RE: Re: Re: Re: Re: RE: Re: re: re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-10 Thread Devine, James

 There _is_ a similarity between religious thinking and Marxian thinking,
i.e., there is a hard core of concepts and even theories that cannot be
falsified. But scientific thinking says (1) that such concepts should be
clearly identified; (2) their role should be minimized relative to the size
of the corpus of scientific thought. 

Thus, I acknowledge that Marx's law of value is a true-by-definition
accounting framework (an alternative to using prices in accounting) that is
used by Marx to break through the fetishism of commodities and thus to
figure out the basic nature  workings of the capitalist mode of production.
But if people stop with that, it's worthless (except as an absolutely
necessary component in understanding Marx). Thus, my research on value
emphasizes the utility of value, applying value concepts to address new
questions. 

-- Jim Devine

-Original Message-
From: Ken Hanly
To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: 2/9/02 6:04 PM
Subject: [PEN-L:22680] Re: Re: Re: Re: RE: Re: re: re: Historical
Materialism

My fuzzy understanding of this is that the hard core of  tautologies
nevertheless supports if the theory is progressive a research program
creating theories that are empirically testable and/or useful in
explaining
empirical data. Most religious theories would employ supernatural
entites
such as a deity or deities in explaining events whereas Marxists avoid
use
of such concepts. There is a certain affinity between the tautological
core
concepts of  some aspects of  Marxism and many theological therories in
that
they are not themselves subject to empirical disconfirmation directly. I
suppose just as Candide found that this is the best of all possible
worlds
was not a very positive research project and lose faith in religions
many
think the same of showing the ultimate revolutionary overthrow of
capitalism
by the working class and lose faith in Marxism.
Can't theories have explanatory power interpret events, make sense
of
them, in an illuminating way even though they may not directly predict
precisely what will happen. Religious theories can give meaning to
individual lives by enabling individual to see the world in terms of
some
basic conceptions, Marxism can play a similar role in peoples lives.

Cheers, Ken Hanly
- Original Message -
From: Ian Murray [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Monday, February 04, 2002 6:24 PM
Subject: [PEN-L:22358] Re: Re: Re: RE: Re: re: re: Historical
Materialism



 - Original Message -
 From: Ken Hanly [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 Sent: Friday, February 01, 2002 10:13 PM
 Subject: [PEN-L:22213] Re: Re: RE: Re: re: re: Historical
 Materialism


 I don't understand this stuff about the observational consequences
 of
 theories at the level of generality of the theory of value. What if
 the
 labor theory of value is part of the central core of Marxism ? If
 that is so
 then in itself it does not have any specific empirical implications
 period.
 Jim Devine seems to take a position of this sort in a piece on
 the web:

 Marx's goals for the LoV were to analyze the societal
  nature and laws of motion of the capitalism; another way of
  saying this is that the LoV summarizes the method of analysis
  that Marx applies in Capital. The LoV is part of what Imre
  Lakatos [1970] terms the hard core of tautologies and
  simplifying assumptions that is a necessary part of any research
  program.1 The quantitative aspect of value should be seen as a
  true-by-definition accounting framework to be used to break
  through the fetishism of commodities -- allowing the analysis of
  capitalism as a social system. Prices, the accounting framework
  most used by economists, both reflect existing social relations
  and distort their appearance. It is necessary to have an
  alternative to prices if one wants to understand what is going
  on behind the level of appearances: looking at what people do
  in production (i.e., labor, value) helps reveal the social
  relations between them.

 If this interpretation is correct then Quine-Duhem's stuff is
 irrelevant not
 that it makes much sense to me anyway. Seems like a neanderthal
 idea to
 speak of theories implying empirical consequences just like that
 without
 assumptions conditions etc. assumed: or of  evidence
 straightforwardly
 supporting a theory. So the Quine-Duhem stuff is not relevant and
 even if it
 were why should it be given any particular weight?  Is  it any less
 dubious
 than the Marxian theory of value?

 Cheers, Ken Hanly

 

 Ok but then what's to stop such skepticism creep? What makes any
 theory non-dubious if not observational consequences? This puts of
 lot of theories on the same level as theology, no?

 Ian





Re: Re: Re: Re: RE: Re: re: re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-09 Thread Ken Hanly

My fuzzy understanding of this is that the hard core of  tautologies
nevertheless supports if the theory is progressive a research program
creating theories that are empirically testable and/or useful in explaining
empirical data. Most religious theories would employ supernatural entites
such as a deity or deities in explaining events whereas Marxists avoid use
of such concepts. There is a certain affinity between the tautological core
concepts of  some aspects of  Marxism and many theological therories in that
they are not themselves subject to empirical disconfirmation directly. I
suppose just as Candide found that this is the best of all possible worlds
was not a very positive research project and lose faith in religions many
think the same of showing the ultimate revolutionary overthrow of capitalism
by the working class and lose faith in Marxism.
Can't theories have explanatory power interpret events, make sense of
them, in an illuminating way even though they may not directly predict
precisely what will happen. Religious theories can give meaning to
individual lives by enabling individual to see the world in terms of some
basic conceptions, Marxism can play a similar role in peoples lives.

Cheers, Ken Hanly
- Original Message -
From: Ian Murray [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Monday, February 04, 2002 6:24 PM
Subject: [PEN-L:22358] Re: Re: Re: RE: Re: re: re: Historical Materialism



 - Original Message -
 From: Ken Hanly [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 Sent: Friday, February 01, 2002 10:13 PM
 Subject: [PEN-L:22213] Re: Re: RE: Re: re: re: Historical
 Materialism


 I don't understand this stuff about the observational consequences
 of
 theories at the level of generality of the theory of value. What if
 the
 labor theory of value is part of the central core of Marxism ? If
 that is so
 then in itself it does not have any specific empirical implications
 period.
 Jim Devine seems to take a position of this sort in a piece on
 the web:

 Marx's goals for the LoV were to analyze the societal
  nature and laws of motion of the capitalism; another way of
  saying this is that the LoV summarizes the method of analysis
  that Marx applies in Capital. The LoV is part of what Imre
  Lakatos [1970] terms the hard core of tautologies and
  simplifying assumptions that is a necessary part of any research
  program.1 The quantitative aspect of value should be seen as a
  true-by-definition accounting framework to be used to break
  through the fetishism of commodities -- allowing the analysis of
  capitalism as a social system. Prices, the accounting framework
  most used by economists, both reflect existing social relations
  and distort their appearance. It is necessary to have an
  alternative to prices if one wants to understand what is going
  on behind the level of appearances: looking at what people do
  in production (i.e., labor, value) helps reveal the social
  relations between them.

 If this interpretation is correct then Quine-Duhem's stuff is
 irrelevant not
 that it makes much sense to me anyway. Seems like a neanderthal
 idea to
 speak of theories implying empirical consequences just like that
 without
 assumptions conditions etc. assumed: or of  evidence
 straightforwardly
 supporting a theory. So the Quine-Duhem stuff is not relevant and
 even if it
 were why should it be given any particular weight?  Is  it any less
 dubious
 than the Marxian theory of value?

 Cheers, Ken Hanly

 

 Ok but then what's to stop such skepticism creep? What makes any
 theory non-dubious if not observational consequences? This puts of
 lot of theories on the same level as theology, no?

 Ian





Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-08 Thread Waistline2
In a message dated 2/8/2002 10:01:20 AM Central Standard Time, [EMAIL PROTECTED] writes:


The measurement of the capital stock is in impossibility. Franklin Fisher
once worked up the requirements for aggregation. Can't be done!

The inability to calculate real depreciation presents another barrier.

I mentioned this in passing before in questioning how seriously we should
take estimates of profit rates as anything more than a rough rule of
thumb.




I absolutely concur with the impossibility of measuring a mode of expression on its own basis, which is the epitome of commodity fetishism. Transformation problem? Indeed. According to whom . . . bourgeois political economy. The question is the velocity of polarization of price and cost from value and why both assume independent modes of expression and finally sperate themselves from value, which in the eyes of the bourgeois is a question of a magnitude of capital yielding a uniform profit. 

But, hey . . . this of course is based on Engels articulation of the nodal line - historical trajectory and conclusion, of value. It was Marx who unfolded the law of value and it remains the amount of socially necessary labor in the production of commodities. 

Melvin


Re: RE: Re: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-08 Thread Rakesh Bhandari

RB writes: Doug thinks Marx was an underconsumptionist; at the same Doug
subscribes to the wage led profit squeeze thesis.

DH writes: See, this is exactly what I was thinking of when I quoted
Callari's observation that VT is a substitute for politics. I don't think
you could ever prove this conclusively one way or the other using numbers.
But in political terms, it's not the least bit ambiguous - the ruling class
felt like it was losing control in the 1970s. Workers were sullen and
rebellious, the U.S. lost the Vietnam War, and the Third World was talking
about a new world economic order. As Paul McCracken's report for the OECD
put it (and I wish I could find this exact quote again, it was a beaut),
anxiety over inflation was inseparable from masses in the streets. The
rebels were crushed.

RB wasn't talking about value theory [VT] above. Instead, he's talking about
a specific crisis theory. That's a different (lower) level of abstraction
than VT. --JD


thanks for the clarification. here is something from Felton Shortall 
that attempts to integrate the two levels (Jim may be interested in 
this book the Incomplete Marx. Avebury, 1994 because it complements 
Michael Lebowitz's argument re: the missing book on wage labor):

Of course intra industry competition will tend to depress 
depreciation charges and hence the imputed value of fixed capital. 
But only to a small degree. If capitals were unable to sustain the 
imputed value of their fixed capital no one would risk investing in 
any industrial capital which had significant proportion of fixed 
capital, since if they did they would face the prospect of the 
devaluation of their capital far outweighing any prospective profit. 
With all the capitals in a particular branch of industry in more or 
less the same boat, the formation of the market value will tend to 
impute the industry's average historic value of fixed capital.

With the preservation of the historic values of fixed capital the 
devaluation of capital due to the increasing social productivity of 
labour becomes deferred. But this gives free play to the effects of 
the rising organic composition of capital on the general rate of 
profit. As capital accumulates on the basis of historic values the 
rate of profit will decline. Sooner or later the critical point is 
reached. Capital has accumulated to such a degreee that it has become 
a barrier to its own self-expansion. Profitable accumulation is at an 
end.

But this is only on the basis of historic values. If capital was 
evaluated ont eh basis of replacment values, if the deferred 
couneracting effects of rising productivity of labor could be brought 
into play, the rate of profit culd be restored to health and 
profitable accumulation resumed. Indeed this is the way capital is 
able to overcome the falling rate of profit as a barrier to further 
accumulation. Through rupture and crisis the long pent up devaluation 
of capital is released all at once. The old structure of historic 
values are forcibly reduced to that of the new. But this does not 
only mean the simple devaluation of capital, but also its widespread 
destruction; its devalorization, bankruptcy and ruin.  p. 404

Yet Shortall seems to me perhaps too sanguine about the ability of 
rupture and crisis to restore in themselves the profitability of 
capital!

Rakesh









Premises, Circularities etc was Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-07 Thread Carrol Cox



Ian Murray wrote:
 
 
 =
 As Blaug and others have pointed out, the LTV has circularities of
 it's own.

I suspect I'm over my head here both re political economy 
epistemology, or whatever is at stake, But I think I'll butt in anyhow.

In _German Ideology_ (I'm paraphrasing from memory) M/E claim they do
have premises -- namely, actual living individuals. (Actual living is
my insertion to allow for the repudiation of the abstract individual in
the Theses on Feurerbach.) I gloss this as affirming that wherever and
whenever we find outselves we are already caught up in, constituted by,
action (social relations), indepently of which we have no existence. So
now the question is how, under given historical conditions, those actual
individuals (defined by their social relations at any historical point)
allocate their living activity; how do they transform their condition
while reproducing it. And I think that starting out there, we get a LOV
totally different from (e.g.) Ricardo's, and moreover, the only place to
start is with that living human activity, whether or not following it up
brings us back to our premises. In other words, we must _either_ hold to
some form of LOV as fundamental, or we must place outselves outside of
time and space, in a Platonic empyrean, examing the world from outside
as Plato attempts to do in the _Republic_.

Not only neoclassical but all bourgeois forms of political economy
(economics) lead us back either to Plato or to William James's blooming
buzzing chaos. (Quote not accurate but makes the point.)

Carrol

P.S. A philological note: _G.I._ does not, I think, have any independent
validity as a source of Marx's or Engels's thought -- i.e. it is valid
(as a source) only as corrected looking backward from their mature work.
When used in isolation from or independently of that later work it makes
one wish the mice had done a better job of criticism.




RE: Premises, Circularities etc was Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-07 Thread Devine, James


Ian Murray wrote:
 As Blaug and others have pointed out, the LTV [sic] has circularities of
 it's own.

what circularities are those? and why is circularity bad, unless there is
nothing to the theory but circularities? Physics and geometry, for example,
both involve circularities (e.g. force is defined by mass times
acceleration, but mass is defined by force/acceleration and acceleration is
defined by force/mass). Are you following Blaug to accept Popperian
falsification, a criterion that makes _all_ social science (or almost all)
worthless? 

Carrol Cox wrote: 
I suspect I'm over my head here both re political economy 
epistemology, or whatever is at stake, But I think I'll butt in anyhow.

In _German Ideology_ (I'm paraphrasing from memory) M/E claim they do
have premises -- namely, actual living individuals. (Actual living is
my insertion to allow for the repudiation of the abstract individual in
the Theses on Feurerbach.)

in the GI, ME are pretty clear that they're talking about actual living
individuals, not abstract ones.

 I gloss this as affirming that wherever and
whenever we find outselves we are already caught up in, constituted by,
action (social relations), indepently of which we have no existence. So
now the question is how, under given historical conditions, those actual
individuals (defined by their social relations at any historical point)
allocate their living activity; how do they transform their condition
while reproducing it. And I think that starting out there, we get a LOV
totally different from (e.g.) Ricardo's, and moreover, the only place to
start is with that living human activity, whether or not following it up
brings us back to our premises. In other words, we must _either_ hold to
some form of LOV as fundamental, or we must place outselves outside of
time and space, in a Platonic empyrean, examing the world from outside
as Plato attempts to do in the _Republic_.

Not only neoclassical but all bourgeois forms of political economy
(economics) lead us back either to Plato or to William James's blooming
buzzing chaos. (Quote not accurate but makes the point.)

that makes sense to me. 

P.S. A philological note: _G.I._ does not, I think, have any independent
validity as a source of Marx's or Engels's thought -- i.e. it is valid
(as a source) only as corrected looking backward from their mature work.
When used in isolation from or independently of that later work it makes
one wish the mice had done a better job of criticism.

yes, but the GI and THE THESES ON FEUERBACH present the clearest explanation
of ME's materialist conception of history. 
-- Jim Devine




Re: RE: Premises, Circularities etc was Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-07 Thread Justin Schwartz


Ian Murray wrote:
  As Blaug and others have pointed out, the LTV [sic] has circularities of
  it's own.

what circularities are those? and why is circularity bad, unless there is
nothing to the theory but circularities? Physics and geometry, for example,
both involve circularities (e.g. force is defined by mass times
acceleration, but mass is defined by force/acceleration and acceleration is
defined by force/mass).

This is a fundamental confusion. Firstly, you talk only about physics and 
not geometry. Geometry proceeds from independent axioms and postulates and 
does not involve circularities. Moreover, the fact that you can rewrite 
equations like F=ma with different variables on the left side of the 
equality does not make physics circular. In fact, the variables are 
implicitly defined in the context of the entire system of equation in which 
they appear.

Are you following Blaug to accept Popperian
falsification, a criterion that makes _all_ social science (or almost all)
worthless?

