fixed order in the closed lists and to improve party 
INTERNAL proportionality in both open and closed lists.

 
 I appreciate the comments and agree with the problem of too much
 control given to party leaders -- but think that it is solvable, and
 that the Condorcet method can be used to resolve any ties with this
 method.   It seems a little more complex than I like, but perhaps it
 can be simply described and counted? Not sure yet.

One reason why Condorcet based proportional methods have not gained popularity 
is that they are even computationally complex (in addition to being quite 
difficult to understand to regular politicians) (when compared to basic single 
winner Condorcet methods that are simpler but do not provide proportionality).

Juho


 
 On Sun, Jul 3, 2011 at 2:06 PM,  padraigdelg...@yahoo.co.uk wrote:
 Hi Kathy,
 
 I can't speak for the person who said it on this list but the primary reason 
 for most people is that it gives control to party elites - those who select 
 the party candidates and decide order on which they come on said list.
 
 Personally I think there are many ways to overcome that problem, and it can 
 be a good method.
 
 
 What, for instance?
 
 
 Kathy Dopp
 http://electionmathematics.org
 Town of Colonie, NY 12304
 One of the best ways to keep any conversation civil is to support the
 discussion with true facts.
 
 Fundamentals of Verifiable Elections
 http://kathydopp.com/wordpress/?p=174
 
 View some of my research on my SSRN Author page:
 http://ssrn.com/author=1451051
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Condorcet divisor method proportional representation

2011-07-04 Thread Juho Laatu
On 3.7.2011, at 20.34, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 Kathy Dopp wrote:
 On Sun, Jul 3, 2011 at 2:33 AM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm
 km_el...@lavabit.com wrote:
 Kathy Dopp wrote:
 I do not like this system and believe it is improper to call it
 Condorcet. It seems to have all the same flaws as IRV - hiding the
 lower choice votes of voters, except if the voter voted for some of
 the less popular candidates.  Thus, I can see there may be lots of
 cases when it eliminates the Condorcet winner.
 Do you mean that it fails to elect the Condorcet winner in some singlewinner
 elections, or in multiwinner ones? If it's the latter, then there's a
 perfectly good reason for that.
 
 Let me pull an old example again:
 
 45: Left  Center  Right
 45: Right  Center  Left
 10: Center  Right  Left
 
 If there's one seat, Center is the CW; but if you want to elect two, it
 seems most fair to elect Left and Right. If Center is elected, the wing
 corresponding to the other winning candidate will have greater power.
 I disagree. In your example, clearly 55 prefer right to left, but only
 45 prefer left to right.  And center is the clear winner overall.
 Thus, if only two will be elected, it should be center and right.
 
 That's incompatible with the Droop proportionality criterion. The DPC says 
 that if there are k seats, and a fraction greater than 1/(k+1) of the 
 electorate all prefer a certain set of candidates to all others, then someone 
 in that set should be elected.
 
 (Actually, the more general sense is that if more than p/(k+1) of the 
 electorate all prefer a set of q candidates to all others, then min(p, q) of 
 these candidates should win.)
 
 You could also consider a single-candidate variant of the majority criterion: 
 If, in a single-winner case, more than 50% vote a certain candidate top, he 
 should win. If, in a two-winner case, more than 33% vote a certain candidate 
 top, he should win. If in an n-winner case, more than 1/(n+1) vote a certain 
 candidate top, he should win. Such a criterion would mean that Left and Right 
 have to be elected, because each is supported by more than 33%.

Here's one more example that I have used to point out the difference between 
proportionality oriented and majority oriented elections. Party A has 55% 
support and two candidates, party B has 45% support and only one candidate.

55: A1A2B
45: BA1A2

A1 is the clear Condorcet winner in single winner elections.

Any proportional multi winner election that elects two representatives would 
elect A1 and B.

If we elect two most popular candidates, then we elect A1 and A2.

If we allow voters to elect any pair of candidates (using a single winner 
Condorcet method), then the candidate sets are {A1, A2}, {A1, B} and {A2, B}. 
Out of these three alternatives {A1, A2} would be a Condorcet winner (since the 
55 A party supporters have a majority and can therefore always decide).

As Kristofer Munsterhjelm points out, proportional methods may and should 
sometimes not elect the (single winner) Condorcet winner. The Condorcet 
criterion can be applied in groups (extended) so that the best group of n 
candidates is does not always contain all candidates of best group of size m, 
where mn (in the single winner Condorcet case m=1). In more general terms my 
point is also that dIfferent elections may have different needs and targets and 
rules.

- We could also have single winner methods that do not always elect the 
Condorcet winner. We could for example have a method that would elect A1 with 
55% probability and B with 45% probability, and that would this way provide 
statistical proportionality in time.

- A Republican government in the U.S.A. could elect only republican candidates 
as ambassadors and judges, maybe in the Condorcet preference order. The voters 
could be Republicans only, or alternatively both Republicans and Democrats, but 
the point is that majority would rule in both cases, until next time when the 
majority could be the other party.

- Also if you elect employees from a group of candidates there is maybe no need 
to be proportional. Just pick the best ones.

((I also note that in principle Condorcet methods need not define a full 
preference order of the candidates. Picking one winner is all that single 
winner methods need to do.))

Juho





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Condorcet divisor method proportional representation

2011-07-04 Thread Juho Laatu
On 4.7.2011, at 16.33, Kathy Dopp wrote:

 I must say then, I simply do not like the Droop quota as a criteria
 because it elects less popular candidates favored by fewer voters
 overall and eliminates the Condorcet winners some times.

If you want the most popular single candidates to be elected (e.g. Condorcet 
winner), and you do not require 100% best proportionality, then maybe you like 
methods that are based on proportional ordering. Also your interest in 
organizing the party lists in some preference order points out in this 
direction.

Proportional order based methods thus do not provide the best possible 
proportionality but they are close. Typical proportional order methods follow 
philosophy where you fist pick the winner if there is only one representative. 
That would be the Condorcet winner. The next candidate is the one that makes a 
two seat representative body most proportional, but with the condition that the 
first candidate will not be changed. And so on for the rest of the seats.

Proportional ordering methods are also algorithmically simpler than methods 
that seek best possible proportionality. (Methods that seek ideal 
proportionality do not respect the condition/limitation of creating an ordering 
that increases the number of representatives one by one.)

If you want to put emphasis on always electing the most popular ones of the 
candidates, but keep good proportionality at the same time, and not allow 
majority to take all the seats, then maybe proportional ordering methods are 
close to what you want. They may also not always elect the next most popular 
candidate, if e.g. some wing has already had its fair share of candidates, but 
maybe they offer a good approximation of what you want.

Juho





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] What's wrong with the party list system?

2011-07-04 Thread Juho Laatu
On 4.7.2011, at 16.53, Kathy Dopp wrote:

 That is an interesting idea that would require a different ballot type
 than in existing party list systems whereby one could rank all the
 candidates within a particular party one votes for.

I just note that if we combine party lists and candidate ranking within those 
lists, then we can have actually quite simple ballots.

In a flat STV election with many candidates voters may need to rank high number 
of candidates in order to be sure that their vote will be counted fully for 
their own party and it will not exhaust in the calculation process before that 
is done. In a list election with STV (or some other ranked method) within the 
parties it is enough to rank just one candidate to be sure that the vote will 
go fully to one's own party. That makes voting simple for those who are in a 
hurry or who don't want to study the background and opinions of all the 
candidates (to be able to rank them).

For the same reason one could live with quite simple ballots without losing 
much and still be able to provide much better party internal proportionality 
than with one single vote (that is the traditional approach in list elections). 
One could e.g have a white ballot paper with three boxes. Voters would mark the 
numbers of their three favourite candidates in those three boxes. From ballot 
complexity and ballot filling effort point of view that would be about as 
simple as it gets (assuming that writing the numbers of the candidates in the 
ballot is not considered to be much more complex than ticking some ordered 
boxes next to the candidates, or giving and ordering number to each candidate). 
And this would work reasonably well also with very high number of candidates 
and elected representatives.

(Of course the idea of having proportionally ordered candidate lists in a 
closer list election would make voting in the actual election even simpler. But 
then one would need to have a primary to find the ordering for each party.)

Juho





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] What's wrong with the party list system?

2011-07-04 Thread Juho Laatu
On 4.7.2011, at 18.59, James Gilmour wrote:

 Juho Laatu   Sent: Monday, July 04, 2011 4:30 PM
 (Of course the idea of having proportionally ordered 
 candidate lists in a closer list election would make voting 
 in the actual election even simpler. But then one would need 
 to have a primary to find the ordering for each party.)
 
 But that would not give proportional representation of the voters, i.e. those 
 who voted in the public election.  Any ordering of a
 party's list by a primary election can, at best, reflect only the views of 
 those entitled to vote in that primary.

Yes, that is not exact proportionality based on the voters of the actual 
election. But this proportionality is quite good still. It  may be ok to 
determine some things also in the primary. There are also options like allowing 
only the party members to vote or allowing everyone to vote. Their results 
offer two different approaches to the philosophy of proportionality. The latter 
case is interesting since it can be used also as a strategy. Allowing non-party 
members to say which candidates are interesting makes the party list more 
interesting / better from the non-regular party voters' point of view, and may 
lead to getting more votes in the actual election.

  That is a
 private, internal matter for each party. For real proportional representation 
 of the VOTERS, the voters must be free to express
 their opinions among the parties and among the candidates within the parties. 
  That can be done only in the actual public election,
 i.e. all at one time, when all the voters know which parties are contesting 
 the election and can see all the candidates of all the
 parties.

I could accept even arrangements where each party has different rules in their 
primary, or arrangements where the votes of different parties will be counted 
in different ways in the actual election. It is true that one would get 
cleanest proportionality if everything would be decided in one go in one big 
election with same rules for all. But if votes can be distributed to the 
parties in some nice and proportional way, they could also have their own 
(democratically chosen) ways to decide who will get seats within that party. Or 
maybe the country would set some minimum requirements for nomination and seat 
allocation within each party. Nomination is anyway usually under the control of 
the parties nowadays, so they can play tricks there (not to nominate certain 
candidates, to nominate candidates so that some of them will have good 
probability of becoming elected).

But I guess I agree with you roughly on which approaches are the cleanest.

Juho


 
 James
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] What's wrong with the party list system?

2011-07-04 Thread Juho Laatu
One possible unwanted feature in Asset like methods is that they make it 
possible for the candidates to trade with the votes. The voters may trust their 
candidate, but they should not trust them too much, since in extreme cases they 
might even sell their valuable vote assets to someone.

One straight forward fix to this problem is that the candidates would declare 
their preferences already before the election. In that case the voters would 
vote for these predeclared preference orders, and the used method could be STV 
or some other ranking based method. This approach could allow also voters to 
provide full rankings themselves, or it could allow short voter given 
preference orders to be completed to longer rankings e.g. so that the 
preference order of their first favourite will be used to continue the given 
preference order.

Since it may be too tedious to study the preference orders of all potential 
candidates one could simplify the structure. That could lead to a tree based 
election where the votes to some candidate will be inherited in a tree so that 
a vote to a candidate would support the smallest branch in the tree that 
contains this candidate. Then to the next smallest branch etc. The tree could 
be ordered also so that not only the leaves but also the branches of the tree 
would contain candidates. Branch candidates would be elected first, leading to 
a preference order among the candidates of that branch.

The basic idea of the tree is that it os easy to understand and politicians 
must declare their true preferences. Trees are not anymore far from basic 
lists. They just give a better structure to the political space.

My point was to show how the problems of Asset could be fixed and that there is 
a continuum of methods between Asset and basic list methods.

Juho



On 4.7.2011, at 17.33, Jameson Quinn wrote:

 
 
 The nice feature of existing party list methods is that it allows the
 election of a large number of candidates to a large national body of
 legislators without requiring voters to rank individually a huge
 number of candidates.
 
 Yes, this is the main reason for people who favor party list systems. Note 
 that this same advantage can be given, without giving any centralized power 
 to party structures, by using Asset or Asset/STV blends.  These can include 
 ballots of any complexity - from vote-for-one to full ratings ballots - and 
 many different proportional vote assignment/transfer rules. They can even do 
 things similar to mixed member systems, in which all votes are local but vote 
 transfers can be regional/national. And parties can voluntarily recreate the 
 effects of either open or closed lists within such systems. The only downside 
 to asset-like PR systems is that they require the candidates to be somewhat 
 more sophisticated. 
 
 Thus, in general, I prefer such systems to party lists. Also, with my house 
 in Guatemala, I've seen close-up how extremely dysfunctional closed party 
 list systems can get.
 
 JQ
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Has this idea been considered?

2011-07-04 Thread Juho Laatu
On 5.7.2011, at 3.09, Russ Paielli wrote:

 Thanks for the feedback, Jameson. After thinking about it a bit, I realized 
 that the method I proposed probably suffers from strategy problems similar to 
 IRV. But at least it avoids the summability problem of IRV, which I consider 
 a major defect.

I agree that if IRV is interesting then also this method is. Some IRV related 
problems remain but you will get summability, clear declarations of candidate 
preferences, very simple voting and ability to handle easily large number of 
candidates. You could say that this method is also an improvement of TTR 
(similar voting, but has ability to pick the winner in one round only, maybe 
smaller spoiler problem).

If people don't like the preference list given by their favourite candidate, 
one could nominate additional fake candidates to offer additional preference 
lists. If the preference list of candidate A is ABC, then thee could be an 
additional (weaker) candidate A1 whose preference order would be A1ACB.

One possible extension would be to allow candidates that are afraid that they 
would be spoilers (that reduce the votes of a stronger favourite candidate too 
much so that he will be eliminated too early) to transfer their votes right 
away. The preference list could have a cutoff. Preference list ABCDE (of 
candidate A) would be interpreted so that votes to A would be added right away 
also to the score of B and C (but not D and E). If A gets transferred votes 
from some other candidates, they will be transferred further (to candidates not 
mentioned above cutoff in the original transfer list) only after A has been 
eliminated. (One could use this trick also in regular IRV.)

If one wants to simplify the inheritance rules even more then we might end up 
using a tree method (I seem to mention it in every mail I send:). In that 
approach there is no risk of having loops in the candidate transfer order. 
Votes would be counted right away for each branch, and the candidate of the 
largest brach of the largest branch of the ... would win.

 
 OK, here's another proposal. Same thing I proposed at the top of this thread, 
 except that voters can vote for more than one candidate, as in Approval 
 Voting. How does that stack up?

You should define that method a bit more in detail. I started wondering if it 
would allow candidate X to win if he asked also 100 of his friends to take part 
in the election and transfer their votes to him.

Juho



 
 By the way, I took a look at SODA, and I must tell you that I don't consider 
 it a practical reform proposal. It's way too complicated to ever be adopted 
 for major public elections. The method I just proposed is already pushing the 
 limit for complexity, and it is much simpler than SODA.
 