In defense of Popper, it does not. I am not a Popperian. And Popper was 
(despite the way he is usually taught) an early discoverer of what is called 
the Quine-Duhem thesis, that you can hold any proposition true by making 
appropriate adjustments elsewhere. The unobjecionable point he had tomake 
about falsificationsim is that a hypothesis sin;t worth much if you threat 
it as true come what may, amking it absolutely immune to testing. If all of 
social science is like that, then it is worthless. But that's not what I 
think of as good social science. I do rather suspect that some of the 
defenses of value theory one display lately have smacked of this vice, 
though.

jks



_
Join the world’s largest e-mail service with MSN Hotmail. 
http://www.hotmail.com




RE: Re: RE: Premises, Circularities etc was Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-07 Thread Devine, James

Ian Murray wrote:
 As Blaug and others have pointed out, the LTV [sic] has circularities of
it's own.

I wrote:what circularities are those? and why is circularity bad, unless
there is nothing to the theory but circularities? Physics and geometry, for
example, both involve circularities (e.g. force is defined by mass times
acceleration, but mass is defined by force/acceleration and acceleration is
defined by force/mass).

Justin says:This is a fundamental confusion. Firstly, you talk only about
physics and not geometry. Geometry proceeds from independent axioms and
postulates and does not involve circularities.

no, the definition of major concepts such as a point and a line are
quite circular. If you drop circularities from geometry, you also drop
circles and other geometric forms. 

Moreover, the fact that you can rewrite equations like F=ma with different
variables on the left side of the equality does not make physics circular.

I didn't say that physics was circular. Rather, I said that physics
involve[s] circularity. That's the difference between the proposition that
P = C and that P includes C as a sub-set. 

 In fact, the variables are implicitly defined in the context of the entire
system of equation in which they appear.

that's exactly what I said. Obviously, you have a different definition of
circularity than I do? 

Are you following Blaug to accept Popperian falsification, a criterion that
makes _all_ social science (or almost all) worthless?

In defense of Popper, it does not. I am not a Popperian.

good for you, but I was asking Ian. I'm not a Popperian popover either, but
I think it's a useful thing for social scientists to try to make falsifiable
predictions. In other words, it's good to take intellectual risks. It's also
good to know when one's system is such that different parts are implicitly
defined in the context of the entire theoretical system, so that one knows
the limits of one's thinking. 

And Popper was (despite the way he is usually taught) an early discoverer
of what is called the Quine-Duhem thesis, that you can hold any proposition
true by making appropriate adjustments elsewhere.

good for him. 

The unobjecionable point he had tomake about falsificationsim is that a
hypothesis sin;t [ain't?] worth much if you threat [treat?] it as true come
what may, amking it absolutely immune to testing. If all of social science
is like that, then it is worthless.

All social science that I know of involves _ceteris paribus_ clauses and the
like, which doesn't make the theory worthless (in my eyes), but does make it
non-falsifiable. (The reason why _my_ theory didn't work was because all
else wasn't equal!) 

BTW, the Popperian falsification criterion is itself immune to
falsification.

 But that's not what I think of as good social science.

good. 

I do rather suspect that some of the  defenses of value theory one display
lately have smacked of this vice, though.

which ones? 

JDevine




Re: Re: Re: Re: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-07 Thread Ian Murray


- Original Message - 
From: Justin Schwartz [EMAIL PROTECTED]







The empirical equivalence thesis is part of Q-D, no? Wasn't meaning
to suggest it was the whole shebang.

I don't think so. It's verificationist. Q-D is not. jks

===

And Q-D incorporates the EET precisely to show it's limitations lead to the UTE, no?

Time for some Web of Belief tweaking eh?

Ian





RE: RE: Premises, Circularities etc was Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-07 Thread Brown, Martin - ARP (NCI)

Fortunately for physics there is an independent determinant of mass, that is
gravitational acceleration which, in turn, is determined by the
gravitational field.  So this provides a way out of this particular
circularity. Is it too much to claim that the concepts of labor, labor-power
and the historically determined reproduction value of labor serve a similar
function in political economy? 

-Original Message-
From: Devine, James [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]]
Sent: Thursday, February 07, 2002 10:17 AM
To: '[EMAIL PROTECTED] '
Subject: [PEN-L:22516] RE: Premises, Circularities etc was Re:
Historical Materialism



Ian Murray wrote:
 As Blaug and others have pointed out, the LTV [sic] has circularities of
 it's own.

what circularities are those? and why is circularity bad, unless there is
nothing to the theory but circularities? Physics and geometry, for example,
both involve circularities (e.g. force is defined by mass times
acceleration, but mass is defined by force/acceleration and acceleration is
defined by force/mass). Are you following Blaug to accept Popperian
falsification, a criterion that makes _all_ social science (or almost all)
worthless? 

Carrol Cox wrote: 
I suspect I'm over my head here both re political economy 
epistemology, or whatever is at stake, But I think I'll butt in anyhow.

In _German Ideology_ (I'm paraphrasing from memory) M/E claim they do
have premises -- namely, actual living individuals. (Actual living is
my insertion to allow for the repudiation of the abstract individual in
the Theses on Feurerbach.)

in the GI, ME are pretty clear that they're talking about actual living
individuals, not abstract ones.

 I gloss this as affirming that wherever and
whenever we find outselves we are already caught up in, constituted by,
action (social relations), indepently of which we have no existence. So
now the question is how, under given historical conditions, those actual
individuals (defined by their social relations at any historical point)
allocate their living activity; how do they transform their condition
while reproducing it. And I think that starting out there, we get a LOV
totally different from (e.g.) Ricardo's, and moreover, the only place to
start is with that living human activity, whether or not following it up
brings us back to our premises. In other words, we must _either_ hold to
some form of LOV as fundamental, or we must place outselves outside of
time and space, in a Platonic empyrean, examing the world from outside
as Plato attempts to do in the _Republic_.

Not only neoclassical but all bourgeois forms of political economy
(economics) lead us back either to Plato or to William James's blooming
buzzing chaos. (Quote not accurate but makes the point.)

that makes sense to me. 

P.S. A philological note: _G.I._ does not, I think, have any independent
validity as a source of Marx's or Engels's thought -- i.e. it is valid
(as a source) only as corrected looking backward from their mature work.
When used in isolation from or independently of that later work it makes
one wish the mice had done a better job of criticism.

yes, but the GI and THE THESES ON FEUERBACH present the clearest explanation
of ME's materialist conception of history. 
-- Jim Devine




RE: Re: RE: Premises, Circularities etc was Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-07 Thread Brown, Martin - ARP (NCI)

Re geometry.  I think Goedel's paradox tends to refute your statement.
Trying to get out of this box, however, has resulted in a tremendous series
of advances in mathematics. I was impressed by this in reading a recent
popular account of the history of mathematics leading up to the solution of
Fermat's last theorem.
Re physics.  I made an analogy in my earlier email.  Here is another F=ma is
subsumed by law of the conservation of energy. Physics problems that can be
solved with F=ma can all be solved much more generally and elegantly with
the Hamiltonian approach to conservation of energy, which is a much more
macro description of the problem.  In Marx, is the analogy the macro
conditions for the equivalence of economic aggregates.  

-Original Message-
From: Justin Schwartz [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]]
Sent: Thursday, February 07, 2002 10:49 AM
To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Subject: [PEN-L:22518] Re: RE: Premises, Circularities etc was Re:
Historical Materialism



Ian Murray wrote:
  As Blaug and others have pointed out, the LTV [sic] has circularities of
  it's own.

what circularities are those? and why is circularity bad, unless there is
nothing to the theory but circularities? Physics and geometry, for example,
both involve circularities (e.g. force is defined by mass times
acceleration, but mass is defined by force/acceleration and acceleration is
defined by force/mass).

This is a fundamental confusion. Firstly, you talk only about physics and 
not geometry. Geometry proceeds from independent axioms and postulates and 
does not involve circularities. Moreover, the fact that you can rewrite 
equations like F=ma with different variables on the left side of the 
equality does not make physics circular. In fact, the variables are 
implicitly defined in the context of the entire system of equation in which 
they appear.

Are you following Blaug to accept Popperian
falsification, a criterion that makes _all_ social science (or almost all)
worthless?

In defense of Popper, it does not. I am not a Popperian. And Popper was 
(despite the way he is usually taught) an early discoverer of what is called

the Quine-Duhem thesis, that you can hold any proposition true by making 
appropriate adjustments elsewhere. The unobjecionable point he had tomake 
about falsificationsim is that a hypothesis sin;t worth much if you threat 
it as true come what may, amking it absolutely immune to testing. If all of 
social science is like that, then it is worthless. But that's not what I 
think of as good social science. I do rather suspect that some of the 
defenses of value theory one display lately have smacked of this vice, 
though.

jks



_
Join the world's largest e-mail service with MSN Hotmail. 
http://www.hotmail.com




Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-07 Thread Ian Murray


- Original Message -
From: Charles Brown [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Thursday, February 07, 2002 1:45 PM
Subject: [PEN-L:22558] Historical Materialism


 Historical Materialism
 by Justin Schwartz
 07 February 2002 05:59 UTC




 
 As we've all been remiss in pointing out until now, the most
 powerful critique of Capital -- in the last decade at the very
 least -- makes no use whatsoever of value theory. What is missing
 from that book.Wall Street, that value theory would
 make substantive improvements on?
 

 well, we have it from very wise people that you can't begin to understand or
 explain capitalism without value theory, we're stucvk at the level of mere
 ecletic phenomenal static description. Sorry, Doug.

 jks

 ^^^

 CB: Actually, you can begin to explain capitalism without value theory, you just 
can't get
anywhere near finishing explaining it without value theory.

===

What do you mean by finishing explaining capitalism? Is there one true way to explain 
capitalism?
Have we transcended Q-D in political economy?

Ian




Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-07 Thread Rakesh Bhandari

  Historical Materialism
by Justin Schwartz
07 February 2002 05:59 UTC 





As we've all been remiss in pointing out until now, the most
powerful critique of Capital -- in the last decade at the very
least -- makes no use whatsoever of value theory. What is missing
from that book.Wall Street, that value theory would
make substantive improvements on?


well, we have it from very wise people that you can't begin to understand or
explain capitalism without value theory, we're stucvk at the level of mere
ecletic phenomenal static description. Sorry, Doug.

jks

^^^

CB: Actually, you can begin to explain capitalism without value 
theory, you just can't get anywhere near finishing explaining it 
without value theory.

Isn't value theory a premise of Doug's book ?


Doug thinks Marx was an underconsumptionist; at the same Doug 
subscribes to the wage led profit squeeze thesis. Doug's an eclectic. 
Doug's hostility to value theory derives in part from his rejection 
of the significance of the Yaffe, Shaikh, Perlo, and Moseley finding 
that despite the so called wage led squeeze on profits,  s/v has had 
a tendency to rise throughout.

Doug thinks his theory is radical because it imlies that since the 
working class had the ability to choke the profitability of the 
working class it may have the power to overthrow the capitalist class.

But there are empirical problems with the wage squeeze theory raised 
by Fred and others, and I don't think Doug has even recognized them. 
And I won't here get into why the implications are not as politically 
radical as Doug thinks.

Moreover, that capital accumulation depends on a rising s/v does in 
fact disclose the limits of this mode of production since as greater 
difficulties are faced in raising the rate of exploitation, the 
system comes to itself depend on convulsive crises by which as a 
result of the destruction and devaluation of capital the value 
composition of capital can be readjusted to the rate of exploitation 
such that accumulation can resumed and the realization of surplus 
value thereby ensured. On the basis of value theory, it is clarified 
that the capitalist way out of crises is not putting more purchasing 
power in the hands of workers or simply increasing the rate of 
exploitation. If the system as a whole cannot be put right even 
through a protracted crisis, then one capital survives ever more only 
at the expense of another, yielding slaughterous destruction in the 
world market and the political tensions to what gives rise. Barbarism 
or socialism.

RB










Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-07 Thread Doug Henwood

Charles Brown wrote:

Isn't value theory a premise of Doug's book ?

If you mean that workers produce everything of value (in conjunction 
with some goods supplied by nature), and that much division and 
redivision of the spoils goes on, and that finance can obscure those 
fundamentals, yes. If you mean the rest of it - OCC, the 
transoformation problem, the distiction between productive and 
unproductive labor, etc. - then no. Damn waste of time, I say.

Doug




Re: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-07 Thread Doug Henwood

Rakesh Bhandari wrote:

Doug thinks Marx was an underconsumptionist; at the same Doug 
subscribes to the wage led profit squeeze thesis.

See, this is exactly what I was thinking of when I quoted Callari's 
observation that VT is a substitute for politics. I don't think you 
could ever prove this conclusively one way or the other using 
numbers. But in political terms, it's not the least bit ambiguous - 
the ruling class felt like it was losing control in the 1970s. 
Workers were sullen and rebellious, the U.S. lost the Vietnam War, 
and the Third World was talking about a new world economic order. As 
Paul McCracken's report for the OECD put it (and I wish I could find 
this exact quote again, it was a beaut), anxiety over inflation was 
inseparable from masses in the streets. The rebels were crushed.

Doug




RE: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-07 Thread Devine, James

 Charles Brown wrote:
 Isn't value theory a premise of Doug's book ?

Doug writes: 
 If you mean that workers produce everything of value (in conjunction 
 with some goods supplied by nature), and that much division and 
 redivision of the spoils goes on, and that finance can obscure those 
 fundamentals, yes. If you mean the rest of it - OCC, the 
 transoformation problem, the distiction between productive and 
 unproductive labor, etc. - then no. Damn waste of time, I say.

The rising OCC theory seems a waste of time except those specifically
interested in crisis theory (and the dogmatic version is just a pain, like
all dogma), while the Ricardian transformation problem (i.e. the
derivation of mathematical relations between prices and values) seems a
total distraction. But your book is suggesting that all of Wall Street is
involved in unproductive labor, Doug. 
Jim D.




Re: RE: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-07 Thread Ian Murray


- Original Message -
From: Devine, James [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Thursday, February 07, 2002 4:01 PM
Subject: [PEN-L:22576] RE: Re: Historical Materialism


  Charles Brown wrote:
  Isn't value theory a premise of Doug's book ?

 Doug writes:
  If you mean that workers produce everything of value (in conjunction
  with some goods supplied by nature), and that much division and
  redivision of the spoils goes on, and that finance can obscure those
  fundamentals, yes. If you mean the rest of it - OCC, the
  transoformation problem, the distiction between productive and
  unproductive labor, etc. - then no. Damn waste of time, I say.

 The rising OCC theory seems a waste of time except those specifically
 interested in crisis theory (and the dogmatic version is just a pain, like
 all dogma), while the Ricardian transformation problem (i.e. the
 derivation of mathematical relations between prices and values) seems a
 total distraction. But your book is suggesting that all of Wall Street is
 involved in unproductive labor, Doug.
 Jim D.



I couldn't help but see it as people playing musical chairs with claims on the future 
of production.

Ian




Re: RE: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-07 Thread Doug Henwood

Devine, James wrote:

But your book is suggesting that all of Wall Street is
involved in unproductive labor, Doug.

But Wall Street is also about arranging the ownership of productive 
assets and allocating investment.

Doug




Re: Re: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-07 Thread Rakesh Bhandari

Doug writes:



Doug thinks Marx was an underconsumptionist; at the same Doug 
subscribes to the wage led profit squeeze thesis.

See, this is exactly what I was thinking of when I quoted Callari's 
observation that VT is a substitute for politics. I don't think you 
could ever prove this conclusively one way or the other using 
numbers.

prove what? problems were surely overcome not by increasing the 
purchasing power of the working class, against your sometimes 
underconsumption theory predicts.