 Regards,
 Russ P.
 
 
 On Mon, Jul 4, 2011 at 1:10 PM, Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com wrote:
 A system based purely on candidates freely transferring their votes until a 
 majority (or Droop quota) is reached is called Asset voting. I believe that 
 Asset voting is a good system, though there are certainly those who'd 
 disagree. It is also possible - and I'd say desirable - to combine aspects of 
 Asset with other systems productively. One such proposal, SODA, is currently 
 my favorite practical reform proposal, something I have real hopes for. So 
 I'd certainly say you have (reinvented) some good ideas here.
 
 With that said, I can see a couple of problems with this system right off. 
 First off, bottom-up elimination is probably the worst feature of IRV, 
 because there is a fairly broad range of situations where it leads inevitably 
 to eliminating a centrist and electing an extremist, in a way that can 
 clearly be criticized as spoiled (the centrist would have won pairwise) and 
 nonmonotonic (votes shifting to the winner can cause them to lose). 
 Secondly, a voter has no power to ensure that their vote is not transferred 
 in a way they do not approve of. This second disadvantage compounds with the 
 first, because a minority bloc will be eliminated early, and their votes 
 transferred more than once before the final result.
 
 Cheers, 
 Jameson
 
 2011/7/4 Russ Paielli russ.paie...@gmail.com
 Hello,
 
 I was somewhat active on this mailing list for a short time several years 
 ago. How is everyone doing?
 
 I have an idea for a single-winner election method, and it seems like a good 
 one to me. I'd like to know if it has been considered before and, if so, what 
 the problems are with it, if any. Here's how it works:
 
 The mechanics of casting a ballot are identical to what we do now (in the US 
 anyway). Each voter simply votes for one candidate. After the votes are 
 counted, the last-place candidate transfers his or her votes to the candidate 
 of his or her choice. Then the next-to-last candidate does the same thing, 
 and so on, until one candidate has a majority.
 
 The transfer of votes at the close of polling could be automated as follows. 
 Weeks before 

Re: [EM] Has this idea been considered?

2011-07-05 Thread Juho Laatu
On 5.7.2011, at 11.19, Russ Paielli wrote:

 If one wants to simplify the inheritance rules even more then we might end up 
 using a tree method (I seem to mention it in every mail I send:). In that 
 approach there is no risk of having loops in the candidate transfer order. 
 Votes would be counted right away for each branch, and the candidate of the 
 largest brach of the largest branch of the ... would win.
 
 That sounds interesting, but I'm not sure I understand what you mean. Can you 
 give an example?

Here's one example.

Tree of candidates + number of personal votes + sum of votes of candidates of 
each branch:

Branch1 (13)
Branch1.1 (7)
A (4)
B (3)
Branch1.2 (6)
C (6)
Branch2 (18)
Branch2.1 (12)
D (5)
E (7)
Branch2.2 (5)
F (3)
G (2)
Branch2.3 (1)
H (1)

- Branch2 has more votes than Branch1 = Branch2 wins
- Branch2.1 has more votes than Branch2.2 and Branch2.3 = Branch2.1 wins
- candidate E has more votes than candidate D = candidate E wins

The tree approach thus forces the order of transfer to be non-cyclic. The 
transfer order of candidate E is E  D  {F, G, H}.

The tree format can be printed on paper and it is easy to grasp. The ballot 
sheet may also follow the same tree format. Branches may have names (e.g. party 
names) or be unnamed. Left wing parties could join forces under one branch. 
Candidates of one party could be divided in smaller groups. Or maybe the 
branches have no party names and party affiliations, maybe just descriptive 
names, maybe no branch names at all.

Juho






Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Has this idea been considered?

2011-07-06 Thread Juho Laatu
On 6.7.2011, at 6.42, Russ Paielli wrote:

 On Tue, Jul 5, 2011 at 2:14 AM, Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk wrote:
 On 5.7.2011, at 11.19, Russ Paielli wrote:
 
 If one wants to simplify the inheritance rules even more then we might end 
 up using a tree method (I seem to mention it in every mail I send:). In that 
 approach there is no risk of having loops in the candidate transfer order. 
 Votes would be counted right away for each branch, and the candidate of the 
 largest brach of the largest branch of the ... would win.
 
 That sounds interesting, but I'm not sure I understand what you mean. Can 
 you give an example?
 
 Here's one example.
 
 Tree of candidates + number of personal votes + sum of votes of candidates of 
 each branch:
 
 Branch1 (13)
 Branch1.1 (7)
 A (4)
 B (3)
 Branch1.2 (6)
 C (6)
 Branch2 (18)
 Branch2.1 (12)
 D (5)
 E (7)
 Branch2.2 (5)
 F (3)
 G (2)
 Branch2.3 (1)
 H (1)
 
 - Branch2 has more votes than Branch1 = Branch2 wins
 - Branch2.1 has more votes than Branch2.2 and Branch2.3 = Branch2.1 wins
 - candidate E has more votes than candidate D = candidate E wins
 
 The tree approach thus forces the order of transfer to be non-cyclic. The 
 transfer order of candidate E is E  D  {F, G, H}.
 
 The tree format can be printed on paper and it is easy to grasp. The ballot 
 sheet may also follow the same tree format. Branches may have names (e.g. 
 party names) or be unnamed. Left wing parties could join forces under one 
 branch. Candidates of one party could be divided in smaller groups. Or maybe 
 the branches have no party names and party affiliations, maybe just 
 descriptive names, maybe no branch names at all.
 
 
 Thanks for the example, but I don't understand. Who decides what the branches 
 are, and based on what? Why is E transferring votes if E has the most votes? 
 And what are the counts after each transfer? Sorry if those are dumb 
 questions. 

Maybe the method is simpler than you expected. It could be as well described as 
a list based method where the parties can be internally split in smaller 
groupings (or they can join also together in larger groups). My references to 
vote transfers are just to explain how this method relates to methods that use 
transfers in the vote counting process. The votes that E transfers are 
actually not taken away from him but counted both for him and all the branches 
that contain him (sorry about using such confusing terms). In this method one 
can in a way transfer all the votes right away to the groups that some 
candidate is part of. We thus just count the votes of each party / grouping 
(i.e. sum up the votes to the candidates of that party). Votes are not 
transferred (or summed up) to other candidates but to the branches of the 
tree (= parties, groups) that represent all the candidates within them. The 
formal vote counting rules will probably not use term transfer at all (maybe 
sum instead).

The numbers in the example show the final counts, where the votes (that were 
all given to the candidates) have been summed up. The vote counting rule starts 
simply the biggest party gets the only seat. In this example Branch2 (= 
party2 or wing2) is bigger than Branch1, and therefore the only available seat 
goes to that party. (Note that the tree method could be used as well in 
multi-member elections.) Then that single seat will be allocated within Branch1 
to the biggest of the party internal branches, i.e. Branch2.1, and then to E 
that has more votes than D.

The branches will be decided by the parties or whatever associations or 
groupings the candidates and their supporters will form. Let's say that 
Branch1.1 and Branch 1.2 are two left wing parties that nominated their 
candidates ( {A, B} and {C} ) themselves and then decided to joins forces and 
form a joint branch (Branch1) to beat the right wing candidates (that was not 
enough though since the right wing parties did the same thing and got more 
votes). Or in a two-party country like the U.S. this example would of course be 
Branch1=Democrats, Branch2=Republicans, and then the candidates of these 
parties would form some groups within that party. Branch2.1. could contain two 
similar minded candidates from California. They joined together since they 
understood that if they would both run alone, they would probably be spoilers 
to each others and they could not win. Party internal groupings could thus be 
arranged by the party itself or by the individual candidates that form the 
sub-branch. It would depend on the election rules who is will formally nominate 
such groups (party vs. already nominated candidates vs. whatever group of 
candidates).