  But in political terms, it's not the least bit ambiguous - the 
ruling class felt like it was losing control in the 1970s. Workers 
were sullen and rebellious,

against rising rates of exploitation or wages not keeping up with 
value of labor power perhaps in part as a result of greater tax 
reductions.


  the U.S. lost the Vietnam War,

leading to inflationary pressure in the process that threatened workers.


and the Third World was talking about a new world economic order.

the terms of trade had turned against OPEC in the 60s; the embargo 
was as much a defensive as offensive action.



  As Paul McCracken's report for the OECD put it (and I wish I could 
find this exact quote again, it was a beaut), anxiety over inflation 
was inseparable from masses in the streets. The rebels were crushed.

Doug

Which should have led to a much greater recovery in the profit rate 
than it did if profits/wage ratio was the main independent variable, 
as you imply when you're not focused on the problem of too high a s/v 
realizing in Dept II output for which there is insufficient consumer 
demand.  That the crushing did not lead to a full restoration of 
profitability underlines the importance of the vcc and u/p labor 
ratio which you want to junk.

At any rate, what value theory explains is why this barbaric 
repression of the working class-- as well as the destruction and 
devaluation of capital in part effected by Volcker's 
bankruptcy-inducing high interest regime and regressive tax reform at 
the expense of social darwinist social policy and the turning of the 
terms of trade against raw materials producers-- restored 
profitability (though only in part as Fred M emphasizes) and renewed 
capitalist accumulation (such that it was).

That this is the capitalist way out of crises is explained on the 
basis of the law of value.

Rakesh




Re: RE: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-07 Thread Rakesh Bhandari

   Charles Brown wrote:
  Isn't value theory a premise of Doug's book ?

Doug writes:
  If you mean that workers produce everything of value (in conjunction
  with some goods supplied by nature), and that much division and
  redivision of the spoils goes on, and that finance can obscure those
  fundamentals, yes. If you mean the rest of it - OCC, the
  transoformation problem, the distiction between productive and
  unproductive labor, etc. - then no. Damn waste of time, I say.

The rising OCC theory seems a waste of time except those specifically
interested in crisis theory (and the dogmatic version is just a pain, like
all dogma),


except that it illuminates what is plain for all to see--the 
importance not greater purchasing power as a 'solution' and/or 
solution but of the destruction and the devaluation of capital in the 
restoration of profitability, accumulation and therefore the 
realization of surplus value.

rb




Re: Re: RE: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-07 Thread Carrol Cox

I have never thought that the productive/unproductive labor opposition
was important -- but I wonder:

Doug Henwood wrote:
 
 Devine, James wrote:
 
 But your book is suggesting that all of Wall Street is
 involved in unproductive labor, Doug.
 
 But Wall Street is also about arranging the ownership of productive
 assets

This, precisely, is unproductive labor as Marx describes it: labor
iinvolved in the realization and distribution of surplus value.


 and allocating investment.

It's been a few years since I read your book, but I sort of remember it
as specifically claiming that Wall Street did NOT allocate investment.

Carrol
 
 Doug




Re: Re: Re: RE: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-07 Thread Doug Henwood

Carrol Cox wrote:

It's been a few years since I read your book, but I sort of remember it
as specifically claiming that Wall Street did NOT allocate investment.

WS doesn't have a large role in funding investment, but firms make 
investments based on what the stock market will like.

Doug




Re: Re: RE: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-07 Thread Doug Henwood

Rakesh Bhandari wrote:

except that it illuminates what is plain for all to see--the 
importance not greater purchasing power as a 'solution' and/or 
solution but of the destruction and the devaluation of capital in 
the restoration of profitability, accumulation and therefore the 
realization of surplus value.

Liquidate liquidate liquidate - this is Mellon and the prophets!

Doug




Re: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-07 Thread Michael Perelman

Rakesh, let Doug speak for himself.

Rakesh Bhandari wrote:


 Doug thinks Marx was an underconsumptionist; at the same Doug
 subscribes to the wage led profit squeeze thesis. Doug's an eclectic.
 Doug's hostility to value theory derives in part from his rejection
 of the significance of the Yaffe, Shaikh, Perlo, and Moseley finding
 that despite the so called wage led squeeze on profits,  s/v has had
 a tendency to rise throughout.

 Doug thinks his theory is radical because it imlies that since the
 working class had the ability to choke the profitability of the
 working class it may have the power to overthrow the capitalist class.

 But there are empirical problems with the wage squeeze theory raised
 by Fred and others, and I don't think Doug has even recognized them.
 And I won't here get into why the implications are not as politically
 radical as Doug thinks.

 Moreover, that capital accumulation depends on a rising s/v does in
 fact disclose the limits of this mode of production since as greater
 difficulties are faced in raising the rate of exploitation, the
 system comes to itself depend on convulsive crises by which as a
 result of the destruction and devaluation of capital the value
 composition of capital can be readjusted to the rate of exploitation
 such that accumulation can resumed and the realization of surplus
 value thereby ensured. On the basis of value theory, it is clarified
 that the capitalist way out of crises is not putting more purchasing
 power in the hands of workers or simply increasing the rate of
 exploitation. If the system as a whole cannot be put right even
 through a protracted crisis, then one capital survives ever more only
 at the expense of another, yielding slaughterous destruction in the
 world market and the political tensions to what gives rise. Barbarism
 or socialism.

 RB

--

Michael Perelman
Economics Department
California State University
Chico, CA 95929

Tel. 530-898-5321
E-Mail [EMAIL PROTECTED]





Re: Re: Re: RE: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-07 Thread Rakesh Bhandari

Rakesh Bhandari wrote:

except that it illuminates what is plain for all to see--the 
importance not greater purchasing power as a 'solution' and/or 
solution but of the destruction and the devaluation of capital in 
the restoration of profitability, accumulation and therefore the 
realization of surplus value.

Liquidate liquidate liquidate - this is Mellon and the prophets!

Doug

But even Mellon here belies the optimistic faith, soon to be 
shattered, that society can master its own crises as long as there is 
no political interference with sharp and short downturns.   Yet as 
Adolf Lowe remarked after the world war the crises intrinsic to the 
capitalist system have lost their virulence; but if we consider an 
international destruction of value like the world war as the modern 
form of crisis in the age of imperialism, and there is much to be 
said for the view, there is little room for extravagant hopes of 
'spontaneous stabilization.'  Quoted in Mattick, Economic Crisis and 
Crisis Theory, p. 120

Doug, as I understand value theory, there is a prediction of an 
inevitable dialectical proces of disturbances, contradictions, and 
crises--not an absolute, purely economic impossibility of 
accumulation, but a constant alternation between the overcoming of 
crisis and its reproduction at a higher level until the destruction 
of the underlying social relations by the working class or the 
self-emancipation of peanuts.

rb





Re: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-06 Thread Justin Schwartz

Q-D underdetermination asserts that if two theories are equivalent
in their empirical entailments then some other criteria needs to be
used to compare explanatory virtues etc.

No, that's Q's empirical equivalence thesis. The Q-D thesis just holds that 
theories are interconnected networks of propositions, and you can hold true 
any one of them (even in the face of empirical refutation) by making 
appropriate adjustmemnts elsewhere.

If the main results of the
LTV and or the LoV whether in a quantitative-qualitative
combination or relying singly on quantitative or qualitative
approaches adds nothing to what can be achieved in terms of
*explanation* without them, then why shouldn't Ockam's razor
apply--to concepts, not entities?

Quite.



_
MSN Photos is the easiest way to share and print your photos: 
http://photos.msn.com/support/worldwide.aspx




RE: Re: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-06 Thread Davies, Daniel



If the main results of the
LTV and or the LoV whether in a quantitative-qualitative
combination or relying singly on quantitative or qualitative
approaches adds nothing to what can be achieved in terms of
*explanation* without them, then why shouldn't Ockam's razor
apply--to concepts, not entities?

Quite.

But this is a perfect example of a fallacy of marginalism.  I think the
strongest anti-LTV/LOV case that you could make in this direction would be
that LTV/LOV don't add anything to what can be explained by neoclassical
marginal/general equilibrium theory.  But even that would be open to the
objection that it was also true that NC theory didn't add anything to
LTV/LOV.  It all depends where you start from ...

And in any case, LTV has the considerable technical merit over NC theory
that it offers a non-circular method to measure the capital stock.  It also
gives some hope of an explanation of the empirical fact that increases in
productivity do not, in general, lead to a shortening of the working day,
which would be a prediction of utility theory given any sensible assumption
about preferences regarding leisure.

dd


___
Email Disclaimer

This communication is for the attention of the
named recipient only and should not be passed
on to any other person. Information relating to
any company or security, is for information
purposes only and should not be interpreted as
a solicitation or offer to buy or sell any security.
The information on which this communication is based
has been obtained from sources we believe to be reliable,
but we do not guarantee its accuracy or completeness.
All expressions of opinion are subject to change
without notice.  All e-mail messages, and associated attachments,
are subject to interception and monitoring for lawful business purposes.
___




Re: RE: Re: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-06 Thread Justin Schwartz


But this is a perfect example of a fallacy of marginalism.  I think the
strongest anti-LTV/LOV case that you could make in this direction would be
that LTV/LOV don't add anything to what can be explained by neoclassical
marginal/general equilibrium theory.

I don't accept GET. I'm basically a Robinsonian/Kaleckian institutionalist 
with a large dash of Austrian thrown in for spice.

But even that would be open to the
objection that it was also true that NC theory didn't add anything to
LTV/LOV.  It all depends where you start from ...

No, I think the LTV fails on its own terms. We do not have empirically 
equivalent theories. We have a theory that points us in the direction of 
some good expalantions that can be stated with its apparatus.


And in any case, LTV has the considerable technical merit over NC theory

No doubt. That's not the only alternative.

jks

_
Chat with friends online, try MSN Messenger: http://messenger.msn.com




RE: Re: RE: Re: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-06 Thread Davies, Daniel


I don't accept GET. I'm basically a Robinsonian/Kaleckian institutionalist 
with a large dash of Austrian thrown in for spice.

Must make for some interesting dinner parties 

But I don't see how saying I'm an institutionalist gets you off the hook
here.  That's not a value theory, and neither Robinson nor Kalecki have
either a way of telling us how to measure the capital stock without a value
theory, or a value theory which is not fundamentally the equivalent of the
LTV (I accept your point about a glass being half-empty or half full, but
surely to heavens, any theory which accepts that value is only produced by
labour is a labour theory of value; I've never understood why Robinson
claimed that she didn't accept LTV).

And in the context of capital and value theory , Austrian isn't a dash of
spice; it's arsenic soup.  It's a marginal theory of value, which hangs you
right back on the hook that you got off with general equilibrium.

I'm sure I don't understand your position properly, and I bet that reading
those two papers will help.  But I think it's clear that there are many good
technical reasons to suppose that economics needs *some* value theory, and
the labour theory of value shapes up pretty well compared to the
competition.

dd



___
Email Disclaimer

This communication is for the attention of the
named recipient only and should not be passed
on to any other person. Information relating to
any company or security, is for information
purposes only and should not be interpreted as
a solicitation or offer to buy or sell any security.
The information on which this communication is based
has been obtained from sources we believe to be reliable,
but we do not guarantee its accuracy or completeness.
All expressions of opinion are subject to change
without notice.  All e-mail messages, and associated attachments,
are subject to interception and monitoring for lawful business purposes.
___




Re: RE: Re: RE: Re: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-06 Thread Justin Schwartz




 I don't accept GET. I'm basically a Robinsonian/Kaleckian 
institutionalist
 with a large dash of Austrian thrown in for spice.

Must make for some interesting dinner parties 

But I don't see how saying I'm an institutionalist gets you off the hook
here.  That's not a value theory, and neither Robinson nor Kalecki have
either a way of telling us how to measure the capital stock without a value
theory, or a value theory which is not fundamentally the equivalent of the
LTV (I accept your point about a glass being half-empty or half full, but
surely to heavens, any theory which accepts that value is only produced by
labour is a labour theory of value; I've never understood why Robinson
claimed that she didn't accept LTV).

I haven't worked it out--I'm not an economist, and I'm not even an academic 
any more, I'm just a lawyer--but I have a sketch of a two-factor theory, 
recognizing labor contribution and demand as dual sources of value.


And in the context of capital and value theory , Austrian isn't a dash of
spice; it's arsenic soup.  It's a marginal theory of value, which hangs you
right back on the hook that you got off with general equilibrium.

No, no. It's institutionalist and realistic.


I'm sure I don't understand your position properly, and I bet that reading
those two papers will help.

Maybe. They onlya ddress VT by the by, WWWE is more on point.

But I think it's clear that there are many good
technical reasons to suppose that economics needs *some* value theory, and
the labour theory of value shapes up pretty well compared to the
competition.

Humnph.

jks

_
Get your FREE download of MSN Explorer at http://explorer.msn.com/intl.asp.




Re: Re: RE: Re: RE: Re: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-06 Thread Rakesh Bhandari

  I don't accept GET. I'm basically a Robinsonian/Kaleckian institutionalist
  with a large dash of Austrian thrown in for spice.

In her essay on Marxian economics, Joan Robinson attempts to point 
Marx's crisis theory in the direction of the kind of 
underconsumptionism that Sweezy was developing and Devine would later 
elaborate. You should understand that Brenner is a forceful critic of 
such underconsumptionism. So what it is that you are saying, Justin, 
is really not quite clear at all.

rb




Re: Re: Re: RE: Re: RE: Re: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-06 Thread Justin Schwartz




  I don't accept GET. I'm basically a Robinsonian/Kaleckian 
institutionalist
  with a large dash of Austrian thrown in for spice.

In her essay on Marxian economics, Joan Robinson attempts to point
Marx's crisis theory in the direction of the kind of
underconsumptionism that Sweezy was developing and Devine would later
elaborate. You should understand that Brenner is a forceful critic of
such underconsumptionism. So what it is that you are saying, Justin,
is really not quite clear at all.


No doubt I am unclear. However, it is possible to accept some of an author's 
views without accepting all of them. I urge this in the case of Robinsin, 
marx, and Brenner. jks


_
Join the world’s largest e-mail service with MSN Hotmail. 
http://www.hotmail.com




Re: Re: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-06 Thread Ian Murray


- Original Message -
From: Justin Schwartz [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Wednesday, February 06, 2002 7:48 AM
Subject: [PEN-L:22458] Re: Re: Historical Materialism


Q-D underdetermination asserts that if two theories are equivalent
in their empirical entailments then some other criteria needs to
be
used to compare explanatory virtues etc.

No, that's Q's empirical equivalence thesis. The Q-D thesis just
holds that
theories are interconnected networks of propositions, and you can
hold true
any one of them (even in the face of empirical refutation) by
making
appropriate adjustmemnts elsewhere.



The empirical equivalence thesis is part of Q-D, no? Wasn't meaning
to suggest it was the whole shebang.

As we've all been remiss in pointing out until now, the most
powerful critique of Capital -- in the last decade at the very
least -- makes no use whatsoever of value theory. What is missing
from that book.Wall Street, that value theory would
make substantive improvements on?

Ian

Few economists pay much attention to corporations, or how they're
owned and run [DH]





Re: RE: Re: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-06 Thread Ian Murray


- Original Message -
From: Davies, Daniel [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Wednesday, February 06, 2002 7:57 AM
Subject: [PEN-L:22460] RE: Re: Re: Historical Materialism




If the main results of the
LTV and or the LoV whether in a quantitative-qualitative
combination or relying singly on quantitative or qualitative
approaches adds nothing to what can be achieved in terms of
*explanation* without them, then why shouldn't Ockam's razor
apply--to concepts, not entities?