From strategic point of view it makes sense to form sub-brances (all the way to 
a binary tree). Within Branch2 sub-branches Branch2.2 and Branch2.3 could have 
also joined forces together (and add one extra level of hierarchy in the tree

Re: [EM] Has this idea been considered?

2011-07-07 Thread Juho Laatu
On 7.7.2011, at 22.54, Russ Paielli wrote:

 Also, consider the fierce opposition that would develop from any group that 
 thinks they would suffer. And who might that be? How about the two major 
 parties! Do you think they would have the power to stop it?

If we assume that one of the main targets of political parties is to get lots 
of votes and lots of power, then any new election method that makes it possible 
that also other parties might win some seats in some elections are something 
that they clearly should oppose. From this point of view all attempts to make a 
two-party system less two-party oriented are doomed.

Actually all administrational systems and organizations resist change for some 
very similar reasons.

From individual representative point of view any changes in the election 
method are extremely risky since they themselves got elected with the old 
method. Changing that to something new might not elect them again. And the old 
method will, with good probability.

IRV is interesting since it looks like a quite radical reform, but it clearly 
favours large parties. Fears of some small party winning a seat are much 
smaller in IRV than e.g. in Condorcet. That may be one reason why IRV has made 
some progress while Condorcet has not.

What didi people think before the nowadays generally agreed idea that all 
countries should be democratic. Maybe some idealists discussed the possibility 
that one day ordinary people might rule the country. I'm sure many others 
laughed at them and told them that such changes are dangerous and will never 
work, particularly since they are not in the interest of the current rulers, 
nor any other rulers that might overthrow the current rulers. So reforms are 
just a joke and idealistic dreams like democracy will never work. There would 
quickly be some new rulers that would kick the poor commoners out and probably 
even kill them.

Today many of us live in democracies and people can make changes if they so 
want. Actually that was the case already before the age of democracy. Changes 
were more difficult to achieve then. Now making such improvements should be 
comparably easy. And despite of having democracy the world is not perfect yet. 
Improvements are still possible. The key problem is actually, as you say, to 
agree on the targets, and make a model that majority of the rulers (voters) 
agree with, and that looks plausible enough so that people can start to believe 
in that change.

 I wish there were a good, viable solution, but I just don't see it happening 
 in the foreseeable future.

We will see.

Juho





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Toby Pereira, PR voting methods

2011-07-07 Thread Juho Laatu
The intended difference was that in option 2 one can use any optimization 
algorithm, and after some time we will see who has found the best slate, while 
in the proposed new variant of the option we would have a known algorithm, that 
would be run with known previously agreed parameters. And after that program 
would finish running, we would know who the winner is. The end result should be 
in most cases the same. The only difference is to have an agreed method vs. a 
competition on who can find the best slate in some agreed time.

Juho



On 8.7.2011, at 1.05, Toby Pereira wrote:

 I'm not sure I exactly followed that. Jameson's option 2 is to look at the 
 nominated slates and see which is best. You could also still use one of the 
 other methods to find a possible winner and then compare it with the best 
 nominated slate (if they are different). Is that anything like what you're 
 saying?
 
 From: Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk
 To: election-methods Methods election-meth...@electorama.com
 Sent: Thu, 7 July, 2011 22:51:45
 Subject: Re: [EM] Toby Pereira, PR voting methods
 
 I'd like to add one more option. It is actually close to option 2 below. 
 Specify separately how to compare two slates (which one is better) and what 
 optimization algorithm will be used when trying to find the best slate. The 
 optimization algorithm may change from one election to the next, but the 
 comparison rule stays the same. Also in this method algorithmic improvements 
 can improve the method.
 
 Juho
 
 
 On 7.7.2011, at 23.17, Jameson Quinn wrote:
 
 Assume you have some way to score the goodness of a slate of 
 representatives. You want to find the best possible such slate, but you 
 don't have the computational resources to score all possible slates. The 
 options are:
 
 1. Add candidates one at a time. Advantages: deterministic and simple. 
 Disadvantages: not very optimal.
 2. Use the best nominated slate. Advantages: takes advantage of any future 
 algorithmic improvements without needing new rules. Disadvantage: could 
 provide an edge to those with more computational resources; requires time 
 for people to nominate slates.
 3. Add candidates N at a time, with N being as big as your computer can 
 handle.
 
 All of the above have been discussed. But there's another possibility, which 
 is probably better than 3:
 
 4. One out and two in - at each step, find the best slate which differs 
 from the prior step by removing M candidates and then adding M+N. This is 
 almost certainly computationally feasible for N=M=1.
 
 2011/7/7 Toby Pereira tdp2...@yahoo.co.uk
 On my web page where I describe my Proportional Range Voting System 
 (http://www.tobypereira.co.uk/voting.html), I have suggested that it should 
 be possible for a computer to sort out the result in a reasonable amount of 
 time. Of course, this may not actually be the case considering the number of 
 possible winning sets of candidates that you might get in some elections.
  
 So as with other systems, a sequential system could be used. Calculate who 
 would be the winning candidate in a single-winner election and then find the 
 best combination of two winners, given that the single winner is elected. 
 Then with these two elected, find the best combination of three and so on. 
 Then if this takes it too far the other way and makes it too easy for a 
 computer to calculate you can select candidates in blocks of two or three. I 
 think I've seen Forest Simmons and others discussing this hybrid version of 
 sequential/non-sequential systems.
  
 I think this would still be a very different system to Reweighted Range 
 Voting, especially consdering that it elects single winners in a different 
 way.
 
 From: Warren Smith warren@gmail.com
 To: election-methods election-meth...@electorama.com
 Sent: Sun, 3 July, 2011 20:25:35
 Subject: [EM] Toby Pereira, PR voting methods
 
 Two are RRV
   http://rangevoting.org/RRV.html
 and asset voting
   http://rangevoting.org/Asset.html
 
 A recent real-world election that used RRV is described here:
   June2011RealWorldRRVvotes.txt
 
 In T.P.'s essay it'd be nice if he subdivided it into smaller chunks
 with subheading titles, and summarized whatever he concluded
 concisely.
 
 -- 
 Warren D. Smith
 http://RangeVoting.org  -- add your endorsement (by clicking
 endorse as 1st step)
 and
 math.temple.edu/~wds/homepage/works.html
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
 
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Learning from IRV's success

2011-07-07 Thread Juho Laatu
I actually already touched this question in another mail. And the argument was 
that (in two-party countries) IRV is not as risky risky from the two leading 
parties' point of view as methods that are more compromise candidate oriented 
(instead of being first preference oriented). I think that is one reason, but 
it is hard to estimate how important.

Juho



On 7.7.2011, at 23.56, Jameson Quinn wrote:

 Russ's message about simplicity is well-taken. But the most successful voting 
 reform is IRV - which is far from being the simplest reform. Why has IRV been 
 successful?
 
 I want to leave this as an open question for others before I try to answer it 
 myself. The one answer which wouldn't be useful would be Because CVD (now 
 FairVote) was looking for a single-winner version of STV. There's a bit of 
 truth there, but it's a long way from the whole truth, and we want to find 
 lessons we can learn from moving forward, not useless historical accidents.
 
 JQ
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Has this idea been considered?

2011-07-08 Thread Juho Laatu
On 8.7.2011, at 8.55, Russ Paielli wrote:

 On Thu, Jul 7, 2011 at 3:32 PM, Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk wrote:
 
 What didi people think before the nowadays generally agreed idea that all 
 countries should be democratic. Maybe some idealists discussed the 
 possibility that one day ordinary people might rule the country. I'm sure 
 many others laughed at them and told them that such changes are dangerous and 
 will never work, particularly since they are not in the interest of the 
 current rulers, nor any other rulers that might overthrow the current rulers. 
 So reforms are just a joke and idealistic dreams like democracy will never 
 work. There would quickly be some new rulers that would kick the poor 
 commoners out and probably even kill them.
 
 
 I'll probably get a bit off topic here, but I think it is important to 
 understand that democracy itself is almost worthless without Constitutionally 
 guaranteed individual rights (as distinct from bogus group rights). That's 
 what the American revolution was all about. The founders certainly did not 
 want a pure democracy. They know very well where that majority rule would 
 lead a tyranny of the majority. That's why they gave us the Bill of Rights.

I think we are on our way from laws of jungle to something more civilized. We 
can invent better and more fine tuned models on how we should operate in order 
to achieve whatever we want to achieve. This is not completely off topic since 
decision making methods are one essential component and tool in making our 
societies work well.

 
 The main problem with our political system today is that far too few people 
 understand what freedom and individual rights mean. The Bill of Rights is 
 just the start of it. Property rights are essential to any real notion of 
 freedom, and they are also essential to prosperity. When half the population 
 thinks the gov't should take from those who have too much and give to 
 others who don't have enough, we are in trouble. Yet that's exactly where 
 we are. The greatest election methods in the world cannot save us from those 
 kind of voters.

Yes, not too much of that, although most societies of course expect those that 
are well off to take care of those that would otherwise be in trouble.

 
 Are some CEOs overpaid? Yes, I think some are. I happen to believe that some 
 CEOs and boards are ripping off their own shareholders, and I would like to 
 see the gov't do something to give shareholders more say in the matter. But 
 the solution is not to just arbitrarily raise taxes on the rich, as so many 
 want to do. People who don't understant the distinction are dangerous, 
 because they fundamentally believe that the gov't really owns everything and 
 let's us keep some of it out of sheer benevolence. If the gov't really owns 
 everything, it owns you too.

One interesting question is if government is considered to be us or them or 
it. I tend to think that the government and rest of the society (like 
companies) should serve the people, not the other way around. In a well working 
democracy we can decide how those structures serve us in the best possible way 
(allowing e.g. freedom and wealth to all).

 
  
 Today many of us live in democracies and people can make changes if they so 
 want. Actually that was the case already before the age of democracy. Changes 
 were more difficult to achieve then. Now making such improvements should be 
 comparably easy. And despite of having democracy the world is not perfect 
 yet. Improvements are still possible. The key problem is actually, as you 
 say, to agree on the targets, and make a model that majority of the rulers 
 (voters) agree with, and that looks plausible enough so that people can start 
 to believe in that change.
 
 
 The fundamental problem now is that too many of us actually want to go back 
 to a state in which gov't is our master rather than our servant. If gov't can 
 arbitrarily take from you when it thinks you have too much, it is the master, 
 and we are the servants. Why is that so hard for some to understand?

I think this is a chicken and egg problem. If government is us, then all the 
money it takes is because we have agreed to proceed that way. In practice 
things are more complicated, and governments easily become money hungry beasts 
that take and spend all the money they can grab.

If we go back to the EM topics, good methods need good and simple and credible 
models and philosophies to allow regular people (voters) to make sensible 
decisions on which routes to take. One does not work well without the other.

Juho


 
 --Russ P.
 
 -- 
 http://RussP.us
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Composite methods (Re: Eric Maskin promotes the Black method)

2011-07-08 Thread Juho Laatu
On 8.7.2011, at 11.00, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 But now consider a parallel universe where the CW always won (and these 
 victories were significant, i.e. people really preferred the CW to the rest). 
 Say Montroll won. Then Kiss-supporters and Wright-supporters might try to 
 unite in the feeling that Montroll wasn't what they wanted (we don't want 
 any steenkin centrists); but if they tried so, there would be a majority who 
 did like Montroll (because he was the CW), and therefore these could block 
 the repeal if it came to a referendum.

Condorcet methods are majority oriented, but unfortunately CW has majority only 
in pairwise comparisons. Majority of the voters would choose the centrist 
rather than X. But it is possible that majority of that majority would want Y 
rather than the centrist. And quite typically majority of the voters prefer 
someone else to the CW.

In a two-party oriented political system both major parties would prefer a 
centrist to the candidate of the other major party. But if they think 
carefully, maybe it would after all be in their interest to just accept the 
fact that the major parties rule each 50% of the time, instead of e.g. the 
centrists ruling 50% of the time, leaving 25% to each of the major parties.

In other words, in order to change the basic rules of distributing power in a 
society one may need also some good will from those currently in power and some 
general support to the new way of distributing power. In societies that are 
based on one party taking all the power after winning the election, giving that 
power to some minor party, or having more than two major parties rotating in 
power (with not much more than 33% support) may be problematic. Also Condorcet 
combined with single seat districts might not provide what people want. One may 
thus need to rethink the whole system to make people accept it and find the 
majority concept of Condorcet methods ideal for them.

CW is ideal for many single winner decisions but the dynamics of the society 
may also work against it. And one may need to be ready to change more than just 
the election method to make the new rules work well.

Juho





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Learning from IRV's success

2011-07-08 Thread Juho Laatu
On 8.7.2011, at 17.16, Andy Jennings wrote:

 Also, I think IRV's seemingly intuitive nature has something to do with it. 
 For those who *did* investigate more deeply, IRV seemed sensible, too: 
 instead of holding a bunch of expensive runoffs, collect all the required 
 information at once and then act as if there were runoffs. That fails to 
 account for the dynamics between the rounds, but that's a subtle detail and 
 might easily be missed.
 
 I, too, must admit that IRV has a natural feeling to it.  I had a friend who 
 described to me a system he thought of on his own and he ended up 
 describing IRV.

I agree with that (as one reason). It is a bit  like natural selection, or a 
like fight of strong men where the weakest ones must leave the arena first.

Juho





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Composite methods (Re: Eric Maskin promotes the Black method)

2011-07-08 Thread Juho Laatu
Some more observations.

Party officials and representatives have more weight in decision making than 
regular voters. The opinions of regular supporters of party A could be 
ACentristB, but the opinions of people whose future and career are tied to 
the party have more ACentristB orientation. Some of them may simply count 
the number of days that they will be in power vs. in opposition. They want to 
rule themselves, not that someone ideologically close to them rules. From that 
point of view a two-party system may be better than one that allows also small 
parties that are ideologically closer to win. Parties that are ideologically 
close may be interpreted also as worst enemies since they may steal votes that 
would otherwise be yours (they might thus even think ABCentrist). These 
people could be more interested in going back to plurality from Condorcet than 
from IRV. And they are the ones that are in power (or have more power than many 
others).

Juho



On 8.7.2011, at 12.43, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 Juho Laatu wrote:
 On 8.7.2011, at 11.00, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:
 But now consider a parallel universe where the CW always won (and
 these victories were significant, i.e. people really preferred the
 CW to the rest). Say Montroll won. Then Kiss-supporters and
 Wright-supporters might try to unite in the feeling that Montroll
 wasn't what they wanted (we don't want any steenkin centrists);
 but if they tried so, there would be a majority who did like
 Montroll (because he was the CW), and therefore these could block
 the repeal if it came to a referendum.
 Condorcet methods are majority oriented, but unfortunately CW has
 majority only in pairwise comparisons. Majority of the voters would
 choose the centrist rather than X. But it is possible that majority
 of that majority would want Y rather than the centrist. And quite
 typically majority of the voters prefer someone else to the CW.
 