Quite.

But this is a perfect example of a fallacy of marginalism.  I think
the
strongest anti-LTV/LOV case that you could make in this direction
would be
that LTV/LOV don't add anything to what can be explained by
neoclassical
marginal/general equilibrium theory.  But even that would be open
to the
objection that it was also true that NC theory didn't add
anything to
LTV/LOV.  It all depends where you start from ...

=
Nah, the big reason we all like Marx vis a vis NC GET etc. is that
he saw Capitalism as a system of power and domination exercised via
money, technology, property etc and that it contradicts everything
we think we know about freedom, co-operation, beneficence and other
human traits that make us potentially different from crocodiles.


And in any case, LTV has the considerable technical merit over NC
theory
that it offers a non-circular method to measure the capital stock.
It also
gives some hope of an explanation of the empirical fact that
increases in
productivity do not, in general, lead to a shortening of the
working day,
which would be a prediction of utility theory given any sensible
assumption
about preferences regarding leisure.

dd

=
As Blaug and others have pointed out, the LTV has circularities of
it's own.

Ian




Re: RE: Re: RE: Re: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-06 Thread Michael Perelman

The measurement of the capital stock is in impossibility.  Franklin Fisher
once worked up the requirements for aggregation.  Can't be done!

The inability to calculate real depreciation presents another barrier.

I mentioned this in passing before in questioning how seriously we should
take estimates of profit rates as anything more than a rough rule of
thumb.

On Wed, Feb 06, 2002 at 04:59:36PM -, Davies, Daniel wrote:
 
 I don't accept GET. I'm basically a Robinsonian/Kaleckian institutionalist 
 with a large dash of Austrian thrown in for spice.
 
 Must make for some interesting dinner parties 
 
 But I don't see how saying I'm an institutionalist gets you off the hook
 here.  That's not a value theory, and neither Robinson nor Kalecki have
 either a way of telling us how to measure the capital stock without a value
 theory, or a value theory which is not fundamentally the equivalent of the
 LTV (I accept your point about a glass being half-empty or half full, but
 surely to heavens, any theory which accepts that value is only produced by
 labour is a labour theory of value; I've never understood why Robinson
 claimed that she didn't accept LTV).
 
 And in the context of capital and value theory , Austrian isn't a dash of
 spice; it's arsenic soup.  It's a marginal theory of value, which hangs you
 right back on the hook that you got off with general equilibrium.
 
 I'm sure I don't understand your position properly, and I bet that reading
 those two papers will help.  But I think it's clear that there are many good
 technical reasons to suppose that economics needs *some* value theory, and
 the labour theory of value shapes up pretty well compared to the
 competition.
 
 dd
 
 
 
 ___
 Email Disclaimer
 
 This communication is for the attention of the
 named recipient only and should not be passed
 on to any other person. Information relating to
 any company or security, is for information
 purposes only and should not be interpreted as
 a solicitation or offer to buy or sell any security.
 The information on which this communication is based
 has been obtained from sources we believe to be reliable,
 but we do not guarantee its accuracy or completeness.
 All expressions of opinion are subject to change
 without notice.  All e-mail messages, and associated attachments,
 are subject to interception and monitoring for lawful business purposes.
 ___
 

-- 
Michael Perelman
Economics Department
California State University
Chico, CA 95929

Tel. 530-898-5321
E-Mail [EMAIL PROTECTED]




Re: Re: Re: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-06 Thread Justin Schwartz





The empirical equivalence thesis is part of Q-D, no? Wasn't meaning
to suggest it was the whole shebang.

I don't think so. It's verificationist. Q-D is not. jks


As we've all been remiss in pointing out until now, the most
powerful critique of Capital -- in the last decade at the very
least -- makes no use whatsoever of value theory. What is missing
from that book.Wall Street, that value theory would
make substantive improvements on?


well, we have it from very wise people that you can't begin to understand or 
explain capitalism without value theory, we're stucvk at the level of mere 
ecletic phenomenal static description. Sorry, Doug.

jks

_
Get your FREE download of MSN Explorer at http://explorer.msn.com/intl.asp.




Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-05 Thread Justin Schwartz


CB: I don't think Marx
 and Engels fold all theory into ideology in the pejorative sense that
 they use it in _The German Ideology_ and elsewhere. So, that the theory 
of
 Marxism is not , paradoxically, unMarxist.

So I argue in the paper.



CB: Do you mean that we agree on this point ? That there is no real paradox 
?


Yes, that is correct.


JKS: [In In Defense of Exploitation] I do use the term [value], after 
defining it. see the last sentence:



Charles: I know you use it , but in order to discard it. Point me more 
specifically to your rationale for discarding its use. I see no logical, 
theoretical, or scientific reason to discard its use ,yet, in what you say. 
Marx argues very convincingly in _Capital+ that the concept of value is 
critical in explaining capital. You don't say anything that dissuades of 
Marx's argument.  Can you give a summary of your most forceful 
argumentative points on that issue ?


I don't in fact discard it in this paper; I assume it arguendo. My limited 
critique of it is published in What's Wrong with Exploitation, Nous 1995, 
also on line at the spoons archive. I have been discussing my objections in 
a thread that is jsut warpping up here.

jks



_
MSN Photos is the easiest way to share and print your photos: 
http://photos.msn.com/support/worldwide.aspx




Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-05 Thread Ian Murray


- Original Message -
From: Charles Brown [EMAIL PROTECTED]


^^^

Haven't you shifted to a different issue ? You started saying that
under  Quine-Duhem underdetermination problem, the burden was on
the proponents of the Marxist theory to demonstrate the
indispensiblity of their theory. But doesn't Quine-Duham
underdetermination deal with a situation in which both theories are
valid and the evidence doesn't help in choosing between them ? If
you are saying that Marx's value theory doesn't correspond to
evidence or can't be tested, that is not a Quine-Duhem
underdetermination problem , is it ?



Charles

===

Q-D underdetermination asserts that if two theories are equivalent
in their empirical entailments then some other criteria needs to be
used to compare explanatory virtues etc. If the main results of the
LTV and or the LoV whether in a quantitative-qualitative
combination or relying singly on quantitative or qualitative
approaches adds nothing to what can be achieved in terms of
*explanation* without them, then why shouldn't Ockam's razor
apply--to concepts, not entities? Especially if some want to say
that the Value concept--polysemy alert-- has no empirical
entailments?

So does the Value concept have empirical entailments or not and
what's the decision procedure for the determination? If we say it
doesn't, then what explanatory work does it do? If we say it does
then it seems to become even more problematic with regards to the
multitude of LTV's in the quantitative version because they haven't
even been shown to be equivalent in their empirical entailments;
that should alert us to something being amiss with the network of
assertions which not only facilitate the construction of the
algorithms for determining the entailments, but the manner in which
the concepts are defined. This assumes, of course, the plausibility
of the analytic-synthetic distinction, an issue also still under
dispute. If we take the qualitative route, then we have to
determine whether or not the Value concept, both in the LTV mode
and the LoV mode passes muster with --take your pick-- any of the
causal theories of reference on offer. If we say that any of the
causal theories of reference on offer don't pass muster in order to
determine the validity of the Value concept, how do we avoid the
idea of having achieved something akin to a Pyhrric victory given
that dueling skepticisms don't facilitate the development of
theories?

Ian






Re: RE: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-04 Thread Justin Schwartz

Well, you know better than I. But they don't teach marxian value theory 
either, and the USSR's early attempt to use what it thought was that theory 
as a planning tool was a disaster. So, anyway, maybe if Daniel was right, we 
don't need a value theory at all. jks


 Oskar Lange used say that Marxian economics is the economics of 
capitalism
 and neoclassical economics is the economics of socialism. If you want to 
do

 monetary and fiscal policy, design an antitrust regime, figure out the
 impact of opening new oilfields on existing transportation options, make 
a
 plan for your own enterprise, you use subjectivist theory. They teach it 
in

 B school cause it works in short and medium term. I don't have to prove 
it:

 the proof is in the practice.

I don't agree with this, and I've been to business school.  The 
subjectivist
value theory of neoclassical economics is the von Neumann/Morgenstern
axioms, and they are completely orthogonal to the economics you learn at
business school (you learn them quite thoroughly in an economics degree, 
but
that's not the same thing).  At business school, you learn in detail the
parts of economics which are not dependent on a value theory and are more
properly part of what one used to call operations research, plus you 
learn
a bit of kiddies' (often surprisingly heterodox) macroeconomics under the
title of International Financial System or some such.

Think about it this way; almost the only module which is compulsory in 
every
MBA at every business school is Marketing, and there is still, after about
150 years of trying, no decent classical or neoclassical theory of the
advertising industry.  Subjectivist value theory is honoured much more in
the ignoring than the observance.

dd


___
Email Disclaimer

This communication is for the attention of the
named recipient only and should not be passed
on to any other person. Information relating to
any company or security, is for information
purposes only and should not be interpreted as
a solicitation or offer to buy or sell any security.
The information on which this communication is based
has been obtained from sources we believe to be reliable,
but we do not guarantee its accuracy or completeness.
All expressions of opinion are subject to change
without notice.  All e-mail messages, and associated attachments,
are subject to interception and monitoring for lawful business purposes.
___



_
Get your FREE download of MSN Explorer at http://explorer.msn.com/intl.asp.




Re: Re: RE: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-04 Thread Michael Perelman

Justin, you keep reminding us of Oskar Lange's economics of socialism
quote.  He thought that General Equilibrium was a proof of the efficacy of
market socialism.  I don't want to debate market socialism -- we have
worked that one over more than enough -- but his proof seems kind of
silly to me.

Phil Mirowski does a great job in his new book of showing how this
approach easily slid into planning for the Pentagon by his disciples.

On Mon, Feb 04, 2002 at 03:10:37PM +, Justin Schwartz wrote:
 Well, you know better than I. But they don't teach marxian value theory 
 either, and the USSR's early attempt to use what it thought was that theory 
 as a planning tool was a disaster. So, anyway, maybe if Daniel was right, we 
 don't need a value theory at all. jks
 
 
  Oskar Lange used say that Marxian economics is the economics of 
 capitalism
  and neoclassical economics is the economics of socialism. If you want to 
 do
 
  monetary and fiscal policy, design an antitrust regime, figure out the
  impact of opening new oilfields on existing transportation options, make 
 a
  plan for your own enterprise, you use subjectivist theory. They teach it 
 in
 
  B school cause it works in short and medium term. I don't have to prove 
 it:
 
  the proof is in the practice.
 
 I don't agree with this, and I've been to business school.  The 
 subjectivist
 value theory of neoclassical economics is the von Neumann/Morgenstern
 axioms, and they are completely orthogonal to the economics you learn at
 business school (you learn them quite thoroughly in an economics degree, 
 but
 that's not the same thing).  At business school, you learn in detail the
 parts of economics which are not dependent on a value theory and are more
 properly part of what one used to call operations research, plus you 
 learn
 a bit of kiddies' (often surprisingly heterodox) macroeconomics under the
 title of International Financial System or some such.
 
 Think about it this way; almost the only module which is compulsory in 
 every
 MBA at every business school is Marketing, and there is still, after about
 150 years of trying, no decent classical or neoclassical theory of the
 advertising industry.  Subjectivist value theory is honoured much more in
 the ignoring than the observance.
 
 dd
 
 
 ___
 Email Disclaimer
 
 This communication is for the attention of the
 named recipient only and should not be passed
 on to any other person. Information relating to
 any company or security, is for information
 purposes only and should not be interpreted as
 a solicitation or offer to buy or sell any security.
 The information on which this communication is based
 has been obtained from sources we believe to be reliable,
 but we do not guarantee its accuracy or completeness.
 All expressions of opinion are subject to change
 without notice.  All e-mail messages, and associated attachments,
 are subject to interception and monitoring for lawful business purposes.
 ___
 
 
 
 _
 Get your FREE download of MSN Explorer at http://explorer.msn.com/intl.asp.
 

-- 
Michael Perelman
Economics Department
California State University
Chico, CA 95929

Tel. 530-898-5321
E-Mail [EMAIL PROTECTED]




RE: Re: RE: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-04 Thread Davies, Daniel

Well this is in Ellman's book which you recommended earlier (Soviet
Planning Today).  It's the difference between economic cybernetics and
political economy as set out by the Central Economic Mathematical
Institute of the USSR Academy of Sciences.  The first of these is what you
learn in business school -- operations research, etc, etc and, as
Kantorovich et al proved, can in general be derived without making any
assumptions about values or preferences, as the outcome of a maximisation
problem in control engineering.

The second of these is what you have to learn to parrot in the approved
manner, or you won't be allowed into business school.  It's the question of
what kind of thing goes into your model; whether you're going to assume that
wage labour is a cost to be minimised, and whether you're going to measure
your output by reference to monotonic, independent, transitive etc utility
functions.  

The confusion between cybernetics and political economy (economics as
engineering and economics as politics) is responsible for a lot of problems
on both sides of (for example) the planning debate (Stalin was of the
opinion that cybernetics was intrinsically bourgeois and beleived that plans
should be made on the basis of purely political-economy considerations, with
predictably disastrous consequences), and the issues dealt with in value
theory economics are right on the cusp of the two approaches.  But I
disagree with you that Marx didn't think that the LTV was basically a
statement about political economy (in the sense used above) and think that
those people are correct who believe that to confine the importance of the
LTV to technical discussions about the production and allocation of goods
under capitalism is to reduce Marx to the status of a minor Ricardian.

cheers

dd

-Original Message-
From: Justin Schwartz [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]]
Sent: 04 February 2002 15:11
To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Subject: [PEN-L:22310] Re: RE: Re: Historical Materialism


Well, you know better than I. But they don't teach marxian value theory 
either, and the USSR's early attempt to use what it thought was that theory 
as a planning tool was a disaster. So, anyway, maybe if Daniel was right, we

don't need a value theory at all. jks


 Oskar Lange used say that Marxian economics is the economics of 
capitalism
 and neoclassical economics is the economics of socialism. If you want to 
do

 monetary and fiscal policy, design an antitrust regime, figure out the
 impact of opening new oilfields on existing transportation options, make 
a
 plan for your own enterprise, you use subjectivist theory. They teach it 
in

 B school cause it works in short and medium term. I don't have to prove 
it:

 the proof is in the practice.

I don't agree with this, and I've been to business school.  The 
subjectivist
value theory of neoclassical economics is the von Neumann/Morgenstern
axioms, and they are completely orthogonal to the economics you learn at
business school (you learn them quite thoroughly in an economics degree, 
but
that's not the same thing).  At business school, you learn in detail the
parts of economics which are not dependent on a value theory and are more
properly part of what one used to call operations research, plus you 
learn
a bit of kiddies' (often surprisingly heterodox) macroeconomics under the
title of International Financial System or some such.

Think about it this way; almost the only module which is compulsory in 
every
MBA at every business school is Marketing, and there is still, after about
150 years of trying, no decent classical or neoclassical theory of the
advertising industry.  Subjectivist value theory is honoured much more in
the ignoring than the observance.

dd


___
Email Disclaimer

This communication is for the attention of the
named recipient only and should not be passed
on to any other person. Information relating to
any company or security, is for information
purposes only and should not be interpreted as
a solicitation or offer to buy or sell any security.
The information on which this communication is based
has been obtained from sources we believe to be reliable,
but we do not guarantee its accuracy or completeness.
All expressions of opinion are subject to change
without notice.  All e-mail messages, and associated attachments,
are subject to interception and monitoring for lawful business purposes.
___



_
Get your FREE download of MSN Explorer at http://explorer.msn.com/intl.asp.