 My point is that a majority of a majority isn't enough in a repeal-or-not 
 referendum. If the repeal side can gather only a majority of a majority, 
 while the keep-it side can gather a full majority, the method remains.
 
 In a two-party oriented political system both major parties would
 prefer a centrist to the candidate of the other major party. But if
 they think carefully, maybe it would after all be in their interest
 to just accept the fact that the major parties rule each 50% of the
 time, instead of e.g. the centrists ruling 50% of the time, leaving
 25% to each of the major parties.
 
 The more general concept that you mention is of course true. I was 
 considering Condorcet methods as new methods versus other methods as new 
 methods, and giving a possibility that Condorcet methods might outlast 
 non-Condorcet methods in voting reform.
 
 If society didn't have any bias at all, and could coordinate, it would 
 quickly converge to the method that would do it best. The society would say 
 We don't like the spoiler effect, let's find a way to fix it. But because 
 voting reform is hard, we can assume that doesn't hold true.
 
 So yes, voting reform will be hard, no matter what new method you want to put 
 in place. I'm merely saying that because of dynamics, it might be easier to 
 replace status quo with a Condorcet method (and have the new method last) 
 than it is to do so with a non-Condorcet method (and have *it* last), because 
 majorities can complain more often in the latter case than in the former.
 
 If people are in favor of two-party rule, well, then Plurality will remain. 
 If they want two-party rule with no chance of minor spoilers upsetting the 
 outcome, they may settle on IRV. But even here, Condorcet wouldn't be worse 
 than IRV: if the voters want two parties, then one would assume they'd vote 
 in a manner consistent with it. Third parties wouldn't break free -- because 
 the voters don't want them -- and a cloneproof Condorcet method would keep 
 minor spoilers out of the way.
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Has this idea been considered?

2011-07-08 Thread Juho Laatu
There are many reasons why it is difficult to find a statement that numerous 
people on this list would be willing to sign. As you know there are probably as 
many different opinions on different methods as there are people on this list. 
There have been some related (inconclusive) discussions also earlier on this 
list.

I'll write few comments below to outline some possible problems.

 1. Commonly agreed to be better than approval.

First I'd like to understand what is the target environment for the method. In 
the absence of any explanation I assume that we are looking for a general 
purpose method that could be used for many typical single-winner elections and 
other decision making in potentially competitive environments.

Numerous people on this list may think that Condorcet methods are better. 
People may find also numerous other methods better than approval, but it may be 
more difficult to find many people with firm and similar opinions on them.

 2. Commonly agreed to be simple for an average voter to feel that they 
 understand what's going on.


Different societies may have very different expectations here, depending on 
what they are used to. Maybe Condorcet voting (ranking) is considered simple 
enough. Maybe the voters need to understand only how to vote, not how to count 
the results.

Some more reasons why people may have problems with signing the statement.
- there is no statement yet
- they don't understand or agree that these two targets would be the key 
targets (why just better than approval, what do the voters need to understand, 
what is simple)
- they may think that there should be more targets or less targets
- it might be easier to find an agreement on even smaller statements, one at a 
time
- this proposal would not meet the needs of their own default target 
environment (maybe some specific society) (maybe their current method is 
already better)
- they are afraid of making public statements that they might regret later
- they don't want to take part in web campaigns in general (e.g. because their 
primary focus is in their academic or other career)
- they are simply too uncertain and therefore stay silent
- there might be one sentence in the statement that they don't like (or one 
method)
- this initiative was not their own initiative
- they have a personal agenda and this initiative does not directly support it 
(maybe some favourite method, or some particular campaign, maybe this 
initiative competes with their agenda)
- technical arguments

I hope you will find some agreements. But I'm not very hopeful if the target is 
to find an agreement of numerous persons on numerous questions. Maybe if the 
statement would be very simple. One approach would be to make a complete 
personal statement and then try to get some support to it (maybe with comments).

Juho



On 8.7.2011, at 19.47, Jameson Quinn wrote:

 I'm sorry, but aarrhh.
 
 I think that people on this list are smart, but this is pathetic. I don't 
 mean to be hard on Dave in particular. But why is it impossible to get any 
 two of us to agree on anything? I want to make a list of systems which are
 
 1. Commonly agreed to be better than approval.
 2. Commonly agreed to be simple for an average voter to feel that they 
 understand what's going on.
 
 I am not asking each person who responds to choose the best or simplest 
 system according to them. I'm asking everyone to vote in the poll and approve 
 (rate higher than 0) all systems which meet those two very low bars. 
 Hopefully, the result will be a consensus. It will almost certainly not be 
 the two best, simplest systems by any individual's personal reckoning.
 
 As to the specific comments:
 
 2011/7/8 Dave Ketchum da...@clarityconnect.com
 What I see:
 . Condorcet - without mixing in Approval.
 
 You need some cycle-breaker. Implicit approval is the only order-N tiebreaker 
 I know; fundamentally simpler than any order-N² tiebreaker like minimax. You 
 don't have to call it approval if you don't like the name.
  
 . SODA - for trying, but seems too complex.
 
 I disagree, but I'm biased. I feel that approve any number of candidates or 
 let your favorite candidate do it for you; most approvals wins is easy to 
 understand. But I can understand if people disagree, so I'm not criticizing 
 this logic.
  
 . Reject Approval - too weak to compete.
 
 Worse than plurality
 
 JQ
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Challenge: two-party methods

2011-07-09 Thread Juho Laatu
On 9.7.2011, at 14.23, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 Juho Laatu wrote:
 After some recent discussions and thoughts around two-party systems I
 thought it would be interesting to discuss two-party systems also in
 a more positive spirit. The assumption is thus that we want the
 system to be two-party oriented. We want to have two strong parties,
 and one of them should rule. We want to allow only well established
 parties with wide support to rule. The first obvious approach is to
 ban all other parties than the two leading parties. But maybe we
 don't want  to be so brutal. Let's not ban the possibly already
 existing, much liked and hopeful third parties. It is also good to
 have some competition in the system. Let's not allow the two leading
 parties think that they don't have to care about the voters and they
 can do whatever they want, and stay in power forever.
 What would be a good such method? In addition to what was already
 said we surely want e.g. to avoid the classical spoiler problems.
 
 I can think of two simple PR-based methods.
 
 In the first, you use ordinary divisor-based PR, but set the divisors so that 
 they have a great large-party bias (even worse than D'Hondt).

It seems that this method would favour large parties so that they would get 
lots of seats, and it would make sense to generally vote for them. One problem 
with respect to the targets might be that small parties may have problems to 
grow since votes to them have less weight than votes to large parties. If left 
wing gets 50% of the votes, and in the right wing there are two parties, 35% 
and 15%, then left wing gets majority. The small party was a spoiler to the 
right wing.

 
 In the second, you also use ordinary divisor-based PR, but top up the list of 
 the largest party so that it always gets 50%+1 of the seats if it would 
 otherwise get below that.

It seems that also here we may have a spoiler problem. In situation 40: L1, 10: 
L2, 40: R1, 10: R2 any additional voters moving from a 40% group to the 10% 
group of the same wing would be spoilers.