___
Email Disclaimer

This communication is for the attention of the
named recipient only and should not be passed
on to any other person. Information relating to
any company or security, is for information
purposes only and should not be interpreted as
a solicitation or offer to buy or sell any

RE: Re: RE: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-04 Thread Devine, James

JKS writes:Well, you know better than I. But they don't teach marxian value
theory either, and the USSR's early attempt to use what it thought was that
theory as a planning tool was a disaster. So, anyway, maybe if Daniel was
right, we don't need a value theory at all.

1. The fact that they don't teach Marx's law of value in business school
should be seen as evidence of its validity. After all, in Marx's theory,
business people's ideology -- what BBAs and MBAs learn -- would be the most
distorted by commodity fetishism (the illusions created by competition). 

2. I've seen nothing in Marx that suggests that the law of value can or
should be used as a planning method. (Where _does_ this idea come from?) In
fact, it was extremely controversial when Stalin said that the so-called
labor theory of value applied under what he called socialism, since some
said (correctly) that value was a concept of commodity production, not of a
system that was supposed to be producing for use, not exchange. (BTW,
cybernetics in this context seems a perfect tool for techno-bureaucratic
rule, as opposed to Stalin's rule by the party machine.) 

3. Charlie Andrews' interesting FROM CAPITALISM TO EQUALITY includes a
version of law of value in his first stage of socialism: he has
not-for-profit organizations competing in socially-controlled markets, so
that (all else equal) prices tend toward values rather than toward prices of
production (as under capitalism). Of course, he doesn't get bogged down in
this first stage and allows for openings to move toward a higher stage of
socialism.

Jim Devine




Re: Re: Re: RE: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-04 Thread Justin Schwartz


Justin, you keep reminding us of Oskar Lange's economics of socialism
quote.  He thought that General Equilibrium was a proof of the efficacy of
market socialism.  I don't want to debate market socialism -- we have
worked that one over more than enough -- but his proof seems kind of
silly to me.

(a) He did not. This is a common myth. In The Economic Theory of Socialism 
defended central planning by shadow pricing. Later, after experiences as an 
actual planner, he became an advocate of market reform, but not via GET.

(b) I don't endorse Lange's use of GET even in defense of planning by using 
his quip, which is just too good to let go. If I quote Tocqueville or 
Churchill or Machiavelli or Goering or even Perlman for an especially apt 
remark, I do not thereby buy into their total potical philosophies. I do not 
confine myself to quotinf only people I agree with, or I would never quote 
anyone.

(c) Anyway, you know, or should by now, that ich bin ein echt Oesterreicher 
on these matters, not a Arrovian-Debreauvnik. I go with the Hayekian 
critique of GET. So you have to take the commebt in the spirit in which it 
was quoted, which is not for its literal truth. Chhez, you marxists are so 
humorless.

Was looking at your Invention of Capitalism in the bookstore the other day, 
looks good, ; I will buy it, but right now I'm busy with other things.

jks

_
Get your FREE download of MSN Explorer at http://explorer.msn.com/intl.asp.




Re: RE: Re: RE: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-04 Thread Michael Perelman

For a terrific study of the relation between economic sybernetics and
modern economics, see Mirowski's new book, Machine Dreams.

On Mon, Feb 04, 2002 at 03:25:17PM -, Davies, Daniel wrote:
 Well this is in Ellman's book which you recommended earlier (Soviet
 Planning Today).  It's the difference between economic cybernetics and
 political economy as set out by the Central Economic Mathematical
 Institute of the USSR Academy of Sciences.  The first of these is what you
 learn in business school -- operations research, etc, etc and, as
 Kantorovich et al proved, can in general be derived without making any
 assumptions about values or preferences, as the outcome of a maximisation
 problem in control engineering.
 
 The second of these is what you have to learn to parrot in the approved
 manner, or you won't be allowed into business school.  It's the question of
 what kind of thing goes into your model; whether you're going to assume that
 wage labour is a cost to be minimised, and whether you're going to measure
 your output by reference to monotonic, independent, transitive etc utility
 functions.  
 
 The confusion between cybernetics and political economy (economics as
 engineering and economics as politics) is responsible for a lot of problems
 on both sides of (for example) the planning debate (Stalin was of the
 opinion that cybernetics was intrinsically bourgeois and beleived that plans
 should be made on the basis of purely political-economy considerations, with
 predictably disastrous consequences), and the issues dealt with in value
 theory economics are right on the cusp of the two approaches.  But I
 disagree with you that Marx didn't think that the LTV was basically a
 statement about political economy (in the sense used above) and think that
 those people are correct who believe that to confine the importance of the
 LTV to technical discussions about the production and allocation of goods
 under capitalism is to reduce Marx to the status of a minor Ricardian.
 
 cheers
 
 dd
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Justin Schwartz [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]]
 Sent: 04 February 2002 15:11
 To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 Subject: [PEN-L:22310] Re: RE: Re: Historical Materialism
 
 
 Well, you know better than I. But they don't teach marxian value theory 
 either, and the USSR's early attempt to use what it thought was that theory 
 as a planning tool was a disaster. So, anyway, maybe if Daniel was right, we
 
 don't need a value theory at all. jks
 
 
  Oskar Lange used say that Marxian economics is the economics of 
 capitalism
  and neoclassical economics is the economics of socialism. If you want to 
 do
 
  monetary and fiscal policy, design an antitrust regime, figure out the
  impact of opening new oilfields on existing transportation options, make 
 a
  plan for your own enterprise, you use subjectivist theory. They teach it 
 in
 
  B school cause it works in short and medium term. I don't have to prove 
 it:
 
  the proof is in the practice.
 
 I don't agree with this, and I've been to business school.  The 
 subjectivist
 value theory of neoclassical economics is the von Neumann/Morgenstern
 axioms, and they are completely orthogonal to the economics you learn at
 business school (you learn them quite thoroughly in an economics degree, 
 but
 that's not the same thing).  At business school, you learn in detail the
 parts of economics which are not dependent on a value theory and are more
 properly part of what one used to call operations research, plus you 
 learn
 a bit of kiddies' (often surprisingly heterodox) macroeconomics under the
 title of International Financial System or some such.
 
 Think about it this way; almost the only module which is compulsory in 
 every
 MBA at every business school is Marketing, and there is still, after about
 150 years of trying, no decent classical or neoclassical theory of the
 advertising industry.  Subjectivist value theory is honoured much more in
 the ignoring than the observance.
 
 dd
 
 
 ___
 Email Disclaimer
 
 This communication is for the attention of the
 named recipient only and should not be passed
 on to any other person. Information relating to
 any company or security, is for information
 purposes only and should not be interpreted as
 a solicitation or offer to buy or sell any security.
 The information on which this communication is based
 has been obtained from sources we believe to be reliable,
 but we do not guarantee its accuracy or completeness.
 All expressions of opinion are subject to change
 without notice.  All e-mail messages, and associated attachments,
 are subject to interception and monitoring for lawful business purposes.
 ___
 
 
 
 _
 Get your FREE download of MSN Explorer at http://explorer.msn.com/intl.asp

Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-04 Thread Justin Schwartz

I said:
  However, I think
I've made a tolerable start by showing how Marx's theory of exploitation,
the core of Capital I, can be resttaed without the LTV (this in my two
papers on exploitation), and by sketching how the theory of commodity
fetishim, the core of Marx's mature theory of ideology, can also be
statedwithout it (this in The Paradox of ideology). The papers are 
available
on line, and I think you have copies, Charles.

^^^
So, since I put some years
into doing that, the ball is now in your court to show how I have failed.

^

CB: Well, I'll take up the volley, although have commented repeatedly over 
the years of our exchange, for example on the equality/liberty issues.  I 
got  The Paradox of Ideology  from you almost ten years ago now,

Gaak, it is that, isn't it?

One question I had on the paradox of ideology is that I don't think Marx 
and Engels fold all theory into ideology in the pejorative sense that 
they use it in _The German Ideology_ and elsewhere. So, that the theory of 
Marxism is not , paradoxically, unMarxist.

So I argue in the paper.



CB: Yes, I was trying to focus in on LTV  in reading In Defense of 
Exploitation  since it is a specific issue that came up here.

For starters , in the following. it seems to me that it is true that since 
embodied socially necessary labor time is equivalent to value, one 
could substitute that phrase whenever Marx uses value, it might work, but 
why not have a single word for this central concept ?  It's like force = 
mass x acceleration, but the theory doesn't improve by just using mass x 
acceleration instead of force.


I do use the term,a fter defining it. see the last sentence:

 Roemer defines Marxian exploitation as the unequal exchange of labour for 
goods (1986b, 260). A worker is exploited if and only if the amount of 
labour embodied in the goods she can purchase with her wage is less than the 
labour she expended to earn the wage. A capitalist is an exploiter if and 
only if the amount of labour embodied in the goods he can sell is greater 
than that (if any) he expended to acquire these goods. The notion of 
'embodied labour' derives from the LTV. A commodity 'embodies' an amount of 
labour in that its value is determined by the socially necessary labour time 
required to produce it.

jks

_
Get your FREE download of MSN Explorer at http://explorer.msn.com/intl.asp.




Re: Re: Re: RE: Re: re: re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-04 Thread Ian Murray


- Original Message -
From: Ken Hanly [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Friday, February 01, 2002 10:13 PM
Subject: [PEN-L:22213] Re: Re: RE: Re: re: re: Historical
Materialism


I don't understand this stuff about the observational consequences
of
theories at the level of generality of the theory of value. What if
the
labor theory of value is part of the central core of Marxism ? If
that is so
then in itself it does not have any specific empirical implications
period.
Jim Devine seems to take a position of this sort in a piece on
the web:

Marx's goals for the LoV were to analyze the societal
 nature and laws of motion of the capitalism; another way of
 saying this is that the LoV summarizes the method of analysis
 that Marx applies in Capital. The LoV is part of what Imre
 Lakatos [1970] terms the hard core of tautologies and
 simplifying assumptions that is a necessary part of any research
 program.1 The quantitative aspect of value should be seen as a
 true-by-definition accounting framework to be used to break
 through the fetishism of commodities -- allowing the analysis of
 capitalism as a social system. Prices, the accounting framework
 most used by economists, both reflect existing social relations
 and distort their appearance. It is necessary to have an
 alternative to prices if one wants to understand what is going
 on behind the level of appearances: looking at what people do
 in production (i.e., labor, value) helps reveal the social
 relations between them.

If this interpretation is correct then Quine-Duhem's stuff is
irrelevant not
that it makes much sense to me anyway. Seems like a neanderthal
idea to
speak of theories implying empirical consequences just like that
without
assumptions conditions etc. assumed: or of  evidence
straightforwardly
supporting a theory. So the Quine-Duhem stuff is not relevant and
even if it
were why should it be given any particular weight?  Is  it any less
dubious
than the Marxian theory of value?

Cheers, Ken Hanly



Ok but then what's to stop such skepticism creep? What makes any
theory non-dubious if not observational consequences? This puts of
lot of theories on the same level as theology, no?

Ian




Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-04 Thread Ian Murray


- Original Message -
From: Charles Brown [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Saturday, February 02, 2002 12:39 PM
Subject: [PEN-L:22240] Historical Materialism


Historical Materialism
by Ian Murray
01 February 2002 22:33 UTC



Ok, but given the Quine-Duhem underdetermination problem-link
below-is not the burden of proof for the indispensability of Marx's
value theory on those who wish to retain it? Steve Fleetwood has an
essay on this in a recent issue of Capital  Class.

Ian



CB: Before you get to that, isn't the burden on you to demonstrate
that the theory alternative to Marx's explains what Marx's theory
does ?  Justin and the AM's haven't quite proven that to everybody
yet.

=

If Marx's value theory is axiomatic and purely analytic how can it
explain? If the quantitative aspects of the theory are not capable
of generating consistent derivations -whether inductive, abductive
or deductive- from the abstractions that are the 'hard core',
what's being explained?  I'm not convinced that explanation=proof
in non-quantitative social theory and it seems that too many have
argued that explanation must = proof for their opponents yet don't
apply this to their own formulations, so round and round we go,
like theists and atheists. What we see from AM's are investigation
of hypotheses that are in KM's corpus and thinking through the
consequences. If those hypotheses don't hold up let them go; if
they do, retain them. It's a matter of discussion as to whether the
hypotheses that are discarded even need to be replaced.

There's still a big Mirowskian-Klamerian project of investigating
all the metaphors, similes etc., in the 'hard core' [metaphor
alert] of Marx's work, no?

Ian






RE: Historical Materialism

2002-02-04 Thread Davies, Daniel

but the period 1917 -- 1939 was not one during which the cybernetics/Stalin
debate occurred.  There was no genuine science of economic cybernetics in
this period; much of the mathematical toolkit had not been developed.  

dd

-Original Message-
From: Charles Brown [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]]
Sent: 04 February 2002 20:57
To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Subject: [PEN-L:22341] Historical Materialism


 Historical Materialism
by Davies, Daniel
04 February 2002 15:30 UTC




dd: (Stalin was of the
opinion that cybernetics was intrinsically bourgeois and beleived that plans
should be made on the basis of purely political-economy considerations, with
predictably disastrous consequences), 

^^

CB: I know that it is dogma on these lists that Stalin could do no right,
but what exactly is your evidence that the economic history of the Soviet
Union in Stalin's time was not an extraordinary historic achievement ? I
believe Russia was about 1/13 the size of the U.S. economically before the
1917 Revolution. Post WWII , despite the extraordinary destruction of the
Nazi invasion, the USSR reached ½ the U.S. GDP/GNP. That means it grew
faster than the U.S. in the Stalin period.


___
Email Disclaimer

This communication is for the attention of the
named recipient only and should not be passed
on to any other person. Information relating to
any company or security, is for information
purposes only and should not be interpreted as
a solicitation or offer to buy or sell any security.
The information on which this communication is based
has been obtained from sources we believe to be reliable,
but we do not guarantee its accuracy or completeness.
All expressions of opinion are subject to change
without notice.  All e-mail messages, and associated attachments,
are subject to interception and monitoring for lawful business purposes.
___




RE: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-03 Thread Davies, Daniel

Oskar Lange used say that Marxian economics is the economics of capitalism 
and neoclassical economics is the economics of socialism. If you want to do

monetary and fiscal policy, design an antitrust regime, figure out the 
impact of opening new oilfields on existing transportation options, make a 
plan for your own enterprise, you use subjectivist theory. They teach it in

B school cause it works in short and medium term. I don't have to prove it:

the proof is in the practice.

I don't agree with this, and I've been to business school.  The subjectivist
value theory of neoclassical economics is the von Neumann/Morgenstern
axioms, and they are completely orthogonal to the economics you learn at
business school (you learn them quite thoroughly in an economics degree, but
that's not the same thing).  At business school, you learn in detail the
parts of economics which are not dependent on a value theory and are more
properly part of what one used to call operations research, plus you learn
a bit of kiddies' (often surprisingly heterodox) macroeconomics under the
title of International Financial System or some such.

Think about it this way; almost the only module which is compulsory in every
MBA at every business school is Marketing, and there is still, after about
150 years of trying, no decent classical or neoclassical theory of the
advertising industry.  Subjectivist value theory is honoured much more in
the ignoring than the observance.

dd


___
Email Disclaimer

This communication is for the attention of the
named recipient only and should not be passed
on to any other person. Information relating to
any company or security, is for information
purposes only and should not be interpreted as
a solicitation or offer to buy or sell any security.
The information on which this communication is based
has been obtained from sources we believe to be reliable,
but we do not guarantee its accuracy or completeness.
All expressions of opinion are subject to change
without notice.  All e-mail messages, and associated attachments,
are subject to interception and monitoring for lawful business purposes.
___




Re: Re: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-02 Thread Ken Hanly

I don't think that your example is quite correct although I understand your
point. A hand-assembled Toyota would most likely be regarded as superior,
command a higher price and represent a greater value than the Toyota that
was mass produced using a great deal of automation.
But assuming they did have the same value then you are correct the value
or abstract socially necessary labor in both would be the same. However, I
dont see how this counters my point. Let us say that Sam who hand builds
Toyota's has to work twice as long as Sally who is in the automated factory
to embody the same value i.e.abstract socially necessary labor time. Doesn't
it follow that Sam's labor power is not equal in value to that of Sally?
That is my point and it does seem to follow from the theory as far as I can
see. A capitalist is not going to buy any Sam labor power when Sally labor
power produces value at twice the rate of Sam. But maybe I don't understand
what you are saying. Much of this is over my head.

Cheers, Ken Hanly

- Original Message -
From: Justin Schwartz [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Friday, February 01, 2002 10:09 PM
Subject: [PEN-L:22211] Re: Re: Historical Materialism






But SNALT implies that an hour of A's labor may not at all produce the same
exchange value as an hour of B's labor. If the SN labor time to produce X
widgets is one hour and A's labor does that  but B's labor only produces
half that number then in this context an hour of A's labor and of B's are
not equal. No? The labor theory of value implies that the same hour of
labor
of different people is unequal qua its exchange value creation, not that
each person's hour of labor produces equal value.



Ken, you are leaving the abstractness and the social necessity of the
labor out of SNALT. A hand-built Toyota contains excatly the same amount of
ABSTRACT labor time that is socially necessary as a factory built one,
although it takes much longer to make it, because from a social pov theextr
atime is socially unnecessay and the labor involved is abstract or simple,
unskilled labor.

jks



_
Join the world's largest e-mail service with MSN Hotmail.
http://www.hotmail.com




Re: re: re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-02 Thread Rakesh Bhandari

Jim writes:




(2) no, Marx shows convincingly in volume III of CAPITAL that as long as (1)
the rate of surplus-value is constant and uncorrelated with the OCC; (2) the
OCC differs between industries; and (3) the rate of profit tends toward
equality between sectors, prices gravitate toward prices of production
(POPs) that differ from values. Maybe you're thinking of Ricardo, who saw
exactly this kind of result from his analysis but assumed that the value/POP
correlation was good enough for early 19th century British political
economy work (embracing what historians of economic thought call the 98%
labor theory of value [i.e., of price]). For Marx, the connection between
prices and values is macroeconomic in nature, with total value = total price
and total surplus-value = total property income, with the macro structure of
accumulation limiting and shaping the microprocesses that make up that
totality. (Charlie Andrews' recent book, FROM CAPITALISM TO EQUALITY, is
good on this.)


I agree with the focus on totality here. but it is a peculiar focus, 
and I am going to make an outlandish guess as to why.

By vol 3, Marx is nearing his descent to the concrete totality, yet 
Marx seems not interested in *individual* capitals even as he 
approaches them because any one individual capital does not yield--as 
a result of the variance in compositions--surplus value at the same 
rate as would the *typical particular* capitalist (that is, the 
prototype of or a perfect aliquot of the whole class; Meek links 
Marx's typical particular of a capital of average composition to 
Sraffa's standard commodity).

In vol 3 Marx remains more interested in total surplus value produced 
by all the individual capitals, and it is only in terms of 
capital-as-a-whole that the total mass of surplus value can be 
defined, and the average rate of profit determined. 
Capital-as-a-whole is thus revealed to be itself a concrete unit with 
its own specific attributes.

So even as Marx comes to appreciate fully individuality, as opposed 
to typical particularity, in the multiplicity of capitals, he is not 
ultimately interested in the the multiplicity or aggregate of 
individual capitals but with the concrete individual that is itself 
capital as a whole.

Itself a concrete individual, capital-as-a-whole is thus not like 
say boats-as-a whole which is merely a *generalized concrete 
abstraction* for small open craft, ocean liners, battleships and and 
exchange carriers.

In this latter case the members are of course more concrete than the 
abstract class.

But in the case of capital-as-a-whole, the class itself has been 
concretized in that it alone has attributes that its members, as 
individuals *abstracted* from that class, do not.

The capitalist *class* is not a not a mere plurality of capitals; it 
is itself a fairly concrete unit.

I do not think we have here a  fallacy of misplaced concreteness or 
an error of hypostatizing.

Though I do not know whether I am making sense either.


And it may be that the fault should be put on capitalist social 
relations, not those social scientists who reject methodological 
individualism which seems only to accord concreteness to members, not 
classes. Such a stricture may be illsuited for the very society that 
produces the standpoint of the individualist.

rakesh












RE: Re: Re: RE: Re: re: re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-02 Thread Devine, James

thanks. I needed that. -- Jim Devine 

Ken Hanly writes: 
I don't understand this stuff about the observational consequences of
theories at the level of generality of the theory of value. What if the
labor theory of value is part of the central core of Marxism ? If that
is so then in itself it does not have any specific empirical implications
period.

Jim Devine seems to take a position of this sort in a piece on the
web:

Marx's goals for the LoV were to analyze the societal
 nature and laws of motion of the capitalism; another way of
 saying this is that the LoV summarizes the method of analysis
 that Marx applies in Capital. The LoV is part of what Imre
 Lakatos [1970] terms the hard core of tautologies and
 simplifying assumptions that is a necessary part of any research
 program.1 The quantitative aspect of value should be seen as a
 true-by-definition accounting framework to be used to break
 through the fetishism of commodities -- allowing the analysis of
 capitalism as a social system. Prices, the accounting framework
 most used by economists, both reflect existing social relations
 and distort their appearance. It is necessary to have an
 alternative to prices if one wants to understand what is going
 on behind the level of appearances: looking at what people do
 in production (i.e., labor, value) helps reveal the social
 relations between them.

If this interpretation is correct then Quine-Duhem's stuff is irrelevant
not that it makes much sense to me anyway. Seems like a neanderthal idea to
speak of theories implying empirical consequences just like that without
assumptions conditions etc. assumed: or of  evidence straightforwardly
supporting a theory. So the Quine-Duhem stuff is not relevant and even
if it
were why should it be given any particular weight?  Is  it any less
dubious
than the Marxian theory of value?

Cheers, Ken Hanly

- Original Message -
From: Ian Murray [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Friday, February 01, 2002 4:27 PM
Subject: [PEN-L:22192] Re: RE: Re: re: re: Historical Materialism



 - Original Message -
 From: Devine, James [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 Sent: Friday, February 01, 2002 2:11 PM
 Subject: [PEN-L:22191] RE: Re: re: re: Historical Materialism


 Ian quotes Joan Robinson:
  The awkwardness of reckoning in terms of values, while
 commodities
  and labor power are constantly changing in values, accounts for
  much of the obscurity of Marx's exposition, and none of the
  important ideas he expresses in terms of the conceptof value
 cannot
  be better expressed without it.

 I don't think the obscurity of Marx's writing (which is supposed to
 be
 pretty easy to read as German theoretical writing goes) is due to
 his use of
 values. Instead it's because he doesn't do what modern writers do,
 i.e., say
 this is what I'm going to say first; then I'll talk about this,
 etc.,
 explaining the level of abstraction and stuff like that (i.e.
 assumptions)
 at each stage. Instead he plays at being Hegel and starts out very
 abstract
 (the Commodity in General) and becomes progressively more concrete
 without
 explaining the logic of his presentation (even though his analysis
 does make
 sense). (Charlie Andrews' recent book follows Marx on value theory,
 but has
 a much better presentation.)

  As a logical process, the ratio of profits to wages for each
  individual commodity, can be calculated when the rate of profit
 is
  known. The transformation is from prices into values, not the
 other
  way.

 this is what's been called the Steedman critique, though obviously
 Robinson
 thought of it first. It's at the center of Analytic Marxism. I
 think it's
 based on a misunderstanding of Marx's project, the facile
 assumption that
 Marx was a minor post-Ricardian who was first and foremost
 interested in
 price theory and distribution theory.

 Jim Devine

 

 Ok, but given the Quine-Duhem underdetermination problem-link
 below-is not the burden of proof for the indispensability of Marx's
 value theory on those who wish to retain it? Steve Fleetwood has an
 essay on this in a recent issue of Capital  Class.

 Ian


 **
 UNDERDETERMINATION

 Empirical equivalence

 Two theories T1 and T2 are empirically equivalent if every
 observational consequence of T1 is also an observational
 consequence of T2.

 e.g. curved space-time vs.
 flat space-time plus forces

 solar system at rest vs.
 solar system moves with uniform rectilinear velocity v


 Underdetermination and Scepticism

 If T1 and T2 are empirically equivalent, every possible piece of
 evidence that supports T1 will also support T2.

 The evidence underdetermines our choice between T1 or T2.
 How do we decide which of T1 and T2 is true?

 Note This problem only arises where there are empirically
 equivalent theories.

  http://www.dur.ac.uk/~dfl0www/modules/scikandr/ROHP.HTM 






Re: Re: re: re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-02 Thread miyachi
on 2/2/02 07:55 PM, Rakesh Bhandari at [EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:

 Jim writes:
 
 
 
 
 (2) no, Marx shows convincingly in volume III of CAPITAL that as long as (1)
 the rate of surplus-value is constant and uncorrelated with the OCC; (2) the
 OCC differs between industries; and (3) the rate of profit tends toward
 equality between sectors, prices gravitate toward prices of production
 (POPs) that differ from values. Maybe you're thinking of Ricardo, who saw
 exactly this kind of result from his analysis but assumed that the value/POP
 correlation was "good enough for early 19th century British political
 economy work" (embracing what historians of economic thought call the 98%
 labor theory of value [i.e., of price]). For Marx, the connection between
 prices and values is macroeconomic in nature, with total value = total price
 and total surplus-value = total property income, with the macro structure of
 accumulation limiting and shaping the microprocesses that make up that
 totality. (Charlie Andrews' recent book, FROM CAPITALISM TO EQUALITY, is
 good on this.)
 
 
 I agree with the focus on totality here. but it is a peculiar focus,
 and I am going to make an outlandish guess as to why.
 
 By vol 3, Marx is nearing his descent to the concrete totality, yet
 Marx seems not interested in *individual* capitals even as he
 approaches them because any one individual capital does not yield--as
 a result of the variance in compositions--surplus value at the same
 rate as would the *typical particular* capitalist (that is, the
 prototype of or a perfect aliquot of the whole class; Meek links
 Marx's typical particular of a capital of average composition to
 Sraffa's standard commodity).
 
 In vol 3 Marx remains more interested in total surplus value produced
 by all the individual capitals, and it is only in terms of
 capital-as-a-whole that the total mass of surplus value can be
 defined, and the average rate of profit determined.
 Capital-as-a-whole is thus revealed to be itself a concrete unit with
 its own specific attributes.
 
 So even as Marx comes to appreciate fully individuality, as opposed
 to typical particularity, in the multiplicity of capitals, he is not
 ultimately interested in the the multiplicity or aggregate of
 individual capitals but with the concrete individual that is itself
 capital as a whole.
 
 Itself a concrete individual, capital-as-a-whole is thus not like
 say boats-as-a whole which is merely a *generalized concrete
 abstraction* for small open craft, ocean liners, battleships and and
 exchange carriers.
 
 In this latter case the members are of course more concrete than the
 abstract class.
 
 But in the case of capital-as-a-whole, the class itself has been
 concretized in that it alone has attributes that its members, as
 individuals *abstracted* from that class, do not.
 
 The capitalist *class* is not a not a mere plurality of capitals; it
 is itself a fairly concrete unit.
 
 I do not think we have here a  fallacy of misplaced concreteness or
 an error of hypostatizing.
 
 Though I do not know whether I am making sense either.
 
 
 And it may be that the fault should be put on capitalist social
 relations, not those social scientists who reject methodological
 individualism which seems only to accord concreteness to members, not
 classes. Such a stricture may be illsuited for the very society that
 produces the standpoint of the individualist.
 
 rakesh
 SIr Rakesh Bhandari
 
 In "Capital" Marx distinguish buyer-seller relation from class relation
Below is this. True, in the act M---L the owner of money and the owner of
labour-power enter only into the relation of buyer and seller, confront one
another only as money-owner and commodity-owner. In this respect they enter
merely into a money-relation. Yet at the same time the buyer appears also
from the outset in the capacity of an owner of means of production, which
are the material conditions for the productive expenditure of labour-power
by its owner. In other words, these means of production are in opposition to
the owner of the labour-power, being property of another. On the other hand
the seller of labour faces its buyer as labour-power of another which must
be made to do his bidding, must be integrated into his capital, in order
that it may really become productive capital. The class relation between
capitalist and wage-laborer therefore exists, is presupposed from the moment
the two face each other in the act M---L (L---M on the part of the laborer).
It is a purchase and sale, a money-relation, but a purchase and sale in
which the buyer is assumed to be a capitalist and the seller a wage-laborer.
And this relation arises out of the fact that the conditions required for
the realisation of labour-power, viz., means of subsistence and means of
production, are separated from the owner of labour-power, being the property
of another. 
 
 
 
 
 
 


Re: Re: re: re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-02 Thread Rakesh Bhandari

Jim writes:



(2) no, Marx shows convincingly in volume III of CAPITAL that as long as (1)
the rate of surplus-value is constant and uncorrelated with the OCC; (2) the
OCC differs between industries; and (3) the rate of profit tends toward
equality between sectors, prices gravitate toward prices of production
(POPs) that differ from values. Maybe you're thinking of Ricardo, who saw
exactly this kind of result from his analysis but assumed that the value/POP
correlation was good enough for early 19th century British political
economy work (embracing what historians of economic thought call the 98%
labor theory of value [i.e., of price]). For Marx, the connection between
prices and values is macroeconomic in nature, with total value = total price
and total surplus-value = total property income, with the macro structure of
accumulation limiting and shaping the microprocesses that make up that
totality. (Charlie Andrews' recent book, FROM CAPITALISM TO EQUALITY, is
good on this.)


I agree with the focus on totality here. but it is a peculiar focus, 
and I am going to make an outlandish guess as to why.

I just want to add a simple point here which echoes Yoshie's point 
from the capitalist point of view, and I think it says better what I 
was trying to say very early this morning.  For Marx, only once one 
has discoverd the average rate of profit for capital-as-a-whole can 
one discover the limits to the profit that any one capitalist can 
make. No matter whether an individual capitalist beats off the fall 
in the average rate of profit at the expense of other capitals, the 
fall in the average rate for the capitalist class can plunge the 
system into the crisis. As GA Cohen may put it: that the only a few 
can fit through the escape door (micro) before it shuts can only be 
clarified by understanding the situation of the capitalist class 
itself (macro). Despite the strictures of methodological 
individualism, it seems to me quite precisely accurate to speak of 
the fate of the supra-individual entity of capital, which again is 
itself a concrete individual unlike say a generalized concreted 
abstraction like boats-as-a-whole (row boats, aircraft carriers, 
tugboats).

rb







Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-02 Thread Justin Schwartz





CB: Before you get to that, isn't the burden on you to demonstrate that the 
theory alternative to Marx's explains what Marx's theory does ?  Justin and 
the AM's haven't quite proven that to everybody yet.