 
 But I think that any two-party system will discourage smaller parties. If 
 only the two major parties can rule, voters will strategically think that 
 either I can use my vote to grant the lesser evil more seats/power so it can 
 defeat the greater evil, or I can use my vote to vote for a small party that 
 hasn't got a chance beyond being the opposition anyway. I'll do the former. 
 That sort of thinking will create an invisible barrier to third parties, 
 because as long as the third parties aren't large enough that they might win 
 (become one of the top two) with a small amount of additional votes, voters 
 won't vote for them, and if they don't vote for them, they'll never get close 
 enough to the threshold.

There might be irrational fears, that may be based on how the old methods have 
worked. The target is anyway to make such fears irrational. The intention is 
that although my favourite small party can not win this election, it is quite 
possible that it will win in the next election, or one after that.

Even If the votes are now 50: A, 45: BCA, 5: CBA, next time they could be 
50: A, 35: BCA, 15: CBA, and next time 50: A, 24: BCA, 26: CBA. C 
should thus be able to grow without disturbing the balance between A and {B, 
C}. (These votes should work in the method that I proposed.)

 
 I can think of two ways to get around that, but both would bend the 
 definition of a two-party system.
 
 Let's call the first an explicit coalition system. The election process 
 itself is party list PR. After the election is done, a group of parties with 
 a total vote share greater than a majority must form a coalition; they do so 
 by an internal supermajority vote, after which this group gets the government 
 and the rest becomes the opposition.
 After that is done, they rule until at least one of the parties (or some 
 fraction of the whole group), plus the opposition (or supermajority thereof), 
 agrees to dissolve the current coalition. After that is done, there are new 
 elections. The current coalition rules until the next coalition can organize 
 itself.

Are you saying that actually many multi-party systems (that work pretty much in 
the described way) are actually single-party governments, and therefore the 
system is essentially a government vs. opposition system, and that would make 
it effectively a two-party system? It is true that governments typically have a 
unified policy, and the opposition takes the opposite position. Technically 
this approach meets the two targets that I set, but I was thinking of somewhat 
more stable parties, not ones that would be redesigned after every election 
based on the results that the numerous smaller parties that participate in the 
election do get :-).

(Note that I wrote the targets for a single-winner election (they talk about 
electing one of the candidates) and we have now expanded the discussion also to 
multi-winner

Re: [EM] Challenge: two-party methods

2011-07-09 Thread Juho Laatu
On 9.7.2011, at 16.14, James Gilmour wrote:

 Juho Laatu   Sent: Saturday, July 09, 2011 10:35 AM
 After some recent discussions and thoughts around two-party 
 systems I thought it would be interesting to discuss 
 two-party systems also in a more positive spirit. The 
 assumption is thus that we want the system to be two-party 
 oriented. We want to have two strong parties, and one of them 
 should rule. We want to allow only well established parties 
 with wide support to rule. The first obvious approach is to 
 ban all other parties than the two leading parties. But maybe 
 we don't want  to be so brutal. Let's not ban the possibly 
 already existing, much liked and hopeful third parties. It is 
 also good to have some competition in the system. Let's not 
 allow the two leading parties think that they don't have to 
 care about the voters and they can do whatever they want, and 
 stay in power forever.
 
 This is a very strange proposal, all the more so because your principal 
 objective is not clear.  Is your objective to manipulate the
 voting system so that all the smaller parties are more or less crushed out of 
 the political system, leaving only two?

The idea is not to manipulate a working system but to provide an ideal 
two-party system. The rules and ideals of a two-party system may be different 
from other systems, so the method may seem strange if seen as a proposal for 
some other kind of elections (e.g. for multi-party countries). There may thus 
be different elections with different kind of requirements. Here the 
requirement is to allow the strongest parties to rule (except that it must be 
possible also for the small parties to become large parties one day). Small 
parties are thus not crushed out of the political system. They are not allowed 
to win yet, but they are well nursed in the hope that one day they will become 
large parties.

  Or is your
 objective to ensure single-party majority government where the government 
 comes directly from the national elections?

The target is to have a single-party government. Majority of voters should 
prefer it over the second largest party (in my example method at least) but 
there is no requirement of having an absolute majority of first preferences (in 
my example the votes were rankings, so the winner may be ranked e.g. second in 
many ballots).

 
 The first of these is not, to my mind, compatible with any definition of 
 democracy.

Ok, I think I escaped that criterion although the intention is not to let the 
small parties rule tis time.

 
 If single-party majority government is the objective, that is very easy to 
 implement.  If no party (in fairly representative
 elections) wins more than half of the seats, allocate 55% of the seats to the 
 party with most votes nationally and divide the
 remaining seats proportionately among the remaining parties.  This has 
 already been done in national public elections, e.g. in Italy
 in the 1920s, when the 'premium' was two-thirds not 55%.

One of the targets was to avoid the spoiler problem. I think in this method a 
small party could reduce the votes of the otherwise largest party so that it 
loses its 55% position.

 
 Assuming you are suggesting this in the context of electing an assembly 
 (national or regional parliament) and not a single-winner
 election (state governor or president)

I talked about single winners in the sense that one party will rule. This could 
mean electing one single president, electing the only representative of a 
single-winner district, or electing an assembly so that it would clearly 
delegate power to one of the large parties (as in the 55% rule).

 , it is very interesting to note what happened in Malta after STV-PR was 
 introduced some 80
 years ago.  Before STV-PR was introduced AND for the first 40 years of its 
 use, candidates from three, four or five parties were
 elected to the Parliament at each election, but for the past 40 years only 
 two parties have been represented in the Parliament.  If
 you believe at all in representative democracy I think it is much the best to 
 leave that aspect of party dynamics to the voters.

I do believe in representative democracy where each section of the voters if 
properly represented in the system. The voters might be split in two or more 
sections, or i no clear sections at all (if e.g. the representation is strongly 
individual based, not party based).

On the other hand a two-party system could be considered a valid form of 
democracy too. In the challenge I tried to seek new approaches to implementing 
two-aprty systems. One could characterize two-party systems so that the 
intention is that the dividing line between the two parties represents the 
median voter. The two parties are expected to change their opinions in time so 
that the median point can be found (otherwise the opposition party will remain 
in opposition for a long time). The most common methods, plurality with 
single-winner districts

Re: [EM] Challenge: two-party methods

2011-07-09 Thread Juho Laatu
 was to improve the system to allow them to grow. 
Another approach in a two-party system would be to allow them to rule 
(together with others or alone) already without growing. And also in 
proportional multi-part systems that is an interesting question (actually there 
I have actively promoted the idea that they should be allowed to have their 
proportional share of representation, without the limits set by thresholds, 
district sizes and related mechanisms).

Juho





 
 James
 
 
 
 Juho Laatu   Sent: Saturday, July 09, 2011 2:53 PM
 
 On 9.7.2011, at 16.14, James Gilmour wrote:
 Juho Laatu   Sent: Saturday, July 09, 2011 10:35 AM
 After some recent discussions and thoughts around two-party
 systems I thought it would be interesting to discuss 
 two-party systems also in a more positive spirit. The 
 assumption is thus that we want the system to be two-party 
 oriented. We want to have two strong parties, and one of them 
 should rule. We want to allow only well established parties 
 with wide support to rule. The first obvious approach is to 
 ban all other parties than the two leading parties. But maybe 
 we don't want  to be so brutal. Let's not ban the possibly 
 already existing, much liked and hopeful third parties. It is 
 also good to have some competition in the system. Let's not 
 allow the two leading parties think that they don't have to 
 care about the voters and they can do whatever they want, and 
 stay in power forever.
 
 This is a very strange proposal, all the more so because your 
 principal objective is not clear.  Is your objective to manipulate the 
 voting system so that all the smaller parties are more or  less crushed 
 out of the political system, leaving only two?
 
 The idea is not to manipulate a working system but to provide 
 an ideal two-party system. The rules and ideals of a 
 two-party system may be different from other systems, so the 
 method may seem strange if seen as a proposal for some other 
 kind of elections (e.g. for multi-party countries). There may 
 thus be different elections with different kind of 
 requirements. Here the requirement is to allow the strongest 
 parties to rule (except that it must be possible also for the 
 small parties to become large parties one day). Small parties 
 are thus not crushed out of the political system. They are 
 not allowed to win yet, but they are well nursed in the hope 
 that one day they will become large parties.
 
 Or is your
 objective to ensure single-party majority government where the 
 government comes directly from the national elections?
 
 The target is to have a single-party government. Majority of 
 voters should prefer it over the second largest party (in my 
 example method at least) but there is no requirement of 
 having an absolute majority of first preferences (in my 
 example the votes were rankings, so the winner may be ranked 
 e.g. second in many ballots).
 
 
 The first of these is not, to my mind, compatible with any definition 
 of democracy.
 
 Ok, I think I escaped that criterion although the intention 
 is not to let the small parties rule tis time.
 
 
 If single-party majority government is the objective, that is very 
 easy to implement.  If no party (in fairly representative
 elections) wins more than half of the seats, allocate 55% 
 of the seats to the party with most votes nationally and divide the
 remaining seats proportionately among the remaining 
 parties.  This has already been done in national public elections, e.g. in 
 Italy
 in the 1920s, when the 'premium' was two-thirds not 55%.
 
 One of the targets was to avoid the spoiler problem. I think 
 in this method a small party could reduce the votes of the 
 otherwise largest party so that it loses its 55% position.
 
 
 Assuming you are suggesting this in the context of electing an 
 assembly (national or regional parliament) and not a single-winner 
 election (state governor or president)
 
 I talked about single winners in the sense that one party 
 will rule. This could mean electing one single president, 
 electing the only representative of a single-winner district, 
 or electing an assembly so that it would clearly delegate 
 power to one of the large parties (as in the 55% rule).
 
 , it is very interesting to note what happened in Malta after STV-PR 
 was introduced some 80 years ago.  Before STV-PR was introduced AND 
 for the first 40 years of its use, candidates from three, four or five 
 parties were elected to the Parliament at each election, but for the 
 past 40 years only two parties have been represented in the 
 Parliament.  If you believe at all in representative democracy I think 
 it is much the best to leave that aspect of party dynamics to the 
 voters.
 
 I do believe in representative democracy where each section 
 of the voters if properly represented in the system. The 
 voters might be split in two or more sections, or i no clear 
 sections at all (if e.g. the representation is strongly 
 individual based

Re: [EM] Two Party Challenge

2011-07-09 Thread Juho Laatu
On 9.7.2011, at 22.23, fsimm...@pcc.edu wrote:

 Here's an idea.
 
 First pick a party (with full knowledge who the candidates are in each party).
 
 Then hold an open primary to pick the winning candidate from the winning 
 party.

This sounds like a two-phase single winner election. The first used 
single-winner method should maybe be such that it elects major parties only 
(i.e. no weak compromise parties). I'm not sure the short description yet 
guarantees a two-party rule. The idea of ordering a late primary is an 
interesting approach to allowing multiple candidates for each party but still 
keeping the method simple (two election days probably needed but otherwise nice 
and clear).

Juho





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Challenge: two-party methods

2011-07-10 Thread Juho Laatu
First I'll try to clarify the definitions a bit. It is so obvious what a 
two-party system is, but when I think more carefully it is not that clear.

Two-party system:
- has a single-party government
- one of the two major parties forms the government and the other one forms 
(the main part of) the opposition
- the two major parties alternate in government and opposition roles
- has typically one or more representative bodies
- government may be elected directly (e.g. the president of the U.S.) or based 
on the power balance of a representative body
- government has typically or often majority support in the representative 
bodies (this means that third parties are usually small enough not to disturb 
the bipolar balance)
- members of the representative bodies come typically but not necessarily from 
small districts with few representatives, often elected using single-winner 
methods


On 10.7.2011, at 12.03, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 Juho Laatu wrote:
 On 9.7.2011, at 14.23, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:
 Juho Laatu wrote:
 After some recent discussions and thoughts around two-party
 systems I thought it would be interesting to discuss two-party
 systems also in a more positive spirit. The assumption is thus
 that we want the system to be two-party oriented. We want to have
 two strong parties, and one of them should rule. We want to allow
 only well established parties with wide support to rule. The
 first obvious approach is to ban all other parties than the two
 leading parties. But maybe we don't want  to be so brutal. Let's
 not ban the possibly already existing, much liked and hopeful
 third parties. It is also good to have some competition in the
 system. Let's not allow the two leading parties think that they
 don't have to care about the voters and they can do whatever they
 want, and stay in power forever. What would be a good such
 method? In addition to what was already said we surely want e.g.
 to avoid the classical spoiler problems.
 I can think of two simple PR-based methods.
 In the first, you use ordinary divisor-based PR, but set the
 divisors so that they have a great large-party bias (even worse
 than D'Hondt).
 It seems that this method would favour large parties so that they
 would get lots of seats, and it would make sense to generally vote
 for them. One problem with respect to the targets might be that small
 parties may have problems to grow since votes to them have less
 weight than votes to large parties. If left wing gets 50% of the
 votes, and in the right wing there are two parties, 35% and 15%, then
 left wing gets majority. The small party was a spoiler to the right
 wing.
 
 It's relatively simple to get around such troubles: just slap an Asset
 patch on it. For that matter, you could have Asset with the requirement
 that the negotiations don't end until one of the parties has greater
 than a majority of the assets.

One problem here is that we are slipping away from a two-party dominance 
towards a system where the ruling party is dependent on the support of smaller 
parties. That gets close to a coalition government although I understood that 
the government would consist of representatives of one party only. The 
government probably does not have majority in the representative body, so other 
parties may stop progress and cancel their support to the government at any 
time.

I was also worried that the right wing will not get 50% of the seats although 
they got 50% of the votes because of the method that favours large parties. The 
small party may thus spoil the election also this way.

 
 In the second, you also use ordinary divisor-based PR, but top up
 the list of the largest party so that it always gets 50%+1 of the
 seats if it would otherwise get below that.
 It seems that also here we may have a spoiler problem. In situation
 40: L1, 10: L2, 40: R1, 10: R2 any additional voters moving from a
 40% group to the 10% group of the same wing would be spoilers.
 
 Same response :-)

Is it then so that the largest coalition will get 50%+1 seats? Maybe the 
largest coalition based on given votes, not based on the seats that they would 
win without this rule (to cancel the balance shifting effect of the method that 
favours large parties) (?).

 
 If you want to deal directly with the spoiler problem, you'd need a
 method that has the property that it grants every party a score, and
 that cloning groups of parties gives one of the group of parties (since
 the method can't know which are clones) the same score as the original
 party would have if there was no cloning.

That is one approach. That sounds pretty much like an exactly proportional 
method. Usually two-party countries don't have good proportionally in the 
representative bodies (except maybe between the two major parties). In the USA 
the representative bodies are clearly dominated by two parties (in the UK less 
so). Also my example method would allow third parties to get seats in the 
representative

<    1   2   3   4   5   >