Well, Marx and Engels collected writings are 50 volumes. However, I think 
I've made a tolerable start by showing how Marx's theory of exploitation, 
the core of Capital I, can be resttaed without the LTV (this in my two 
papers on exploitation), and by sketching how the theory of commodity 
fetishim, the core of Marx's mature theory of ideology, can also be 
statedwithout it (this in The Paradox of ideology). The papers are available 
on line, and I think you have copies, Charles. So, since I put some years 
into doing that, the ball is now in your court to show how I have failed. 
Btw, for crisuis theory and the rest of the main line of Capital, see Daniel 
Little, The Scientific Marx. Robert Brenner's book The Turbulent Economy 
does the same with crisis theory. I will say, too, that in many years of 
explaining Marx to students and others, I have never had to rely onthe LTV 
for any core point; I mean, I'd try to explain it and explain Marx's 
thinking, but then I'd restate it without the LTV. I still don't 
understandwhat I'm supposed to me missing. (Sorry, Jim; I've read your 
papers too, and remains opaque to me).

jks



_
MSN Photos is the easiest way to share and print your photos: 
http://photos.msn.com/support/worldwide.aspx




Re: Re: Re: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-02 Thread Justin Schwartz





I don't think that your example is quite correct although I understand your
point. A hand-assembled Toyota would most likely be regarded as superior,
command a higher price and represent a greater value than the Toyota that
was mass produced using a great deal of automation.

My example assumes that the finished products are identical, or near enough. 
There are real world examples all the time, such as with the machine looms 
that laid waste to the handlooms of India and England. The hand looms took 
longer to make the same cloth, but the value of the product dropped 
preciptously, because the extra time was no longer socially necessary.

 But assuming they did have the same value then you are correct the 
value
or abstract socially necessary labor in both would be the same. However, I
dont see how this counters my point. Let us say that Sam who hand builds
Toyota's has to work twice as long as Sally who is in the automated factory
to embody the same value i.e.abstract socially necessary labor time. 
Doesn't
it follow that Sam's labor power is not equal in value to that of Sally?

This is not a well-formed question. The value of labor power is the wage 
necesasry to reproduce the worker, not the amount of time he must work to 
produce the product. You confuse here the value of the product with the 
value of the producer's labor time. The value of the product is a certain 
amount (the socially necessary part) of the labor time necessary to produce 
the commodity.


That is my point and it does seem to follow from the theory as far as I can
see. A capitalist is not going to buy any Sam labor power when Sally labor
power produces value at twice the rate of Sam.

Quite right. Ask the hand loom weavers. So what's your point?

jks



_
Send and receive Hotmail on your mobile device: http://mobile.msn.com




Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-01 Thread Justin Schwartz


CB: What would be the advantage of formulating [exploitation theory] 
without Marx's way of formulating it , or Engels' way ?

^

Making it clearer, getting it right, avoiding ambiguities, problems, and 
objections with their versions.



I want to say this respectfully, but I think it is slanderous or insult 
without foundation to characterize those who adhere more strictly to Marx 
and Engels position in the law of value debate with AM as religiously 
fundamentalist .

I didn't do that, but there are those who think that Marx wrote it, I 
believe it, and that settles it! I'm sure you've met some. Louis' Marxism 
list is full of 'em.


As far as I am concerned it is like claiming that any physicist or 
biologist who adhere's closely to Einstein or Darwin's positions is being 
worshipfully religious. Horseshit !


Fundamentalism is an attitude. A biologist or physicist may be F about 
Darwin or Einstein if she insista on using the original texts (most 
biologists have physicists have never read Origin of Species or the 1905, 
etc. papers on relativity theory), reject any variation from those formulae, 
treat any objections as wrong in advance, hand on the the ideas even in the 
face of severe predictive and explanatory failures and the degenerating 
utility of certain approaches . . . . Einstein was a fundamentalist about 
determinism, he didn't care hwo good quantum theory looked; Mach about 
atomism.

Anyway, me, I'm not an AM, I don't even call myself a Marxist. But I do 
think the AMs had the right attitude of total irreverence towards 
classics. Marx deserves our respectful attention, and should get the 
scientific criticism he said he welcomed.

jks


_
Get your FREE download of MSN Explorer at http://explorer.msn.com/intl.asp.




re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-01 Thread Devine, James

[I sent this to Justin -- and not the list as a whole -- by mistake. The
e-mail program at my office works one way and the one at home another!] 

Justin writes: However, I argued that it [Marx's theory of exploitation]
did not require the labor theory of value in Marx's canonical formulation to
state it. More generally, the point is that capitalism is exploitative, a
point that _can_ be put without reference to any theory of  value at
all--Roemer has an argument to this effect. I think that Roemer's version
loses a lot of the point of Marx's socological analysis, which, as I say,
can be maintained without holding that labor creates all value or that price
is proportional to value understood as socially necessary abstract labor
time.

Marx didn't say that price is proportional to value. As is pretty clear if
you read all three volumes of the damn book, in volume I of CAPITAL, he
_assumed_ such proportionality in order to break through the fetishism of
commodities, to reveal the macro- and micro-sociology of exploitation.
(Trading at value is a standard of equal exchange, in some ways like an
assumption of perfect competition for modern orthodox economists (MOEs).)
Marx did this without assuming that sociology can be separated from
economics the way orthodox social science assumes; to think that one can
dump Marx's economics without his sociology seems naive at best. In fact one
of his major points is that the economy is one part of society, so that
economics is a form of sociology (i.e., social relations). That's what all
that stuff in volumes I and III about commodity fetishism and the illusions
created by competition -- to my mind the heart of Marx's law of value --
is about. 

As for labor creating all value, that's a matter of definition. There's
some tautology in the theory, akin the tautology that Roemer embraces from
orthodox economics, i.e., individuals are rational utility maximizers. As
Sweezy said in his commentary on the Bohm-Bawerk/Hilferding debate, the
difference is that by using value, Marx starts with the notion that people
live in a society, working together in an interconnected whole, whereas B-W,
the Austrian school, and the MOEs (not to mention the LARRYs and CURLYs)
start with the notion that people are isolated individuals and don't get
further than that, getting stuck in Thatcher-land. 

I spent a lot of time reading and struggling to understand Roemer's theory
of exploitation, BTW. As far as I could tell, it was Henry George's or
George Bernard Shaw's theory of scarcity rent as exploitation, duded up with
math so that people thought it was more profound than it was. And it's not
true that he didn't use a theory of value: Roemer used the Walrasian theory
of value in most of his work, along with some silly game theory. (The
Walrasian theory, for those who don't know, assumes that the totality of
society is held together by a god-like Auctioneer, or some equally silly
assumption.) 

It's possible that the theory of capitalist exploitation could be done
without reference to value (I did something like this in a book that Bill
Dugger edited, called INEQUALITY or something like that), but value is in
the background. (People use philosophy, methodology, etc. without knowing
it.) Marx was speaking the language of the time, working with
Ricardian-classical economics (and criticizing it). (Unfortunately, this led
all sorts of people to mistakenly think that Marx was a Ricardian.) If he
had started with neoclassical economics (like Roemer), I'm afraid, he would
have had a much much harder time understanding the world. Roemer, as far as
I can tell, was able to develop a theory of exploitation only because he
knew that Marx had done so -- and then only did a half-assed job, because he
was blinded by the institutional power of neoclassical economics (it's the
MOEs that grant tenure  promotion) and the romance of mathematical rigor.
He misses the social relations of capitalist domination, both in society and
in the workplace. 

I will add that Jim and Chris B have cast amniadversions on the 
reductionism of classical analytical Marxism, which has largely been
abandoned by its founders (Erik Olin Wright excepted, also Alan Carling). 

As far as I could tell from previous debates on the subject, the only way to
define analytical Marxism without it being simply all Marxism that makes
sense is to have it be reductionist _by definition_, so that by rejecting
reductionism they were rejecting analytical Marxism. 

But the points I am making do not require reductionism of any sort. What
remains of AM--and it does survive in places like the journal Historical
Materialism--is an emphasis on clarity, precision, explicitness, and
rigorous standardss of argument, along with a totally unworshipful attitude
towards traditional formulations or classic texts. These are worth
preserving.

Of course, all of these nice adjectives also apply to Rudolph Hilferding,
Harry Braverman, Paul Sweezy, Louis Althusser, and 

re: re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-01 Thread Devine, James

The following is (1) Justin's reply to what I said in the message I just
forwarded to pen-l, plus (2) my reply to him. -- Jim Devine 

I originally said: Marx didn't say that price is proportional to value. As
is pretty clear if you read all three volumes of the damn book,

(1) Justin responded:  Uh, Jim, you suggesting that I haven't?

(2) no: I never aim messages simply at the person to whom I am responding.
It's aimed at all of the pen-l list. (Even when I'm coresponding with
another individual, I ask what would a third observer say?) BTW, I wish
everyone on pen-l would follow this practice, because it helps avoid
personal insults.
 
 in volume I of CAPITAL, he _assumed_ such proportionality in order to
break through the 
fetishism of commodities, to reveal the macro- and micro-sociology of
exploitation. (Trading at value is a standard of equal exchange, in some
ways like an assumption of perfect competition for modern orthodox
economists (MOEs).)

(1)  Maybe we are not talking the same language. I do not mean by saying
that Marx holds that prices are prop, to value that commodities trade at
value, just that there is a function that takes you from value to prices,
and that this function is statistically true, that is--that over the long
run he thinks prices will tend to fluctuate around values, moreover, that
values explain price levels. Surely he believed that!

(2) no, Marx shows convincingly in volume III of CAPITAL that as long as (1)
the rate of surplus-value is constant and uncorrelated with the OCC; (2) the
OCC differs between industries; and (3) the rate of profit tends toward
equality between sectors, prices gravitate toward prices of production
(POPs) that differ from values. Maybe you're thinking of Ricardo, who saw
exactly this kind of result from his analysis but assumed that the value/POP
correlation was good enough for early 19th century British political
economy work (embracing what historians of economic thought call the 98%
labor theory of value [i.e., of price]). For Marx, the connection between
prices and values is macroeconomic in nature, with total value = total price
and total surplus-value = total property income, with the macro structure of
accumulation limiting and shaping the microprocesses that make up that
totality. (Charlie Andrews' recent book, FROM CAPITALISM TO EQUALITY, is
good on this.) 

BTW, later on in volume III, Marx is very clear that individual participants
in the capitalist system don't give a shite about values or surplus-value.
They see prices, profits, interest, rent, etc., what he sees as superficial
representations of value and surplus-value. 

As for labor creating all value, that's a matter of definition.
 
(1)  Agreed, but definitions can be better or worse.

(2) Definitions are always part and parcel of a theory, defined relative to
other parts of the theory, as with the Newtonian force equation of physics:
force = mass*acceleration. Each of the terms is defined by the other two.
This says that better or worse have to be seen in terms of the theory as a
whole. 

I spent a lot of time reading and struggling to understand Roemer's theory
of exploitation, BTW. As far as I could tell, it was Henry George's or
George Bernard Shaw's theory of scarcity rent as exploitation, duded up with
math so that people thought it was more profound than it was.

(1) I also spent a lot of time on it, learned from your work too.

(2) Good. Do you agree that Roemer attempts a shot-gun marriage between
neoclassical orthodoxy and Marxian theory, one that ultimately fails? 

And it's not true that he didn't use a theory of value: Roemer used the
Walrasian theory of value in most of his work, along with some silly game
theory.

(1) I didn't say R didn't use a theory of value. In this context value
theory is the LTV.

(2) why is that? who sets the context? the long tradition of writings on the
so-called labor theory of value (what I would call the law of value
following Marx or the labor theory of property for clarity's sake) has
contrasted the objective theory of value of Ricardo and Marx with the
subjective theory of value of the neoclassicals, Austrians, etc. (cf.,
e.g., John Strachey's THEORY OF CAPITALIST CRISIS, 1935). I don't really
like that distinction, so I would differentiate labor theories of property
(Locke, Marx) from labor theories of price (Smith, Ricardo) and scarcity
theories of price (the MOEs). But I think that the old tradition of seeing a
theory of value as the philosophical/methodological moment or means of
analytical entry makes a lot of sense. The MOE theory of value that
Roemer embraces -- or embraced, since he's retreated into purely normative
analysis -- is that prices _are_ values, so that only what Marx called the
surface of society (supply, demand, non-market institutions, property
rights, and the like) counts. 
 
It's possible that the theory of capitalist exploitation could be done
without reference to value (I did something like this...), but 

RE: Re: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-01 Thread Devine, James

dd writes: Out of interest, what's wrong with the labour theory of value
[LTV]?  Do the AMs [analytical Marxists] have an alternative theory of
value, or do you try to get along without one? Feel free to not answer if it
would take more labour than is worth bothering with.

A central question is: what in heck do we mean by a labor theory of value?
by a theory of value? If those terms are clearly defined, a lot of silly
debating disappears.

To my mind, Marx did not have a labor theory of value the way Ricardo did,
i.e., a theory aimed at explaining prices by reference to assumedly
pre-existing values. Marx was not a price theorist but a political
economist. Rather, with John Locke, Marx had what I call a labor theory of
property (though obviously, Locke's theory is different from Marx's).
Modern orthodox economics -- embraced by folks such as Roemer and some or
all AMs -- embrace a scarcity theory of price, based on a
philosophical/methodological basis of individualism. Crucial to their
theory of value is the assumption that the word value can only be
interpreted as meaning price. 

jks writes:  I don't want to get into this in great detail, but here's the
short version.  What's called the LTV has two meanings. The [loose] meaning,
intended by most people, is the vulgar version, that labor is the only
source of value, which Marx accepts, 

this ignores the issue of what's meant by value. I believe that for Marx,
it has the following kind of meaning: since he views all societies as
essentially communities of workers (and perhaps non-workers), the value of a
product represents the contribution of its producer to the community as a
whole, from the perspective of the community. (Price would be from the
perspective of individual participants in the system.) In this perspective,
labor is value, as judged from the perspective of the society (that's the
socially-necessary part of SNALT). 

(The term SNALT should not evoke Gesundheit! it refers to
socially-necessary abstract labor time.)

but not in the sense used by most of its adherents, who think that the
vulgar version implies taht workers are entitled,  morally, to the value
that their labor is the source of. Marx was not interested in claims of
justice and would have regarded the labor theory of property underlying this
argument as so much ideology. The vulgar version is wrong in any case
because there is no reason to deny that there may be many factors, including
subjective ones (demand) that go into value.

Marx is pretty clear at the beginning of volume I of CAPITAL that if there's
no demand for a commodity, the labor that goes into it doesn't produce
value. 

 The strict version, used by Marx, holds that price is roughly proportional
to socially necessary abstract labor time. This faces the famous
transformation problem, roughly that there is no nice way to
[mathematically] turn labor values into prices. Marx's own solution is
fatally falwed,a s is universally acknowledged. Borktiwiesz developed a
mathemaeticall adequate solution (expalined simply by Sweezy in The Theory
of Cap Dev.), but the conditions under which it holds are so special and
unrealistic taht it is doubtful that the model has much applicability--you
have to assume constant returns to scale, no alternative production methods,
etc. In addition  there is the neoRicardan critique (Sraffa and Steedman,
arrived at independently by Samuelson) onw hich labor valuesa rea  fifth
wheel: we can compute them from wages and technical input, and under
especial conditions establish a proportionality to prices, but you can get
the prices  directly from the other factors, so why bother with the labor
values?

As I said before, Marx did not believe that price is roughly proportional
to socially abstract labor time. In terms of the idea posited above that
value is the contribution of an individual producer to the community as a
whole (as evaluated by that community), it's important to remember that for
Marx, capitalism is an alienated community. Thus, there is no presumption on
his part (except as a simplifying assumption in volume I of CAPITAL and
under that mythical system called simple commodity production) that
individual contributions to the whole (values) are always proportional to
the society's rewards to an individual (exchange-values, prices). 

Further, if values were always (or always tended toward being) proportional
to exchange-values or prices, the nature of the economic system would be
much more transparent: neither commodity fetishism nor the illusions created
by competition would be important. 

 Finally, there's the point that is key to my mind, which is that the
theory have proved fruitless. There is a minor industry of defending the
LTV, but the fact is that no one has done any interesting work using the
theory for over 100 years. 

Of course, there's a minor industry _debunking_ the so-called LTV, so that
the two industries form a predator/prey relationship. In many ways, both
sides of 

Re: re: re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-01 Thread Ian Murray


- Original Message -
From: Devine, James [EMAIL PROTECTED]


(1)  Maybe we are not talking the same language. I do not mean by
saying
that Marx holds that prices are prop, to value that commodities
trade at
value, just that there is a function that takes you from value to
prices,
and that this function is statistically true, that is--that over
the long
run he thinks prices will tend to fluctuate around values,
moreover, that
values explain price levels. Surely he believed that!

(2) no, Marx shows convincingly in volume III of CAPITAL that as
long as (1)
the rate of surplus-value is constant and uncorrelated with the
OCC; (2) the
OCC differs between industries; and (3) the rate of profit tends
toward
equality between sectors, prices gravitate toward prices of
production
(POPs) that differ from values. Maybe you're thinking of Ricardo,
who saw
exactly this kind of result from his analysis but assumed that the
value/POP
correlation was good enough for early 19th century British
political
economy work (embracing what historians of economic thought call
the 98%
labor theory of value [i.e., of price]). For Marx, the connection
between
prices and values is macroeconomic in nature, with total value =
total price
and total surplus-value = total property income, with the macro
structure of
accumulation limiting and shaping the microprocesses that make up
that
totality. (Charlie Andrews' recent book, FROM CAPITALISM TO
EQUALITY, is
good on this.)

BTW, later on in volume III, Marx is very clear that individual
participants
in the capitalist system don't give a shite about values or
surplus-value.
They see prices, profits, interest, rent, etc., what he sees as
superficial
representations of value and surplus-value.

=

The awkwardness of reckoning in terms of values, while commodities
and labor power are constantly changing in values, accounts for
much of the obscurity of Marx's exposition, and none of the
important ideas he expresses in terms of the conceptof value cannot
be better expressed without it.

As a logical process, the ratio of profits to wages for each
individual commodity, can be calculated when the rate of profit is
known. The transformation is from prices into values, not the other
way.

Joan Robinson

Comments?

Ian







RE: Re: re: re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-01 Thread Devine, James

Ian quotes Joan Robinson: 
 The awkwardness of reckoning in terms of values, while commodities
 and labor power are constantly changing in values, accounts for
 much of the obscurity of Marx's exposition, and none of the
 important ideas he expresses in terms of the conceptof value cannot
 be better expressed without it.

I don't think the obscurity of Marx's writing (which is supposed to be
pretty easy to read as German theoretical writing goes) is due to his use of
values. Instead it's because he doesn't do what modern writers do, i.e., say
this is what I'm going to say first; then I'll talk about this, etc.,
explaining the level of abstraction and stuff like that (i.e. assumptions)
at each stage. Instead he plays at being Hegel and starts out very abstract
(the Commodity in General) and becomes progressively more concrete without
explaining the logic of his presentation (even though his analysis does make
sense). (Charlie Andrews' recent book follows Marx on value theory, but has
a much better presentation.)

 As a logical process, the ratio of profits to wages for each
 individual commodity, can be calculated when the rate of profit is
 known. The transformation is from prices into values, not the other
 way.

this is what's been called the Steedman critique, though obviously Robinson
thought of it first. It's at the center of Analytic Marxism. I think it's
based on a misunderstanding of Marx's project, the facile assumption that
Marx was a minor post-Ricardian who was first and foremost interested in
price theory and distribution theory. 

Jim Devine




Re: RE: Re: re: re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-01 Thread Ian Murray


- Original Message -
From: Devine, James [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Friday, February 01, 2002 2:11 PM
Subject: [PEN-L:22191] RE: Re: re: re: Historical Materialism


Ian quotes Joan Robinson:
 The awkwardness of reckoning in terms of values, while
commodities
 and labor power are constantly changing in values, accounts for
 much of the obscurity of Marx's exposition, and none of the
 important ideas he expresses in terms of the conceptof value
cannot
 be better expressed without it.

I don't think the obscurity of Marx's writing (which is supposed to
be
pretty easy to read as German theoretical writing goes) is due to
his use of
values. Instead it's because he doesn't do what modern writers do,
i.e., say
this is what I'm going to say first; then I'll talk about this,
etc.,
explaining the level of abstraction and stuff like that (i.e.
assumptions)
at each stage. Instead he plays at being Hegel and starts out very
abstract
(the Commodity in General) and becomes progressively more concrete
without
explaining the logic of his presentation (even though his analysis
does make
sense). (Charlie Andrews' recent book follows Marx on value theory,
but has
a much better presentation.)

 As a logical process, the ratio of profits to wages for each
 individual commodity, can be calculated when the rate of profit
is
 known. The transformation is from prices into values, not the
other
 way.

this is what's been called the Steedman critique, though obviously
Robinson
thought of it first. It's at the center of Analytic Marxism. I
think it's
based on a misunderstanding of Marx's project, the facile
assumption that
Marx was a minor post-Ricardian who was first and foremost
interested in
price theory and distribution theory.

Jim Devine



Ok, but given the Quine-Duhem underdetermination problem-link
below-is not the burden of proof for the indispensability of Marx's
value theory on those who wish to retain it? Steve Fleetwood has an
essay on this in a recent issue of Capital  Class.

Ian


**
UNDERDETERMINATION

Empirical equivalence

Two theories T1 and T2 are empirically equivalent if every
observational consequence of T1 is also an observational
consequence of T2.

e.g. curved space-time vs.
flat space-time plus forces

solar system at rest vs.
solar system moves with uniform rectilinear velocity v


Underdetermination and Scepticism

If T1 and T2 are empirically equivalent, every possible piece of
evidence that supports T1 will also support T2.

The evidence underdetermines our choice between T1 or T2.
How do we decide which of T1 and T2 is true?

Note This problem only arises where there are empirically
equivalent theories.

 http://www.dur.ac.uk/~dfl0www/modules/scikandr/ROHP.HTM 





Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-01 Thread Justin Schwartz

Justin: clip...The vulgar version is wrong in any case
because there is no reason to deny that there may be many factors, 
including
subjective ones (demand) that go into value.

^^

CB: This suggests lack of understanding of  Marx's analytical distinction 
between use-value and exchange-value ( value).  Demand  or want and its 
subjective  source compose use-value, which does not impact the labor 
theory of value, or law of value.


As MArx exaplins it himself in CI, value is whatever it is about useful 
things that enables them to explain at more or less stable ratios. That 
might be lots of things--he says, what else could it be but labor (time)? 
But in fact desirability is another feature, and there may be others. 
Obviously a two factor theory is not the tradituonal LTV, but I reject the 
traditional LTV. That is a disagreement, not a lack of undferstanding.

^^^

Justin: Finally, there's the point that is key to my mind, which is that 
the theory
have proved fruitless.

CB: Says you.  The LTV is a key component of the science founded in 
_Capital_.  It seems an analyticist style error to detach the LTV from the 
entire ( whole) theory of Marx..   _Capital_ has born much fruit in 
theoretical political economy. Some of the better known works are by Lenin, 
Luxemburg,  Sweezy, Perlo, Perelman..etc., etc.,etc. And of course 
_Capital_ has proved extraordinarily more fruitful in practice, in actually 
changing the world, than most theories ( any other theories ).


I think that every important proposition of Marx, including the theory of 
commodity fetishism, the fact of exploitation, the allegedfalling rate of 
profit, the recurrence of crisis, etc. can be stated without the LTV. I was 
in the business of explaining Marx to student sfor 15 years, and I found I 
had to translate it out of LTVese and into English to get the ideas across. 
So, I embrace this analyticist error with fervor. The LTV is obsolete 
obscurantism,a nd moreover I think that Mrx doesn't even hold it--i explain 
why (briefly), in What's Wrong With Exploitation, Nous 1995, on the net 
also,w hich reconstructs exploitation theory without the LTV.

As to the practical successes you attribute to Capital, insofaras the 
experience of fomerly existing communsim can bea ttributed to Capital, it 
wasn't a great success--but we have been through that recently; and I 
actually agree with Gramsci who called the Russian Revolution the 
Revolution Against Capitsl, he meant in a double sense, because it wasa 
aginst capitalism and against the traditional idea in Capital that 
revolution required a high level of development. I think that formeraly 
existing communsim has not much to do with Capital.


CB: This implies that neo-classical subjectivist theory has proven fruitful 
in a way that Marx's theory hasn't.  You haven't adduced evidence of that 
here.


Oskar Lange used say that Marxian economics is the economics of capitalism 
and neoclassical economics is the economics of socialism. If you want to do 
monetary and fiscal policy, design an antitrust regime, figure out the 
impact of opening new oilfields on existing transportation options, make a 
plan for your own enterprise, you use subjectivist theory. They teach it in 
B school cause it works in short and medium term. I don't have to prove it: 
the proof is in the practice.

jks

_
Send and receive Hotmail on your mobile device: http://mobile.msn.com




Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-01 Thread Ken Hanly

But SNALT implies that an hour of A's labor may not at all produce the same
exchange value as an hour of B's labor. If the SN labor time to produce X
widgets is one hour and A's labor does that  but B's labor only produces
half that number then in this context an hour of A's labor and of B's are
not equal. No? The labor theory of value implies that the same hour of labor
of different people is unequal qua its exchange value creation, not that
each person's hour of labor produces equal value.

Cheers, Ken Hanly

- Original Message -
From: Charles Brown [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Friday, February 01, 2002 1:30 PM
Subject: [PEN-L:22176] Historical Materialism


 Historical Materialism
 by Davies, Daniel
 01 February 2002 16:01 UTC


 Why? The question is, what work does this alleged quantity do? I agree
that

 LTV talk is useful heuristic way to saying that there's exploitation. But
 we
 can say that without LTV talk, that is, without denying that there are
 other
 sources of value than labor or that SNALT does not provide a useful
measure

 of a significant quantity.

 I would have thought that a more important reason for trying to hang onto
 the LTV is that it embodies a fundamental egalitarian principle; if we
 believe that my life is equally as valuable as your life, then an hour of
my
 life must be worth the same as an hour of your life, and I think that this
 ends up implying something like the LTV.

 dd

 ^^^

 CB: Yes, and in a related idea, there is a principle of seeming inherent
human sense of equality underlying Engels and Marx historical materialist
first principle that the history of exploitative class society is the
history of exploited and oppressed  classes struggling against their
oppression and exploitation.







Re: Re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-01 Thread Justin Schwartz





But SNALT implies that an hour of A's labor may not at all produce the same
exchange value as an hour of B's labor. If the SN labor time to produce X
widgets is one hour and A's labor does that  but B's labor only produces
half that number then in this context an hour of A's labor and of B's are
not equal. No? The labor theory of value implies that the same hour of 
labor
of different people is unequal qua its exchange value creation, not that
each person's hour of labor produces equal value.



Ken, you are leaving the abstractness and the social necessity of the 
labor out of SNALT. A hand-built Toyota contains excatly the same amount of 
ABSTRACT labor time that is socially necessary as a factory built one, 
although it takes much longer to make it, because from a social pov theextr 
atime is socially unnecessay and the labor involved is abstract or simple, 
unskilled labor.

jks



_
Join the world’s largest e-mail service with MSN Hotmail. 
http://www.hotmail.com




Re: Re: RE: Re: re: re: Historical Materialism

2002-02-01 Thread Ken Hanly

I don't understand this stuff about the observational consequences of
theories at the level of generality of the theory of value. What if the
labor theory of value is part of the central core of Marxism ? If that is so
then in itself it does not have any specific empirical implications
period.
Jim Devine seems to take a position of this sort in a piece on the web:

Marx's goals for the LoV were to analyze the societal
 nature and laws of motion of the capitalism; another way of
 saying this is that the LoV summarizes the method of analysis
 that Marx applies in Capital. The LoV is part of what Imre
 Lakatos [1970] terms the hard core of tautologies and
 simplifying assumptions that is a necessary part of any research
 program.1 The quantitative aspect of value should be seen as a
 true-by-definition accounting framework to be used to break
 through the fetishism of commodities -- allowing the analysis of
 capitalism as a social system. Prices, the accounting framework
 most used by economists, both reflect existing social relations
 and distort their appearance. It is necessary to have an
 alternative to prices if one wants to understand what is going
 on behind the level of appearances: looking at what people do
 in production (i.e., labor, value) helps reveal the social
 relations between them.

If this interpretation is correct then Quine-Duhem's stuff is irrelevant not
that it makes much sense to me anyway. Seems like a neanderthal idea to
speak of theories implying empirical consequences just like that without
assumptions conditions etc. assumed: or of  evidence straightforwardly
supporting a theory. So the Quine-Duhem stuff is not relevant and even if it
were why should it be given any particular weight?  Is  it any less dubious
than the Marxian theory of value?

Cheers, Ken Hanly

- Original Message -
From: Ian Murray [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Friday, February 01, 2002 4:27 PM
Subject: [PEN-L:22192] Re: RE: Re: re: re: Historical Materialism



 - Original Message -
 From: Devine, James [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 Sent: Friday, February 01, 2002 2:11 PM
 Subject: [PEN-L:22191] RE: Re: re: re: Historical Materialism


 Ian quotes Joan Robinson:
  The awkwardness of reckoning in terms of values, while
 commodities
  and labor power are constantly changing in values, accounts for
  much of the obscurity of Marx's exposition, and none of the
  important ideas he expresses in terms of the conceptof value
 cannot
  be better expressed without it.

 I don't think the obscurity of Marx's writing (which is supposed to
 be
 pretty easy to read as German theoretical writing goes) is due to
 his use of
 values. Instead it's because he doesn't do what modern writers do,
 i.e., say
 this is what I'm going to say first; then I'll talk about this,
 etc.,
 explaining the level of abstraction and stuff like that (i.e.
 assumptions)
 at each stage. Instead he plays at being Hegel and starts out very
 abstract
 (the Commodity in General) and becomes progressively more concrete
 without
 explaining the logic of his presentation (even though his analysis
 does make
 sense). (Charlie Andrews' recent book follows Marx on value theory,
 but has
 a much better presentation.)

  As a logical process, the ratio of profits to wages for each
  individual commodity, can be calculated when the rate of profit
 is
  known. The transformation is from prices into values, not the
 other
  way.

 this is what's been called the Steedman critique, though obviously
 Robinson
 thought of it first. It's at the center of Analytic Marxism. I
 think it's
 based on a misunderstanding of Marx's project, the facile
 assumption that
 Marx was a minor post-Ricardian who was first and foremost
 interested in
 price theory and distribution theory.

 Jim Devine

 

 Ok, but given the Quine-Duhem underdetermination problem-link
 below-is not the burden of proof for the indispensability of Marx's
 value theory on those who wish to retain it? Steve Fleetwood has an
 essay on this in a recent issue of Capital  Class.

 Ian


 **
 UNDERDETERMINATION

 Empirical equivalence

 Two theories T1 and T2 are empirically equivalent if every
 observational consequence of T1 is also an observational
 consequence of T2.

 e.g. curved space-time vs.
 flat space-time plus forces

 solar system at rest vs.
 solar system moves with uniform rectilinear velocity v


 Underdetermination and Scepticism

 If T1 and T2 are empirically equivalent, every possible piece of
 evidence that supports T1 will also support T2.

 The evidence underdetermines our choice between T1 or T2.
 How do we decide which of T1 and T2 is true?

 Note This problem only arises where there are empirically
 equivalent theories.

  http://www.dur.ac.uk/~dfl0www/modules/scikandr/ROHP.HTM